Syllabus for NEH Institute David Hume in the 21St Century: Perpetuating the Enlightenment July 11 – August 5, 2022

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Syllabus for NEH Institute David Hume in the 21St Century: Perpetuating the Enlightenment July 11 – August 5, 2022 Syllabus for NEH Institute David Hume in the 21st Century: Perpetuating the Enlightenment July 11 – August 5, 2022 Schedule of Topics, Speakers, and Readings (subject to change) ____________________________________________________________________________________________________ Abbreviated references to Hume’s writings: Treatise = A Treatise of Human Nature (followed by Book, Part, section #) EPM = Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (followed by Part, section #) EHU = Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (followed by Part, section #) Essays = Essays: Moral, Political, Literary History = History of England DCNR = Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion Access to most readings will be provided electronically. Editions of Hume’s works are readily available, including online. For instance, the website davidhume.org has acceptable editions of all of Hume’s works. (The Oxford Critical Editions of the Treatise, EPM, EHU, and DCNR are now generally considered the standard editions.) Formal sessions each day will begin at 9 am and end at noon, with a brief break. We will have opportunities for small group meetings in the afternoons to discuss pedagogy or to meet with guest faculty on topics of special interest. Afternoon participation is optional. ______________________________________________________________________________________________________ Sat-Sun July 9-10 Check in on campus – Information to come July 10 Welcoming social – Information to come _____________________________________________________________________________________________________ Week 1 Hume’s Naturalism and Skepticism / Hume on the Mind Mon-Tues July 11-12 Introduction and welcome (Co-directors Angela Coventry and Elizabeth Radcliffe) Naturalism and Skepticism (Don Garrett, NYU) Evidence and the Correction of Skeptical Doubts: Hume writes in An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding that the “undistinguished doubts" of 2 "excessive skepticism ... are, in some measure, corrected by common sense and reflection.” How, within Hume's epistemology of evidence, does this correction occur? How does it allow Hume to combine mitigated skepticism with naturalism? Readings: 1. Hume, EHU: Sections 4-6, and 12 2. Hume, Treatise: 1.1.3.1-2, 1.3.7.3, 1.3.8.11-12, 1.3.10.11-12, 1.3.13.1-3, 1.3.13.9, 1.4.2.41, 1.4.5.30, 1.4.7.7, 3.3.1.14-18 3. Reid, Thomas. Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man: Essay II, Chapter 20 Supplemental Readings: 1. Hume, EHU: Section 10 2. Hume, DCNR: Part 1 3. Garrett, Don. Hume (Routledge 2015): Chapters 4-5 Weds-Thurs July 13-14 Naturalism and Skepticism (Paul Russell, UBC and Lund) Hume’s irreligious views in the context of his naturalism and his skepticism Readings: 1. Hume's Treatise / Hobbes's Leviathan 2. Paul Russell, Riddle of Hume's Treatise (2008), esp. Chs. 1-6, 17-20. 3. Paul Russell, "Hume's Philosophy of Irreligion and the Myth of British Empiricism", in P. Russell, ed. Oxford Handbook of David Hume (2016). 4. Paul Russell (and Anders Kraal), “Hume on Religion,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hume-religion/ Fri July 15 Hume on Space, Time and Passions (Angela Coventry, Portland State) Hume’s treatment of space and time is examined, particularly in relation to the passions. Readings: Hume, Treatise 1.1-2 and 2.3.7-8 Supplemental Readings: 1. Lorne Falkenstein, “Hume on Manners of Disposition and the Ideas of Space and Time.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79 (2). 1997: 179-201. 2. Marina Frasca-Spada, Space and the Self in Hume's Treatise, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998, especially Chapters 1-2 3 3. Donald Baxter, “Hume on Space and Time,” In Paul Russell (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of David Hume, Oxford: Oxford University Press USA, 2014. 4. Don Garrett, Hume, Routledge, 2015, chapter 2 5. Jonathan Cottrell, “Hume on Space and Time: A Limited Defense,” in Angela M. Coventry and Alexander Sager (eds), The Humean Mind, New York: Routledge, 2019 _____________________________________________________________________________________________________ Week 2 Moral Psychology / Morality and Society / Economics Mon July 18 Hume’s Moral Psychology (Elizabeth Radcliffe, William & Mary) Hume’s theory of the passions and reason as background to his moral theory: How does Hume’s theory differ from other early modern theories of the passions? What are the respective roles of passion and reason in producing action? Does Hume think there is any way of moderating the passions, given that he argues that reason cannot do it? Finally, what is the role of passion in moral judgment and in moral agency? Readings: 1. Hume, T 2.3, 3.1 2. Hume, EPM Part 1, Appendix 1 Supplemental Readings: 1. Rachel Cohon, Hume’s Morality (Oxford University Press 2008), Chaps. 3-4. 2. P.J.E. Kail, Projection and Realism in Hume’s Philosophy (OUP 2007), Chap 8. 3. Elizabeth Radcliffe, Hume, Passion, and Action (OUP, 2018), Introduction, Chaps. 2 & 6. Tues July 19 Hume on Morality (Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, UNC Chapel Hill) Hume and taking up “the general point of view” in moral judgment; how this point of view connects with the natural virtues, such as gratitude and benevolence. Readings: 1. Hume, Treatise 3.1.1-2, 3.3.1, 3.3.3-5 2. Sayre-McCord, “On Why Hume’s ‘General Point of View’ Isn’t Ideal -- and Shouldn’t Be,” in Social Philosophy & Policy, volume 11, number 1 (Winter 1994), pp. 202-228. 3. Sayre-McCord, “Hume and Smith on Sympathy, Approbation, and Moral Judgment,” in Social Philosophy and Policy, 2013, vol. 30, #1-2, pp. 208-236. 4 Weds July 20 Hume on Society (Geoffrey Sayre-McCord) The general point of view and artificial virtues such as honesty and justice. Readings: 1. Hume, Treatise 3.2.1-6 2. Sayre-McCord, "Hume and the Bauhaus Theory of Ethics,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. XX (University of Notre Dame Press, 1996), pp. 280-298. 3. Sayre-McCord, “Hume on the Artificial Virtues,” in the Oxford Handbook of David Hume, edited by Paul Russell (Oxford University Press, 2016), pp. 435- 469. Thurs-Fri July 21-22 Hume’s Economics (Margaret Schabas, University of British Columbia) A study of Hume’s key texts on economic theory, including his essays on money, the interest rate, and trade; Hume’s efforts to forge policies on public finance; Hume’s vision for economic prosperity, both national and global. Readings: 1. From the Liberty On-line text of Hume’s Essays (pp. 253-365): “Of Commerce,” Of Refinement in the Arts,” “Of Money,” “Of Interest,” “Of the Balance of Trade,” “Of the Jealousy of Trade,” “Of Taxes,” and “Of Public Credit.” 2. Margaret Schabas and Carl Wennerlind, “Hume on Money, Commerce, and the Science of Economics,” Journal of Economic Perspectives 25.3 (Summer 2011): 217-30. Supplemental Readings: 1. Margaret Schabas, “’Let Your Science Be Human’: David Hume and the Honourable Merchant,” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 21.6 (December 2014): 977 - 990. 2. Margaret Schabas, “Hume on Economic Well-Being”. Continuum Companion to David Hume. Eds. Alan Bailey and Dan O’Brien. Continuum Press, 2012. Reprinted in paperback as The Bloomsbury Companion to Hume. Bloomsbury, 2015. 332-48. 3. Carl Wennerlind, “David Hume’s Political Philosophy: A Theory of Commercial Modernization,” Hume Studies 28.2 (2002): 247-70. 4. Carl Wennerlind, “David Hume’s Monetary Theory Revisited: Was He Really a Quantity Theorist and an Inflationist?” Journal of Political Economy. February 2005. Vol. 113. No. 1: 223-37. 5 ______________________________________________________________________________________________________ Week 3 Hume the Historian / Non-Western Philosophy / Race Mon July 25 David Hume, the Historian (Mark Spencer, Brock) An introduction to Hume’s monumental work, A History of England. Readings: 1. Selections from Hume’s History of England, ed. by William Todd (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1983): • Vol. V, Section on “The king’s [Charles I] trial – And execution – And character,” pp. 535-48. • Vol. V, “Appendix to the Reign of James I,” pp. 124-55. • Vol. VI, Section on “Manners, arts and science,” pp. 530-45. • Vol. IV, “Appendix III [to the Reign of Elizabeth],” pp. 354-86. 2. Mark G. Spencer, “Hume the Historian,” in Angela M. Coventry and Alexander Sager, eds, The Humean Mind (New York: Routledge, 2019), pp. 287-99. Supplemental Reading: Mark G. Spencer, “Was David Hume, the Historian, a Plagiarist? A Submission from His History of England,” CLIO: A Journal of Literature, History, and the Philosophy of History, Vol. 47, Issue 1 (2019), pp. 25-50. Tues July 26 David Hume, the Historian, cont. (Mark Spencer) Readings: 1. Selections from Hume’s History of England, ed. by William Todd (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1983): • Vol. I, “Appendix I: The Anglo-Saxon Government and Manners,” pp. 160-85. • Vol. I, “Appendix II: The Feudal and Anglo-Norman Government and Manners,” pp. 455-88. • Vol. II, Last paragraphs that Hume writes for his History, pp. 518-25. 2. E. C. Mossner, “Hume as Literary Patron: A Suppressed Review of Robert Henry’s ‘History of Great Britain,’ 1773,” Modern Philology, Vol. 39, No. 4 (1942), pp. 361-82. 3. F. L. van Holthoon, “Hume and the End of History,” in Mark G. Spencer, ed. David Hume: Historical Thinker, Historical Writer (University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 2013), pp. 143-62. 6 Supplemental Reading: Roger L. Emerson and Mark G. Spencer, “A Bibliography for Hume’s History of England: A Preliminary View,” Hume Studies, Vol. 40, No. 1 (Apr. 2014), 53-71. Weds-Thurs July 27-28 Hume and Non-Western Philosophy (Jay Garfield, Smith and Harvard) Homologies between Hume’s Indian Mādhyamikas’ treatment of custom, the self, and ethical cultivation. Readings: 1. Selections from Garfield, The Concealed Influence of Custom: Hume's Treatise from the Inside Out. 2. Garfield, “Hume as a Western Mādhyamika,” in G Davis, ed., Ethics Without Self; Dharma Without Atman: Western and Buddhist Philosophical Traditions in Dialogue. London: Routledge. (2018), pp. 131-144.
Recommended publications
  • Medieval Western Philosophy: the European Emergence
    Cultural Heritage and Contemporary Change Series I, Culture and Values, Volume 9 History of Western Philosophy by George F. McLean and Patrick J. Aspell Medieval Western Philosophy: The European Emergence By Patrick J. Aspell The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy 1 Copyright © 1999 by The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy Gibbons Hall B-20 620 Michigan Avenue, NE Washington, D.C. 20064 All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Aspell, Patrick, J. Medieval western philosophy: the European emergence / Patrick J. Aspell. p.cm. — (Cultural heritage and contemporary change. Series I. Culture and values ; vol. 9) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Philosophy, Medieval. I. Title. III. Series. B721.A87 1997 97-20069 320.9171’7’090495—dc21 CIP ISBN 1-56518-094-1 (pbk.) 2 Table of Contents Chronology of Events and Persons Significant in and beyond the History of Medieval Europe Preface xiii Part One: The Origins of Medieval Philosophy 1 Chapter I. Augustine: The Lover of Truth 5 Chapter II. Universals According to Boethius, Peter Abelard, and Other Dialecticians 57 Chapter III. Christian Neoplatoists: John Scotus Erigena and Anselm of Canterbury 73 Part Two: The Maturity of Medieval Philosophy Chronology 97 Chapter IV. Bonaventure: Philosopher of the Exemplar 101 Chapter V. Thomas Aquinas: Philosopher of the Existential Act 155 Part Three: Critical Reflection And Reconstruction 237 Chapter VI. John Duns Scotus: Metaphysician of Essence 243 Chapter
    [Show full text]
  • Western Philosophy Rev
    Designed by John Cornet, Phoenix HS (Ore) Western Philosophy rev. September 2012 The very process of philosophy has been a driving force in the tranformation of the world. From the figure who dwells upon how to achieve power, to the minister who contemplates the paradox of the only truth (their faith) yet which is also stagnent, to the astronomers who are searching the stars for signs of other civilizations, to the revolutionaries who sought to construct a national government which would protect the rights of the minority, the very exercise of philosophy and philosophical thought is at a core of human nature. Philosophy addresses what are sometimes called the "big questions." These include questions of morality and ethics, ideology/faith,, politics, the truth of knowledge, the nature of reality, and the meaning of human existance (...just to name a few!) (Religion addresses some of the same questions, but while philosophy and religion overlap in some questions, they can and do differ significantly in the approach they take to answering them.) Subject Learning Outcomes Skills-Based Learning Outcomes Behavioral Expectations and Grading Policy Develop an appreciation for and enjoyment of Organize, maintain and learn how to study from a learning, particularly in how learning should subject-specific notebook Attendance, participation and cause us to question what we think we know Be able to demonstrate how to take notes (including being prepared are daily and have a willingness to entertain new utilizing two-column format) expectations perspectives on issues. Be able to engage in meaningful, substantive discussion A classroom culture of respect and Students will develop familiarity with major with others.
    [Show full text]
  • St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death
    The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Williams Honors College, Honors Research The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors Projects College Spring 2020 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death Christopher Choma [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects Part of the Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, European History Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Please take a moment to share how this work helps you through this survey. Your feedback will be important as we plan further development of our repository. Recommended Citation Choma, Christopher, "St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death" (2020). Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects. 1048. https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects/1048 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College at IdeaExchange@UAkron, the institutional repository of The University of Akron in Akron, Ohio, USA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects by an authorized administrator of IdeaExchange@UAkron. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. 1 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death By: Christopher Choma Sponsored by: Dr. Joseph Li Vecchi Readers: Dr. Howard Ducharme Dr. Nathan Blackerby 2 Table of Contents Introduction p. 4 Section One: Three General Views of Human Nature p.
    [Show full text]
  • Feng Youlan's Interpretation of Western Philosophy
    ASIANetwork Exchange | Fall 2014 | volume 22 | 1 Feng Youlan’s Interpretation of Western Philosophy: A Critical Examination from the Perspective of Metaphysical Methodology Derong Chen Abstract: This paper concentrates on Feng’s interpretation of Western philosophy from the perspective of metaphysical methodology and aims to display a limited observation of Feng’s interpretation of Western philosophy through the window of metaphysical methodology. Based on a brief review of the recent studies of Feng Youlan and Western philoso- phy, this paper analyzes the progress and insufficient aspects in current studies on this issue and particularly clarifies what are the metaphysics and metaphysical methods in the context of Feng Youlan’s philosophy. In clarifying Feng’s interpreta- tion of Western philosophy from the perspective of methodology, this paper further critically analyzes Feng’s positive metaphysical methods and negative metaphysical methods, and assumes that Feng’s negative metaphysical methods essentially is a kind of attitude towards metaphysics but neither a kind of metaphysics nor a kind of metaphysical methods. Instead of characterizing metaphysical methods as positive and negative as Feng did, this paper suggests an alternative division of metaphysical methods: direct and indirect methods of dealing with metaphysical issues. Keywords Feng Youlan; metaphysics; metaphysical methods; Western philosophy; negative metaphysics In the twentieth century, Feng Youlan was one of the Chinese intellectuals most deeply Derong Chen is a Sessional involved in the dialogue and interaction between Chinese and Western philosophies. In Lecturer II at the University of addition to studying Western philosophy at Columbia University, he systematically con- Toronto Mississauga. ducted research on Western philosophy, specifically the philosophy of life.
    [Show full text]
  • Norton Anthology of Western Philosophy: After Kant Table of Contents
    NORTON ANTHOLOGY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY: AFTER KANT TABLE OF CONTENTS Volume 1: The Interpretive Tradition Preface Acknowledgments GENERAL INTRODUCTION PROLOGUE Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) "What is Enlightenment?" (Translated by Lewis White Beck) From Critique of Pure Reason, Preface (Translated by Norman Kemp Smith) From Critique of Practical Reason, Conclusion (Translated by Lewis White Beck) I. IDEALISMS: SPIRITUALITY AND REALITY Introduction Friedrich Schiller (1759–1805) From On the Aesthetic Education of Man Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814) From Science of Knowledge (Translated by Peter Heath and John Lachs) From Vocation of Man (Translated by William Smith) Friedrich Schelling (1775–1854) From Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature (Translated by Errol E. Harris and Peter Heath) From Of Human Freedom (Translated by James Gutmann) Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) Introductions On Philosophy: From The Encyclopedia of Philosophical [Wissenschaften] (Translated by William Wallace) On Philosophy and “Phenomenology”: From Phenomenology of [Geist] (Translated by J. B. Baillie) On Philosophical “Logic”: From The [Wissenschaft] of Logic (Encyclopedia, part 1) (Translated by William Wallace) On Nature: From Philosophy of Nature (Encyclopedia, part 2) (Translated by A. V. Miller) On the History of Philosophy: From Lectures on the History of Philosophy (Translated by E. S. Haldane) On History and Geist: From Lectures on the Philosophy of History (Translated by J. Sibree) On Geist: From Philosophy of [Geist] (Encyclopedia, part 3) (Translated by William Wallace and A. V. Miller) Subjective Geist 2 On Subjective (and Intersubjective) Geist: From Philosophy of [Geist] (Translated by William Wallace and A. V. Miller) On Consciousness and Self-Consciousness: From Phenomenology of [Geist] (Translated by J.
    [Show full text]
  • The Postmodern Retrieval of Neoplatonism in Jean-Luc Marion
    The Postmodern Retrieval of Neoplatonism in Jean-Luc Marion and John Milbank and the Origins of Western Subjectivity in Augustine and Eriugena Hermathena, 165 (Winter, 1998), 9-70. Neoplatonism commanded important scholarly energy and poetic and literary talent in the later two-thirds of our century. Now it attracts considerable philosophical and theological interest. But this may be its misfortune. The Dominican scholar M.-D. Chenu judged the Leonine utilization of St. Thomas to have been detrimental for our understanding of his doctrine. Thomas was made an instrument of an imperialist Christianity. The use of Aquinas as a weapon against modernity required a “misérable abus.” The Holy Office made Fr. Chenu pay dearly enough for attempting accurate historical study of the Fathers and medieval doctors to make us give him heed.1 The present retrieval of our philosophical and theological past has a very different relation to institutional interests than belonged to Leonine Neothomism. The problems intellectuals now have with truthfulness come more from within themselves than from outside. There is, nonetheless, much in the character of the postmodern turn to Neoplatonism by Christian theologians to cause concern that the ecclesiastical subordination of theoria to praxis which distorted the most recent Thomism may have an analogue for Neoplatonism recovered to serve our desires.2 And if, in fact, our eye has become self-distorting, the problem in our relation to our history will be worse than anything external pressures can cause. This paper aims to begin assessing the character of this distortion in respect to a central question, our understanding of the history of western subjectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • Department of Philosophy, CC 4, History of Western Philosophy
    Department of Philosophy, CC 4, History of Western Philosophy. David Hume (1711 - 1776) Impressions and Ideas. The epistemological project of John Locke, questioning the validity of metaphysical claims, is perceived to attain logical finality in the mitigated skepticism of David Hume. Hume is a foundationalist. He asserts that all knowledge claims are rooted in sense experience. If the cognitive faculties are allowed to function unimpeded by passions and background assumptions, objective truth will be achieved through sensations without fail. This naive faith is common to all classical empiricism and rationalism. Hume divides the contents of mind into impressions and ideas. Impressions, like Lockean simple ideas, are the immediate data of experience, while ideas are images, based on impressions. The rigorous empiricism of Hume consists in his assertion that knowledge is derivative from impressions alone. Ideas are faint copies of impressions. His slogan, no ideas without impressions, is a token of his uncompromising empiricism. The slogan precludes the possibility of acquiring any idea, not grounded in sensation or impression. As metaphysical propositions or ideas, like the idea of substance or of necessary connection, are not derivable from impressions of sense (or analytic reason ), any theory of occult substance or an entailment theory of causation are instances of sophistry and illusion , liable to be thrown into flame. This is the epoch making stance of Hume, instrumental in the genesis of Kantian critical philosophy. The distinction between impressions and ideas is quantitative. When the knower looks at a room, she acquires impressions of the room. When she closes her eyes and contemplates about the room, she has ideas of the room.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoplatonism and Paramadvaita
    Comparative Philosophy Volume 4, No. 2 (2013): xxx-xxx Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org NEOPLATONISM AND PARAMĀDVAITA MICHAL JUST ABSTRACT: There has long been a debate on the possible similarity between some forms of Indian and Greek idealistic monism (Advaita and Neoplatonism). After a basic historical introduction to the debate, the text proposes that Paramādvaita, also known as Kashmiri Shaivism, is a more suitable comparandum for Neoplatonism than any other form of Advaita, suggested in the debate. Paramādvaita’s dynamic view of reality summarized in the terms prakāśa-vimarśa or unmeṣa-nimeṣa, corresponds quite precisely to the viewpoint of Neoplatonism, summarized in the similar bipolar terms such as prohodos-epistrophe. The context of the dynamic nature of reality doctrine is also quite similar (svataḥsiddhatva, authypostasis). My arguments are based on the texts of Plotinus and Proclus (Neoplatonism) and the texts of Abhinavagupta, Utpaladeva and Kṣemarāja (Paramādvaita). Several parallel doctrines of both systems are further discussed: the doctrine of creative multilevel subjectivity, the doctrine of mutual omnipresence of all in all, the doctrine of creative multilevel speech, and some corresponding doctrines on aesthetic beauty and its important role in the Soul’s return towards its ultimate source. Some implications of the high degree of correspondence between both systems are considered at the end of the paper, for instance whether some similarities of compared systems might be explained on a structural
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 11-30-2007 Between Being and Nothingness: The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil Brian Keith Kooy Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Kooy, Brian Keith, "Between Being and Nothingness: The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2007. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/32 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BETWEEN BEING AND NOTHINGNESS: THE METAPHYSICAL FOUNDATIONS UNDERLYING AUGUSTINE’S SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF EVIL by BRIAN KEITH KOOY Under the Direction of Dr. Timothy M. Renick ABSTRACT Several commentators make the claim that Augustine is not a systematic thinker. The purpose of this thesis is to refute that claim in one specific area of Augustine's thought, the metaphysical foundations underlying his solutions to the problem of evil. Through an exegetical examination of various works in which Augustine writes on evil, I show that his solutions for both natural and moral evil rely on a coherent metaphysical system,
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Theory of Free Will
    ISSN 1923-1555[Print] Studies in Literature and Language ISSN 1923-1563[Online] Vol. 11, No. 5, 2015, pp. 41-44 www.cscanada.net DOI:10.3968/7800 www.cscanada.org Augustine’s Theory of Free Will LONG Bo[a],*; FENG Fei[a] [a]School of Political Science and Public Administration, Southwest influenced by the Greek skepticism. Later on reading University, Chongqing, China. the works of Platon, since then, the new Platon doctrine *Corresponding author. philosophy has an indelible impact on his mind. Received 24 August 2015; accepted 19 October 2015 In 386 AD, Augustine came to Milan to visit Published online 26 November 2015 Ambrose. In Milan, the most important event in the life of Augustine’s mind. In the story of a Christian friends Abstract casually from San Antonio to recognize the letter, and two Augustine is a master of ancient Christian patristic Roman officials because occasionally read Anthony deeds thought, is regarded as one of the four early Christian from dedicated to serve the Lord anecdotes, Augustine fathers. Free will be a problem in the traditional western heard and violent vibration. After the guests left, philosophy. Augustine by thinking of free will, expounds Augustine toward the garden, feel an upsurge of emotion, the origin of evil, uplifts the subjective initiative of confusion, suddenly listen to next door children sing “take human being. However, in his later years, Augustine has up a book and read it, pick up the book to read.” However restricted the early free will theory, and completely falls he never heard the song, he hurried back to the garden just into God determinism.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine of Hippo: a Historical Theology Critique
    Olivet Nazarene University Digital Commons @ Olivet Honors Program Projects Honors Program Spring 5-2021 Augustine of Hippo: A Historical Theology Critique Zachary Monte Olivet Nazarene University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.olivet.edu/honr_proj Part of the Applied Ethics Commons, Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, History of Christianity Commons, History of Religions of Western Origin Commons, Liturgy and Worship Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Missions and World Christianity Commons, Other Anthropology Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, Political Theory Commons, Practical Theology Commons, Religious Education Commons, Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons, and the Rhetoric Commons Recommended Citation Monte, Zachary, "Augustine of Hippo: A Historical Theology Critique" (2021). Honors Program Projects. 122. https://digitalcommons.olivet.edu/honr_proj/122 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Honors Program at Digital Commons @ Olivet. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Program Projects by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Olivet. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Monte ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank the Olivet Honors Program Faculty for their investment in my academic career. I especially thank Dr. Mark Frisius for his patience and oversight of this research. I would also like to thank my lovely fiancée, Hannah Lewis, for all her support through this season of life. Most of all, I would like to thank my parents for sacrificing as much as needed for my development into a minister and a scholar. Monte iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Renegade Ockham
    Reshaping the Concept of Substance: The Renegade Ockham HANS KRAML, INNSBRUCK The importance attributed to the concept of substance in the philosophy of the Latin Middle Ages may sometimes be exaggerated in retrospect. Sub- stance is of crucial importance in the philosophies of Spinoza and John Locke, for instance, much later in history. Nevertheless, the importance given to substance in some philosophical movements is part of the medie- val heritage up to our days. This, on the other hand, is a reaction to the ne- glect of the concept of substance in the Aristotelian sense within the tradi- tion of modern natural sciences. The modern sciences as we know them developed out of the medieval learning. But the novelty of this type of sci- ence consisted in the definite refusal to answer questions about the essence of anything. The propagators of the new science tried to answer questions like how things influence one another and act upon another. Nobody knows, for instance, what gravity is, but it is well known and generally ac- cepted that two bodies attract or, to say it less metaphorically, move to- wards one another directly proportionally to the product of their masses and indirectly proportionally to the square of their distance. Evidently in a formula of this kind there is nothing said about what gravity is, there is only talk about how it works. The word “gravity” itself does not mean anything beyond the equation given. Gravity is just the ac- celeration in the movement of two bodies towards one another, if no addi- tional force is present, nothing else.
    [Show full text]