The Structures of Authority and Political Use of Religious Practices in Thomas Hobbes and Carl Schmitt

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Structures of Authority and Political Use of Religious Practices in Thomas Hobbes and Carl Schmitt The Structures of Authority and Political Use of Religious Practices in Thomas Hobbes and Carl Schmitt Luke COLLISON September 2020 Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the Centre for Research in Modern European Philosophy (CRMEP), Kingston University for the award of Doctor of Philosophy. 1 Abstract This thesis examines the structures of authority in the political theories of Thomas Hobbes and Carl Schmitt. In milieux marked by crises of political legitimacy, civil unrest and war, both Hobbes and Schmitt strove to develop new theoretical foundations in support of their conservative visions of the authority of the state. The exhaustion of traditional means of legitimation, such as divine right or romantic ideals of community, demanded innovative alternatives. Though Hobbes and Schmitt drew on a wide range of sources, I argue that religious practices were centrally important. Focussing on questions of the source and genesis of authority, my study argues that in different ways both identify participation as key to the origination of authority. In part one, through a chronological investigation of Hobbes’ works, I demonstrate that he assembles a multi-faceted theoretical support for authority. While the covenant is essential for establishing the artifice of sovereign potestas, I argue that Hobbes progressively supplements this fragile artifice with a series of additional apparatuses: civil worship based on religious practices, authorisation based on theatrical analogies and educational and pedagogical practices drawn from a general, almost polytheistic, conception of religion. However, I show that ultimately Hobbes’ mechanistic psychology undermines his attempt at an integrated and scientific account of worship and pedagogy. In part two, I divide Schmitt’s oeuvre into monarchical and democratic writings. Investigating the monarchical works, I trace his elaboration of a distinctive ‘commissary authority’ from the Roman dictator to the katechon. I show that this ‘personalist office’ can be understood as an attempt to renovate the traditional doctrine of divine right. Returning to the democratic writings of 1923-32, I contextualise Schmitt’s revisionist conception of democracy and focus on the legitimating role of acts of acclamation, understood as an act of assent, rather than legal or contractual consent. I argue that a key influence on this participatory model of authority is Georges Sorel’s energetic and enthusiastic vision of political activity. 2 Acknowledgements This research project would not have been possibly without the support from colleagues at CRMEP and friends. I would like to thank my supervisor Peter Hallward for his dedicated support, encouragement, criticism and provocations over the last four years. His detailed comments on drafts and numerous discussions over the years have helped me immensely. I would also like to thank my second supervisor Howard Caygill and the professors of CRMEP, especially Étienne Balibar and Éric Alliez for their provocative questions, comments and criticisms. In addition, I am grateful for the various discussions and questions concerning my research prompted by reading groups at CRMEP, Brighton University and elsewhere. I would especially like to thank Kyle Moore, Luís Carneiro, Jorge Varela, Melayna Lamb, German Primera Villamizar, Daniel Steuer, Jeronimo Rilla, Cillian Ó Fathaigh and Austin Gross for their assistance with proof-reading, discussion or advice. Finally, I would like to thank Pamela Perniss, for the numerous forms of assistance, advice, criticism and support she has provided over the duration. The research project was generously funded by three-year full-time studentship from Kingston University London. 3 Contents Abstract 2 Acknowledgements 3 Contents 4 Abbreviations 6 Introduction: Hobbes, Schmitt, Auctoritas, Religion and Law 9 1 The Problem of Authority in Hobbes and Schmitt 10 2 Authority, Auctoritas and Power 22 3 Religion, Theology and Politics 29 4 Law and Recht 33 Part I: Thomas Hobbes 35 Chapter 1: Worship, Potentia and Authorisation 36 1 Chivalry or Deceit: Two Visions of Early Modern Authority 39 (i) Lipsius’ Auctoritas and Reason of State 39 (ii) Stuart Chivalry: Charles, Augustus and the Reform of the Nobility 43 2 The Artifice of the Contract 45 3 Worship and Potentia 57 4 Author and Actor 69 Chapter 2: Religion, Politics and Pedagogy 76 1 Hobbes’ Sacred History 79 (i) The Judaic Period: Abraham and Moses 80 (ii) The Regeneration as the Divine Interregnum 82 (iii) The Kingdom to Come 85 2 Authority of the Arbiter: Christianity in the Hobbesian State 86 3 Natural Religion and the Consecration of the State 91 4 Pedagogical Authority: The Divine Right of Sovereign Pastor 97 5 The Aporia of Juridical and Pedagogical Authority 104 Part II : Carl Schmitt 110 Chapter 3: Commissary Authority 111 1 Max Weber and the Bureaucratic Apparatus 114 2 The Commissary Dictator 120 (i) The Task 125 (ii) The Hierarchy 129 3 The Dignity of the Representative 132 Political Theology and Authority 132 Representation 134 4 (i) Mediation 136 (ii) Commission (Stellvertretung) 140 4 The Katechon and Nomos 145 5 The Divine Right of the Katechon 153 Chapter 4: The Energy of Democratic Authority 159 1 ‘Democracy’ in Weimar 162 2 The People and the Enemy 167 (i) The Doctrine of the Volksgeist 168 (ii) The Enemy 172 (iii) Enthusiasm and Energy 174 (iv) Participation 179 3 Acclamation: The People Can Only Cry ‘Yes’ or ‘No’ 180 (i) Acclamation and Democracy 183 (ii) Acclamation contra Voting 185 (iii) The People Can Only Answer 187 (iv) Acclamation as Assent 189 4 State, Movement, People 194 (i) The ‘Concrete’ State Form of the Twentieth Century 195 (ii) The Führerprinzip and Homogeneity 200 Conclusion 204 Bibliography 211 5 Abbreviations Thomas Hobbes 3D Thomas Hobbes, Three Discourses: A Critical Modern Edition of Newly Identified Work of the Young Hobbes, Ed, ed. Noel B. Reynolds and Arlene W. Saxonhouse (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). AW Thomas Hobbes, Thomas White’s De Mundo Examined, trans. Harold Whitmore Jones (London: Crosby Lockwood Staples, 1976). B Thomas Hobbes, ‘Behemoth, or the Long Parliament’, in The Clarendon Edition of the Works of Thomas Hobbes, Vol. 10: Behemoth, or The Long Parliament, ed. Paul Seaward, Thomas Hobbes, and Paul Seaward (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009). Corresp Thomas Hobbes, The Correspondence: Volume I: 1622-1659 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994). DC Thomas Hobbes, On the Citizen, ed. Richard Tuck and M. Silverthorne (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998). Latin edition used: Thomas Hobbes, De Cive. The Latin Version: A Critical Edition by Howard Warrender, ed. Howard Warrender, The Clarendon Edition of the Philosophical Works of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983). DCLE Thomas Hobbes, A Dialogue Between a Philosopher and a Student of the Common Laws of England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997). EL Thomas Hobbes, The Elements of Law, Natural & Politic, ed. M. M. Goldsmith Ferdinand Tönnes (London: Frank Cass & Co. Ltd, 1969). EW Thomas Hobbes, The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury (London: J. Bohn, 1845). HE Thomas Hobbes, Historia Ecclesiastica. Critical Edition, Including Text, Translation, Introduction, Commentary and Notes, ed. Patricia Springborg, Patricia Stablein, and Paul Wilson, trans. Patricia Springborg, vol. 31 (Paris: Honoré Champion, 2008). L&N Thomas Hobbes and John Bramhall, Hobbes and Bramhall on Liberty and Necessity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). Lev Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, with Selected Variants from the Latin 6 Edition of 1668, ed. Edwin Curley (Cambridge: Hackett, 1994). Latin edition used: Thomas Hobbes, The Clarendon Edition of the Works of Thomas Hobbes, Vol. 4: Leviathan: The English and Latin Texts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012). I follow the convention advocated by the European Hobbes Society and cite the chapter and paragraph numbers, rather than page numbers. TTE Thomas Hobbes, Three-Text Edition of Thomas Hobbes’s Political Theory: The Elements of Law, De Cive and Leviathan, ed. Deborah Baumgold (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017). Carl Schmitt Where specific terminology is at stake, I distinguish the English and German (Deutsch) page numbers by a preceding ‘E’ or ‘D’ respectively. Otherwise, I cite only the English translations where they are available. 3P Carl Schmitt, ‘Three Possibilities for a Christian Conception of History’, Telos, no. 147 (2009): 167–70. The review essay ‘Drei Möglichkeiten eines christlichen Geschichtsbildes’ was originally published as ‘Drei Stufen historischer Sinngebung’ in Universitas 5 (1950): 927–31. 3T Carl Schmitt, On the Three Types of Juristic Thought, trans. Joseph W. Bendersky (London: Praeger Publishers, 2004 [1934]). CP Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss, The Concept of the Political Expanded Edition, ed. and trans. George Schwab (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007 [1927, 1932]). German editions used: Carl Schmitt, ‘Der Begriff des Politischen’, ed. Emil Lederer, Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 58, no. 10 (1927): 1–33; Carl Schmitt, Der Begriff des Politischen: Text von 1932 mit einem Vorwort und drei Corollarien (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1991). Crisis Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, trans. Ellen Kennedy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988 [1923]). German edition used: Carl Schmitt, Die geistesgeschichtliche Lage des heutigen Parlamentarismus, vol. 1 (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 2017). CT Carl Schmitt, Constitutional Theory,
Recommended publications
  • Carl Schmitt and the Critique of Lawfare
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Case Western Reserve University School of Law Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law Volume 43 | Issue 1 2010 Carl Schmitt nda the Critique of Lawfare David Luban Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/jil Part of the International Law Commons Recommended Citation David Luban, Carl Schmitt na d the Critique of Lawfare, 43 Case W. Res. J. Int'l L. 457 (2010) Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/jil/vol43/iss1/26 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Journals at Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law by an authorized administrator of Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. File: Luban 2 Created on: 12/27/2010 2:26:00 PM Last Printed: 4/5/2011 8:10:00 PM CARL SCHMITT AND THE CRITIQUE OF LAWFARE David Luban “Lawfare” is the use of law as a weapon of war against a military adversary. Lawfare critics complain that self-proclaimed “humanitarians” are really engaged in the partisan and political abuse of law—lawfare. This paper turns the mirror on lawfare critics themselves, and argues that the critique of lawfare is no less abusive and political than the alleged lawfare it attacks. Radical lawfare critics view humanitarian law with suspicion, as nothing more than an instrument used by weak adversaries against strong military powers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Method of Antinomies: Oakeshott and Others Others and Oakeshott Antinomies: of Method the VOLUME 6 | ISSUE 1 + 2 2018 6 | ISSUE VOLUME
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy 2018 The ethoM d of Antinomies: Oakeshott nda Others Stephen Turner University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/phi_facpub Scholar Commons Citation Turner, Stephen, "The eM thod of Antinomies: Oakeshott nda Others" (2018). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 309. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/phi_facpub/309 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Method of Antinomies: Oakeshott and Others STEPHEN TURNER Email: [email protected] Web: http://philosophy.usf.edu/faculty/sturner/ Abstract: Michael Oakeshott employed a device of argument and analysis that appears in a number of other thinkers, where it is given the name “antinomies.” These differ from binary oppositions or contradictories in that the two poles are bound to- gether. In this discussion, the nature of this binding is explored in detail, in large part in relation to Oakeshott’s own usages, such as his discussion of the relation of faith and skepticism, between collective goal-oriented associations and those based on contract, and between a legal regime based on neutral rules and one oriented to policy goals . Other examples might include Weber’s distinction between the politics of intention and the politics of responsibility. Moreover, such ambiguous concepts as “rights,” have antinomic interpretations. In each of these cases, the full realization of one ideal led, in practice, to consequenc- es associated with the other: in political practice, neither polar ideal was realizable without concessions to the other.
    [Show full text]
  • The Method of Antinomies: Oakeshott and Others Others and Oakeshott Antinomies: of Method the VOLUME 6 | ISSUE 1 + 2 2018 6 | ISSUE VOLUME
    The Method of Antinomies: Oakeshott and Others STEPHEN TURNER Email: [email protected] Web: http://philosophy.usf.edu/faculty/sturner/ Abstract: Michael Oakeshott employed a device of argument and analysis that appears in a number of other thinkers, where it is given the name “antinomies.” These differ from binary oppositions or contradictories in that the two poles are bound to- gether. In this discussion, the nature of this binding is explored in detail, in large part in relation to Oakeshott’s own usages, such as his discussion of the relation of faith and skepticism, between collective goal-oriented associations and those based on contract, and between a legal regime based on neutral rules and one oriented to policy goals . Other examples might include Weber’s distinction between the politics of intention and the politics of responsibility. Moreover, such ambiguous concepts as “rights,” have antinomic interpretations. In each of these cases, the full realization of one ideal led, in practice, to consequenc- es associated with the other: in political practice, neither polar ideal was realizable without concessions to the other. But these features are rooted in the deep history of institutions. They are contingent, not philosophical. They nevertheless preclude con- ventional approaches to political theory. Keywords: Michael Oakeshott, antinomies, meta-politics, democratic theory, Max Weber, Hans Morgenthau, genealogy 54 COSMOS + TAXIS COSMOS Several of Michael Oakeshott’s writings, including On vision of politics is different from relativism in any simple Human Conduct ([1975] 1991), employ an argumentative sense of this term. It is specifically distinct from, and op- device that is shared with several other twentieth century posed to, the idea that there can be an ideological “solu- thinkers, but which has not received much attention on its tion” to the antinomies in question.
    [Show full text]
  • Property and Sovereignty: How to Tell the Difference
    243 Property and Sovereignty: How to Tell the Difference Arthur Ripstein* Property and sovereignty are often used as models for each other. Landowners are sometimes described as sovereign, the state’s territory sometimes described as its property. Both property and sovereignty involve authority relations: both an owner and a sovereign get to tell others what to do — at least within the scope of their ownership or sovereignty. My aim in this Article is to distinguish property and sovereignty from each other by focusing on what lies within the scope of each. I argue that much confusion and more than a little mischief occurs when they are assimilated to each other. The confusion can arise in both directions, either by supposing that property is a sort of stewardship, or that sovereignty is a large-scale form of ownership. One of the great achievements of modern (i.e., Kantian) political thought is recognizing the difference between them. INTRODUCTION Property and sovereignty are often used as models for each other. In introducing his account of rights, H.L.A. Hart describes a right-holder as a “small-scale sovereign.”1 So, too, discussions of sovereignty often appeal to proprietary metaphors of ownership. These parallels are unsurprising, both historically and conceptually. Historically, early modern discussions of sovereignty, such * University Professor and Professor of Law and Philosophy, University of Toronto. I am grateful to David Dyzenhaus, Larissa Katz, and Douglas Sanderson for comments and discussion, to audience members at the Property and Sovereignty Conference at Columbia Law School, September 2015, and at the North American Workshop on Private Law Theory in Toronto, October 2015.
    [Show full text]
  • Interrogating Illiberalism Through Chinese Communist Party Regulations Samuli Sepp¨Anen†
    \\jciprod01\productn\C\CIN\52-2\cin202.txt unknown Seq: 1 1-MAY-20 11:13 Interrogating Illiberalism Through Chinese Communist Party Regulations Samuli Sepp¨anen† Can the exercise of political leadership, which is meant to transcend laws, nevertheless, be governed by formal rules? This Article examines the relationship between the illiberal governance project and rule-based gov- ernance in the context of the Chinese Communist Party’s internal “intraparty” regulations. In the past few years, Chinese Communist Party leaders have sought to strengthen the Party’s political leadership by extending its discipline inspection mechanisms further into Chinese state organs. The Party leaders have also sought to regulate Party cadres’ uses of power more closely through intraparty regulations. The efforts to strengthen the Party’s political leadership through improving intraparty regulations point to a number of puzzling contradictions and even para- doxes in the illiberal governance project. Rules make the Party more gov- ernable and at least potentially limit space for corruption and other unsanctioned personal projects; but at the same time, they provide oppor- tunities for resisting Party leadership and divide the Party into organiza- tional departments with conflicting interests. This Article discusses such contradictions and paradoxes within the context of global illiberal political thought and argues that prominent solutions to the tension between illib- eral political leadership and rule-based governance mask uncertainty about what illiberal political leadership actually entails. Introduction ..................................................... 268 R I. Rules and Political Leadership in Illiberal Political Thought .................................................. 273 R A. Privileging the Political ................................ 274 R B. Appealing to the Irrational ............................ 278 R II.
    [Show full text]
  • Edmund Burke's German Readers at the End of Enlightenment, 1790-1815 Jonathan Allen Green Trinity Hall, University of Cambridg
    Edmund Burke’s German Readers at the End of Enlightenment, 1790-1815 Jonathan Allen Green Trinity Hall, University of Cambridge September 2017 This dissertation is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Declaration This dissertation is the result of my own work and includes nothing which is the outcome of work done in collaborations except as declared in the Declaration and specified in the text. All translations, unless otherwise noted or published in anthologies, are my own. It is not substantially the same as any that I have submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for a degree or diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University of similar institution except as declared in the Declaration and specified in the text. I further state that no substantial part of my dissertation has already been submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for any such degree, diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Declaration and specified in the text. It does not exceed the prescribed word limit for the Faculty of History Degree Committee (80,000 words). Statement of Word Count: This dissertation comprises 79,363 words. 1 Acknowledgements Writing this dissertation was a challenge, and I am immensely grateful to the many friends and colleagues who helped me see it to completion. Thanks first of all are due to William O’Reilly, who supervised the start of this research during my MPhil in Political Thought and Intellectual History (2012-2013), and Christopher Meckstroth, who subsequently oversaw my work on this thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Jürgen Habermas and Carl Schmitt in the Paradigm of Modernity for a Critique of the Modern Law
    UNIVERSIDADE DE BRASÍLIA – FACULDADE DE DIREITO PROGRAMA DE PÓS-GRADUAÇÃO EM DIREITO – DOUTORADO ÁREA DE CONCENTRAÇÃO: CONSTITUIÇÃO E DEMOCRACIA Jürgen Habermas and Carl Schmitt in the paradigm of modernity For a critique of the modern law Orientador: Prof. Dr. Miroslav Milović Vanja Grujić Brasília, Setembro 2017 Dedicatória Gostaria de expressar a minha sincera gratidão à Universidade Nacional de Brasília e à Faculdade de Direito por me dar a honra e a oportunidade para defender a minha tese aqui. Também queria expressar minha apreciação ao meu professor Prof. Dr. Miroslav Milović. Você tem sido um inspirador mentor para mim. Gostaria de agradecer-lhe por encorajar minha pesquisa e por me permitir crescer na esfera acadêmica. Gostaria também de agradecer aos meus membros da comissão, a professora Rochelle Cysne Frota D'Abreu, ao professor Marcelo da Costa Pinto Neves, ao professor Paulo César Nascimento, e ao professor Juliano Zaiden Benvindo por servir como membros do meu comitê, mesmo em dificuldades. Além disso, gostaria de expressar o agradecimento aos funcionários da secretaria de pós-graduação da Faculdade de Direito por me ajudar sempre que necessário. Também, gostaria de agradecer a CAPES (Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior) para o financiamento do meu doutorado no Brasil, e para a oportunidade de fazer parte do programa doutorado sanduíche no exterior. Sem essas bolsas, meus estudos de doutorado não seriam possíveis. Sincera gratidão a todos os colegas e professores da Faculdade de Direito em Brasília. Ouvir suas ideias e comentários foi uma experiência incrível e aprendi muito com vocês. Por último, mas não menos importante, agradeço aos professores e colegas da ZERP (Zentrum für Europäische Rechtspolitik der Universität Bremen) por seus frutíferos comentários, palavras de encorajamento e amizade que certamente deixaram uma marca importante no meu trabalho.
    [Show full text]
  • Carl Schmitt's Political Theology*
    Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology* HUGO BALL I. Carl Schmitt ranks among the few German savants who are equal to the pro - fessional dangers of a teaching chair in the present era. I do not hesitate to suggest that he has taken and established for himself the type of the new German savant. If the writings of this remarkable professor (not to say confessor) served only towards the recognition and study of its author’s catholic (universal) physiog - nomy, that alone would be enough to assure him a preeminent status. In a fine essay, “On Ideals,” Chesterton says that the remediation of our confused and des - perate age in no way requires the great “practical man” who is clamored for the world over, but rather the great ideologist. “A practical man means a man accus - tomed to mere daily practice, to the way things commonly work. When things do not work, you must have the thinker, the man who has some doctrine about why they work at all. It is wrong to fiddle while Rome is burning; but it is quite right to study the theory of hydraulics while Rome is burning.” 1 Carl Schmitt belongs to those who “study the theory of hydraulics.” He is an ideologist of rare conviction, and indeed it’s safe to say that he will restore to this word a new prestige, which among Germans has carried a pejorative meaning since Bismarck. 2 * This essay first appeared in Hochland 21, issue 2 (April–September 1924), pp. 263–86. Reprinted in Der Fürst dieser Welt: Carl Schmitt und die Folgen , ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Carl Schmitt: an Improper Name Adam Sitze
    editor’s introduction carl schmitt: an improper name Adam Sitze 1 The proper name, it must be said, has a curious place and function in the discourse of the history of political thought. On the terms of this discourse, a name like “Aristotle” does not designate a specific mortal being who lived and died in a particular place and at a particular time. Quite the opposite: it designates something in this mortal being—his thought—that exceeds his mortal being, and thus too his particular place and time. Even so, “Aristotle” doesn’t refer equally to all of Aris- totle’s thought: political theorists typically use this name to designate the positions in The Politics and Nicomachean Ethics, not those in Quaestiones Mechanicae or The Souls of Animals. The name also can be used to refer to works not written by Aristotle at all. Converted into an adjective, “Aristo- telian” refers to transmissible attributes that have come to be associated with Aristotle’s thought—idiosyncratic conceptual habits or techniques that are common enough to be found reiterated in the works of others, and that with su<cient iteration can come to constitute a school (the “Lyceum”) or tradition (“Aristotelianism”). This adjectivalization can go to such an extreme that some thinkers can come to be categorized more with reference to Aristotle’s name than by their own (Aquinas, for some, always will be first and foremost a particular sort of “Aristote- lian”). These descriptions, paradoxically, can even come to displace the Downloaded from http://read.dukeupress.edu/books/book/chapter-pdf/582697/9780822374855-001.pdf by guest on 28 September 2021 objects they ostensibly only nickname.
    [Show full text]
  • 9781474454780 Russias New
    For Olivia 66256_Lewis.indd256_Lewis.indd iiii 220/02/200/02/20 112:242:24 PPMM Russia’s New Authoritarianism Putin and the Politics of Order DAVID G. LEWIS 66256_Lewis.indd256_Lewis.indd iiiiii 220/02/200/02/20 112:242:24 PPMM Edinburgh University Press is one of the leading university presses in the UK. We publish academic books and journals in our selected subject areas across the humanities and social sciences, combining cutting-edge scholarship with high editorial and production values to produce academic works of lasting importance. For more information visit our website: edinburghuniversitypress.com © David G. Lewis, 2020 Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun – Holyrood Road, 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry, Edinburgh EH8 8PJ Typeset in 10/13 Giovanni by IDSUK (DataConnection) Ltd, and printed and bound in Great Britain. A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 1 4744 5476 6 (hardback) ISBN 978 1 4744 5478 0 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 1 4744 5479 7 (epub) The right of David G. Lewis to be identifi ed as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498). 66256_Lewis.indd256_Lewis.indd iivv 220/02/200/02/20 112:242:24 PPMM CONTENTS Preface / vii Acknowledgements / xiv Note on Transliteration and Translation / xv ONE / Authoritarianism, Ideology and Order / 1 Understanding Russian Authoritarianism / 1 Order, Smuta and the Russian State / 6 Russia as Weimar / 12 Carl Schmitt and Authoritarian
    [Show full text]
  • Sociological Theory III: Conservative Social Thought
    SOC6201H (Sociological Theory III) Conservative Social Thought: From the Intransigent Right to the End of History D. Silver Winter 2018 Course Description: In 1992, Perry Anderson identified four seminal authors as the intellectual basis for “the intransigent right”: F.A. Hayek, Carl Schmitt, Michael Oakeshott, and Leo Strauss. All coming of age in the inter-war period, these four authors have not only been tremendously influential among scholars and intellectuals. They have informed and inspired prime ministers, presidents, and their advisors. At the same time, they provided much of the basic intellectual template for subsequent conservative social thinkers as they confronted rapid and dramatic social changes from the 1960s to the present: trenchant critiques of the ideas of progress, social engineering, and social justice; assertion of the national and particular over and against the cosmopolitan and the global; defense of human nature over and against relativism and constructionism; the dangers of emancipatory self-expression for the maintenance of political and social order; and more. Given that the right remains as intransigent as ever, understanding its intellectual basis remains as important as ever. In this seminar, we will attempt to enter into and understand these ideas in their own terms, while also engaging with authors who have undertaken critical assessments of this intellectual tradition. Our primary focus will be close examination of ideas and texts, with an eye to how they have informed contemporary debates. Assignments: Bi-weekly discussion board post in-class presentation course paper Introduction 1) Getting to know the conservative mind (I) (Selections TBD) “What is Conservative Social and Political Thought” (Jerry Muller) “Conservative Thought” (Karl Mannheim, selections TBD) o Suggested: .
    [Show full text]
  • Carl Schmitt's Radical Democracy
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School 2012 Carl Schmitt's radical democracy: Schmitt, Hobbes and the return to political identity Ndifreke Ette Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Ette, Ndifreke, "Carl Schmitt's radical democracy: Schmitt, Hobbes and the return to political identity" (2012). LSU Master's Theses. 3752. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/3752 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CARL SCHMITT’S RADICAL DEMOCRACY: SCHMITT, HOBBES AND THE RETURN TO POLITICAL IDENTITY A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Political Science by Ndifreke Ette B.A., Louisiana State University, 2008 May, 2012 DEDICATION This work is dedicated to God who grants me wisdom and endurance, for in Him I live, move and have my being; to the members of The Apostolic Church, Baton Rouge who guide me spiritually; and to my family. My parents, Dr. Aniedi Ette and Odot Ette introduced me to a house full of books. My brothers Ifiok and Edifon let me read them. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This thesis celebrates the combined efforts of known, unknown, and imagined influences, of help from various quarters, of men, and women, who hewed the rock, crushed the ore, purified the molten metal, and finally shaped the product.
    [Show full text]