A Unified Model of Complex Specified Information

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Unified Model of Complex Specified Information Research Article A Unified Model of Complex Specified Information George D. Montanez*˜ Department of Computer Science, Harvey Mudd College, Claremont, CA, USA Abstract A mathematical theory of complex specified information is introduced which unifies several prior methods of computing specified complexity. Similar to how the exponential family of probability distributions have dissimilar surface forms yet share a common underlying mathematical identity, we define a model that allows us to cast Dembski’s semiotic specified complexity, Ewert et al.’s algorithmic specified complexity, Hazen et al.’s functional information, and Behe’s irreducible complexity into a common mathematical form. Adding additional constraints, we introduce canonical specified complexity models, for which one-sided conservation bounds are given, showing that large specified complexity values are unlikely under any given continuous or discrete distribution and that canonical models can be used to form statistical hypothesis tests, by bounding tail probabilities for arbitrary distributions. Cite As: Montanez˜ GD (2018) A Unified Model of Complex Specified Information. BIO-Complexity 2018 (4):1-26. doi:10.5048/BIO-C.2018.4. Editor: Robert J. Marks II Received: June 29, 2018; Accepted: November 30, 2018; Published: December 14, 2018 Copyright: © 2018 George D. Montanez.˜ This open-access article is published under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits free distribution and reuse in derivative works provided the original author(s) and source are credited. Notes: A Critique of this paper, when available, will be assigned doi:10.5048/BIO-C.2018.4.c. *Email: [email protected] \Life must depend on a higher level of complexity, structure without predictable repetition, he argued." - James Gleick, \The Information: A History, a Theory, a Flood", ch. 9 INTRODUCTION Recent work in specified complexity has proposed using algorithmic information theory as a way of com- Specified complexity, the property of an object being both putationally grounding specified complexity, under the unlikely and structurally organized, has been proposed name of algorithmic specified complexity (ASC) [5, 6]. as a signifier of design [1{3]. Objects exhibiting specified Ewert and collaborators have shown that under any pro- complexity must be both complex (e.g., unlikely under posed discrete distribution, sequences exhibiting high the relevant probability distribution) and specified (e.g., levels of ASC must be unlikely [6]. We extend this body conform to an independent or detached specification). of work by generalizing the result of Ewert et al. [6], While mathematical methods for measuring specified showing that all specified complexity models of a certain complexity have changed over the decades [1, 4{6], the class, which we call canonical models, share this property. underlying components of specification and complex- We re-derive the existing result of Ewert et al. [6] as a ity have remained constant. Possible applications of corollary to our general theorem, and prove a number specified complexity include differentiating malicious net- of previously unknown results, including a conservation work behavior from non-intentional anomalies, identify- result for a variant of semiotic specified complexity, in- ing genetically-modified material in agricultural products troduced in Dembski (2005) [4]. These results add to (such as artificially engineered gene sequences), identify- a body of work generally known as conservation of in- ing intelligently engineered extra-terrestrial signals, and formation theorems, which prove that in many contexts testing for artificial general intelligence [7]. At its core, it takes as much information to find an object as you it has been proposed as a method of sorting artificial might gain by using that object, rendering explanations or teleological structures from naturally occurring unin- that rely on such specialized objects as cases of special tentional ones. Specified complexity has been severely pleading. Viewed as a conservation theorem, if one char- criticized, both for its underlying logic and its various acterizes specified complexity as a form of information formulations [8{11]. signal measurable in bits, the probability under the pro- Volume 2018 j Issue 4 j Page 1 A Unified Model of Complex Specified Information posed distribution of encountering a structure exhibiting the function prior to observing x, but need not be, as b or more bits of complex specified information is no long as the function itself is not conditioned on x when greater than 2−b, thus incurring an information cost of computing the value for x. In other words, specification at least b bits. functions of the form νx(x) or ν(xjx) are invalid. This More importantly, this work formally reduces speci- danger of fabrication is a general vulnerability of statis- fied complexity testing to a form of statistical hypothe- tical hypothesis testing, since one could inappropriately sis testing, a view inspired by Dembski (2005) [4] (and choose the significance level α (acting as the specification preceded by Milosavljevi´c[12]). Accordingly, we demon- function) in response to the observed test statistic value, strate the connection for canonical specified complexity or even define a test statistic Tx(X) = c · 1fX = xg models, where the model core (called a kardis) plays the (where 1{·} denotes the indicator function, which equals same role as a p-value under a null distribution. We 1 when the argument evaluates to true, and 0 otherwise) prove that for such models the null-distribution probabil- that always assigns a large value c to the particular x ity mass of values as extreme as the one observed is upper observed and zero to all other possible observations, lead- bounded by the significance level α, which is the crucial ing to the smallest possible critical region, a singleton property for p-value significance tests. Thus, we formally set containing only the observation itself. If the danger establish the canonical model as a particular statistical of fabrications forces us to reject specified complexity hypothesis test statistic, one which would prove useful hypothesis testing then we must also reject many other in cases where only a likelihood and a specification value statistical hypothesis tests, which all suffer from the same are available and the behavior of the distribution outside vulnerability. of the given observation is otherwise unknown. We begin by reviewing the general structure of speci- 1.1 Common Form and Canonical Models fied complexity models and defining their common and We begin with a few definitions. canonical model forms, along with providing a general Definition 1 (ν(X )). For any integrable nonnegative recipe for constructing new specified complexity models. specification function ν : X! , define ν(X ) as We then review statistical hypothesis testing and the R≥0 follows: level-α property, formally reducing p-value testing to a 8 form of specified complexity model hypothesis testing. R ν(x)dx if continuous, Conservation and level-α test properties of canonical <> X ν(X ) := P ν(x) if discrete, (1) specified complexity models are proven, and instructions x2X :>R for conducting specified complexity model hypothesis X dν(x) in general. tests are also given. Algorithmic specified complexity, Definition 2 (Common Form and Kardis). For any semiotic specified complexity, and functional informa- probability distribution p(x) on space X , any strictly tion are reduced to common form, canonical variants positive scaling constant r 2 and any nonnegative are derived, and conservation theorems are proven for R>0 function ν : X! , we define a common form model each as corollaries to our results for the general canonical R≥0 as specified complexity models. While criticisms of speci- fied complexity [8{11] (and their rebuttals [2, 13{16]) are p(x) SC(x) := − log r (2) duly acknowledged, we do not attempt to address them 2 ν(x) here, as the purpose of this manuscript is to prove the mathematical commonality of several complexity metrics, with specified complexity kardis κ(x) = r(p(x)/ν(x)). not to defend them individually. Definition 3 (Canonical Specified Complexity Model). Any common form model constrained such that ν(X ) ≤ r 1. SPECIFIED COMPLEXITY MODELS is a canonical specified complexity model. A specified complexity model is a function of an obser- vation X taking values in some space X , where X is It should be stated explicitly that the constraint for distributed according to probability distribution p(x) canonical models is what allows us to bound the proba- (denoted as X ∼ p). It contains two components, one bility of observing extreme specified complexity values, measuring the likelihood of the observation under p (re- and that ideally ν(X ) = r, which allows us to obtain ferred to as the complexity term for historical reasons), tight bounds. In addition, the scaling constant r should and another component that measures the specificity not depend on x. To define a canonical model, it suffices 1 of the observation, according to a specification function to define the kardis κ(x) and ensure that the constraints ν(x). This function should be computable or capable of are satisfied for r, p, and ν. As a useful example, given being estimated given x and should be definable indepen- any kardis κ(x) from a canonical specified complexity dently of the particular observation x, to avoid cherry- 1From Greek kardi´a (heart) and Ilocano kardis (pigeon pea, picking and fabrications. This can be done by defining which is a small component contained in a larger pod). Volume 2018 j Issue 4 j Page 2 A Unified Model of Complex Specified Information model, we can define an augmented kardis (and thus f(x) is the original function and ≥ 0 is some small augmented model) that incorporates a significance level constant used to prevent undefined values. If needed, term within the model. We do so as follows. we can then rescale γ(x) into the range [0; 1] by using zero-one scaling: Definition 4 (rα, κα(x), and SCα(x)).
Recommended publications
  • Intelligent Design, Abiogenesis, and Learning from History: Dennis R
    Author Exchange Intelligent Design, Abiogenesis, and Learning from History: Dennis R. Venema A Reply to Meyer Dennis R. Venema Weizsäcker’s book The World View of Physics is still keeping me very busy. It has again brought home to me quite clearly how wrong it is to use God as a stop-gap for the incompleteness of our knowledge. If in fact the frontiers of knowledge are being pushed back (and that is bound to be the case), then God is being pushed back with them, and is therefore continually in retreat. We are to find God in what we know, not in what we don’t know; God wants us to realize his presence, not in unsolved problems but in those that are solved. Dietrich Bonhoeffer1 am thankful for this opportunity to nature, is the result of intelligence. More- reply to Stephen Meyer’s criticisms over, this assertion is proffered as the I 2 of my review of his book Signature logical basis for inferring design for the in the Cell (hereafter Signature). Meyer’s origin of biological information: if infor- critiques of my review fall into two gen- mation only ever arises from intelli- eral categories. First, he claims I mistook gence, then the mere presence of Signature for an argument against bio- information demonstrates design. A few logical evolution, rendering several of examples from Signature make the point my arguments superfluous. Secondly, easily: Meyer asserts that I have failed to refute … historical scientists can show that his thesis by not providing a “causally a presently acting cause must have adequate alternative explanation” for the been present in the past because the origin of life in that the few relevant cri- proposed candidate is the only known tiques I do provide are “deeply flawed.” cause of the effect in question.
    [Show full text]
  • Arguments from Design
    Arguments from Design: A Self-defeating Strategy? Victoria S. Harrison University of Glasgow This is an archived version of ‘Arguments form Design: A Self-defeating Strategy?’, published in Philosophia 33 (2005): 297–317. Dr V. Harrison Department of Philosophy 69 Oakfield Avenue University of Glasgow Glasgow G12 8LT Scotland UK E-mail: [email protected] Arguments from Design: A Self-defeating Strategy? Abstract: In this article, after reviewing traditional arguments from design, I consider some more recent versions: the so-called ‘new design arguments’ for the existence of God. These arguments enjoy an apparent advantage over the traditional arguments from design by avoiding some of Hume’s famous criticisms. However, in seeking to render religion and science compatible, it seems that they require a modification not only of our scientific understanding but also of the traditional conception of God. Moreover, there is a key problem with arguments from design that Mill raised to which the new arguments seem no less vulnerable than the older versions. The view that science and religion are complementary has at least one significant advantage over other positions, such as the view that they are in an antagonistic relationship or the view that they are so incommensurable that they are neither complementary nor antagonistic. The advantage is that it aspires to provide a unified worldview that is sensitive to the claims of both science and religion. And surely, such a worldview, if available, would seem to be superior to one in which, say, scientific and religious claims were held despite their obvious contradictions.
    [Show full text]
  • Intelligent Design Creationism and the Constitution
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Washington University St. Louis: Open Scholarship Washington University Law Review Volume 83 Issue 1 2005 Is It Science Yet?: Intelligent Design Creationism and the Constitution Matthew J. Brauer Princeton University Barbara Forrest Southeastern Louisiana University Steven G. Gey Florida State University Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_lawreview Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, Education Law Commons, First Amendment Commons, Religion Law Commons, and the Science and Technology Law Commons Recommended Citation Matthew J. Brauer, Barbara Forrest, and Steven G. Gey, Is It Science Yet?: Intelligent Design Creationism and the Constitution, 83 WASH. U. L. Q. 1 (2005). Available at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_lawreview/vol83/iss1/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington University Law Review by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Washington University Law Quarterly VOLUME 83 NUMBER 1 2005 IS IT SCIENCE YET?: INTELLIGENT DESIGN CREATIONISM AND THE CONSTITUTION MATTHEW J. BRAUER BARBARA FORREST STEVEN G. GEY* TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT ................................................................................................... 3 INTRODUCTION..................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Evidence for Design in Physics and Biology: from the Origin of the Universe to the Origin of Life
    52 stephen c. meyer Pages 53–111 of Science and Evidence for Design in the Universe. The Proceedings of the Wethersfield Institute. Michael Behe, STEPHEN C. MEYER William A. Dembski, and Stephen C. Meyer (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2001. 2000 Homeland Foundation.) EVIDENCE FOR DESIGN IN PHYSICS AND BIOLOGY: FROM THE ORIGIN OF THE UNIVERSE TO THE ORIGIN OF LIFE 1. Introduction In the preceding essay, mathematician and probability theo- rist William Dembski notes that human beings often detect the prior activity of rational agents in the effects they leave behind.¹ Archaeologists assume, for example, that rational agents pro- duced the inscriptions on the Rosetta Stone; insurance fraud investigators detect certain ‘‘cheating patterns’’ that suggest intentional manipulation of circumstances rather than ‘‘natu- ral’’ disasters; and cryptographers distinguish between random signals and those that carry encoded messages. More importantly, Dembski’s work establishes the criteria by which we can recognize the effects of rational agents and distinguish them from the effects of natural causes. In brief, he shows that systems or sequences that are both ‘‘highly com- plex’’ (or very improbable) and ‘‘specified’’ are always produced by intelligent agents rather than by chance and/or physical- chemical laws. Complex sequences exhibit an irregular and improbable arrangement that defies expression by a simple formula or algorithm. A specification, on the other hand, is a match or correspondence between an event or object and an independently given pattern or set of functional requirements. As an illustration of the concepts of complexity and speci- fication, consider the following three sets of symbols: 53 54 stephen c.
    [Show full text]
  • Irreducible Complexity (IC) Has Played a Pivotal Role in the Resurgence of the Creationist Movement Over the Past Two Decades
    Irreducible incoherence and Intelligent Design: a look into the conceptual toolbox of a pseudoscience Abstract The concept of Irreducible Complexity (IC) has played a pivotal role in the resurgence of the creationist movement over the past two decades. Evolutionary biologists and philosophers have unambiguously rejected the purported demonstration of “intelligent design” in nature, but there have been several, apparently contradictory, lines of criticism. We argue that this is in fact due to Michael Behe’s own incoherent definition and use of IC. This paper offers an analysis of several equivocations inherent in the concept of Irreducible Complexity and discusses the way in which advocates of the Intelligent Design Creationism (IDC) have conveniently turned IC into a moving target. An analysis of these rhetorical strategies helps us to understand why IC has gained such prominence in the IDC movement, and why, despite its complete lack of scientific merits, it has even convinced some knowledgeable persons of the impending demise of evolutionary theory. Introduction UNTIL ITS DRAMATIC legal defeat in the Kitzmiller v. Dover case, Intelligent Design Creationism (IDC) had been one of the most successful pseudosciences of the past two decades, at least when measured in terms of cultural influence. It is interesting to explore the way this species of creationism had achieved this success, notwithstanding its periodic strategic setbacks as well as its complete lack of scientific merits. Of course, a full explanation would include religious, socio-political, and historical reasons; instead, in this paper, we will take a closer look at the conceptual toolbox and rhetorical strategies of the ID creationist.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution, Creationism, and Intelligent Design Discussion Assignment 3
    Evolution, Creationism, and Intelligent Design Discussion Assignment 3 Is evolution a science? Is intelligent design based on a scientific theory? What about Creationism? Why are these concepts so controversial? This case study will help you understand the basic differences among these theories. 1. What is Evolution? Evolution can be a difficult concept for people to come to terms with, especially if they do not have much experience with life sciences. Is evolution a fact or a theory? Or is it both? Does evolution explain the origin of life or not? These are important questions which people need to be able to understand and answer. Unfortunately, there are too many examples of people who don't understand any of these theories and no criticism will be valid when it proceeds from gross misrepresentations of the facts. It is important to remember that evolution is not a minor matter - it is, in fact, the cornerstone of all modern biology. Please review your textbook and the information in this case study for more information about evolution. 2. What is Creationism? Like evolution, creationism can have more than one meaning. At its most basic, creationism is the belief that the universe was created by a deity of some sort; after that, there is quite a lot of variety among creationists as to just what they believe and why. People may lump all creationists together in one group, but it is important to understand where they differ in their ideas and theology because they can make very different critiques of evolution. You yourself won't be able to adequately respond to creationist arguments or offer counter- arguments unless you understand what sort of creationism you're dealing with.
    [Show full text]
  • Specified Complexity
    Reading Guide 12 Specified complexity For this class, we are reading Dembski [1998], Meyer [2009, pp. 215{224], and Stenger [2007], all of which are available on the class website. In the first of these readings, Dembski introduces his idea of \specified complexity," and explains how he uses it to draw inferences about intelligent design. He does not provide an application, however. For that, we go to the chapter by Meyer. Finally, Stenger's article provides a critique of these ideas. 12.1 Dembski [1998]: Science and design 1. What does Dembski mean by complexity? By specification? 2. Dembski agrees that if selection operates with reference to a goal, then it can produce specified complexity. But natural selection has no goal, and for this reason cannot generate specified complexity. Would you agree? Why or why not? 12.2 Meyer [2009, pp. 215{224]: Beyond the reach of chance Meyer considers the probability that a particular protein, consisting of 150 amino acids, might evolve by random chance. There are 20 kinds of amino acid, so the number of possible proteins of this length is 150 times z }| { 20 × 20 × · · · × 20 = 20150 ≈ 10195: In an apparent typo, Meyer puts this number at 10164. No matter|you end up with the same conclusion either way. 1. Let us assume that Meyer is right about the three constants|1080, 1017, and 1043. Does the product, 10140 of these three seem like a sensible upper bound on the number of events that have ever happened in the history of the universe? 2. Let's also accept that there are 10164 possible proteins of length 150.
    [Show full text]
  • William A. Dembski, “The Logical Underpinnings of Intelligent Design,”
    Debating Design From Darwin to DNA Edited by WILLIAM A. DEMBSKI Baylor University MICHAEL RUSE Florida State University CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE Contents The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia Ruiz de Alarcon 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org © Cambridge University Press 2004 Notfs on Contributors page vii This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, INTRODUCTION no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. I. General Introduction 3 William A. Dembski and Michael Ruse First published 2004 2. The Argument from Design: A Brief History 13 Printed in the United States of America Michael Ruse :t Who's Afraid of ID? A Survey of the Intelligent Design TypefaceITC New Baskerville 10/12 pt. SystemIMEX 2s [TB] Movement 32 A catalogrecord for this bookis availablefrom the British Library. Angus Menuge Library of CongressCatalogi,ng in Publication data available PART I: DARWINISM 1. Design without Designer: Darwin's Greatest Discovery 55 ISBN O 521 82949 6 hardback FranciscoJ Ayal,a :>.The Flagellum Unspun: The Collapse of "Irreducible Complexity" 81 Kenneth R. Miller Ii. The Design Argument 98 Elliott Sober 7. DNA by Design? Stephen Meyer and the Return of the God Hypothesis 130 Robert T.
    [Show full text]
  • Meyer, Stephen C
    DNA BY DESIGN: AN INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION FOR THE ORIGIN OF BIOLOGICAL INFORMATION STEPHEN C. MEYER INTRODUCTION n the second chapter of Philosophy and Biology,Elliott Sober warns historians I and philosophers of biology against the danger of anachronism. In particular, he notes that many contemporary evolutionary biologists regard the design hypothe- sis as inherently untestable and, therefore, unscientific in principle, simply because it no longer commands scientific assent. He notes that while logically unbeatable versions of the design hypothesis have been formulated (involving, for example, a “trickster God” who creates a world that appears undesigned), design hypotheses in general need not assume an untestable character. A design hypothesis could, he argues, be formulated as a fully scientific “inference to the best explanation.” He notes that scientists often evaluate the explanatory power of a “hypothesis by test- ing it against one or more competing hypotheses.”1 On these grounds, he notes that William Paley’s version of the design hypothesis was manifestly testable, but was rejected precisely because it could not explain the relevant evidence of then con- temporary biology as well as the fully naturalistic theory of Charles Darwin. Sober then casts his lot with the neo-Darwinian explanation on evidential rather than methodological grounds. But the possibility remains, he argues, that there is some other version of the design hypothesis that both disagrees with the hypothesis of evolution and also is a more likely explanation of what we observe. No one, to my knowledge, has developed such a version of the design hypothesis. But this does not mean that no one ever will.2 This paper will develop a design hypothesis, not as an explanation for the origin of species, but as an explanation for the origin of the information required to make a living system in the first place.
    [Show full text]
  • Emergence, Intelligent Design, and Artificial Intelligence
    Emergence, Intelligent Design, and Artificial Intelligence Eric Scott, Andrews University 23 February, 2011 Abstract We consider the implications of emergent complexity and compu- tational simulations for the Intelligent Design movement. We discuss genetic variation and natural selection as an optimization process, and equate irreducible complexity as defined by William Dembski with the problem of local optima. We disregard the argument that method- ological naturalism bars science from investigating design hypotheses in nature a priori, but conclude that systems with low Kolmogorov complexity but a high apparent complexity, such as the Mandelbrot set, require that such hypotheses be approached with an high degree of skepticism. Finally, we suggest that computer simulations of evolu- tionary processes may be considered a laboratory to test our detailed, mechanistic understandings of evolution. 1 Introduction \Die allgemeine Form des Satzes ist: Es verh¨altsich so und so." { Das ist ein Satz von jener Art, die man sich unz¨ahlige Male wiederholt. Man glaubt, wieder and wieder der Natur nachz- ufahren, und f¨ahrtnur der Form entlang, durch die wir sie betra- chten. \The general form of propositions is: This is how things are." { That is the kind of proposition one repeats to himself countless times. One thinks that one is tracing nature over and over again, and one is merely tracing round the frame through which we look at it. { Ludwig Wittgenstein1 The origin of life's immense complexity and adaptability is tantalizing in at least two respects: 1) We want to understand where we and our world came from, and 2) We want to imitate nature in our engineering projects.
    [Show full text]
  • The College Student's Back to School Guide to Intelligent Design
    Revised November, 2014 Part I: Letter of Introduction: Why this Student’s Guide? Part II: What is Intelligent Design? Part III: Answers to Your Professors’ 10 Most Common Misinformed Objections to Intelligent Design (1) Intelligent Design is Not Science (2) Intelligent Design is just a Negative Argument against Evolution (3) Intelligent Design Rejects All of Evolutionary Biology (4) Intelligent Design was Banned from Schools by the U.S. Supreme Court (5) Intelligent Design is Just Politics (6) Intelligent Design is a Science Stopper (7) Intelligent Design is “Creationism” and Based on Religion (8) Intelligent Design is Religiously Motivated (9) Intelligent Design Proponents Don’t Conduct or Publish Scientific Research (10) Intelligent Design is Refuted by the Overwhelming Evidence for Neo-Darwinian Evolution Part IV: Information About the Discovery Institute’s Summer Seminars on Intelligent Design COPYRIGHT © DISCOVERY INSTITUTE, 2014 — WWW.INTELLIGENTDESIGN.ORG PERMISSION GRANTED TO COPY AND DISTRIBUTE FOR NONPROFIT EDUCATIONAL PURPOSES. 2 Part I: Letter of Introduction: Why this Student’s Guide? Welcome to College, Goodbye to Intelligent Design? The famous Pink Floyd song that laments, “We don’t need no education / We don’t need no thought control,” is not just the rant of a rebellious mind; it is also a commentary on the failure of education to teach students how to think critically and evaluate both sides of controversial issues. Few scientists understood the importance of critical thinking better than Charles Darwin. When he first proposed his theory of evolution in Origin of Species in 1859, Darwin faced intense intellectual opposition from both the scientific community and the culture of his day.
    [Show full text]
  • An Overview of Intelligent Design Theory a Young-Earth Creationist Once Told Me That He Took the Genesis Account of the Creation
    AN OVERVIEW OF INTELLIGENT DESIGN THEORY David P. Johnson—Department of Mechanical Engineering young-earth creationist once told me that he took the Genesis A account of the creation as literal historical fact: the universe is about 6000 years old and was created in about 4000 B.C. I asked him about evidences of a much older earth and universe: radiometric dating, geological dating, astronometric dating. In his opinion, there are flaws in all of these techniques which render them unreliable. In fact, he thought there was a vast conspiracy in the scientific community hiding the fact that earth and its surrounds were created by God. I hope this article is not perceived like that. My intent is to add to My intent is to add the conversation about evolution’s implications and possible limitations. to the conversation Observation leads me to accept evolution in the physical world; I accept theology on faith. I believe that these two positions are compatible. about evolution’s Intelligent design (ID) theory of late adds context to this belief. Since many implications and of the observations of the ID community draw heavily on engineering and computer science, my background in engineering permits me an possible limitations. interesting perspective from which to review material coming from ID. Perhaps the biggest reason I want to add to this conversation is what I see happening to the public view of science. As I discussed in my previous paper (Perspective, Volume 6 Number 2), the American public tell pollsters in overwhelming majorities that they believe in some form of creation.
    [Show full text]