Mathematical Induction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mathematical Induction U.U.D.M. Project Report 2020:21 Mathematical Induction Hanna Wedin Examensarbete i matematik, 15 hp Handledare: Inger Sigstam Examinator: Veronica Crispin Quinonez Juni 2020 Department of Mathematics Uppsala University Abstract Mathematical Induction is used in all fields of mathematics. In this thesis we will do an overview of mathematical induction and see how we can use it to prove statements about natural numbers. We will take a look at how it has been used in history and where the name mathematical induction came from. We will also look at different types of induction, weak and strong induction. You can also do induction on other types of structures, like the length of propositions. 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 History . 4 1.2 Paradoxes with induction . 5 2 Mathematical Induction 5 2.1 Axiom . 6 2.2 Examples . 6 2.2.1 The sum of i ......................... 6 2.2.2 The sum of i2 ......................... 7 3 Strong Induction 8 3.1 Examples . 9 3.1.1 Example . 9 3.1.2 The Fibonacci sequence . 10 3.1.3 Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic . 10 3.1.4 The sum jk .......................... 10 4 Induction on other structures 12 4.1 Examples . 13 5 More Examples 15 5.1 The Ackermann function . 15 5.1.1 Example 1 . 15 5.1.2 Example 2 . 16 5.1.3 Example 3 . 16 5.1.4 Example 4 . 17 5.2 Linear algebra . 18 5.3 Binomial coefficients . 18 5.3.1 Binomial . 18 5.3.2 The Binomial Theorem . 19 5.4 Calculus . 20 5.4.1 The General Power Rule . 20 5.4.2 The Leibniz rule . 21 5.4.3 Taylor's theorem . 22 6 Conclusion 24 2 1 Introduction Mathematical induction has a big influence in mathematics. It is a way to prove mathematical statements about natural numbers. You start learn about math- ematical induction and the principle of induction in the later upper secondary school in Sweden. You also learn about induction in the university if you study mathematics. The principle of Mathematical Induction consist of three steps: 1. Base case, show that it holds for the first value. 2. Induction step: Here you assume that the statements holds for a random value, and then you show that it also holds for the value after that. 3. Conclusion, because the statement holds for the base and for the inductive step, it is true for every value. You can think of induction in an illustrating way, think of a ladder. In the Base case we check that we have a first step to step on. Then in the induction step we go to an arbitrary step p and then we show that if we go to p there is a step after, p + 1. So if we go to an arbitrary step on the ladder we want to show that we can lift our leg and go to the next step. Why does this work? Because if our base case is p and then we can show that we can go to the second step p + 1, if we now let the second step be p we can show that we can go to the third step, p + 1, and then we can let the third step be p, and so it goes on and therefore we have show that we can go to any step on the ladder. Figure 1: A ladder, an illustration of induction. You can also think of mathematical induction like a domino effect. The 3 base step is that the first domino will fall, and then if any domino fall then the domino after also will fall. So all dominoes will fall. [4] 1.1 History Mathematical induction has been used in mathematics way back in history. Some people think that even Euclid used induction when he proved that there are infinitely many primes, even though there is no evidence that he used it, but some writers think that he implied it without being stated directly. Some also thinks that Plato and Pappus used induction but there are no evidence that they used it[3]. The Italian mathematician Francesco Maurolico (1494 − 1575) did a nonin- ductive proof concerning the sum of the first n natural numbers. Even though Maurolico did a noninductive proof there are people who think that Pascal got his inspiration for the induction principle from Maurolico, when Pascal in the 16th century showed by induction what the sum of the first n natural numbers is [3]. In [3] it says that sometimes induction is compared to the method of ex- haustion, like Calivieres principle where he calculates the area of a circle. There he draws polygons that fits in the circle, because he knew how to calculate the area of a polygon, and then he draws larger and larger polygons, until he has drawn a polygon which is almost in the same size as the circle. The similarities with induction and the method of exhaustion is that you start with a guess, and to prove your guess you do infinitely many iterations which follows from earlier steps. There are some proofs that are used with the method of exhaustion that can be translated into an inductive proof. There was an Egyptian called ibn al-Haytham (969-1038) who used inductive reasoning to prove the formula for n X n 1 1 1 i4 = + n n + (n + 1)n − : 5 5 2 3 i=1 Levi ben Gerson (1288-1344), used mathematical induction, he called the method \rising step by step without end". Comparing to how we are used to use induc- tion where we first do the base case and then the induction step to show that it hold for n to n + 1, Levi started with the induction step and then he showed for the base. He used induction to show that (1 + 2 + ··· + n)2 = n3 + (1 + 2 + ··· + (n − 1))2: Levi also did an inductive proof where he went from n to n − 1 [5]. As you can see mathematicians in history have used mathematical induction and inductive reasoning for a long time, but there were no one who had named this method yet. According to [2] the first ones who started to name induction was the Englishman John Wallis (1616 − 1703) and the Swiss Jacob Bernoulli (1655 − 1705). Wallis used a kind of induction called incomplete induction to 4 Pn 2 2 find the ratio between i=1 i and n (n + 1). Wallis incomplete induction both got bad and good criticism. Bernoulli was one of the ones who gave Wallis bad criticism and he introduced the principle argument from n to n + 1. Bernoulli criticized Wallis but he also thought that even though Wallis used incomplete induction it was a start to induction. Bernoulli showed the Binomial theorem with the argument when you go from n to n + 1. Georg Simon Kl¨ugel(1739 − 1812) explained the weakness of Wallis induc- tion in his dictionary, he also explains Bernoullis proof from n to n + 1. Then in England Thomas Simpson (1710 − 1761) used the n to n + 1, but neither did he give it a name. In the early part of the nineteenth century George Peacock, 1830, used induction, and the n to n + 1 argument and he called it \demonstrative induction". In 1833 Augustus De Morgan suggested a new name \successive in- duction", but in the end of his article he used \mathematical induction". Both the names \demonstrative induction" and \mathematical induction" are used by writers. But then the \demonstrative induction" get disused. In the USA induction was used but not called by its name, in Europe, the name \mathe- matical induction" was used. The Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano (1858 − 1932) formulated the axiom system we call the Peano's axiom in 1889. With Peano's axiom we can construct all the natural numbers, and one of his axiom is the one we call the Induction axiom. You will see the axiom in section 2.1. There are a lot more of well-known mathematicians who has used mathe- matical induction, if you want to read more about it you can look in the history section in [3]. There are a lot more sources where you can find more information if you are interested. 1.2 Paradoxes with induction There are some paradoxes with induction and inductive reasoning. [3] has some fun examples of different paradoxes. One example is about a teacher who told his students that next week they will get an unprepared test. And the students think that if they don't have had the test on Thursday night they cannot have it on Friday because then they will know that the test must be on Friday and it will not be unprepared. So the test cannot be on Friday, by the same argument the test cannot be on Thursday, and either on Wednesday, or Tuesday or Monday. So they will not have a test next week. Another example is about being bald, if you don't have any hair on you head you are bald but if you only have one hair you will still be bald, so if you only have one hair more you will still be bald, therefore everyone is bald. 2 Mathematical Induction The most common induction is induction over integers. This is the one you start learn in school and use to prove simpler theorems. It is easy to think that math- ematical induction is something you only use in logic and algebra, but the fact is 5 that you use mathematical induction in almost all fields of mathematics.
Recommended publications
  • Chapter 3 Induction and Recursion
    Chapter 3 Induction and Recursion 3.1 Induction: An informal introduction This section is intended as a somewhat informal introduction to The Principle of Mathematical Induction (PMI): a theorem that establishes the validity of the proof method which goes by the same name. There is a particular format for writing the proofs which makes it clear that PMI is being used. We will not explicitly use this format when introducing the method, but will do so for the large number of different examples given later. Suppose you are given a large supply of L-shaped tiles as shown on the left of the figure below. The question you are asked to answer is whether these tiles can be used to exactly cover the squares of an 2n × 2n punctured grid { a 2n × 2n grid that has had one square cut out { say the 8 × 8 example shown in the right of the figure. 1 2 CHAPTER 3. INDUCTION AND RECURSION In order for this to be possible at all, the number of squares in the punctured grid has to be a multiple of three. It is. The number of squares is 2n2n − 1 = 22n − 1 = 4n − 1 ≡ 1n − 1 ≡ 0 (mod 3): But that does not mean we can tile the punctured grid. In order to get some traction on what to do, let's try some small examples. The tiling is easy to find if n = 1 because 2 × 2 punctured grid is exactly covered by one tile. Let's try n = 2, so that our punctured grid is 4 × 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Induction
    Mathematical Induction Lecture 10-11 Menu • Mathematical Induction • Strong Induction • Recursive Definitions • Structural Induction Climbing an Infinite Ladder Suppose we have an infinite ladder: 1. We can reach the first rung of the ladder. 2. If we can reach a particular rung of the ladder, then we can reach the next rung. From (1), we can reach the first rung. Then by applying (2), we can reach the second rung. Applying (2) again, the third rung. And so on. We can apply (2) any number of times to reach any particular rung, no matter how high up. This example motivates proof by mathematical induction. Principle of Mathematical Induction Principle of Mathematical Induction: To prove that P(n) is true for all positive integers n, we complete these steps: Basis Step: Show that P(1) is true. Inductive Step: Show that P(k) → P(k + 1) is true for all positive integers k. To complete the inductive step, assuming the inductive hypothesis that P(k) holds for an arbitrary integer k, show that must P(k + 1) be true. Climbing an Infinite Ladder Example: Basis Step: By (1), we can reach rung 1. Inductive Step: Assume the inductive hypothesis that we can reach rung k. Then by (2), we can reach rung k + 1. Hence, P(k) → P(k + 1) is true for all positive integers k. We can reach every rung on the ladder. Logic and Mathematical Induction • Mathematical induction can be expressed as the rule of inference (P(1) ∧ ∀k (P(k) → P(k + 1))) → ∀n P(n), where the domain is the set of positive integers.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 Induction and Recursion
    Chapter 4 Induction and Recursion 4.1 Induction: An informal introduction This section is intended as a somewhat informal introduction to The Principle of Mathematical Induction (PMI): a theorem that establishes the validity of the proof method which goes by the same name. There is a particular format for writing the proofs which makes it clear that PMI is being used. We will not explicitly use this format when introducing the method, but will do so for the large number of different examples given later. Suppose you are given a large supply of L-shaped tiles as shown on the left of the figure below. The question you are asked to answer is whether these tiles can be used to exactly cover the squares of an 2n × 2n punctured grid { a 2n × 2n grid that has had one square cut out { say the 8 × 8 example shown in the right of the figure. 1 2 CHAPTER 4. INDUCTION AND RECURSION In order for this to be possible at all, the number of squares in the punctured grid has to be a multiple of three. By direct calculation we can see that it is true when n = 1; 2 or 3, and these are the cases we're interested in here. It turns out to be true in general; this is easy to show using congruences, which we will study later, and also can be shown using methods in this chapter. But that does not mean we can tile the punctured grid. In order to get some traction on what to do, let's try some small examples.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 7. Induction and Recursion
    Chapter 7. Induction and Recursion Part 1. Mathematical Induction The principle of mathematical induction is this: to establish an infinite sequence of propositions P1,P2,P3,...,Pn,... (or, simply put, Pn (n 1)), it is enough to verify the following two things ≥ (1) P1, and (2) Pk Pk ; (that is, assuming Pk vaild, we can rpove the validity of Pk ). ⇒ + 1 + 1 These two things will give a “domino effect” for the validity of all Pn (n 1). Indeed, ≥ step (1) tells us that P1 is true. Applying (2) to the case n = 1, we know that P2 is true. Knowing that P2 is true and applying (2) to the case n = 2 we know that P3 is true. Continue in this manner, we see that P4 is true, P5 is true, etc. This argument can go on and on. Now you should be convinced that Pn is true, no matter how big is n. We give some examples to show how this induction principle works. Example 1. Use mathematical induction to show 1 + 3 + 5 + + (2n 1) = n2. ··· − (Remember: in mathematics, “show” means “prove”.) Answer: For n = 1, the identity becomes 1 = 12, which is obviously true. Now assume the validity of the identity for n = k: 1 + 3 + 5 + + (2k 1) = k2. ··· − For n = k + 1, the left hand side of the identity is 1 + 3 + 5 + + (2k 1) + (2(k + 1) 1) = k2 + (2k + 1) = (k + 1)2 ··· − − which is the right hand side for n = k + 1. The proof is complete. 1 Example 2. Use mathematical induction to show the following formula for a geometric series: 1 xn+ 1 1 + x + x2 + + xn = − .
    [Show full text]
  • 3 Mathematical Induction
    Hardegree, Metalogic, Mathematical Induction page 1 of 27 3 Mathematical Induction 1. Introduction.......................................................................................................................................2 2. Explicit Definitions ..........................................................................................................................2 3. Inductive Definitions ........................................................................................................................3 4. An Aside on Terminology.................................................................................................................3 5. Induction in Arithmetic .....................................................................................................................3 6. Inductive Proofs in Arithmetic..........................................................................................................4 7. Inductive Proofs in Meta-Logic ........................................................................................................5 8. Expanded Induction in Arithmetic.....................................................................................................7 9. Expanded Induction in Meta-Logic...................................................................................................8 10. How Induction Captures ‘Nothing Else’...........................................................................................9 11. Exercises For Chapter 3 .................................................................................................................11
    [Show full text]
  • Proofs and Mathematical Reasoning
    Proofs and Mathematical Reasoning University of Birmingham Author: Supervisors: Agata Stefanowicz Joe Kyle Michael Grove September 2014 c University of Birmingham 2014 Contents 1 Introduction 6 2 Mathematical language and symbols 6 2.1 Mathematics is a language . .6 2.2 Greek alphabet . .6 2.3 Symbols . .6 2.4 Words in mathematics . .7 3 What is a proof? 9 3.1 Writer versus reader . .9 3.2 Methods of proofs . .9 3.3 Implications and if and only if statements . 10 4 Direct proof 11 4.1 Description of method . 11 4.2 Hard parts? . 11 4.3 Examples . 11 4.4 Fallacious \proofs" . 15 4.5 Counterexamples . 16 5 Proof by cases 17 5.1 Method . 17 5.2 Hard parts? . 17 5.3 Examples of proof by cases . 17 6 Mathematical Induction 19 6.1 Method . 19 6.2 Versions of induction. 19 6.3 Hard parts? . 20 6.4 Examples of mathematical induction . 20 7 Contradiction 26 7.1 Method . 26 7.2 Hard parts? . 26 7.3 Examples of proof by contradiction . 26 8 Contrapositive 29 8.1 Method . 29 8.2 Hard parts? . 29 8.3 Examples . 29 9 Tips 31 9.1 What common mistakes do students make when trying to present the proofs? . 31 9.2 What are the reasons for mistakes? . 32 9.3 Advice to students for writing good proofs . 32 9.4 Friendly reminder . 32 c University of Birmingham 2014 10 Sets 34 10.1 Basics . 34 10.2 Subsets and power sets . 34 10.3 Cardinality and equality .
    [Show full text]
  • MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION SEQUENCES and SERIES
    MISS MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION SEQUENCES and SERIES John J O'Connor 2009/10 Contents This booklet contains eleven lectures on the topics: Mathematical Induction 2 Sequences 9 Series 13 Power Series 22 Taylor Series 24 Summary 29 Mathematician's pictures 30 Exercises on these topics are on the following pages: Mathematical Induction 8 Sequences 13 Series 21 Power Series 24 Taylor Series 28 Solutions to the exercises in this booklet are available at the Web-site: www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/~john/MISS_solns/ 1 Mathematical induction This is a method of "pulling oneself up by one's bootstraps" and is regarded with suspicion by non-mathematicians. Example Suppose we want to sum an Arithmetic Progression: 1+ 2 + 3 +...+ n = 1 n(n +1). 2 Engineers' induction € Check it for (say) the first few values and then for one larger value — if it works for those it's bound to be OK. Mathematicians are scornful of an argument like this — though notice that if it fails for some value there is no point in going any further. Doing it more carefully: We define a sequence of "propositions" P(1), P(2), ... where P(n) is "1+ 2 + 3 +...+ n = 1 n(n +1)" 2 First we'll prove P(1); this is called "anchoring the induction". Then we will prove that if P(k) is true for some value of k, then so is P(k + 1) ; this is€ c alled "the inductive step". Proof of the method If P(1) is OK, then we can use this to deduce that P(2) is true and then use this to show that P(3) is true and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Logicism, Interpretability, and Knowledge of Arithmetic
    ZU064-05-FPR RSL-logicism-final 1 December 2013 21:42 The Review of Symbolic Logic Volume 0, Number 0, Month 2013 Logicism, Interpretability, and Knowledge of Arithmetic Sean Walsh Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science, University of California, Irvine Abstract. A crucial part of the contemporary interest in logicism in the philosophy of mathematics resides in its idea that arithmetical knowledge may be based on logical knowledge. Here an implementation of this idea is considered that holds that knowledge of arithmetical principles may be based on two things: (i) knowledge of logical principles and (ii) knowledge that the arithmetical principles are representable in the logical principles. The notions of representation considered here are related to theory-based and structure- based notions of representation from contemporary mathematical logic. It is argued that the theory-based versions of such logicism are either too liberal (the plethora problem) or are committed to intuitively incorrect closure conditions (the consistency problem). Structure-based versions must on the other hand respond to a charge of begging the question (the circularity problem) or explain how one may have a knowledge of structure in advance of a knowledge of axioms (the signature problem). This discussion is significant because it gives us a better idea of what a notion of representation must look like if it is to aid in realizing some of the traditional epistemic aims of logicism in the philosophy of mathematics. Received February 2013 Acknowledgements: This is material coming out of my dissertation, and I would thus like to thank my advisors, Dr. Michael Detlefsen and Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Proofs by Mathematical Induction Are Generally Not Explanatory MARC LANGE
    Why proofs by mathematical induction are generally not explanatory MARC LANGE Philosophers who regard some mathematical proofs as explaining why the- orems hold, and others as merely proving that they do hold, disagree sharply about the explanatory value of proofs by mathematical induction. I offer an argument that aims to resolve this conflict of intuitions without making any controversial presuppositions about what mathematical explanations would be. 1. The problem Proposed accounts of scientific explanation have long been tested against certain canonical examples. Various arguments are paradigmatically expla- natory, such as Newton’s explanations of Kepler’s laws and the tides, Darwin’s explanations of various biogeographical and anatomical facts, Wegener’s explanation of the correspondence between the South American and African coastlines, and Einstein’s explanation of the equality of inertial and gravitational mass. Any promising comprehensive theory of scientific explanation must deem these arguments to be genuinely explanatory. By the same token, there is widespread agreement that various other arguments are not explanatory – examples so standard that I need only give their famil- iar monikers: the flagpole, the eclipse, the barometer, the hexed salt and so forth. Although there are some controversial cases, of course (such as ‘expla- nations’ of the dormitive-virtue variety), philosophers who defend rival accounts of scientific explanation nevertheless agree to a large extent on the phenomena that they are trying to save. Alas, the same cannot be said when it comes to mathematical explanation. Philosophers disagree sharply about which proofs of a given theorem explain why that theorem holds and which merely prove that it holds.1 This kind of disagreement makes it difficult to test proposed accounts of mathematical explanation without making controversial presuppositions about the phe- nomena to be saved.
    [Show full text]
  • Proofs by Induction Maths Delivers! Proofs by Induction
    1 Maths delivers! 2 3 4 5 6 12 11 7 10 8 9 A guide for teachers – Years 11 and 12 Proofs by induction Maths delivers! Proofs by induction Professor Brian A. Davey, La Trobe University Editor: Dr Jane Pitkethly, La Trobe University Illustrations and web design: Catherine Tan, Michael Shaw For teachers of Secondary Mathematics These notes are based in part on lecture notes and printed notes prepared by the author for use in teaching mathematical induction to first-year students at Latrobe University. © The University of Melbourne on behalf of the Australian Mathematical Sciences Institute (AMSI), 2013 (except where otherwise indicated). This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 Unported License. 2011. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/ Australian Mathematical Sciences Institute Building 161 The University of Melbourne VIC 3010 Email: [email protected] Website: www.amsi.org.au The principle of mathematical induction ........................ 4 A typical proof by induction ................................ 6 Two non-proofs by induction ................................ 7 Modified or strong induction ................................ 9 The Tower of Hanoi puzzle ................................. 10 A two-colour theorem .................................... 14 If you can’t prove it, prove something harder! ..................... 17 Answers to exercises ..................................... 20 maths delivers! Proofs by induction The principle of mathematical induction The idea of induction: falling dominoes There are two steps involved in knocking over a row of dominoes. Step 1. You have to knock over the first domino. Step 2. You have to be sure that when domino k falls, it knocks over domino k 1. Å These are the same as the steps in a proof by induction.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Induction Sept
    COMP 250 Fall 2016 9 - Mathematical induction Sept. 26, 2016 You will see many examples in this course and upcoming courses of algorithms for solving various problems. It many cases, it will be obvious that the algorithms do what you think. However, it many cases it will not be obvious, and one needs to argue very convincingly (or "prove") why the algorithms are correct. To do so, and to understand the arguments of others, we need to learn about how such proofs work. In particular, the next core topic in the course is recursion. We will look at a number of recursive algorithm and analyze how long they take to run. Recursion can be a bit confusing when one first learns about it. One way to understand recursion is to relate it to a proof technique in mathematics called mathematical induction. In a nutshell, you can use mathematical induction to prove that recursive algorithms are correct. Today I will introduce the basics of mathematical induction, and in the following few lectures we'll look at some recursive algorithms. Before I introduce induction, let me give an example of a convincing proof of a statement you have seen many times before:. n(n + 1) 1 + 2 + 3 + ··· + (n − 1) + n = : 2 One trick for showing this statement is true is to add up two copies of the left hand side, one forward and one backward: 1 + 2 + 3 + ··· + (n − 1) + n n + (n − 1) + :::: + 3 + 2 + 1: Then pair up terms: 1 + n; 2 + (n − 1); 3 + (n − 2); :::(n − 1) + 2; n + 1 and note that each pair sums to n + 1 and there are n pairs, which gives (n + 1) ∗ n.
    [Show full text]
  • Peano Axioms to Present a Rigorous Introduction to the Natural Numbers Would Take Us Too Far Afield
    Peano Axioms To present a rigorous introduction to the natural numbers would take us too far afield. We will however, give a short introduction to one axiomatic approach that yields a system that is quite like the numbers that we use daily to count and pay bills. We will consider a set, N,tobecalledthenatural numbers, that has one primitive operation that of successor which is a function from N to N. We will think of this function as being given by Sx x 1(this will be our definition of addition by 1). We will only assume the following rules. 1.IfSx Sy then x y (we say that S is one to one). 2. There exists exactly one element, denoted 1,inN that is not of the form Sx for any x N. 3.IfX N is such that 1 X and furthermore, if x X then Sx X, then X N. These rules comprise the Peano Axioms for the natural numbers. Rule 3. is usually called the principle of mathematical induction As above, we write x 1 for Sx.We assert that the set of elements that are successors of successors consists of all elements of N except for 1 and S1 1 1. We will now prove this assertion. If z SSx then since 1 Su and S is one to one (rule 1.) z S1 and z 1.If z N 1,S1 then z Su by 2. and u 1 by 1. Thus u Sv by 2. Hence, z SSv. This small set of rules (axioms) allow for a very powerful system which seems to have all of the properties of our intuitive notion of natural numbers.
    [Show full text]