Group Selection

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Group Selection Group Selection A Gardner, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK © 2013 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. This article is a revision of the previous edition article by MJ Wade, volume 2, pp 894–899, © 2001, Elsevier Inc. Glossary individual’s character on her own fitness) and indirect ’ Adaptation The appearance of design in the living world, (impact of an individual s character on the fitness of her originally attributed to deities and now known to be due genetic relations) components. to natural selection. Levels of selection An approach to group selection Between-group selection The part of natural selection theory that defines group selection as that component that owes either to the impact of the group character upon of natural selection that owes to fitness differences individual fitness (contextual-analysis approach) or to the between groups. differential fitness of groups (levels-of-selection Natural selection The component of evolutionary change approach). in heritable characters that owes to fitness differences Contextual analysis An approach to group selection between individuals (within and between groups, and theory that defines group selection as that component of mediated by their own characters and those of their social natural selection ascribable to the impact of the group groups). character upon individual fitness. Superorganism The idea that a social group can be Group adaptation The appearance of design at the group considered an adapted organism in its own right, which is level, driven by between-group selection, that obtains only valid only in the absence of conflicts of interest within the when within-group selection is negligible. group. Inclusive fitness The quantity that individuals appear Within-group selection The part of natural selection that ’ designed to maximize as a consequence of the action of owes either to the impact of the individual s character natural selection. upon her own fitness (contextual-analysis approach) or to Kin selection theory A theory of social evolution that the differential fitness of individuals within groups partitions natural selection into its direct (impact of an (levels-of-selection approach). The Origin of Group Selection selection, which for many years was considered empirically dis- tinct from the kin selection hypothesis. Interestingly, Darwin As with many of the big ideas in evolutionary biology, the concept himself did not clearly distinguish the two ideas, pointing to of group selection has its origins in the writings of Charles Darwin. blood relationship between group mates as a key factor driving Darwin discussed problems of social evolution in The Origin of the individual’s incentive to act for the good of her group. Species, focusing upon the paradox presented by the sterile castes The idea of group selection has sometimes been attributed to of social insect colonies. Here, the problem is to explain how the the co-discoverer of natural selection, Alfred Russel Wallace. exquisite adaptations exhibited by these individuals (and, indeed, Indeed, Peter Bowler has argued that a striking difference between that are unique to them) could be molded by natural selection, Darwin’s and Wallace’s papers on natural selection, presented at given that these individuals do not produce offspring. His solution the meeting of the Linnean Society in 1858, is that the former was to notice that kin tend to share heritable characters in com- describes natural selection at the level of individuals, while the mon such that, for example, a cattle breeder who slaughters an latter describes natural selection at the level of groups or ‘vari- animal and finds that it has particularly good meat can select for eties’. However, Michael Bulmer has pointed out that Wallace’s this character by preferentially breeding from the close relatives of notion of a variety simply corresponds to a type – such as a the slaughtered individual. Hence, sterile workers can evolve adap- white-flowering variety within a polymorphic plant species – tations, provided these improve the fitness of their fertile family and that Wallace’s conception of the theory of natural selection members. This is the theory of kin selection, which was more fully is not substantively different from Darwin’sinthisrespect. elaborated a century later by W. D. Hamilton. Certainly, the idea that selection at the group level might counter In the Descent of Man, Darwin took an alternative approach to and even overpower selection within groups is due to Darwin. understanding social traits. He noted that those human beha- viors considered moral typically place the individual at a fitness disadvantage relative to her social partners, but benefit the social The Modern Theory of Group Selection group as a whole. Darwin suggested that these behaviors could have been driven by natural selection acting at the group level. Today, we – like Darwin – understand that the kin selection Groups of ancestral humans would have come into conflict over and group selection approaches to social evolution are exactly limiting resources, and Darwin suggested that the resulting equivalent. Both describe the same evolutionary process, that selection for the most cooperative groups would often have is, natural selection, but split up its action in somewhat differ- overpowered the selection operating against such cooperation ent ways. The kin selection approach splits natural selection within groups. This was the launch of the theory of group into the direct effect of a heritable character on the individual’s 362 Brenner’s Encyclopedia of Genetics, 2nd Edition, Volume 3 doi:10.1016/B978-0-12-374984-0.00663-X Group Selection 363 own reproductive success and the indirect effect of the character has been devised that partitions Price’sequationinaslightly on the reproductive success of the individual’s genetic relatives. different way. This is the contextual-analysis approach, and it The group selection approach instead splits natural selection splits up eqn [1] as follows: into its within-group and between-group components. ÀÁÀÁÀÁÀÁ Δ ðÞ¼β ; j ; þ β ; j ; Irrespective of how one chooses to split up the components NSEg vij gij gi cov gij gij vij gi gij cov gi gij of natural selection, they will always add to give the same sum, ½3 and so kin selection and group selection theories yield exactly where β terms are partial regression coefficients obtained by the same predictions about social evolution. fitting the linear multiregression model E(v |g and g )=E(v )+ However, there is some disagreement as to exactly how the ij ij i ij β(v ,g |g )(g – E(g )) + β(v ,g |g )(g – E(g )) + ε to the popula- group selection split should be made. The first – and most ij ij i ij ij ij i ij i ij ij tion (g ,g,v ) data by means of least squares (i.e., minimizing popular – approach to the theory of group selection is that ij i ij the quantity E(ε 2)). The β(v ,g |g ) term describes the effect of pioneered by George Price and subsequently developed by ij ij ij i the individual’s character value on her own fitness, holding Hamilton, which has been termed the ‘levels-of-selection’ fixed any effect of her group’s average character value, and so approach. This takes Price’s general equation of natural selec- the quantity β(vij,gij|gi)cov(gij, gij) has been interpreted as a form tion as a starting point: of within-group selection. Conversely, the β(vij,gi|gij) term ’ ΔNSEðgÞ¼covðv; gÞ½1 describes the effect of the group s average character value on the individual’s fitness, holding fixed any effect of her own Price’s equation expresses the change in the average value of character value, and so the quantity β(vij,gi|gij)cov(gi,gij) has any heritable character between consecutive generations, been interpreted as a form of between-group selection. under the action of natural selection, as being equal to the The contextual-analysis approach avoids the problem of covariance of relative fitness v and character value g over all diagnosing group selection for nonsocial traits. However, it the individuals in the population. Assigning individuals to does diagnose the action of group selection even in scenarios groups (for simplicity, I assume that there is an equal number where there are no fitness differences between groups. For exam- of individuals in every group), and assigning every group a ple, if density-dependent regulation maintains all groups at a unique index i ∈ I and every individual within each group a fixed size, then individuals with defective livers may achieve high unique index j ∈ J, eqn [1] can be partitioned into the fitness, provided that their group mates also have defective livers, between-group and average within-group covariance between but will achieve lower fitness if their group mates primarily have relative fitness and character value: properly functioning livers. Contextual analysis suggests that group selection is acting here and, moreover, that it favors Δ EðgÞ¼cov ðv ; g ÞþE ðcov ðv ; g ÞÞ ½2 NS I i i I J ij ij defective livers, even though they bring no advantage to the where vi = EJ(vij) and gi = EJ(gij) are the average fitness and char- group as a whole. acter value, respectively, among the individuals belonging to As a consequence of these perceived failures of levels- the ith group. of-selection and contextual-analysis approaches to the theory of The first term on the right-hand side (RHS) of eqn [2] is the group selection, some authors - including David Wilson and covariance of group fitness and group character value, taken Edward Wilson - have suggested that group selection defies for- over all the groups in the population, and defines the action of mal analysis altogether. However, a more pragmatic outlook ‘between-group’ selection. The second term on the RHS of eqn recognizes that the alternative approaches address somewhat [2] is the average, taken over all groups in the population, of different problems, and in a potentially useful way.
Recommended publications
  • Cultural Group Selection Plays an Essential Role in Explaining Human Cooperation: a Sketch of the Evidence
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2016), Page 1 of 68 doi:10.1017/S0140525X1400106X, e30 Cultural group selection plays an essential role in explaining human cooperation: A sketch of the evidence Peter Richerson Emily K. Newton Department of Environmental Science and Policy, University of California– Department of Psychology, Dominican University of California, San Rafael, CA Davis, Davis, CA 95616 94901 [email protected] [email protected] http://emilyknewton.weebly.com/ www.des.ucdavis.edu/faculty/richerson/richerson.htm Nicole Naar Ryan Baldini Department of Anthropology, University of California–Davis, Graduate Group in Ecology, University of California–Davis, Davis, CA 95616 Davis, CA 95616 [email protected] https://sites.google.com/site/ryanbaldini/ [email protected] Adrian V. Bell Lesley Newson Department of Anthropology, University of Utah, Salt Lake City, UT 84112 Department of Environmental Science and Policy, University of California– [email protected] http://adrianbell.wordpress.com/ Davis, Davis, CA 95616 [email protected] [email protected] Kathryn Demps https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Lesley_Newson/ Department of Anthropology, Boise State University, Boise, ID 83725 [email protected] Cody Ross http://sspa.boisestate.edu/anthropology/faculty-and-staff/kathryn- Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, NM 87501 demps/ [email protected] http://scholar.google.com/citations?user=xSugEskAAAAJ Karl Frost Graduate Group in Ecology, University of California–Davis, Davis, CA 95616 Paul E. Smaldino [email protected] https://sites.google.com/site/karljosephfrost/ Department of Anthropology, University of California–Davis, Davis, CA 95616 [email protected] http://www.smaldino.com/ Vicken Hillis Department of Environmental Science and Policy, University of California– Timothy M.
    [Show full text]
  • A Group Selection Perspective on Economic Behavior, Institutions and Organizations Jeroen C.J.M
    A Group Selection Perspective on Economic Behavior, Institutions and Organizations Jeroen C.J.M. van den Bergh, John M. Gowdy To cite this version: Jeroen C.J.M. van den Bergh, John M. Gowdy. A Group Selection Perspective on Economic Behavior, Institutions and Organizations. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Elsevier, 2009, 72 (1), pp.1. 10.1016/j.jebo.2009.04.017. hal-00695532 HAL Id: hal-00695532 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00695532 Submitted on 9 May 2012 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Accepted Manuscript Title: A Group Selection Perspective on Economic Behavior, Institutions and Organizations Authors: Jeroen C.J.M. van den Bergh, John M. Gowdy PII: S0167-2681(09)00125-5 DOI: doi:10.1016/j.jebo.2009.04.017 Reference: JEBO 2384 To appear in: Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization Received date: 8-4-2008 Revised date: 30-4-2009 Accepted date: 30-4-2009 Please cite this article as: van den Bergh, J.C.J.M., Gowdy, J.M., A Group Selection Perspective on Economic Behavior, Institutions and Organizations, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization (2008), doi:10.1016/j.jebo.2009.04.017 This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication.
    [Show full text]
  • Persistent Misunderstandings of Inclusive Fitness and Kin Selection Park, Justin H
    University of Groningen Persistent misunderstandings of inclusive fitness and kin selection Park, Justin H. Published in: Evolutionary Psychology DOI: 10.1177/147470490700500414 IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 2007 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Park, J. H. (2007). Persistent misunderstandings of inclusive fitness and kin selection: Their ubiquitous appearance in social psychology textbooks. Evolutionary Psychology, 5(4), 860 - 873. https://doi.org/10.1177/147470490700500414 Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). The publication may also be distributed here under the terms of Article 25fa of the Dutch Copyright Act, indicated by the “Taverne” license. More information can be found on the University of Groningen website: https://www.rug.nl/library/open-access/self-archiving-pure/taverne- amendment. Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum.
    [Show full text]
  • Kin Selection, Group Selection, and the Varieties of Population Structure
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilSci Archive Kin Selection, Group Selection, and the Varieties of Population Structure Jonathan Birch Abstract: Various results show the ‘formal equivalence’ of kin and group selec- tionist methodologies, but this does not preclude there being a real and useful distinction between kin and group selection processes. I distinguish individual- and population-centred approaches to drawing such a distinction, and I proceed to develop the latter. On the account I advance, the differences between kin and group selection are differences of degree in the structural properties of popula- tions. A spatial metaphor (‘K-G space’) provides a useful framework for thinking about these differences: kin and group selection may be conceptualized as large, overlapping regions of K-G space. I then consider some implications of the ac- count, defend it from possible objections, and further argue that the structural features characteristic of both kin and group selection may recur at multiple levels of biological organization. 1 Introduction 2 2 Equivalence Results and Their Limitations 3 2.1 An example of an equivalence result . 3 2.2 Limitations . 6 3 Individual- and Population-Centred Approaches 8 4 Two Influences: Hamilton and Godfrey-Smith 11 5 K and G 14 5.1 K ..................................... 15 5.2 G ..................................... 16 5.3 K-G space . 18 6 The rb , 0 Requirement 20 1 7 Levels of Organization 23 8 The Key Substantive Questions 24 1 Introduction The relationship between kin selection and group (or multi-level) selection is a longstanding source of controversy in the social evolution literature.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Sociobiology: Inclusive Fitness and the Core Genome Herbert Gintis
    An Introduction to Sociobiology: Inclusive Fitness and the Core Genome Herbert Gintis June 29, 2013 The besetting danger is ...mistaking part of the truth for the whole...in every one of the leading controversies...both sides were in the right in what they affirmed, though wrong in what they denied John Stuart Mill, On Coleridge, 1867 A Mendelian populationhas a common gene pool, whichis itscollective or corporate genotype. Theodosius Dobzhansky, Cold Springs Harbor Symposium, 1953. The interaction between regulator and structural genes... [reinforces] the concept that the genotype of the individual is a whole. Ernst Mayr, Populations, Species and Evolution, 1970 Abstract This paper develops inclusive fitness theory with the aim of clarifying its appropriate place in sociobiological theory and specifying the associated principles that render it powerful. The paper introduces one new concept, that of the core genome. Treating the core genome as a unit of selection solves problems concerning levels of selection in evolution. 1 Summary Sociobiology is the study of biological interaction, both intragenomic, among loci in the genome, and intergenomic, among individuals in a reproductive popula- tion (Gardner et al. 2007). William Hamilton (1964) extended the theory of gene frequencies developed in the first half of the Twentieth century (Crow and I would like to thank Samuel Bowles, Eric Charnov, Steven Frank, Michael Ghiselin, Peter Godfrey-Smith, David Haig, David Queller, Laurent Lehmann, Samir Okasha, Peter Richerson, Joan Roughgarden, Elliot Sober, David Van Dyken, Mattijs van Veelen and Edward O. Wilson for advice in preparing this paper. 1 Kimura 1970, B¨urger 2000, Provine 2001) to deal with such behavior.
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of Extreme Cooperation Via Shared Dysphoric Experiences
    The Evolution of Extreme Cooperation via Shared Dysphoric Experiences Whitehouse, H., Jong, J., Buhrmester, M. D., Gomez, A., Bastian, B., Kavanagh, C. M., Newson, M., Matthews, M., Lanman, J. A., McKay, R., & Gavrilets, S. (2017). The Evolution of Extreme Cooperation via Shared Dysphoric Experiences. Nature Scientific Reports, 7, 1-10. [44292]. https://doi.org/10.1038/srep44292 Published in: Nature Scientific Reports Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Queen's University Belfast - Research Portal: Link to publication record in Queen's University Belfast Research Portal Publisher rights © The Author(s) 2017 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons license, unless indicated otherwise in the credit line; if the material is not included under the Creative Commons license, users will need to obtain permission from the license holder to reproduce the material. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Queen's University Belfast Research Portal is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The Research Portal is Queen's institutional repository that provides access to Queen's research output. Every effort has been made to ensure that content in the Research Portal does not infringe any person's rights, or applicable UK laws.
    [Show full text]
  • Hamilton's Model of Kin Selection*
    Heredity (1982), 49(2), 163—169 0018-067X/82/05140163$02.OO 1982. The Genetical Society of Great Britain ADDITIVEPOLYGENIC FORMULATION OF HAMILTON'S MODEL OF KIN SELECTION* KENICHI AOKI National Institute of Genetics, Mishima, Shizuoka -ken 411, Japan Received16.iii.82 SUMMARY Hamilton's condition for the evolution of altruism by kin selection is rederived on an additive polygenic model. The approach uses intraclass correlation. It is then shown that the mean inclusive fitness is non-decreasing. The differences between and the relative efficacy of kin and group selection are discussed. 1. INTRODUCTION HAMILTON (1964) generalized Fisher's (1930) and Haldane's (1955) seminal argument to show heuristically that altruism between same-gener- ation kin would evolve if the following approximate inequality were satisfied: br>c. (1) Here, r is the correlation between the additive genotypic values of the interacting kin as evaluated from the pedigree. In Hamilton's model of benefit dispensation, an altruist suffers a cost in fitness c while donating a total benefit b, which is distributed evenly among the recipients. A recipient experiences its share of the benefit as an increment to its fitness; the total benefit to a recipient is the sum of increments received from all sources. Inequality (1) was first proposed to hold in a random mating population with discrete non-overlapping generations (Hamilton, 1964), and then extended to accommodate inbreeding (Hamilton, 1971, 1972). For sym- metrical relationships, which we alone consider in this paper, r is equal to 2f/(1 +fo), where fo is the inbreeding coefficient, and fi is the coefficient of consanguinity of the interacting kin (Wright, 1922).
    [Show full text]
  • Coevolution: a Pattern of Reciprocal Adaptation, Caused by Two Species Evolving in Close Association
    Coevolution: a pattern of reciprocal adaptation, caused by two species evolving in close association. coevolution is a change in the genetic composition of one species (or group) in response to a genetic change in another. More generally, the idea of some reciprocal evolutionary change in interacting species is a requisite for coevolution – Host-parasite – Plant- herbivore – Predator-Prey – Mutualisms Parasites may evolve rapidly due to: Short generation times High fecundity Founder effects and drift High mutation rates Consider plants and insects: it is sometimes difficult to determine whether plants' secondary compounds arose for the purpose of preventing herbivores from eating plant tissue. Certain plants may have produced certain compounds as waste products and herbivores attacked those plants that they could digest. Parasites and hosts: when a parasite invades a host, it will successfully invade those hosts whose defence traits it can circumvent because of the abilities it carries at that time. Thus presence of a parasite on a host does not constitute evidence for coevolution. These criticisms are quite distinct from the opportunity for coevolution once a parasite has established itself on a host. The main point is that any old interaction, symbiosis, mutualism, etc. is not synonymous with coevolution. In one sense there has definitely been "evolution together" but whether this fits our strict definition of coevolution needs to be determined by careful 1) observation, 2) experimentation and 3) phylogenetic analysis The classic analogy is the coevolutionary arms race: a plant has chemical defenses, an insect evolves the biochemistry to detoxify these compounds, the plant in turn evolves new defenses that the insect in turn "needs" to further detoxify.
    [Show full text]
  • Group Selection, Kin Selection, Altruism and Cooperation: When Inclusive Fitness Is Right and When It Can Be Wrong Matthijs Van Veelen
    Group selection, kin selection, altruism and cooperation: When inclusive fitness is right and when it can be wrong Matthijs van Veelen To cite this version: Matthijs van Veelen. Group selection, kin selection, altruism and cooperation: When inclusive fitness is right and when it can be wrong. Journal of Theoretical Biology, Elsevier, 2009, 259 (3), pp.589. 10.1016/j.jtbi.2009.04.019. hal-00554605 HAL Id: hal-00554605 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00554605 Submitted on 11 Jan 2011 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Author’s Accepted Manuscript Group selection, kin selection, altruism and cooperation: When inclusive fitness is right and when it can be wrong Matthijs van Veelen PII: S0022-5193(09)00189-1 DOI: doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2009.04.019 Reference: YJTBI5543 www.elsevier.com/locate/yjtbi To appear in: Journal of Theoretical Biology Received date: 12 January 2009 Revised date: 19 March 2009 Accepted date: 21 April 2009 Cite this article as: Matthijs van Veelen, Group selection, kin selection, altruism and coop- eration: When inclusive fitness is right and when it can be wrong, Journal of Theoretical Biology, doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2009.04.019 This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication.
    [Show full text]
  • Group Selection As Behavioral Adaptation to Systematic Risk
    Group Selection as Behavioral Adaptation to Systematic Risk Ruixun Zhang1, Thomas J. Brennan2, Andrew W. Lo3,4* 1 MIT Department of Mathematics, Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States of America, 2 Northwestern University School of Law, Chicago, Illinois, United States of America, 3 MIT Sloan School of Management, CSAIL, and EECS, Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States of America, 4 AlphaSimplex Group, LLC, Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States of America Abstract Despite many compelling applications in economics, sociobiology, and evolutionary psychology, group selection is still one of the most hotly contested ideas in evolutionary biology. Here we propose a simple evolutionary model of behavior and show that what appears to be group selection may, in fact, simply be the consequence of natural selection occurring in stochastic environments with reproductive risks that are correlated across individuals. Those individuals with highly correlated risks will appear to form ‘‘groups’’, even if their actions are, in fact, totally autonomous, mindless, and, prior to selection, uniformly randomly distributed in the population. This framework implies that a separate theory of group selection is not strictly necessary to explain observed phenomena such as altruism and cooperation. At the same time, it shows that the notion of group selection does captures a unique aspect of evolution—selection with correlated reproductive risk–that may be sufficiently widespread to warrant a separate term for the phenomenon. Citation: Zhang R, Brennan TJ, Lo AW (2014) Group Selection as Behavioral Adaptation to Systematic Risk. PLoS ONE 9(10): e110848. doi:10.1371/journal.pone. 0110848 Editor: Claude Wicker-Thomas, CNRS, France Received July 15, 2014; Accepted September 25, 2014; Published October 29, 2014 Copyright: ß 2014 Zhang et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Group Selection and Kin Selection: Formally Equivalent Approaches
    Opinion Group selection and kin selection: formally equivalent approaches James A.R. Marshall Department of Computer Science/Kroto Research Institute, University of Sheffield, Sheffield, S3 7HQ, UK Inclusive fitness theory, summarised in Hamilton’s Historical roots rule, is a dominant explanation for the evolution of The roots of the theories of social evolution discussed here social behaviour. A parallel thread of evolutionary the- extend back into at least the mid-19th century. Over these ory holds that selection between groups is also a many years, concepts and terminology have shifted, even candidate explanation for social evolution. The mathe- when used by the same authors. This section summarises matical equivalence of these two approaches has long these roots, which are discussed at greater length else- been known. Several recent papers, however, have objected that inclusive fitness theory is unable to deal with strong selection or with non-additive fitness effects, and concluded that the group selection frame- Glossary work is more general, or even that the two are not Altruism: donation of aid to another individual or individuals, such that their equivalent after all. Yet, these same problems have lifetime individual fitness is increased while the lifetime individual fitness of already been identified and resolved in the literature. the donor is decreased (see ‘Benefit’ and ‘Cost’). Benefit: the lifetime individual fitness increment resulting from receipt of aid Here, I survey these contemporary objections, and (see ‘Altruism’). examine them in the light of current understanding Cost: the lifetime individual fitness decrement resulting from donation of aid of inclusive fitness theory. (see ‘Altruism’).
    [Show full text]
  • Shifting the Natural Selection Metaphor to the Group Level
    Behavior and Philosophy, 28, 83-101 (2000). © 2000 Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies SHIFTING THE NATURAL SELECTION METAPHOR TO THE GROUP LEVEL Nicholas S. Thompson Clark University ABSTRACT: Group selection is said to occur when the traits of groups that systematically out-reproduce competing groups eventually come to characterize the species. Evolutionists have long disputed over the degree to which group selection is effective—that is, over the degree to which social group characteristics can be attributed to selection on these characteristics. The intractability of this controversy arises from three ambiguities in the natural selection metaphor that manifest themselves when that metaphor is shifted to the group level: (1) uncertainty about what constitutes the analogue for “flock” in the group level metaphor; (2) uncertainty about how to identify the group “parents” of offspring groups; and (3) uncertainty about what constitutes a group trait for the purposes of group selection. When group selection is specified as a theory about the evolution of emergent properties of groups through differential group productivity mediated by quantitative inheritance of group traits, these ambiguities disappear. Individual selection is said to occur when the heritable traits of individuals that out-reproduce their competitors eventually come to characterize the species. Individual selection would always seem to be the natural explanation for selfish traits of humans—traits like sexual aggressiveness or food hoarding that advance the individual’s interests against those of the individual’s group. It would seem to oppose the evolution of any altruistic trait—that is, any trait of individuals that systematically favor their competitors. In particular, it would seem to oppose the evolution of altruism directed toward groups—that is, any trait, costly to an individual, that favors the group of which the individual is part.
    [Show full text]