'Physiological Decapitation' As a Heuristic for Understanding

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

'Physiological Decapitation' As a Heuristic for Understanding The Signs of Death Pontifical Academy of Sciences, Scripta Varia 110, Vatican City 2007 www.pas.va/content/dam/accademia/pdf/sv110/sv110-shewmon.pdf MENTAL DISCONNECT: ‘PHYSIOLOGICAL DECAPITATION’ AS A HEURISTIC FOR UNDERSTANDING ‘BRAIN DEATH’ *,1 D. ALAN SHEWMON 1. STATEMENT OF THE PROBLEM The important task entrusted to this Conference by Popes Benedict XVI and his predecessor John Paul II has been clearly articulated by Bishop Chancellor Sánchez Sorondo: ‘The Academy is thus faced with the task of seeing whether the criterion of brain death (according to its full definition) indicates the biological state of death of an individual …’ (Conference Brochure, p. 4, ‘The Purpose of the Meeting’). It is remarkable that in the last decade or so, the various position state- ments and official commentaries on brain death by neurological and other medical societies have failed to state why brain death should be regarded as death of the individual. The same can be said for many recent books and chapters by neurologists on the subject. The equivalence is simply taken for granted as common knowledge, and the discussions focus rather on such aspects as diagnostic criteria for determining that the brain is dead, con- troversies over how much of the brain must be destroyed for the brain as a whole to be dead, etc. The American Academy of Neurology, for example, in its ‘Practice Parameters for Determining Brain Death in Adults’ (1995), which still remain the gold-standard diagnostic criteria in the United States, did not offer a single reason why it considers death of the brain to be death. Neither did fellow conferee Dr. Eelco Wijdicks in his accompanying commentary on the ‘Practice Parameters’ (Wijdicks, 1995) or in the chapter on brain death in his book on critical care neurology (Wijdicks, 2003, pp. 547-62). Nor, in his recent book on brain death (Wijdicks, 2001a), does he state why he him- * The views expressed with absolute freedom in this paper should be understood as representing the views of the author and not necessarily those of the Pontifical Academy of Sciences. 1 Although not publicly discussed, this paper was added because Professor Shewmon sent it in before the meeting and it was privately viewed and discussed by the participants. MENTAL DISCONNECT 293 self believes brain death to be death; rather, that apologetic task was dele- gated to co-conferee Dr. James Bernat, who has become somewhat of the unofficial brain-death-theory spokesperson for mainstream neurology (not without good reason), in whose chapter only a single paragraph is devoted to answering what he himself characterizes as ‘the most serious challenges thus far to the brain death concept’ (namely my publications as of that time) (Bernat, 2001, p. 180). Neither does fellow conferee Dr. Allan Ropper, in the sections on brain death in his two widely read textbooks, state why he considers brain death to be death (Ropper and Brown, 2005, pp. 306-7, 961-2; Ropper et al., 2004, pp. 157-64). Along similar lines, in their intro- ductory essay for the conference brochure entitled ‘Why the Concept of Brain Death is Still Valid as a Definition of Death’, Dr. Ropper and col- leagues concern themselves with rebutting the weakest arguments against brain death, while ignoring or glibly dismissing the strongest arguments, without in the end offering a single reason ‘why the concept of brain death is still’ – or ever was – ‘valid as a definition of death’. Discussions at this conference regarding the history of brain death, dis- orders that are not brain death, neuroimaging, apnea testing, determina- tion of irreversibility, determination of totality of brain nonfunction or destruction, controversies over what constitutes a ‘critical’ function of the brain, etc., interesting and important though they may be, will not bring the Church any closer to an understanding of whether and why death of the brain, so diagnosed, ‘indicates the biological state of death of an individu- al’. I daresay that doctors in general, and neurologists in particular, have come to an overwhelming consensus that brain death is death, not because they have examined the evidence and concluded it for themselves, but pure- ly and simply from a professional herd mentality. When queried about it, few can give a coherent explanation why brain death is death itself, as opposed to deep coma in a dying patient. In a revealing survey of physicians and nurses involved in transplantation, who surely ought to have a solid understanding of brain death for the sake of their own consciences, 58% did not use a coherent concept of death consistently and 19% held a con- cept of death that would logically classify patients in a persistent vegetative state as dead (Youngner et al., 1989). This is a serious mental disconnect in professionals who should have clear and coherent thoughts on the matter. 2. FOUR CANDIDATE RATIONALES FOR EQUATING BRAIN DEATH WITH DEATH Across the half-century of brain-death history up to the present, the many proposed reasons for equating death of the brain with death of the 294 D. ALAN SHEWMON individual have fallen into four basic categories: (1) because death is not an objective physical state but a relativistic legal definition or custom based on what seems most useful to a given society at a given time (societal relativism); or (2) because the brain is the organ of the mind, which is the essence of the person; therefore, the irreversible cessation of mind is cessation of the person, i.e., ‘death of the individual’ (person/mind reductionism); or (3) because the brain is the central integrating organ of the body, so that without brain function the body ceases to be a unified biological organism and begins the irrevocable process of disintegration, thereby indicating ces- sation of ‘the corporal reality of the person’ (to quote Pope John Paul II, 2000) (somatic integration rationale). (4) because the permanent loss of both mental functions and bodily unity, attendant upon death of the brain, constitutes – again in the words of Pope John Paul II (2000) – ‘the total disintegration of that unitary and integrated whole that is the personal self’ (psychosomatic integration rationale). A fifth rationale is not listed, because it is only a pseudo-rationale, name- ly the ‘fatal lesion fallacy’ (brain death is death because it will imminently lead to death). Remarkably, some experts still offer this as an implicit ration- ale for brain death (e.g., Dr. Wijdicks, 2001b, p. 76): ‘In the United States, pri- mary brainstem death does not fit into the concept of whole brain death, but it has been accepted in the United Kingdom and rightly so, because no sur- vivor has been reported when all brainstem function has been lost’. There are no other broad categories of proposed reasons why death of the brain as an organ should constitute death of the individual person. Let us now examine these four rationales in somewhat greater detail. (1) Societal relativism was the rationale of, among others, Dr. Henry Beecher, chairman of the Harvard Committee, as made clear in some of his commentaries following the revolutionary Harvard Committee report of 1968, which marked the beginning of the general acceptance of brain death as death (Beecher et al., 1968). ‘At whatever level we choose to call death, it is an arbitrary decision. Death of the heart? The hair still grows. Death of the brain? The heart may still beat. The need is to choose an irreversible state where the brain no longer functions. It is best to choose a level where, although the brain is dead, usefulness of other organs is still present (p. 120). … Here we arbitrarily accept as death, destruction of one part of the body; but it is the supreme part, the brain (p. 121). … Can society afford to discard the tissues and organs of the hopelessly unconscious patient so greatly needed for study and experimental trial to help those who can be MENTAL DISCONNECT 295 salvaged? (p. 122)’ (Beecher and Dorr, 1971) (emphasis mine). Needless to say, societal relativism is incompatible with any sort of objective meta- physics of life and death, and as such is incompatible with the fundamen- tal tenets of many of the world’s religions, including Catholicism. (2) Person/mind reductionism declares the person to be dead when there is no longer a personal mind or consciousness, even in potency (e.g., excluding states of sleep or coma from which there is a potential to awak- en; whether human embryos are excluded or not varies across authors). According to this view, truly irreversible coma, as well as permanent vege- tative state (defined according to the American Academy of Neurology and many other professional societies in terms of unawareness of self and envi- ronment – cf. Shewmon, 2004a; Shewmon, 2004b) are therefore death of a person, regardless of the biological life/death status of the (former) person’s body (also prescinding here from the subtle controversies surrounding the terms ‘irreversible’ and ‘permanent’ (Cole, 1992; Lizza, 2005; Lizza, 2006, pp. 102-7; Tomlinson, 1993). This rationale is frequently referred to in the literature as the ‘higher brain’ formulation of brain death. It has had and continues to have many advocates. Such equating of person with mind is patently Platonic/Cartesian and contrary to the Aristotelian/Thomistic notion, which the Church endorses, that the human person is a corpo- ral/mental hybrid, so that the spiritual soul is at once both the center and source of intellectual and volitional powers of the mind, as well as substan- tial form (life-principle) of the body (Council of Vienne [1312], 1957). This psychological rationale was most strikingly articulated by one of the participants of the Pontifical Academy of Sciences’ Second Working Group on Brain Death: ‘[T]he Cartesian ‘cogito ergo sum’ principle is still applicable in our days.
Recommended publications
  • What You Lose When You Sign That Donor Card Giving Away Your Organs Sounds Noble, but Have Doctors Blurred the Line Between Life and Death?
    What You Lose When You Sign That Organ-Donor Card - WSJ.com http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052970204603004577269910... Dow Jones Reprints: This copy is for your personal, non-commercial use only. To order presentation-ready copies for distribution to your colleagues, clients or customers, use the Order Reprints tool at the bottom of any article or visit www.djreprints.com See a sample reprint in PDF format. Order a reprint of this article now LIFE & CULTURE Updated March 13, 2012, 10:11 a.m. ET What You Lose When You Sign That Donor Card Giving away your organs sounds noble, but have doctors blurred the line between life and death? By DICK TERESI The last time I renewed my driver's license, the clerk at the DMV asked if she should check me off as an organ donor. I said no. She looked at me and asked again. I said, "No. Just check the box that says, 'I am a heartless, selfish bastard.'" Becoming an organ donor seems like a win-win situation. Some 3.3 people on the transplant waiting list will have their lives extended by your gift (3.3 is the average yield of solid organs per donor). You're a hero, and at no real cost, apparently. But what are you giving up when you check the donor box on your license? Your organs, of course—but much more. You're also giving up your right to informed consent. Doctors don't have to tell you or your relatives what they will do to your body during an organ harvest operation because you'll be dead, with no legal rights.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Know If You're Dead
    How to Know If You're Dead Beating-heart cadavers, live burial, and the scientific search for the soul A patient on the way to surgery travels at twice the speed of a patient on the way to the morgue. Gurneys that ferry the living through hospital corridors move forward in an aura of purpose and push, flanked by caregivers with long strides and set faces, steadying IVs, pumping ambu bags, barreling into double doors. A gurney with a cadaver commands no urgency. It is wheeled by a single person, calmly and with little notice, like a shopping cart. For this reason, I thought I would be able to tell when the dead woman was wheeled past. I have been standing around at the nurses' station on one of the surgery floors of the University of California at San Francisco Medical Center, watching gurneys go by and waiting for Von Peterson, public affairs manager of the California Transplant Donor Network, and a cadaver I will call H. "There's your patient," says the charge nurse. A commotion of turquoise legs passes with unexpected forward-leaning urgency. H is unique in that she is both a dead person and a patient on the way to surgery. She is what's known as a "beating-heart cadaver," alive and well everywhere but her brain. Up until artificial respiration was developed, there was no such entity; without a functioning brain, a body will not breathe on its own. But hook it up to a respirator and its heart will beat, and the rest of its organs will, for a matter of days, continue to thrive.
    [Show full text]
  • From Modern to Postmodern Medicine: the Case of Organ Transplants
    FROM MODERN TO POSTMODERN MEDICINE: THE CASE OF ORGAN TRANSPLANTS A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY NİHAN BOZOK IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE DEPARTMENT OF SOCIOLOGY FEBRUARY 2015 Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences Prof. Dr. Meliha Altunışık Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Prof. Dr. Ayşe Saktanber Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Assoc. Prof. Dr. Erdoğan Yıldırım Supervisor Examining Committee Members Prof. Dr. Ş. Halil Turan (METU, PHIL) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Mustafa Şen (METU, SOC) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Erdoğan Yıldırım (METU, SOC) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Nedim Karakayalı (Bilkent U, POL. SCI) Asst. Prof. Dr. Çağatay Topal (METU, SOC) PLAGIARISM I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name: Nihan Bozok Signature : iii ABSTRACT FROM MODERN TO POSTMODERN MEDICINE: THE CASE OF ORGAN TRANSPLANTS Bozok, Nihan Ph.D., Department of Sociology Supervisor: Assoc. Prof. Dr. Erdoğan Yıldırım February, 2015, 240 pages This thesis investigates the constituent tendencies of postmodern medicine, concentrating upon the organ transplantation therapy.
    [Show full text]
  • Brain Death S34 (1)
    BRAIN DEATH S34 (1) Brain Death Last updated: December 19, 2020 CRITERIA FOR BRAIN DEATH .................................................................................................................. 1 APNEA TEST (S. APNEA CHALLENGE) ...................................................................................................... 5 ANCILLARY STUDIES ............................................................................................................................... 6 CARE OF ORGAN DONOR .......................................................................................................................... 9 ORGAN DONATION AFTER CARDIAC DEATH .......................................................................................... 11 PEDIATRIC ASPECTS ............................................................................................................................... 12 Diagnosing brain death must never be rushed or take priority over the needs of the patient or the family BRAIN DEATH (BD) or DEATH BY NEUROLOGICAL CRITERIA (DNC) – permanent loss of brain function* (cerebrum nor brain stem nor cerebellum) (i.e. no clinical detection at bedside).** *vs. brain activity (such as laboratory detection of cellular-level neuronal and neuroendocrine activity) is compatible with brain death, e.g. osmolar control - some patients develop diabetes insipidus only after clinical signs of brain death (i.e. diabetes insipidus is not required for BD diagnosis). **vs. VEGETATIVE STATE - brain stem is intact. It is suggested
    [Show full text]
  • Pediatric Forensic Pathology: Limits and Controversies
    Pediatric Forensic Pathology: Limits and Controversies Commissioned by The Inquiry into Pediatric Forensic Pathology Ontario, Canada (As amended, 15 February 2008) Authors: Stephen Cordner Jonathon Ehsani Lyndal Bugeja Joseph Ibrahim Victorian Institute of Forensic Medicine November 2007 Paediatric Forensic Pathology: Limits and Controversies i Title Page This paper was written by Stephen Cordner (1), Jonathon Ehsani (2), Lyndal Bugeja (3), and Joseph Ibrahim (4) from the Victorian Institute of Forensic Medicine in Australia for the Inquiry into Pediatric Forensic Pathology in Ontario, Canada. The authors thank Dr Jeffrey Hubbard, Albany, New York for his comments on this paper. Any faults are ours, however. Editorial decisions and the opinions expressed are the responsibility of the first author and do not represent those of the Victorian Institute of Forensic Medicine or Monash University or of the Inquiry into Pediatric Forensic Pathology or the Commissioner. 1—Stephen Cordner AM MA MB BS BMedSc DipCrim DMJ FRCPA FRCPath Professor of Forensic Medicine, Monash University. Director, Victorian Institute of Forensic Medicine, Australia. 2—Jonathon Ehsani BMedSci, MPH (International), MH.Sci (Public Health) PhD Candidate, Monash University Accident Research Centre, Victoria, Australia. Senior Research Officer, Victorian Institute of Forensic Medicine, Victoria, Australia. 3—Lyndal Bugeja BA (Hons - Criminology) PhD Candidate, Monash University Accident Research Centre, Victoria, Australia. Senior Research Officer, Victorian Institute of Forensic Medicine, Victoria, Australia. 4—Joseph Ibrahim MB BS Grad Cert HE PhD MRACMA FAFPHM FRACP Consultant Physician, Victorian Institute of Forensic Medicine, Victoria, Australia. The authors acknowledge with thanks the assistance of Ms Kerry Johannes, Library Manager at the Victorian Institute of Forensic Medicine.
    [Show full text]
  • Bea2017.Pdf (3.251Mb)
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. No Heroics, Please Mapping Deceased Donation Practices in a Catalan Hospital Sara Bea PhD in Science Technology and Innovation Studies The University of Edinburgh 2016 Declaration I declare that the thesis has been composed by myself and that the work presented is my own, except where explicitly indicated otherwise in the text. (Sara Bea) ii iii Abstract This thesis presents an in-depth ethnographic mapping of deceased donation in a Catalan hospital. A unique site in terms of leading edge technoscientific practices, high rates of donation and its consolidated specialised team of transplant coordinators (TCs). The thesis situates donation as an embedded medical practice and traces the practicalities and specificities of making donation a possibility at the hospital. The empirical accounts offer a distinctive contribution that complements and challenges existing social sciences literature about donation.
    [Show full text]
  • Jain Digest Dec 2015.Pdf
    A Publication of the Federation of Jain Associations in North America (JAINA) email: [email protected] JAINA is an umbrella organization of local Jain Associations in U.S.A. and Canada. The purpose of the organization is to preserve, practice, and promote Jain Dharma and Jain Way of life. JAINA Headquarters: 722 S Main St, Milpitas, CA 95035 Tele: 408-262-6242, email: [email protected], Web: www.jaina.org JAINA Executive Committee JAIN DIGEST Editorial Team 310-721-5947 President Ashok Domadia email: [email protected] [email protected] Jain Digest Committee Chairman First VP: Gunvant Shah Mahesh Wadher [email protected] Editors Treasurer: Rita Sheth Dilip Parekh [email protected] Sanjay Bhandari Yogendra Bobra Secretory: Shobha Vora Reena Shah [email protected] Art and Design VP Northeast: Dr. Mamta Shaha Jayana Shah [email protected] Rishita Dagli Pooja Shah VP Mideast: Prakash Mehta [email protected] IT Support Giriraj Jain VP Midwest: Hemant T. Shah [email protected] Advertisements Mahesh Wadher VP Southeast: Rajendra Mehta Shobha Vora [email protected] VP Southwest: Pradeep Shah [email protected] VP West: Mahesh Wadher [email protected] VP Canada: Raj Patil [email protected] Past President: Prem Jain [email protected] YJA Chair: Puja Savla Disclosure [email protected] The Editorial Team endeavors to publish all the materials that are submitted but reserves the right to reduce, revise, reject, or edit any article, letter, or YJA Chair: Sunny Dharod abstract for clarity, space, or policy reasons. The views [email protected] expressed in the articles are those of the authors and do not necessarily represent the views of the Editorial YJP Co-Chair : Neal Daftary Team.
    [Show full text]
  • A Study of Some Jain Responses to Non-Jain Religious Practices, by Phyllis Granoff 1 2
    THE JOURNAL OF THE INTERNATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF BUDDHIST STUDIES EDITOR-IN-CHIEF 93-^.M Roger Jackson Dept. of Religion Carleton College Northfield, MN 55057 V''-, W=:- ..- '• / USA cT£ . O"". °^ EDITORS Peter N. Gregory Ernst Steinkellner University of Illinois University of Vienna Urbana-Champaign, Illinois, USA Wien, Austria Alexander W. Macdonald Jikido Takasaki University de Paris X University of Tokyo Nanterre, France Tokyo, Japan Steven Collins Robert Thurman Concordia University Columbia University Montreal, Canada New York, New York, USA Volume 15 1992 Number 1 CONTENTS L ARTICLES 1. The Violence of Non-Violence: A Study of Some Jain Responses to Non-Jain Religious Practices, by Phyllis Granoff 1 2. Is the Dharma-kaya the Real "Phantom Body" of the Buddha?, by Paul Harrison 44 3. Lost in China, Found in Tibet: How Wonch'uk Became the Author of the Great Chinese Commentary, by John Powers 95 U. PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS Some Observations on the Present and Future of Buddhist Studies, by D. Seyfort Ruegg 104 HL AN EXCHANGE The Theatre of Objectivity: Comments on Jose Cabezon's Interpretations of mKhas grub rje's and C.W. Huntington, Jr.'s Interpretations of the TibetaV Translation of a Seventh Century Indian Buddhist Text, by C W. Huntington, Jr. 118 On Retreating to Method and Other Postmodern Turns: A Response to C. W. Huntington, Jr., by Jos6 Ignacio Cabezdn 134 IV. BOOK REVIEWS 1. Choix de Documents tibttains conserve's d la Bibliotheque Nationale compliti par quelques manuscrits de I'India Office et du British Museum, by Yoshiro Imaeda and Tsugohito Takeuchi (Alexander W. Macdonald) 144 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Bioethical Issues in Jain Perspective Dr. N.L. Kachhara And
    National Seminar on Engaging Jainism on Modern Issues, Ladnun, Feb 2017 Some Bioethical Issues in Jain Perspective Dr. N.L. Kachhara and Dr. I.L. Jain Abstract Advances in biology and medicine have raised issues of new types of ethics and has forced various religions to express their views on these developments. These developments are being introduced with the aim of passing the benefits of scientific advancements for the well being of humans and other living beings. Study of these biological and medical advancements from moral point of view has given rise to the new discipline of bioethics. Bioethics today is concerned with life sciences, biotechnology, medicine, politics, law and philosophy. Some of the important recent biological and medical practices are abortion, euthanasia, cloning, artificial insemination and infertility, blood transfusion, body modification, human enhancement, contraception and population control, life extension, organ donation and organ transplant, surrogacy, etc. No Jain scholar or religious leader is known to have expressed views on these practices in scientific community. The principle of non violence forms the foundation of Jain religion. The life in Jain philosophy is characterized by jiva (soul) or atman which is non-corporeal and eternal and cannot be destroyed by any means. The worldly soul is embodied and occupies the body (gross) according to his karma. The body is supported by vital powers in the form of prana in its existence. Killing in Jainism is defined as depriving the body of prana , pranaatipaata , so that the material body is no longer sustained and death occurs. There are ten pranas which exist in two forms one as power of the soul, bhava prana , and the other as vital powers, dravya prana .
    [Show full text]
  • RAISING CAIN the Role of Serious Mental Illness in Family Homicides
    RAISING CAIN The Role of Serious Mental Illness in Family Homicides E. Fuller Torrey, M.D. Founder and Board Member Treatment Advocacy Center Robert D. (Joe) Bruce Caratunk, Maine H. Richard Lamb, M.D. Emeritus Professor of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences Keck School of Medicine of the University of Southern California Board Member, Treatment Advocacy Center Carla Jacobs Board Member, Treatment Advocacy Center Coordinator, California Treatment Advocacy Coalition D.J. Jaffe Director, Mental Illness Policy Org John Snook Executive Director Treatment Advocacy Center June 2016 Online at TACReports.org/raising-cain © 2016 Treatment Advocacy Center TABLE OF CONTENTS Executive Summary 1. Introduction 2. Methods 3. Results 3.1 Parents Killing Children 3.2 Children Killing Parents 3.3 Spouses Killing Spouses 3.4 Siblings Killing Siblings 3.5 Other Family Combinations 4. Family Homicides: Just the Tip of the Iceberg 5. Conclusions 6. Recommendations Acknowledgments and Financial Disclosures Endnotes EXECUTIVE SUMMARY Most individuals with serious mental illness are not dangerous. However, a small num- ber of them, most of whom are not being treated, may become dangerous to them- selves or to others. Some of these individuals may assault or even kill family members. This problem has received insufficient attention. • Although there have been previous studies of particular types of family homi- cides, such as children killed by parents, this is the first study of the role of serious mental illness in all family homicides. • For a sample of the nation’s homicides, local law enforcement agencies volun- tarily submit Supplementary Homicide Reports (SHRs) to the FBI that include the relationship between the person committing the homicide (offender) and the victim.
    [Show full text]
  • Double Heart Surgeon I Found Conversations with Relatives After Very Difficult Operations Unpleasant
    Published by Black Inc., an imprint of Schwartz Books Pty Ltd Level 1, 221 Drummond Street Carlton VIC 3053, Australia [email protected] www.blackincbooks.com Copyright © Verlagsgruppe Random House GmBH, München, Germany, 2019 Copyright © English translation Gert Reifarth, 2021 Originally published as Der Takt des Lebens. Warum das Herz unser wichtigstes Sinnesorgan ist by Reinhard Friedl, with Shirley Michaela Seul This edition published in 2021 This book is intended for informational purposes only. It is not a substitute for professional medical advice, diagnosis or treatment. The experiences of patients described in this book have been fictionalised. ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form by any means electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior consent of the publishers. 9781760642570 (paperback) 9781743821534 (ebook) Cover design: zero-media.net Cover image: FinePic®, Munich Text design and typesetting by Typography Studio For Josef and Olivia REINHARD FRIEDL For Tex Poole (1926–2020), whose noble heart gave out aged ninety-three GERT REIFARTH ‘You always hear of people who lost their mind because of love. But there are also many who lost love because of their mind.’ JEAN PAUL, novelist ‘I had explored the mysteries of the brain, and it was time to devote as much academic rigour and hard science to exploring the secrets of the heart.’ JAMES R. DOTY, clinical professor of neurosurgery at Stanford, and the
    [Show full text]
  • The Biomedical Ethics of Cell and Organ Harvest
    Providence College DigitalCommons@Providence Common Reading Essay Contest Winners Common Reading Program 2012 It’s MY Body: The Biomedical Ethics of Cell and Organ Harvest Christina Perri Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.providence.edu/cr_essays Part of the Bioethics and Medical Ethics Commons, Biology Commons, Business Law, Public Responsibility, and Ethics Commons, Commercial Law Commons, Health Law and Policy Commons, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine Commons, Laboratory and Basic Science Research Commons, Literature in English, North America, Ethnic and Cultural Minority Commons, Medical Jurisprudence Commons, Science and Technology Law Commons, and the United States History Commons Perri, Christina, "It’s MY Body: The Biomedical Ethics of Cell and Organ Harvest" (2012). Common Reading Essay Contest Winners. 1. https://digitalcommons.providence.edu/cr_essays/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Common Reading Program at DigitalCommons@Providence. It has been accepted for inclusion in Common Reading Essay Contest Winners by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Providence. For more information, please contact [email protected]. It’s MY Body: The Biomedical Ethics of Cell and Organ Harvest Christina Perri It all seems very simple. All we can rely on as our own in this world are our minds, souls, and bodies. But are they really “our own”? Medical precedent suggests that it may not be as clear-cut as that. The line where cells and tissues cease to belong to us and begin to belong to the scientific community is thin at best. When do cells cross this line? Is it when they leave our bodies? Is it when we die and are no longer using them? Or are they, perhaps, never ours? In the first half of the twentieth century, biomedical ethics was not even a vague concept.
    [Show full text]