3.5 the Atlantis Myth. the Ideal, Fantasy and Critical Commentary – Timaeus and Critias
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
The Chimera of the Philosopher King
Roberto R. Aramayo The Chimera of the Philosopher King Around the Kantian Distinction between Moral Politician and Political Moralist: The Dilemmas of Power, or the Frustrated Love Affair between Ethics and Politics Dialectica Kantiana Hermeneutica Kantiana CTK E-Books Digital Library of Kantian Studies (DLKS) Biblioteca Digital de Estudios Kantianos (BDEK) Series Translatio Kantiana (TK) Quaestiones Kantianae (QK) Hermeneutica Kantiana (HK) Dialectica Kantiana (DK) Esta biblioteca digital se integra en la revista Con-Textos Kantianos International Journal of Philosophy (CKT-IJP) ISSN: 2386-7655 Diseño del logo de la colección CTK E-Books: Armando Menéndez e-mail: [email protected] Página web: www.con-textoskantianos.net © Roberto Rodríguez Aramayo, 2019 © De la traducción, Damián Bravo Zamora, 2019 © CTK E-Books, Ediciones Alamanda, Madrid, 2019 Diseño y maquetación: Nuria Roca ISBN: 978-84-949436-3-8 La edición electrónica de este libro es de acceso abierto y se distribuye bajo los términos de una licencia de uso y distribución Creative Common Attribution (CC BY-NC-ND International 4.0) que permite la descarga de la obra y compartirla con otras personas, siempre que el autor y la fuente sean debidamente citados, pero no se autoriza su uso comercial ni se puede cambiar de ninguna manera. Ediciones Alamanda General Zabala, 5 E-28002 Madrid CTK E-Books▐ Serie Hermeneutica Kantiana Roberto R. Aramayo The Chimera of the Philosopher King Around the Kantian Distinction between Moral Politician and Political Moralist: The Dilemmas of Power, or the Frustrated Love Affair between Ethics and Politics Traducción de Damián Bravo Zamora Índice PREAMBLE .................................................................................. 11 I. THE GYGES SYNDROME ........................................................ -
The Analysis of the Plutarch Political Thought
Advances in Economics, Business and Management Research (AEBMR), volume 23 2017 2nd International Conference on Politics, Economics and Law (ICPEL 2017) The Analysis of the Plutarch Political Thought Ya Feng Shijiazhuang University of Applied Technology Shijiazhuang, China [email protected] Abstract—Plutarch is hailed as a great biographer, moralist, greeks, but Plutarch still could not help but to such a world but not a politician. In his code of ethics, however, politics has praise the Lord, he is "make millions of primitive tribe to the been the most prominent. He thinks the best political system is civilization of the great philosopher." The idea of [4] was the monarchy. He has a low opinion of ordinary people, who obviously influenced by Plato's philosopher-king. But it has to believe that they are ignorant and short-sighted, and that he be clear that the monarchies that Plutarch appreciates must be thinks that democracy is but a government of rabble. He virtuous, moderate and competent. Otherwise, once the king inherited Plato's philosophy that the monarch should be held by has fallen, the monarchy will become a tyrant. The tyrannical a good philosopher. But when Plutarch lived, it was impossible to rule of Plutarch is the same as that of Plato and Aristotle's achieve it, so he proposed that the philosopher should be assisted tyrannical system, which refers to the rule that no king is only by the concept of the monarch. for his subjects. Keywords—Plutarch; Political thought; Democracy; Analysis With regard to "minority rule", Plutarch clearly divided it into "aristocracy" and "oligopoly". -
Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms
Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms Plato's theory of Forms or theory of Ideas[1] [2] [3] asserts that non-material abstract (but substantial) forms (or ideas), and not the material world of change known to us through sensation, possess the highest and most fundamental kind of reality.[4] When used in this sense, the word form is often capitalized.[5] Plato speaks of these entities only through the characters (primarily Socrates) of his dialogues who sometimes suggest that these Forms are the only true objects of study that can provide us with genuine knowledge; thus even apart from the very controversial status of the theory, Plato's own views are much in doubt.[6] Plato spoke of Forms in formulating a possible solution to the problem of universals. Forms Terminology: the Forms and the forms The English word "form" may be used to translate two distinct concepts that concerned Plato—the outward "form" or appearance of something, and "Form" in a new, technical nature, that never ...assumes a form like that of any of the things which enter into her; ... But the forms which enter into and go out of her are the likenesses of real existences modelled after their patterns in a wonderful and inexplicable manner.... The objects that are seen, according to Plato, are not real, but literally mimic the real Forms. In the allegory of the cave expressed in Republic, the things that are ordinarily perceived in the world are characterized as shadows of the real things, which are not perceived directly. That which the observer understands when he views the world mimics the archetypes of the many types and properties (that is, of universals) of things observed. -
Reason and Necessity: the Descent of the Philosopher Kings
Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2011 Reason and Necessity: The Descent of the Philosopher Kings Damian Caluori Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Caluori, D. (2011). Reason and necessity: The descent of the philosopher kings. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 40, 7-27. This Post-Print is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Damian Caluori, Reason and Necessity: the Descent of the Philosopher-Kings Reason and Necessity: the Descent of the Philosopher-Kings One of the reasons why one might find it worthwhile to study philosophers of late antiquity is the fact that they often have illuminating things to say about Plato and Aristotle. Plotinus, in particular, was a diligent and insightful reader of those great masters. Michael Frede was certainly of that view, and when he wrote that ”[o]ne can learn much more from Plotinus about Aristotle than from most modern accounts of the Stagirite”, he would not have objected, I presume, to the claim that Plotinus is also extremely helpful for the study of Plato.1 In this spirit I wish to discuss a problem that has occupied modern Plato scholars for a long time and I will present a Plotinian answer to that problem. The problem concerns the descent of the philosopher kings in Plato’s Republic. -
What Is Authority?
What Is Authority? In order to avoid misunderstanding, it might have been wiser to ask in the title: What was-and not what is-authority? For it is my contention that we are tempted and entitled to raise this question because authority has vanished from the modern world. Since we can no longer fall back upon authentic and undisputable experiences common to all, the very term has become clouded by controversy and confusion. Little about its nature ap- pears self-evident or even comprehensible to everybody, except that the political scientist may still remember that this concept was once funda- mental to political theory, or that most will agree that a constant, ever- widening and deepening crisis of authority has accompanied the development of the modern world in our century. ·This crisis, apparent since the inception of the century, is political in , origin and nature. The rise of political movements intent upon replacing the party system, and the development of a new totalitarian form of gov- ernment, took place against a background of a more or less general, more or less breakdown of all traditional authorities. Nowhere was this breakdown the direct result of the regimes or movements themselves; it rather seemed as though totalitarianism, in the form of movements as well as of regimes, was best fitted to take advantage of a general political and social atmosphere in which the party system had lost its prestige and the government's authority was no longer recognized. The most significant symptom of the crisis, indicating its depth and seriousness, is that it has spread to such prepolitical areas as child-rearing and education, where authority in the widest sense has always been ac- From Between Past and Future. -
The Form of the Good in Plato's Timaeus
THANASSIS GKATZARAS | 71 One of the many philosophical problems The Form of the Good in that we face in the Timaeus is raised by the Plato’s Timaeus claim that the God who created the world (from now on we shall call him ‘Demiurge’)1 is good (Tim. 29d7-30a2). A satisfying explanation of Demiurge’s goodness is far from easy, and dif- ferent approaches have been proposed. How- ever, in this paper I’ll try to show that a clear, sufficient and relatively simple interpretation is possible, if we are based on the hypothesis that Timaeus follows the theory of causation in the Phaedo (including the distinction between ‘safe’ and ‘elegant’ cause) and the concept of the Thanassis Gkatzaras Form of the Good in the Republic.2 University of Ioannina [email protected] To be more specific, I’ll try to show that the Form of the Good of the Republic is also presupposed in the Timaeus and it plays the same role, and we should consider it as a first principle of platonic cosmology, independ- ent from the existence of Demiurge or even the Divine Paradigm (i.e. the model accord- ing to which the Demiurge creates the world). On first impression, this interpretation looks barely possible, since there is no direct refer- ence in the text to this particular Form, with the possible exception of what is said at Tim. 46c7-d1.3 In my opinion, this absence has to do ABSTRACT with specific purposes Timaeus serves, and not with the abandonment of the Good as a cause. -
The Theodicy of Plato's Timaeus
Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 8-10-2021 Reincarnation and Rehabilitation: the Theodicy of Plato's Timaeus John Garrett Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Garrett, John, "Reincarnation and Rehabilitation: the Theodicy of Plato's Timaeus." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2021. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/298 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. REINCARNATION AND REHABILITATION: THE THEODICY OF PLATO’S TIMAEUS by JOHN GARRETT Under the Direction of Timothy O’Keefe, PhD A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in the College of Arts and Sciences Georgia State University 2021 ABSTRACT Plato wonders why a good God might allow the existence of evil. This problem is especially pertinent to his dialogue Timaeus, in which Plato describes the creation of the cosmos by a benevolent divine craftsman called the Demiurge. A justification for why God allows evil to exist is called a theodicy. Readers of the Timaeus have interpreted the theodicy of this dialogue in many ways. After showing the shortcomings of some common interpretations, I offer a largely original interpretation of the theodicy of the Timaeus. I claim that in the Timaeus evil is caused by conflict between souls, and this conflict is something that the good (but not omnipotent) Demiurge could not avoid. -
Freedom and Responsibility in the Myth of Er
Freedom and responsibility in the myth of Er Author: Marina McCoy Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3019 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Published in Ideas y valores: Revista Colombiana de Filosofia, vol. 61, no. 149, pp. 125-141, September 2012 These materials are made available for use in research, teaching and private study, pursuant to U.S. Copyright Law. The user must assume full responsibility for any use of the materials, including but not limited to, infringement of copyright and publication rights of reproduced materials. Any materials used for academic research or otherwise should be fully credited with the source. The publisher or original authors may retain copyright to the materials. Freedom and Responsibility in the Myth of Er Libertad y responsabilidad en el mito de Er Marina Berzins McCoy* Boston College - USA Abstract Plato uses the myth of Er in the Republic in order to carve out space for political freedom and responsibility for human freedom in the ordinary polis. While much of the Republic concentrates on the development of an ideal city in speech, that city is fundamentally a mythos presented in order for Socrates and his friends to learn something about political and individual virtue. The city in which Socrates and his friends exist is an imperfect city and myth of Er is intended for those audience members. Its emphasis on the necessity for personal responsibility in the midst of freedom can be understood as a political claim about the place of individual choice in a world that is constrained by both political and cosmic “necessity”. -
Greeks Bearing Gifts John M
1 Greeks Bearing Gifts John M. Frame The ancient Greeks were not the first civilization in the west, but they made such immense contributions to art, architecture, science, politics, warfare, education, poetry, history, and philosophy that many discussions of these subjects, even today, begin with them. Until the twentieth century, when eastern religion and philosophy began to make a major impact, western thought had two roots: the Greek and the Biblical. Some thinkers tried to synthesize these traditions in various ways. Others saw an antithesis between them and sought to be consistent with one or the other. Although I greatly admire the creative brilliance of the Greek thinkers, I believe it is a serious mistake to adopt their worldviews or to try to synthesize their thinking with the worldview of the Bible. The Greeks and the biblical writers did explore many common themes: God and gods, the nature of reality, the origin of the world, human nature, wisdom, knowledge, ethics, politics, even salvation. We can still learn much from the Greek discussions of these topics. But the ancient wariness about “Greeks bearing gifts” should be applied to the study of Greek worldviews.1 The chief benefit in studying Greek thought is to understand better the philosophical and cultural consequences of rejecting biblical theism. The word “rejecting” may seem harsh. Did the Greeks have access to Scripture? And if not, how could they have rejected it? The early Christian writer Justin Martyr thought that Plato got the idea for his Demiurge (a godlike figure in the dialogue Timaeus) from the writings of Moses. -
The Myth of Er As a Rationalizing Recording Device Michael Weinman Bard College Berlin, Germany [email protected]
Volume 12, No 2, Fall 2017 ISSN 1932-1066 The Myth of Er as a Rationalizing Recording Device Michael Weinman Bard College Berlin, Germany [email protected] Abstract: This essay introduces the idea of a rationalizing recording device, a mechanism by which the thoughts and actions of one or more persons are both preserved and made more accessible to reason. Plato's Myth of Er is depicted as being such a device, since its story is cinematic in the contemporary sense. Just as films can affect viewers by making one aware of thoughts that cannot be carried in the medium of the moving image itself, so too does Plato express his thoughts about the telos of the cosmos and the moral judgment one must make when confronted with choosing how to live through the external medium of a moving image. Keywords: Plato; Er; myth; dialectic; poetry; narrative; film-philosophy; representation. Poetry, Myth, and Philosophy moments of Er's tale show how a soul's salvation can be achieved through the recording and reproduction Plato's Myth of Er is best understood as a rationalizing of lives and show what makes this experience recording device, by which I mean a form of recording cinematic in a contemporary sense of the term that is technology that both preserves some person, place, not anachronistic and not metaphorical. The argument or activity and does so in such a way that makes that here rests on an understanding of the cinematic as an person, place, or activity accessible to reason.1 The affection of the soul that is integral to understanding essential character of this kind of recording technology Er's story as expressive of Plato's commitment to the resembles cinematic imagery in the contemporary independent resourcefulness of myth as a form of sense; which does not mean that its formal features poetic, productive discourse that is irreducible to logical are like film but that the experience of the myth is expression, and for this reason carries the distinctive like the experience of film. -
Necessity and Form-Copies: Republic, Timaeus, and Laws [Abstract] Plato's Metaphysics Employs Three Distinct Ontological State
Necessity and Form-Copies: Republic, Timaeus, and Laws [Abstract] Plato’s metaphysics employs three distinct ontological states: Forms, particulars, and form-copies. Fundamentally, Forms are static beings; particulars are dynamic non-beings; form- copies are dynamic instances of being(s). Plato’s metaphysics is met with difficulty when we start to question how exactly form-copies, mixtures of two seemingly incompatible ontological states (Forms and particulars), come into existence. In this paper, I offer an analysis concerning the relationship between Plato’s two cosmological causes (i.e. Reason and Necessity) and form- copy generation. I am chiefly interested in what finalizes the union between particulars and Forms to generate form-copies. I refer to this finalizing agent as the “form-copy agent.” Plato puts forth two causes: Reason and Necessity. Both Reason and Necessity possess operative limits (authority) defined by causal capabilities. The abstract parts and machinery are subsumed under Reason, while Necessity is broadly associated with physical reality. The causal role of Reason is to define all being. Necessity’s causal role, on the other hand, remains somewhat obscure. If Reason defines being, what does Necessity accomplish as a cause? Plato’s metaphysics needs a catalyzing agent that can account for particulars’ transition into form- copies. Necessity, I argue, is this agent. 1 Introduction In Plato’s first real attempts to outline the theory of Forms (Phaedo), two principal modes of being are posited: being (οὐσία) and participation (μετέχειν). These two modes of being give rise to three definitive ontological states: Forms, particulars, and form-copies. Forms are defined by being (οὐσία). -
A Study of Plato's Use of Myths and Its Relation to Philosophy and Moral
A Study of Plato’s Use of Myths and its Relation to Philosophy and Moral Education Yoshiaki Nakazawa Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy under the Executive Committee of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2016 © 2015 Yoshiaki Nakazawa All rights reserved ABSTRACT A Study of Plato’s Use of Myths and its Relation to Philosophy and Moral Education Yoshiaki Nakazawa The way in which Plato’s uses of myth relate to his theory of moral education and his conception of philosophy is examined. Plato’s use and conception of myth (muthos) is notoriously difficult to determine, however, especially because it is difficult to determine whether and in what way Plato wishes to contrast muthos with logos. I argue that muthos plays an integral role in Plato’s philosophical investigation and dialectic, and therefore it is best understood as a “guise” of logos. Myth is not a suspension nor transcendence of logos, as scholars have suggested. Plato uses myth when he is concerned with moral education, that is, the moral transformation of the reader and the interlocutor. According to this line of interpretation, Plato’s myths play a heuristic role in service of his moral pedagogical goals. I outline Plato’s pedagogical goals in the context of his theory of moral education, and conclude with some suggestions about the integration of philosophical myths in educational settings today. Table of Contents Prologue ……………………………………………………………….….p. 1 Chapter 1: Introduction ………………………………………………......p. 10 Chapter 2: Muthos and Logos …………………………….………………p. 27 Chapter 3: Myth and Education in Protagoras, Gorgias, and Meno …….p.