Hannah Ginsborg on Aesthetic Judgement Paul Guyer Downloaded from by Guest on 28 September 2021

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hannah Ginsborg on Aesthetic Judgement Paul Guyer Downloaded from by Guest on 28 September 2021 20May201620May20163June2016 Symposium Paper One Act or Two? Hannah Ginsborg on Aesthetic Judgement Paul Guyer Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/bjaesthetics/article/57/4/407/3811073 by guest on 28 September 2021 Hannah Ginsborg rejects my ‘two-acts’ interpretation of Kant’s conception of aesthetic judgement as untrue to Kant’s text and as philosophically problematic, especially because it entails that every object must be experienced as beautiful. I reject her criticisms, and argue that it is her own ‘one- act’ interpretation that is liable to these criticisms. But I also suggest that her emphasis on Kant’s ‘transcendental explanation’ of pleasure as a self-maintaining mental state suggests an alternative to the common view that pleasure is a distinctive feeling, even if Ginsborg herself does not draw that conclusion. Hannah Ginsborg has been tenaciously defending a controversial interpretation of Kant’s conception of aesthetic judgement since her 1989 Harvard dissertation on The Role of Taste in Kant’s Theory of Cognition.1 As the title of her dissertation suggests, her interpretation of Kant’s conception of aesthetic judgement has been part of a larger interpretation, not of Kant’s aesthetics, but of Kant’s epistemology, where this means primarily Kant’s theory of empirical concepts and empirical knowledge, such as that is, rather than his argument for the existence of synthetic a priori cognition. In the last decade she has been developing a general theory of empirical concepts on the basis of her approach to Kant, an ambi- tion which she has said was the original reason for her interest in Kant. The subtitle of her collection, ‘Essays on Kant’s Critique of Judgement,’ suggests that this volume collects only some of her papers specifically on Kant, but that is a little misleading. The volume is divided into three parts, ‘Aesthetics’, ‘Cognition’, and ‘Teleology’, and the papers in the first and third parts do chiefly concern topics in Kant’s third Critique, namely his concep- October tion of aesthetic judgement in Part I and his qualified revival of a teleological approach to conceiving and explaining organisms and the system of nature as a whole in Part III. The papers in Part II, however, are more focused on her general approach to empirical concepts, although the first of these papers, ‘Reflective Judgement and Taste’ (originally published in 1990, thus the earliest paper in the collection) is still focused primarily on the case of aesthetic judgement, and would better have been included in Part I. Ginsborg has consistently presented her interpretation of Kant’s model of aesthetic judgement as an alternative to the interpretation that I offered in Kant and the Claims of Taste2 as well as to that proposed by Donald Crawford in his Kant’s Aesthetic Theory 1 Hannah Ginsborg, The Role of Taste in Kant’s Theory of Cognition (New York: Garland Publishing, 1990). 2 Paul Guyer, Kant and the Claims of Taste (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1979); See also the second edition which has a foreword on subsequent literature and an additional chapter on ‘Kant’s Conception of Fine Art’ (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997). British Journal of Aesthetics Vol. 57 | Number 4 | October 2017 | pp. 407–419 DOI:10.1093/aesthj/ayw050 © British Society of Aesthetics 2017. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the British Society of Aesthetics. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected] 408 | PAUL GUYER (1974)3 (which appeared after I had completed my dissertation in 1973 but before I re- wrote it as the 1979 book). With the exception of one paper, ‘The Harmony of the Faculties Revisited’, most of my further work on Kant’s third critique has concerned topics in Kant’s aesthetics more broadly construed, such as his theory of adherent beauty, fine art, genius, and the sublime, as well as his place in the larger history of aesthetics, which Ginsborg does not address, as well as Kant’s teleology, which she does, but where I am not as much of a target for her as I am in the case of aesthetic Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/bjaesthetics/article/57/4/407/3811073 by guest on 28 September 2021 judgement.4 So it would seem natural for me to take this occasion to respond to her critique of, and alternative to, my interpretation of Kant’s basic conception of aes- thetic judgement. I will first briefly restate the basic idea of my interpretation and, next, discuss Ginsborg’s chief objections to it and explain how her own approach is intended to resolve those objections. Then I will raise what might be considered an internal objection to her theory and finally argue that my model of Kant offers a more plausible account of the phenomenology of aesthetic experience than does Ginsborg’s. But before I turn to the details, I might suggest that the difference between her trans- lation of the title of Kant’s work, Kritik der Urteilskraft, and mine already reflects key differences in our interpretation. I chose to translate Kant’s title as Critique of the Power of Judgement because I believed that ‘power of judgement’ is a literal translation of Kant’s term Urteilskraft, but also because I thought Kant meant that title to indicate that his cri- tique concerns different domains of the faculty of judgement, namely the aesthetic use of judgement and its teleological judgement, and further because in the case of aesthetic judgement he distinguishes between Beurteilung and Urteil, the activity of judging and the product of such activity, namely a judgement, the assertion of a proposition or the prop- osition asserted.5 Translating Kant’s title term as the ‘power of judgement’ rather than conflating Urteilskraft with Urteil preserves room for the distinctions that Kant makes, especially that between Beurteilung and Urteil, or at least does not prejudice the reader of the translation against that distinction from the outset. But the gist of Ginsborg’s approach to Kant’s conception of aesthetic judgement is precisely to collapse the distinc- tion between Beurteilung and Urteil, between the activity or activities that may lead up to the judgement of taste, the judgement that an object is beautiful, and that judgement itself or even its assertion, and her unexplained retention of the traditional translation of Kant’s title may be reflective of her approach. But it also suggests that Ginsborg’s approach may not have quite as much textual support as she likes to claim. 3 Donald W. Crawford, Kant’s Aesthetic Theory (Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 1974). 4 This appears both in Paul Guyer, Values of Beauty: Historical Essays in Aesthetics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) and Rebecca Kukla, Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant’s Critical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), in which Ginsborg’s paper ‘Thinking the Particular as Contained Under the Universal’, essay 7 of Hannah Ginsborg, The Normativity of Nature: Essays on Kant’s Critique of Judgement (Oxford: OUP, 2015) also first appeared. 5 Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, ed. Paul Guyer, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000). In the original, Kant used Fettdruck or larger, heavier type to indicate emphasis, and in the Cambridge edition we use bold type to indicate that; this leaves me free to use italics to indicate my own emphasis of words in quotations from Kant (which, however, will also be explicitly noted). For the original text see Kants gesammelte Schriften, ed. Royal Academy of Sciences, subsequently German, trans. Berlin-Brandenburg Academy of Sciences, vol. 29 (Berlin: Georg Reimer, subsequently Walter de Gruyter, 1900–). When referencing my translation I use the format (Akademie Volume: Page), in accordance with the original work. ONE ACT OR TWO? HANNAH GINSBORG ON AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT | 409 Having said all that, I will begin by re-stating my interpretation of Kant’s core notion of aesthetic judgement. In Section 9 of the Critique of the Aesthetic Power of Judgement, which he labels the ‘key to the critique of taste’, Kant poses the question ‘whether in the judgement of taste [Geschmacksurteile] the feeling of judgement precedes the judging [Beurteilung] of the object or the latter precedes the former?’ and then answers that: If the pleasure in the given object came first, and only its universal communicability Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/bjaesthetics/article/57/4/407/3811073 by guest on 28 September 2021 were to be attributed to the representation of the object, then such a procedure would be self-contradictory. For such a pleasure would be none other than mere agreeable- ness in sensation, and hence by its very nature could have only private validity.6 My claim is that this answer is correct if, but only if, Kant is talking about the pleasure that one takes in a beautiful object as preceding the judgement of taste (Geschmacksurteil), not the judging (Beurteilung) of the object. In order to be properly judged to be universally valid or communicable rather than merely privately valid, which is what is asserted of pleasure in a given object by the judgement ‘This is beautiful’ or the judgement of taste, the pleasure must be due to activity of the cognitive powers of imagination and under- standing (in the simple case that Kant calls ‘pure’ or ‘free’ beauty; the response to art will involve reason as well) leading to the harmonious state that he calls the ‘free play’ of those faculties rather than to mere sensory stimulation (the ‘agreeable’). Kant supposes that the latter is variable from individual to individual, but the former response can be expected to be invariable among different individuals, at least if they are all in optimal conditions, because this response involves the fundamental faculties of cognition itself and these, Kant further supposes, can be expected to work the same way in all normal human beings.
Recommended publications
  • Kant and the Problem of Experience Hannah Ginsborg
    Kant and the Problem of Experience Hannah Ginsborg (Version for Phil. Topics: September 16, 2006.) As most of its readers are aware, the Critique of Pure Reason is primarily concerned not with empirical, but with a priori knowledge. For the most part, the Kant of the first Critique tends to assume that experience, and the knowledge that is based on it, is unproblematic. The problem with which he is concerned is that of how we can be capable of substantive knowledge independently of experience. At the same time, however, the notion of experience plays a crucial role in the central arguments of the Critique. For, again as most readers of the Critique know, Kant aims to show how we can have synthetic a priori knowledge by showing that the categories, or pure concepts of the understanding, are conditions of the possibility of experience. This means that, whether or not Kant is concerned with the notion of experience for its own sake, his account of a priori knowledge carries with it at least some commitments regarding the character of experience. If the account of a priori knowledge is to be successful, then experience has to be the kind of thing for which the categories can, in principle, serve as conditions of posibility. More specifically, experience must involve not only the senses, but also thought or understanding, for otherwise the claim that it presupposes a certain specific set of concepts is simply unintelligible. And indeed at least some parts of the Critique, in particular the so-called subjective deduction in the first edition, and the briefer passages which correspond to it in the second edition, seem to be intended to show how this requirement is met.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Beauty, Art and Testimony: Subjectivity and Objectivity in Aesthetics Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/0gd4w6z8 Author Klempner, Erica Diane Publication Date 2018 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Beauty, Art and Testimony: Subjectivity and Objectivity in Aesthetics by Erica Diane Klempner A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Hannah Ginsborg, Co-chair Professor Barry Stroud, Co-chair Professor John MacFarlane Professor Line Mikkelsen Spring 2018 Copyright © 2018 by Erica Diane Klempner All rights reserved Abstract Beauty, Art and Testimony: Subjectivity and Objectivity in Aesthetics by Erica Diane Klempner Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professor Hannah Ginsborg and Professor Barry Stroud, Co-chairs We acquire beliefs on the basis of what others tell us all the time. If you tell me that your house is painted red, chances are that I will simply believe you without question; and if someone asks me what color your house is, I will simply tell her that it is red. Yet we do not seem to accept others’ testimony about beauty and art in the same way. If you tell me that the Taj Mahal is beautiful, or that Middlemarch is a great novel, it would be strange for me simply to adopt your view, even if I have a lot of confidence in your judgment. In order for me to be in a position to believe or to claim that the Taj Mahal is beautiful, or that Middlemarch is a great novel, I must experience these things myself—by going to Agra, or by reading the book.
    [Show full text]
  • July 2015 Issue of the Reasoner
    Volume 9, Number 7 July 2015 thereasoner.org ISSN 1757-0522 been at the forefront of a recent surge of interest in Kant’s Cri- Contents tique of Judgment, and in the literature she was one of the first to promote a unified reading of the book’s unusual combination Editorial 55 of philosophy of biology and aesthetics. Her book The Normativity of Nature, a collection of essays Features 55 on Kant’s Critique of Judgment, appeared in print earlier this year, and I take our meeting as an opportunity to ask her about News 57 her reading and what lessons she thinks we can take from Kant. What’s Hot in . 61 Angela Breitenbach University of Cambridge Events 62 Courses and Programmes 63 Features Jobs and Studentships 64 Interview with Hannah Ginsborg Angela Breitenbach: The Normativity of Nature is a collection of essays you published over the last twenty years or so. Can Editorial you tell us a bit about the main themes of the collection? It’s a great pleasure to edit this issue of The Reasoner and I am Hannah Ginsborg: One major theme underlying all the es- grateful to Hannah Ginsborg for agreeing to meet with me for says is the normativity associated with the faculty of judgment, an interview in Berlin where which I have labelled ‘primitive normativity’. Another is the she currently spends her sab- unity of the Critique of Judgment, in particular the relevance of batical leave. Kant’s aesthetic theory to the discussion of the purposiveness Hannah Ginsborg is Pro- of nature and to his account of organisms.
    [Show full text]
  • Rule-Following, Enculturation, and Normative Identity
    University of Central Florida STARS Honors Undergraduate Theses UCF Theses and Dissertations 2021 Rule-Following, Enculturation, and Normative Identity Nicholas Odom University of Central Florida Part of the Philosophy Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the UCF Theses and Dissertations at STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Undergraduate Theses by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Recommended Citation Odom, Nicholas, "Rule-Following, Enculturation, and Normative Identity" (2021). Honors Undergraduate Theses. 917. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses/917 RULE-FOLLOWING, ENCULTURATION, AND NORMATIVE IDENTITY by NICHOLAS JOHN ODOM A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Honors in the Major Program in Philosophy in the College of Arts and Humanities and in the Burnett Honors College at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Spring Term 2021 Thesis Chair: Derek Green ABSTRACT Rule-following has been a controversial issue in professional philosophical literature since Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Many authors have developed accounts of rule-following along different lines, including those that naturalistically reduce rule-following to non-normative phenomena and those that take rule-following to be an irreducible aspect of cognition and agency. Hannah Ginsborg, a prominent contributor to rule-following literature, has developed a partially reductive account of rule-following, combining features of both reductionist and nonreductionist accounts. But naturalizing or internalistic theories of rule- following, or even Ginsborg’s partial reduction of rule-following, ignore important facets of what it is to follow a rule, particularly its social aspect.
    [Show full text]
  • Analytic Kantianism
    Philosophical Topics VOLUME 34, NUMBERS 1 & 2 SPRING AND FALL 2006 ANALYTIC KANTIANISM Contents Kantian Lessons about Mind, Meaning, and Rationality 1 Robert Brandom Meaning and Aesthetic Judgment in Kant 21 Eli Friedlander Carnap and Quine: Twentieth-Century Echoes of Kant and Hume 35 Michael Friedman Kant and the Problem of Experience 59 Hannah Ginsborg Kant on Beauty and the Normative Force of Feeling 107 Arata Hamawaki Spontaneity and Receptivity in Kant’s Theory of Knowledge 145 Andrea Kern Logicist Responses to Kant: (Early) Frege and (Early) Russell 163 Michael Kremer Kant’s Spontaneity Thesis 189 Thomas Land Prolegomena to a Proper Treatment of Mathematics in the Critique of Pure Reason 221 Thomas Lockhart Self-Consciousness and Consciousness of One’s Own Body: Variations on a Kantian Theme 283 Béatrice Longuenesse Sensory Consciousness in Kant and Sellars 311 John McDowell The Bounds of Sense 327 A. W. Moore Logical Form as a Relation to the Object 345 Sebastian Rödl Kant on the Nature of Logical Laws 371 Clinton Tolley PHILOSOPHICAL TOPICS VOL. 34, NOS. 1 & 2, SPRING AND FALL 2006 Kantian Lessons about Mind, Meaning, and Rationality Robert Brandom University of Pittsburgh Kant revolutionized our thinking about what it is to have a mind. Some of what seem to me to be among the most important lessons he taught us are often not yet sufficiently appreciated, however. I think this is partly because they are often not themes that Kant himself explicitly emphasized. To appreciate these ideas, one must look primarily at what he does, rather than at what he says about what he is doing.
    [Show full text]
  • THESIS on the NORMATIVITY of SEMANTIC NORMS and INTENTIONS Submitted by Jonathan Keyzer Department of Philosophy in Partial Fulf
    THESIS ON THE NORMATIVITY OF SEMANTIC NORMS AND INTENTIONS Submitted by Jonathan Keyzer Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University Fort Collins, Colorado Summer 2013 Master’s Committee: Advisor: Michael Losonsky Jeff Kasser Brad MacDonald Copyright by Jonathan Hugh Fulton Keyzer 2013 All Rights Reserved ABSTRACT ON THE NORMATIVITY OF SEMANTIC NORMS AND INTENTIONS This thesis clarifies the assumption that meaning is normative and defends this assumption from recent criticism by Anandi Hattiangadi and Akeel Bilgrami. Against Hattiangadi, I argue that the paradigmatic examples of moral and semantic obligations are strictly-speaking more like ‘limit’ hypotheticals in that having an obligation is contingent on some conditions, but these conditions are quite different than that those of the typical examples of means-end hypotheticals. I argue that the conditions relevant to limit hypotheticals are widely- satisfied by constitutive facts about beings with certain rational and linguistic competence like us. The ‘limitation’ is that being this kind of thing isn’t something one chooses, but is a constitutive for what one is. Against Bilgrami, I argue that a meaning intention is a normative state of commitment. Having a meaning intention means that one is prepared to speak and being prepared to speak is something one must live up to by having and maintaining a plan. I argue that part of this plan is to make some minimal effort to be interpretable to others. ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am indebted to Michael Losonsky for his patience and invaluable comments. I owe the central insights of this thesis to him, for recognizing them as insights and for encouraging me to develop them.
    [Show full text]
  • Leaps in the Dark: Epistemological Skepticism in Kripke's Wittgenstein
    From G. Anthony Bruno and A.C. Rutherford (eds.), Skepticism: historical and contemporary inquiries (Oxford and New York: Routledge, 2018) First published 2018 Contents by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2018 selection and editorial matter, G. Anthony Bruno and A.C. Rutherford; individual chapters, the contributors The right of G. Anthony Bruno and A.C. Rutherford to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Notes on contributors vii All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, Acknowledgments XI or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Introduction 1 Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks G. ANTHO:--.:Y BRUNO AND A.C. RUTHERFORD or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data PART! A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Forms of skepticism 5 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Bruno, G. Anthony, editor. Title: Skepticism: historical and contemporary inquiries/ 1 Homeric contributions to skepticism 7 edited by G. Anthony Bruno and A.C.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein on Going On
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy (2020), 50: 1, 1–17 doi:10.1017/can.2019.48 DISTINGUISHED LECTURE Wittgenstein on Going On Hannah Ginsborg Department of Philosophy, University of California, Berkeley Email: [email protected] 1. Introduction In a famous passage from the Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein describes a pupil who has been learning to write out various sequences of numbers in response to orders such as “+1” (for the natural numbers) and “+2” (for the series 0, 2, 4, 6, 8…). He has shown himself competent for numbers up to 1000, but when we have him continue the “+2” sequence beyond 1000, he writes the numerals 1004, 1008, 1012. As Wittgenstein describes the case: We say to him, “Look what you’re doing!”—He doesn’t understand us. We say “You should have added two; look how you began the series!”—He answers: “Yes! Isn’t it right? I thought that’s how I should [sollen] do it. — Or suppose he were to say, pointing to the series, “But I went on in the same way!” (PI §185)1 The passage continues: — It would now be no use to us to say “But don’t you see…?”—and repeat for him the old explanations and examples. — In such a case, we might perhaps say: this person naturally understands our order, once given our explanations, as we would understand the order “Add 2 up to 1000, 4 up to 2000, 6 up to 3000, and so on.” (ibid.) This example of the aberrant pupil has generated a lot of discussion. It is clear that Wittgenstein intends to use it to say something about the phenomenon of rule-following, but it is not at all clear what that is.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology Without History Is Blind
    Erkenn (2011) 75:505–524 DOI 10.1007/s10670-011-9334-7 Epistemology Without History is Blind Philip Kitcher Received: 27 September 2011 / Accepted: 27 September 2011 / Published online: 14 October 2011 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Abstract In the spirit of James and Dewey, I ask what one might want from a theory of knowledge. Much Anglophone epistemology is centered on questions that were once highly pertinent, but are no longer central to broader human and scientific concerns. The first sense in which epistemology without history is blind lies in the tendency of philosophers to ignore the history of philosophical problems. A second sense consists in the perennial attraction of approaches to knowledge that divorce knowing subjects from their societies and from the tradition of socially assembling a body of transmitted knowledge. When epistemology fails to use the history of inquiry as a laboratory in which methodological claims can be tested, there is a third way in which it becomes blind. Finally, lack of attention to the growth of knowledge in various domains leaves us with puzzles about the character of the knowledge we have. I illustrate this last theme by showing how reflections on the history of mathematics can expand our options for understanding mathematical knowledge. 1 Scrutinizing the Traditional Agenda of Epistemology In a famous (possibly the most famous) passage in Pragmatism, William James declares his commitment to the ‘‘pragmatic principle of Peirce’’: Many thanks to Uljana Feest and Thomas Sturm for conceiving the conference at which this essay was originally presented, and for inviting me to take part in it.
    [Show full text]
  • 82 Wissenschaftskolleg Zu Berlin Jahrbuch 2010/2011 the View
    The VieW from Inside Hannah Ginsborg Hannah Ginsborg is Professor of Philosophy at the university of California, Berkeley, where she has been teaching since 1988. She grew up in edinburgh, Scotland, and received a B.A. in Philosophy and Modern Languages (French) from Oxford university (1980) and a Ph.D. in Philosophy from Harvard university (1989). Much of her work has been concerned with Kant, in particular Kant’s Critique of Judgment, but she has recently been working in a number of areas in contemporary philosophy including philosophy of mind, theory of knowledge, philosophy of language and philosophy of biology. She also has an interest in aesthetics, in particular philosophy of music. – Address: Department of Philosophy, university of California, Berkeley, 314 Moses Hall 2390, Berkeley, CA 94720-2390, uSA. e-mail: [email protected] One of the philosophical ideas floating vaguely at the back of my mind when I arrived at Wiko had to do with the contrast between what we might call “inside” and “outside” perspectives on human language. think of an everyday word like “green” in english. If you are an english-speaker, the sounds made when you say “green” and the marks on paper produced when you write it are not just sounds and marks. From your point of view they have a special character that we usually take for granted but that, in certain frames of mind, can come to seem mysterious, almost magical. they have meaning. If you are an english-speaker and you look at the shapes made on the page by the ink when the word “green” – or any of the words on this page – are printed, you do not see them merely as shapes made by the ink on the paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty
    Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Moran, Richard. 2012. Kant, Proust, and the appeal of beauty. Critical Inquiry 38(2): 398-329. Published Version doi:10.1086/662744 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:8920788 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty Richard Moran 1 A familiar feature of the history of modern aesthetics is the cycle of suspicion and defensiveness connected with the idea of beauty, as though its very appearance suggested something exaggerated, something requir- ing deflation, which then provokes a certain polemical stance on the part of both its defenders and detractors. People who would not be tempted by a reductive account of other concepts (for example, of thought, or desire, or action), may still feel that beauty has to be shown to be illusory or explained as a mere guise of some other force or quality altogether in the end. One might, for instance, have reasons to be suspicious of pleasure itself, its role in culture, or the exaggerated claims for it, or one may have metaphysical scruples deriving from the idea that beauty can be no prop- erty of things in themselves but can only be a projection of our own sen- sibilities upon the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Hannah Ginsborg Department of Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-2390 Email: [email protected] Office Phone: 510 664 9077
    Hannah Ginsborg Department of Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-2390 Email: [email protected] Office phone: 510 664 9077 EMPLOYMENT Willis S and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 2018-present Chair, Department of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 2016- 2019 Professor of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 2006- present Associate Professor of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 1990-2006 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 1988-1990 Teaching Fellow, Harvard University, 1982-1984 and 1986-1987 EDUCATION Harvard University, 1980-1988 Ph.D. in Philosophy awarded 1989. Dissertation: “The Role of Taste in Kant’s Theory of Cognition,” supervised by Burton Dreben and John Rawls University of Oxford, 1976-1980 Major Scholar at Wadham College, reading Philosophy and Modern Languages (French). B.A. (First Class Honours) awarded 1980 Freie Universität, Berlin, Germany, 1985-1986 Study in philosophy Université de Paris-1, France , 1978-1979. Study in logic and philosophy ACADEMIC PRIZES, AWARDS AND FELLOWSHIPS Reimar Lüst Prize (awarded by the Humboldt Foundation and the Fritz Thyssen Foundation), 2019 Visiting Scholar, Humboldt University, Berlin, 2019-2020 U. C. Berkeley Humanities Research Fellowship, 2019-2020 Taylor Fellowship (University of Otago, New Zealand), July 2019 Visiting Research Professor, Ludwig-Maximilian University of Munich, Fall 2014 Fellow, Wissenschaftskolleg zu Berlin (Institute of Advanced Study, Berlin), 2010-2011 Senior Fellow, Townsend Center for the Humanities, U.C. Berkeley, 2008-2009 Visiting Scholar, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin, summers 2006, 2007 and 2008 Visting Scholar, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin, 2004-2005 American Council of Learned Societies Fellowship, 2004-2005 U.C.
    [Show full text]