Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Moran, Richard. 2012. Kant, Proust, and the appeal of beauty. Critical Inquiry 38(2): 398-329. Published Version doi:10.1086/662744 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:8920788 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty Richard Moran 1 A familiar feature of the history of modern aesthetics is the cycle of suspicion and defensiveness connected with the idea of beauty, as though its very appearance suggested something exaggerated, something requir- ing deflation, which then provokes a certain polemical stance on the part of both its defenders and detractors. People who would not be tempted by a reductive account of other concepts (for example, of thought, or desire, or action), may still feel that beauty has to be shown to be illusory or explained as a mere guise of some other force or quality altogether in the end. One might, for instance, have reasons to be suspicious of pleasure itself, its role in culture, or the exaggerated claims for it, or one may have metaphysical scruples deriving from the idea that beauty can be no prop- erty of things in themselves but can only be a projection of our own sen- sibilities upon the world. In different ways, then, there can seem to be a certain extravagance built into the notion of the beautiful itself, as though it were internal to its invocation that it claims more for itself than it can deliver on. Familiar as these thoughts are, however, their import is far from clear. The thought about projection, for instance, need not be any more skeptical than the parallel claims that are made about secondary qualities generally, the supervenience of which on our sensory dispositions is not I had the pleasure of presenting some of this material at a Warren Quinn Conference at the University of California, Los Angeles, where I benefitted from comments by Franklin Bruno; at a Sawyer Seminar at the University of Chicago, hosted by David Wellbery and James Conant; in a series of seminars at Johns Hopkins University hosted by Michael Fried; at a workshop on philosophy and literature and film organized by Susan Wolf at the University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill; and at the New York University Conference on Modern Philosophy and Aesthetic Judgment, organized by Beatrice Longuenesse, John Richardson, and Don Garett, where I had helpful comments from Rebecca Kukla. The paper benefitted from all these occasions, particularly from the hosts in question, as well as from audiences at the University of Illinois, University of Chicago, Stanford University, and the University of Illinois, Urbana- Champaign. For conversations either on those occasions or much earlier I am grateful to Stanley Cavell, Fred Neuhouser, Alexander Nehamas, Paul Guyer, Jonathan Lear, Lanier Anderson, Joshua Landy, Katalin Makkai, Meredith Williams, Robert Pippin, Wayne Martin, Brent Kalar, Michael Williams, Hannah Ginsborg, Katalin Makkai, Thomas Teufel, Melissa Merritt, Tim Scanlon, and David Sussman. At early stages of the project conversations with Martin Stone helped orient me in the topic, and toward the end of it conversations with Arata Hamawaki were crucial to giving shape to the story. The paper is dedicated to the memory of Mary Mothersill. Critical Inquiry 38 (Winter 2012) © 2012 by The University of Chicago. 0093-1896/12/3802-0010$10.00. All rights reserved. 298 Critical Inquiry / Winter 2012 299 usually taken to be equivalent to their being simply unreal or to be incom- patible with the idea that in calling the sky blue one is claiming something beyond one’s subjective experience.1 The idea of beauty, however, can lend itself to repudiation of an- other kind, as being a perfectly useless concept, the residue of pieties we can no longer take seriously. And in the life of an individual, something in the idea of beauty makes possible its characteristic forms of disillu- sion and not merely disappointment. One may be disappointed with one’s experience of ordinary pleasures, finding in them less than one hoped to find or even losing one’s taste altogether for certain of them. In relation to beauty, however, there is room for the possibility of not just disappointed expectations but disillusionment and, with that, re- pudiation of the very idea of beauty, as though the very idea were a form of mystification. What I take this to show is that the very possibility of such skepticism is testament to the fact that there is something addi- tional it would make sense to reject in the claim of beauty, something beyond the thought that something is a special source of pleasure. It is only against the background of something supposedly beyond ordinary pleasure and pain that there is the possibility of rejecting its claim, finding it perhaps quaint or hollow. With regard to beauty, there seems to be room for a different kind of rejection of its reality or genuineness 1. Consider this well-known passage: Attend to Palladio and Perrault, while they explain all the parts and proportions of a pillar. They talk of the cornice, and frieze, and base, and entablature, and shaft, and architrave; and give the description and position of each of these members. But should you ask the description and position of its beauty, they would readily reply, that the beauty is not in any of the parts or members of a pillar, but results from the whole, when that complicated fig- ure is presented to an intelligent mind, susceptible to those finer sensations. Till such a spectator appear, there is nothing but a figure of such particular dimensions and propor- tions: from his sentiments alone arise its elegance and beauty. [David Hume, An Inquiry into the Principles of Morals (Middlesex, 2006), p. 81] Here Hume seems to derive a claim about the subjectivity of beauty from the common fact of the constitution of one set of properties by another. Palladio could just as rightly say that the strength of the pillar is not in any of its parts or members, but it would hardly follow from this that its strength was somehow unreal or a mere projection of the sentiments. R ICHARD M ORAN is the Brian D. Young Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University. He is the author of Authority and Estrangement: An essay on self- knowledge. He is completing Self-Expression and the Modes of Address, a book on intersubjectivity in the acts of speaking and telling. 300 Richard Moran / Beauty or the thought that it can’t be and never was all that it presents itself as being.2 There is, however, another related set of reasons why the concept of beauty is subject to forms of skepticism peculiar to it. Far more than most other concepts of philosophical interest the idea of beauty has a well- developed cultural mythology that is as much a part of it as are any theories of it that have been proposed. Indeed, the competing philosophical theo- ries themselves have little point taken in isolation from the various depic- tions of the encounter with beauty that make their appearance throughout the Western tradition, from Plato to the Christian era, through romanti- cism, modernism, and whatever comes after that. Part of what I mean by mythology is that these ideas are something like a common cultural re- source, that they inform our actual experience and thinking about the thing in question, and are for that reason to be seen as belonging to the concept itself, whether part of its literal or figurative content. There needn’t be anything elaborate in such depictions, so let me begin with some simple examples, neither original nor exhaustive. So, for instance, beauty is commonly associated with mystery, as something that beckons but also withdraws and withholds, something whose nature belongs with appearing but that also presents itself as containing in itself more than is apparent. While it belongs to the sensory, to the realm of feeling, and is in that sense fully present to experience, at the same time it partakes of con- cealment in ways not shared by the rest of sensory life. A familiar trope of beauty is that of something not just pointing beyond itself but as harboring a secret or posing a question to be answered. And this is itself one of the classic settings for the disappointment and disillusion associated with beauty. A running theme in Marcel Proust’s Swann’s Way, for instance, is the repeated frustration of the narrator in his attempts to penetrate the secret that seems to be held by the scenes he finds most enthralling, which seem to pose a question that he cannot formulate, let alone answer.3 The beautiful not only beckons but also charms, enthralls, and other- 2. Or compare beauty with ordinary pleasure and pain with regard to the possibility of error. Given the appearance of pleasure or pain, it is hard to imagine a place for a further question about its genuineness or reality. Given the appearance of beauty, we may later come to question its genuineness or reality and perhaps come to the conclusion that the appearance of beauty here was a false one. It didn’t hold up to scrutiny; its promise was false or meretricious.
Recommended publications
  • Beauty As a Transcendental in the Thought of Joseph Ratzinger
    The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Theses 2015 Beauty as a transcendental in the thought of Joseph Ratzinger John Jang University of Notre Dame Australia Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses Part of the Philosophy Commons COMMONWEALTH OF AUSTRALIA Copyright Regulations 1969 WARNING The material in this communication may be subject to copyright under the Act. Any further copying or communication of this material by you may be the subject of copyright protection under the Act. Do not remove this notice. Publication Details Jang, J. (2015). Beauty as a transcendental in the thought of Joseph Ratzinger (Master of Philosophy (School of Philosophy and Theology)). University of Notre Dame Australia. https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/112 This dissertation/thesis is brought to you by ResearchOnline@ND. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of ResearchOnline@ND. For more information, please contact [email protected]. School of Philosophy and Theology Sydney Beauty as a Transcendental in the Thought of Joseph Ratzinger Submitted by John Jang A thesis in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Master of Philosophy Supervised by Dr. Renée Köhler-Ryan July 2015 © John Jang 2015 Table of Contents Abstract v Declaration of Authorship vi Acknowledgements vii Introduction 1 Structure 3 Method 5 PART I - Metaphysical Beauty 7 1.1.1 The Integration of Philosophy and Theology 8 1.1.2 Ratzinger’s Response 11 1.2.1 Transcendental Participation 14 1.2.2 Transcendental Convertibility 18 1.2.3 Analogy of Being 25 PART II - Reason and Experience 28 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Herman Bavinck's Theological Aesthetics: a Synchronic And
    TBR 2 (2011): 43–58 Herman Bavinck’s Theological Aesthetics: A Synchronic and Diachronic Analysis Robert S. Covolo PhD candidate, Fuller Theological Seminary In 1914 Herman Bavinck wrote an article for the Almanak of the Vrije Universiteit entitled, “Of Beauty and Aesthetics,” which has recently been translated and republished for the English-speaking world in Essays on Religion, Science, and Society.1 While this is not the only place where Bavinck treats the subject of beauty, this article stands out as a unique, extended glimpse into Bavinck’s theological aesthetics.2 In it we see that Bavinck was conversant with philosophical aesthetics and aware of the tensions of doing theological aesthetics from both a small “c” catholic and a distinctly Reformed perspective. There are many ways to assess Bavinck’s reflections on aesthetics. For example, one could look at the intimations in Bavinck’s works of the aesthetics formulations of later Dutch Reformed writers such as Rookmaker, Seerveld, or Wolterstorff.3 1. Herman Bavinck, “Of Beauty and Aesthetic” in Essays on Religion, Science and Society, ed. John Bolt, trans. Harry Boonstra and Gerrit Sheeres (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2008), 245–60. 2. See also Herman Bavinck, Reformed Dogmatics, vol. 2, God and Creation, ed. John Bolt, trans. John Vriend (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker, 2004), 252–55. 3. This in itself would prove to be a very interesting study. In one section of the essay Bavinck entertains an idea by a “Mister Berland” who maintains “the characterization of an anarchist situation in the arts.” See Bavinck, “Of Beauty and Aesthetics,” 252.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Aesthetic Judgment of Taste, Yogācāra, and Open
    THESIS BEAUTY AND OPENNESS: KANT’S AESTHETIC JUDGMENT OF TASTE, YOGĀCĀRA, AND OPEN PRESENCE MEDITATION Submitted by Kate Brelje Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University Fort Collins, Colorado Summer 2014 Master’s Committee: Advisor: Jane Kneller Co-Advisor: Matthew MacKenzie Kathleen Kiefer Copyright by Katherine Brelje 2014 All Rights Reserved ABSTRACT BEAUTY AND OPENNESS: KANT’S AESTHETIC JUDGMENT OF TASTE, YOGĀCĀRA, AND OPEN PRESENCE MEDITATION This paper provides a comparative analysis of Kant’s aesthetic judgment of taste and Open Presence meditation interpreted through a Yogācāra philosophical framework. I begin with an expository analysis of Kant’s cognitive and aesthetic judgments, highlighting the presence of attention, form of reflection, and structure of purposeless purposiveness in the judgment. Next, I address the Buddhist idealist Yogācāra philosophical tradition. Through this theoretical lens, I examine Open Presence meditation, with an emphasis on meditative non-dualism, attention, and meditative goals. In the final chapter, I tie together the groundwork laid in the first two chapters into a comparative analysis identifying points of compatibility and contention within the general areas of judgment, attention, purposeless purposiveness, and transformation. Finally, I suggest that, given the results of this analysis, Kant’s aesthetic judgment of taste might benefit from being construed as a type of meditation. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENT I would like to thank my advisors, Dr. Jane Kneller and Dr. Matthew MacKenzie, for their support throughout the process of crafting this thesis. Their expertise, patience, and guidance were essential for bringing this project to fruition.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and the Problem of Experience Hannah Ginsborg
    Kant and the Problem of Experience Hannah Ginsborg (Version for Phil. Topics: September 16, 2006.) As most of its readers are aware, the Critique of Pure Reason is primarily concerned not with empirical, but with a priori knowledge. For the most part, the Kant of the first Critique tends to assume that experience, and the knowledge that is based on it, is unproblematic. The problem with which he is concerned is that of how we can be capable of substantive knowledge independently of experience. At the same time, however, the notion of experience plays a crucial role in the central arguments of the Critique. For, again as most readers of the Critique know, Kant aims to show how we can have synthetic a priori knowledge by showing that the categories, or pure concepts of the understanding, are conditions of the possibility of experience. This means that, whether or not Kant is concerned with the notion of experience for its own sake, his account of a priori knowledge carries with it at least some commitments regarding the character of experience. If the account of a priori knowledge is to be successful, then experience has to be the kind of thing for which the categories can, in principle, serve as conditions of posibility. More specifically, experience must involve not only the senses, but also thought or understanding, for otherwise the claim that it presupposes a certain specific set of concepts is simply unintelligible. And indeed at least some parts of the Critique, in particular the so-called subjective deduction in the first edition, and the briefer passages which correspond to it in the second edition, seem to be intended to show how this requirement is met.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Beauty Only Skin Deep? Exploring the Connections Between Makeup and Perception Shawn Kuehl Concordia University, Saint Paul
    Concordia Journal of Communication Research Volume 5 Article 1 6-1-2018 Is Beauty Only Skin Deep? Exploring the Connections Between Makeup and Perception Shawn Kuehl Concordia University, Saint Paul Scarlett eD Wild Concordia University, Saint Paul Jessica Mai Concordia University, Saint Paul Mai Yeng Yang Concordia University, Saint Paul Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.csp.edu/comjournal Part of the Gender, Race, Sexuality, and Ethnicity in Communication Commons Recommended Citation Kuehl, Shawn; DeWild, Scarlett; Mai, Jessica; and Yeng Yang, Mai (2018) "Is Beauty Only Skin Deep? Exploring the Connections Between Makeup and Perception," Concordia Journal of Communication Research: Vol. 5 , Article 1. Available at: https://digitalcommons.csp.edu/comjournal/vol5/iss1/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@CSP. It has been accepted for inclusion in Concordia Journal of Communication Research by an authorized editor of DigitalCommons@CSP. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Running Title: Is BeautyKuehl Only et al.: SkinIs Beauty Deep? Only Skin Deep? Exploring the Connections Between Makeu Is Beauty Only Skin Deep? Exploring the Connections Between Makeup and Perception Shawn Kuehl, Scarlett DeWild, Jessica Mai, and Mai Yeng Yang Concordia University, St. Paul In Partial Fulfillment Of the Requirements for the Course Com: 441 Methods in Research and Com: 442 Research Theory 2017 Published by DigitalCommons@CSP, 2018 1 IS BEAUTY ONLY SKINConcordia DEEP? Journal of Communication Research, Vol. 5 [2018], Art. 1 ABSTRACT This study explored college students’ perceptions of the use of makeup. In order to determine what effect makeup had on first impressions, an online survey was conducted.
    [Show full text]
  • Roger-Scruton-Beauty
    Beauty This page intentionally left blank Beauty ROGER SCRUTON 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York # Horsell’s Farm Enterprises Limited The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2009 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available Typeset by SPI Publisher Services, Pondicherry, India Printed in Italy and acid-free paper by Lego S.p.A ISBN 978–0–19–955952–7 13579108642 CONTENTS Picture Acknowledgements vii Preface ix 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Of the Standard of Taste: David Hume's Aesthetic Ideology
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Of the Standard of Taste: David Hume's Aesthetic Ideology 著者 Okochi Sho journal or SHIRON(試論) publication title volume 42 page range 1-18 year 2004-12-20 URL http://hdl.handle.net/10097/57594 SHIRON No.42 (2004) Of the Standard of Taste: David Hume’s Aesthetic Ideology Sho Okochi The relationship between moral philosophy and aesthetics still remains one of the most important problems to be clarified in eighteenth-century British intellectual history. Both of these theoretical discourses have one important question in common—the question of how sentiment, which seems individual and idiosyncratic, can be the standard of judgment. As many commentators have already suggested, in the background of the emergence of moral philosophy and aesthetics during the period was the rapid commercialization of British society.1 After Mandeville inveighed against Shaftesbury’s theory of virtue, the theorists of moral senti- ments—many of whom were Scottish—tried to answer the question of how a modern commercial society that approves individual desires and passions as the driving force of commerce can avoid moral corruption.2 They constructed subtle arguments to demonstrate that principles regu- lating moral degeneration were incorporated into the mechanism of human sentiment. Theorists of ethics and aesthetics in the age from Shaftesbury to Richard Payne Knight never ceased to discuss the prob- lem of taste. The term ‘taste,’ derived from bodily palate, served British moral philosophers as the best metaphor through which to signify the inner faculty that intuitively grasps general rules of art and of life and manners.
    [Show full text]
  • The Real Truth About Beauty: a Global Report”
    “THE REAL TRUTH ABOUT BEAUTY: A GLOBAL REPORT” Findings of the Global Study on Women, Beauty and Well-Being September 2004 Dr. Nancy Etcoff – Harvard University Dr. Susie Orbach – London School of Economics Dr. Jennifer Scott – StrategyOne Heidi D’Agostino – StrategyOne Commissioned by Dove, a Unilever Beauty Brand “‘Beauty is truth, truth beauty’ -- that is all Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.” John Keats – Ode on a Grecian Urn 1 ABOUT THE STUDY The Real Truth About Beauty study was commissioned by Dove, one of Unilever’s largest beauty brands, to further the global understanding of women, beauty and well-being – and the relationship between them. It had its genesis in a growing concern that portrayals of female beauty in popular culture were helping to perpetuate an idea of beauty that was neither authentic nor attainable. Dove was concerned that this limited portrayal of beauty was preventing women from recognizing and enjoying beauty in themselves and others. The company was also aware that – in a world where female beauty is highly valued – this situation could also impact women’s well-being, happiness and self-esteem. Dove’s mission, in commissioning The Real Truth About Beauty study, was to explore empirically what beauty means to women today and why that is. Further, Dove wanted the study to assess whether it was possible to talk and think about female beauty in ways that were more authentic, satisfying and empowering. The Real Truth About Beauty findings detailed in this White Paper are based on quantitative data collected from a global study of 3,200 women, aged 18 to 64.
    [Show full text]
  • Antecedents and Consequences of Creativity and Beauty Judgements in Consumer Products
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by OpenArchive@CBS Creativity at Work: Antecedents and consequences of creativity and beauty judgements in consumer products. By Bo T Christensen, Tore Kristensen & Rolf Reber October 2009 Page 1 / 26 Creative Encounters Working Paper #29 Abstract The literature in consumer psychology has tended to lack a clear separation between theoretical models of creativity and beauty evaluations of products. The present study examined whether creativity and beauty affected willingness to pay jointly or separately. In three experiments using paintings, wrist watches and designer lamps as stimuli, the present study shows how creativity and beauty both positively influence consumer willingness-to-pay for the product, but each explains different parts of the variance. Further, product complexity differentially affects consumer judgments of creativity and beauty. The results show that it is essential to develop separate models of creativity and beauty evaluations in consumer psychology, in that they seem to be distinct factors, explaining different parts of the variance in their consequences on willingness to pay, and are affected differentially by antecedent factors, such as complexity. Address of Correspondence: Bo T. Christensen, Department of Marketing Solbjerg Plads 3 2000 Frederiksberg C DENMARK Phone: +45 38152123; email: [email protected] Page 2 / 26 Creative Encounters Working Paper #29 Antecedents and consequences of creativity and beauty judgements in consumer products. Bo T Christensen, Tore Kristensen Copenhagen Business School Rolf Reber University of Bergen The aesthetic qualities of consumer products are increasingly becoming important factors in consumer behavior and preference formation.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Beauty, Art and Testimony: Subjectivity and Objectivity in Aesthetics Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/0gd4w6z8 Author Klempner, Erica Diane Publication Date 2018 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Beauty, Art and Testimony: Subjectivity and Objectivity in Aesthetics by Erica Diane Klempner A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Hannah Ginsborg, Co-chair Professor Barry Stroud, Co-chair Professor John MacFarlane Professor Line Mikkelsen Spring 2018 Copyright © 2018 by Erica Diane Klempner All rights reserved Abstract Beauty, Art and Testimony: Subjectivity and Objectivity in Aesthetics by Erica Diane Klempner Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professor Hannah Ginsborg and Professor Barry Stroud, Co-chairs We acquire beliefs on the basis of what others tell us all the time. If you tell me that your house is painted red, chances are that I will simply believe you without question; and if someone asks me what color your house is, I will simply tell her that it is red. Yet we do not seem to accept others’ testimony about beauty and art in the same way. If you tell me that the Taj Mahal is beautiful, or that Middlemarch is a great novel, it would be strange for me simply to adopt your view, even if I have a lot of confidence in your judgment. In order for me to be in a position to believe or to claim that the Taj Mahal is beautiful, or that Middlemarch is a great novel, I must experience these things myself—by going to Agra, or by reading the book.
    [Show full text]
  • Romanticism in English Poetry
    ROMANTICISM IN ENGLISH POETRY A MLiCT AHfMOTATeO BiaUOQRAPHV SUBMITTtp m PARTIAL FULFH-MENT FOR TNf AWARD OF THE OCQflEE OF of librarp aiili itifarmation i^tteme 19t344 Roll Mo. t3 LSM-17 EnroliMM No. V-1432 Undsr th* SuparvMon of STBD MUSTIIFIIUIDI (READER) DEPARTMENT OF LIBRARY A INFORMATION SCIENCE ALIGARH MUSLIM UNIVERSITY ALIGARH (INDIA) 1994~ AIAB ^ **' r •^, '-fcv DS2708 DEDICATED TO MY LATE MOTHER CONTENTS page Acknowl edg&a&it ^ Scope and Methodology iii PART - I introduction 1 PART - II Annotated Bibliography ^^ List of Periodicals 113 PART - III Author index ^-^^ Title index 124 (i) ACKNOWLEDGEMENT I wish to express my sincere and earnest thanks to my teacher and Supervisor . kr» S. Mustafa Zaidi, who inspite of his many pre-occupations spared his precious time to guide and inspire me at each and every step/ during the course of this investigation. His deep critical understanding of the problem helped me in conpiling this bibliography. I am highly indebted to eminent teacher professor Mohd. sabir Husain, Chairman/ Department of Liberary & Information Science/ Aligarh Muslim University Allgarh for the encourage­ ment that I have always received from him during the period I have been associated with the department of Library Science. I am also highly grateful to the respected teachers of my Department Mr. Al-Muzaffar Khan, Reader, Mr. shabahat Husain, Reader/ Mr. Ifasan zamarrud. Reader. They extended their full cooperation in all aspects, whatever I needed. I am also thankful to the Library staff of Maulana Azad Library, A.M.U., Aligarh, Seminar Library Department of English, AMU Aligarh, for providing all facilities that I needed for my work.
    [Show full text]
  • African American Philosophy
    African American Dance - Philosophy, Aesthetics, and “Beauty” Thomas F. DeFrantz “A metaphysics, ontology, epistemology, or aesthetics is necessarily distorted by communicative practices which invariably include inherited and privileged structures, forms, assumptions, and codes that remain unstated. The subject, on such accounts, may be considered problematic because the subject may inappropriately present its ideas as ones that surmount the limitations of what it is to be a subject - contextually bounded.” (Harris, 1996: 197) Aesthetics in dance, and especially the terms of “beauty” as they might relate to African American artistry, remain extremely difficult to discuss. How can aesthetic theory be engaged in relation to African American dance practice? What sorts of aesthetic imperatives surround African American dance and how does black performance make sense of these imperatives?” Who names the quality of performance, or who determines that a performance may be accurately recognized as “black? More than this, how can African American dance participate on its own terms in a discourse of “beauty?” This essay offers portions of my current research project to consider the recuperation of “beauty” as a productive critical strategy in discussions of African American dance. I argue that black performance in general, and African American concert dance in particular, seek to create aesthetic sites that allow black Americans to participate in discourses of recognition and appreciation to include concepts of “beauty.” In this, I suggest that “beauty” may indeed produce social change for its attendant audiences. I also propose that interrogating the notion of “beauty” may allow for social change among audiences that include dance theorists and philosophers.
    [Show full text]