<<

Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Harro Maas Excerpt More information

one



The Prying Eyes of the Natural Scientist

William Stanley Jevons (1835–1882) isunquestionably one of thegreat minds inthe history of economics. Today, he is remembered as one of the “fathers” of the so-called marginalist revolution in economics. Withhis Theory of Po- litical (1871), decisions of economic agents came to be analysedby means of thecalculus, interms ofdeliberations over marginalincrements of . In this “mechanics of utility and self-” (TPE2 90), economic agents – whetherintheir roleof consumers, workmen, or other – came to be seen as maximising utilityfunctions. Themarginalist revolution was a definitive breakwith the labour theory of –value came to be iden- tifiedwith exchange value, and this was identifiedwith marginal , not with the costs ofproduction. Jevons isalso rememberedforhis inno- vative contributions to theempirical, statistical study of the economy. He ardently propagated the use of graphstopictureand analyse statisticaldata. He introducedindex numberstomake causalinferences about economic phenomena. In short, there isnoparticleof economicscience, theoretical or empirical,towhich Jevons did not make important contributions that are, today,consideredrevolutionary. Jevons is one of the fathersof modern economics, indeed. This summary evaluation of the importance of Jevons’s contributions to economics contrasts starkly with the image wegain fromasuperficial glance at hiscontemporaries. In his lifetime, Jevons was well valued as an able statistician, but many of the leading contemporary political consideredhis pursuits in as obscuring thesubject. It was only the younger generation of scientists and economists – likeGeorge Darwinand FrancisYsidro Edgeworth – whoappreciated thenovelty and

1

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

2  William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics

fruitfulness ofhis ideas.1 It is worthquoting from John StuartMill’s fa- mous letter to Cairnes on Jevons’s Theory to illustrate his reservations (Mill 17:1862–3):2

I have not seen Mr. Jevons’s book, but as far as I can judge from such notices ofitashave reached me, I do not expect thatIshall thinkfavourably ofit. He is a man of some ability, but he seems to have a mania for encumbering questions with useless complications, andwith a notation implying the existence of greaterprecision inthe data than the questions admitof.

Mill (1806–1873) was not alone in his judgement.Reviewsof the book – from, amongst others, (1842–1924)and John Elliot Cairnes (1823–1875)–were quite sceptical.3 (1838–1900), thegreat utilitarian philosopher, downplayed the importance of Jevons’s use of the calculus whileacknowledging the importance ofhisnew utility theory of value.4 In the 1875 re-edition of John Elliot Cairnes’s influential Lectures on the Character and Logical Method of ,Cairnes even wrote that the work ofhis “able friend” did not give himanyreason to alter the views on methodhe had expressed as early as 1857.Reservations to the Theory weremade not only by those whom Jevons explicitly attacked –theclassical economists – but also by political economists of the historical school, such as Cliffe Leslie(1825–1882)and John KellsIngram (1823–1907), who favoured detailedhistorical explanations over theoryabstractedfrom historicaldetail, whether expressed verbally or mathematically. These conflicting appraisals from past andpresent leave us with an enigma ofhow to evaluate Jevons’s place inthe history of economics. Using Roy Weintraub’s recent distinction between the body and the image of ascience

1 See also Schabas (1990), Chapter 7. 2 Mill, Letter 1698, 5 December 1871,toCairnes. 3 In lateryears, Marshall admitted that he was angry about the bookfor two reasons. Firstly, he hadbeen thinking along the lines of Jevons; secondly, being an ardent admirer ofRicardo and theClassicalSchool, he feltthat injustice hadbeen done to them inthe Theory.See Schabas (1989). Amore general account of the reception of the Theory istobe foundin Schabas (1990). Inoue’s recent collection ofreviewsof Jevons’s work corrects the impression that the general response to the Theory was negative. This was farfrom the full picture.See Inoue (2002, 2:187–297). 4 Sidgwickfully acknowledged theadditional challenge Jevons’stheory of utilityposed to classicalpolitical economy that had come under severe pressure with William Thornton’s On Labour and John StuartMill’ssubsequent “recantation” of the fund theory. For Thornton’s influence on economictheory, see, for example, Chaigneau (1997), Donoghue (1998), Ekelund and Thornton (2001), Vint (1994), and White (1994b).

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

The Prying Eyes of the Natural Scientist  3

(2002, 1–2)–that is, between its substance andits perceived methodsand history –this book traces these conflicting appraisalsof Jevons back to thecontrasting images ofpolitical economy that were defendedbyJevons himself andhiscontemporaries. From an evaluation of these contrasting images, itmaybeunderstoodwhyand to what extent Jevons can be seen as one of the fathersof modern economics. Hence, myfocus isonthe changing methodsofpolitical economy, not on thechanges in its theoretical content.Beforegoingintoanydetail,itwillbeusefulto brieflyreviewexisting appraisalsof Jevons’s work.

Jevons’s Place in the History of Economics Muchhas been written about Jevons’s place inthe history of economics. Starting withKeynes’sandRobbins’s centenary appraisalsof Jevons, these studies have considerably deepened ourknowledge and understanding of Jevons’s work and thecontextin whichit was produced. In his beautiful and dense essay on Jevons, Keynes paid equally high tribute to the Theory and to Jevons’s statistical studies. At home as well inabstract theory as inthe “black arts ofinductive economics”, Jevons was, according to Keynes, “the first theoretical to surveyhis materialwith the prying eyes and fertile, controlledimagination of the natural scientist” (Keynes [1936] 1988, 66).Robbins even wenttotheextreme when he noted that the “sheer genius” of Jevons’s “capacityin handling facts”,morethan the Theory, was perhaps his “most conspicuous claimtofame” (Robbins [1936] 1988, 101). Keynes’s portrayal of Jevons – as scrutinising the data, spending “hours arranging hischarts, plotting them, sifting them, tinting them neatly with delicate palecolours liketheslides of the anatomist, and all thetime poring over them andbrooding over them to discover their secret” ([1936] 1988, 66)–rightly describes himaspursuing an anatomy,orphysiology,of society, althoughKeynes’s account ismore imaginative than informative.Scientists use instruments and experiments to let the data speak,and thismight be only vaguely inferredfrom Keynes’s description. Moreover, Keynes seems to have meant this description only for Jevons’sempirical studies, whereas it was generally considered that his most important innovation was the introduction of aspecific instrument – thecalculus – into economics. Collison Blackdeliveredhis centennial commemoration of Jevons’sfirst airing ofhismarginalist ideas in his “Notice of aMathematical Theory of

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

4  William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics

PoliticalEconomy” (readin 1862 to sectionFof the British Association for theAdvancement ofScience (BAAS)). In 1962, Blackhadjust recently discov- ered a wealth of materialinthe possession of Jevons’sgranddaughter,Mrs Kone¨ kamp, whichprovided newinsight into Jevons’s lifeandwork. Con- trary to what might perhaps beexpectedfrom Black’smodestywithregard to hiseminent predecessors, hisandKone¨ kamp’sedition of these papers, from 1972 through to 1981, have greatly contributed to a renewedinterest inJevons’s work. Various detailed studies appearedregarding exactly what Jevons’s contribution was to the so-called marginalist revolution (see, espe- cially, Black et al. 1973). His contribution to the development of statistics and is discussedin detail inseveralhighly valuable studies (e.g., Stigler 1982; Aldrich 1987, 1992; Morgan 1990). His relation to his predeces- sorsand successors has also been extensively examined (e.g., Bostaph and Shieh 1986;Schabas 1989, 1990;Kim 1995;Peart 1993, 1995a, 1996; White 1989, 1991b, 1994a, 1994b, 2004b). From these in-depth studies, a muchricherim- age emerges of Jevons as one of the foundersof“modern economics” –asin thetitleofBlack’s contribution to the Bellagioconference on themarginal- ist revolution in economics (Black et al. 1973). Thetermechoes Robbins’s depiction of marginalist economictheory as theunifying coreof modern economics (White 2004). The Bellagioconference on themarginalist revolution deserves some special attention. Obviously, not only was Jevons’s work addressed, but also themore generalissue ofwhether there was any unifying coreatall inthe work of thethree founding fathersof the “marginalist revolution”,aswas once claimedbySchumpeter. Was itsheer coincidence that Jevons, Menger, and Walras all published their tracts inthefirst half of the 1870s, orwerethese different authors, unknowledgeableabout each other’s work,nevertheless working on the same project: the introduction of amarginalist theory of choice in which actors maximised their utilityin lightof given means? It is certainly not mypurpose to repeat this discussion; I willsummarise it briefly. Though toaconsiderable extent Jevons and Walras were inagreement with their approach to economictheory,this was certainly not the case for Menger.5 It was argued that most of Jevons’stheoreticalinnovations – such

5 Jaffe´’s 1976 de-homogenisation of the “fathers” of themarginalist revolution has been recently discussedinaspecialissue of the American Journal of Economics and .See Comim(1998), Fontaine (1998), He´bert(1998), andPeart(1998).

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

The Prying Eyes of the Natural Scientist  5

as , maximising behaviour,and emphasis on theory – were present inthe work of other economists long before Jevons, though not inthe Ricardian mainstream. Upon closerinspection, Jevons proved moretied to theclassical cost ofproduction theory than was sug- gestedbyhisvehement rejection of the “wrong-headed” doctrines ofRi- cardoand Mill. Theonly thing that most authorsagreed upon as being Jevons’sgenuine contribution to modern economics was his insistence on the use of mathematics, especially thecalculus, in framing economicthe- ory. This is despite the fact that it was evident – as indeed Jevons him- self hadpointed out inthe second edition of the Theory (1879)–that Jevons had manyprecursors, especially inFrance, some ofwhom had shownconsiderably moreskill in handling thecalculus than Jevons (see Ekelund and He´bert 1999). Instead ofplacing theemphasisonacontinu- ity ordiscontinuitywithhis predecessors interms of theoretical content, the attention shifted to Jevons’s methodological contribution. His use of thecalculus seemed to concurwith theunityinmethodhe defendedwith regard to all of thesciences – the natural and the social – including eco- nomics.6 From very different perspectives, Mirowski’s highly influential More Heat than Light (1989)andSchabas’s 1990 monograph on Jevons investigated this thesismoreclosely. Schabas explicitly addressed Jevons’s use of thecalculus in lightofhis philosophy of science as set out in The Principles of Science (1874). The Principles isabookwhich, until then, hadhardly been no- ticed outsidethe realmof the natural sciences – a fact whichwas explained by the philosopher of science Ernst Nagelin his introduction to the 1958 Dover edition as being due to its lack ofdiscussion of the distinct meth- odsof the natural and the social sciences.Schabas forged thisallegedde- fect of the bookinto its very strength. From herdiscussion, ittranspired that therearegood grounds fordefending thethesisthat Jevons foreshad- owed the so-calledhypotheticaldeductive method as theunifying approach to thesciences (whichwas distinctly one of the reasons for Nagel’senthu- siasm for the Principles), and sheapproached Jevons’s Theory of Political Economy from this perspective.

6 As hadbeen argued as early as 1962 by the logician WolfeMays, “there isaclose relationship between Jevons’s philosophy of the natural sciences andhismethodology of thesocial sciences” (Mays[1962] 1988, 212).

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

6  William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics

Granted that this isthe case, itunfortunately does not explain why the calculus can beof use in economics, norwhyasubjective theory of value should be preferred to a cost ofproduction theory. Even more pressing, such aunified method ofinquiry does not entail that thesubject matter ofpolitical economybe quantitative in –Jevons’smainargument for treating economics mathematically. As Schabas (1990, 80–1) contends, Jevons’s “appeal to the quantitative complexion of economics”was “perhaps the most simplisticof [his] arguments” even thoughitmight have been “to Jevonsandhiscontemporaries ...perfectlycogent”. It enabledtheeconomist to freely “explore analogies to the natural sciences”,especially “to mechanics” (80, 84). As we will see inmore detail inthis book,Jevons’s “appeal” to mechan- ical analogies was not at all “cogent” to hiscontemporaries. Farfrom un- equivocally agreeing with Jevons’sappeal to the “quantitative complexion of economics”,contemporary economists reacteddismissively orwithpuz- zlement to Jevons’s use of mathematics in political economy. Even though theywould have agreedwith the complexion ofpolitical economy,this did not makethesubject fit the use of mathematics to unravelits secrets, nor did thismake analogies legitimate with mechanics – quite thecontrary. Hence, Mirowski’s penetrating and,asit happened, highly provocative the- sisthat early marginalists like Stanley Jevons modelled their new theories and method onaspecific brand ofphysics that rose to the fore inmid- century Europe, thermodynamics, seemed amuch more promising route than that ofSchabas to explainthe rift between classical economists and the newly emerging marginalist theory. However“totalising” Mirowski’snar- rative maybe(Weintraub 2002, 6), itclearly opened new vistas withinthe history of economics. But Mirowski’sstrong language was not particularly helpful to make his case, depicting early marginalists like Jevons as incompetent engineers who lured economists into the wrong theory because of their lack of understand- ing of thenewphysics and the mathematics that went withit. In her own account of Jevons, Schabas (1990, 6)clearly showedherself annoyedwith such a “conspiracy thesis”,and she was not alone inthis. Ifwe look through Mirowski’snormative language, however, it remains undeniablethat there weremovesbetween physics and economics innineteenth-century Europe in which thermodynamics played asignificant role.

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

The Prying Eyes of the Natural Scientist  7

In relation to Jevons, these exchanges have recently been detailedby Michael White (2004b). White argues that Jevons’s summary statement of the fundamental“problem of economics”7 andhis reworking ofhisoriginal outline in between its presentation to the BAASin 1862 and the Theory in 1871 aretobeunderstoodin relation to his engagement with the debates over the conservation of energyinthe 1860s. Jevons’s Question (1865), whichwas somewhat of a hit in hisown day,servesasamajor source inthis regard. But even without such a detailed analysis, itmight seem obvious that Jevons’senergy came from energyphysics. In the prefacetothe Theory we read:8

The natureofwealth and value isexplainedbytheconsideration of an indefinitely small amount ofpleasureandpain, just as thetheory of statics ismadetorest upon theequality ofindefinitely small amounts of energy. (TPE2 44)

Thisobvious relation between Jevons’s program in economics and energy physics produces a serious problem. White’s investigations into thecontext of thealterations Jevons’s program underwent inthe 1860sand onwards reveal that its initialimpetus lay not in his engagements withdebates over the conservation of energy, but elsewhere. After all, Jevons’sfirst airing of hisnew mathematical theory to the BAASin 1862, publishedin 1866 as the Brief Account,certainly did not rely on notions of energy. Jevons used mechanical metaphors well before he recasted some (not all)of them in terms of energy. More importantly,asWhite notes, Jevons’s references to the “energyframework...leftnomark on the formal mathematics (i.e. calculus and geometry)of TPE” (2004b, 242).Referring to his 1862 paper, Jevons wrote inthe introduction to the Theory :“All thechiefpoints of thetheory weresketched out ten yearsago” (TPE2 77). NeitherSchabas’s recourse to Jevons’s Principles nor Mirowski’snarrative about thetransfer of energyphysics to economics isthus sufficient to explainthe rift in method between Jevons and theclassical economists.

7 Jevons stated this problem intheconcluding remarksof the Theory. It reads:“Given, a certain population, with various needsandpowersofproduction, in possession of certain landsand other sources of material: required,themodeof employing their labourwhich will maximizetheutility of the produce” (TPE2 254). 8 The phrasing isanallusion to White (1991d).

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

8  William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics

Perhaps because of these difficulties, Sandra Peart, in her monograph on Jevons (1996), approached the differences between theclassical economists and Jevons fromamore pragmatic perspective. Whileemphasising theoretical continuitybetween Mill and Jevons, sheaimed to locate their differences in perspective intheir widely diverging approaches to empirical research. Turning to the methodologicalwritings of classical economists like Mill and Cairnes, it is easily seen that differences intheir opinions on the fitness ofpolitical economy to mathematics did not reside inanagreement ordisagreement about thesimilaritybetween political economy and the natural sciences per se. Whatever mayhave been the differences between the methodological viewsof these classical economists and Jevons – and there were many –there was no dispute about the lawsofpolitical economy appealing to the same status as the lawsobtainedinthe natural sciences, though this status as such met withradically different appraisalbyMill and Cairnes on the one hand and Jevons on theother. Indeed,oneof themain purposes of John StuartMill’s famous 1836 essay on the properdefinition and method ofpolitical economyhadbeen to secure for the lawsof economics the same status as naturallaws. Peartargues that what economists likeMill and Cairnes on the one hand and Jevons on theother did not agree on was how to assess these laws. Jevons’s distinction between the mathematical character ofpolitical econ- omy andits exactness is relevant here.Peartscrutinised this distinction even more incisively in her articleonMill and Jevons (1995a).She pinpoints the disagreements between Mill and Jevons intheir different attitudes towards the problem of multiple causation,aserious conundrum inthose days. Ac- cording to Mill,the “abstract truths” ofpolitical economy could not be perceived empirically due to the interference ofdisturbing causes. Jevons, incontrast, treated these disturbing causes as “noxious errors”whichwould averageoutonthe whole. As a consequence, Mill resisted the introduction of statistical toolsand techniques that inJevons’s perception formed the alphaand omega of thetoolbox of the social scientist. Peart reinterprets Jevons’s Principles of Science inthis light. Jevons’sex- tensive discussions inthe Principles of methods for correcting measure- ment errors naturally concurwithhis statisticalinnovations.Peart’sac- count of Jevons enforces the image one forms from the detailed studies on hisempiricalwork mentioned earlier, in which Jevons is depicted as a forerunner of the probabilistic revolution (Aldrich 1992), or at least one of

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

The Prying Eyes of the Natural Scientist  9

those paving the wayfor the rise of econometrics inthethirties (Morgan 1990). On Peart’s reading, what hadbeen considered the distinguishing featureof Jevons’s work at the Bellagioconference – the introduction of thecalculus – typically enough turns out to beoffarless importance than is commonly thought. In her view,the distinguishing contribution of Jevons to economics did not reside intreating political economy mathematically, but where it was locatedbyKeynes andRobbins:in hisscrutinising an avalancheof numer- icaldata to unravel their hidden secrets. On Peart’s reading, research on Jevons seems to bethrown back to Robbins’s statement at thevery begin- ning ofhis 1936 essay on Jevons’s place inthe history of economics:“It is not easy...to define the exact natureofhisachievement....He formed no school. He created no system”. His summary statement seems to bethe most that can besaid of Jevons:“The totality ofhisachievement, the wide range ofhis activities, the fertility ofhis imagination, themarvellous lucidity and attack ofhisexpository style, rather than the perfection of any one ofhis constructions ...gives him his place in history” ([1936] 1988, 94).

The Distinction Between Mind and Matter in Victorian Britain Maybe weshould acquiesce, like Robbins, inappraising Jevons’s lively and fertile imagination as hismainclaimtofame. Unityis not always found. In Jevons’s case, however,there isafirm reason to dig deeper. Why else would he have proclaimedinthe Theory that there is but one methodfor all of the sciences and threw uphis hands in dismay at those whothoughtotherwise:

Thereexists muchprejudice against attempts to introduce the methods andlanguage of mathematics into anybranch of themoral sciences. Most persons appear to hold that the physical sciences formthe proper sphere of mathematical method,and that themoral sciences demand some other method,Iknow not what. (TPE1 3)

The most notable distinction inthis quotation isthat between the “nat- ural” and the “moral” sciences. The question that maybe raisedis why Jevons denied a distinction between different fieldsof thesciences that ap- parently was so obvious to “most persons”? Neil DeMarchi’s 1972 short, but

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521827124 - William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics Harro Maas Excerpt More information

10  William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics

still extremely complete, survey of the differences and agreements between Jevons andhis predecessors isvery helpfulin searching for an answer. Mathematics, DeMarchi (1972, 350) notes, “was not essential to thecon- ceptof marginal utility nor to the principleofdiminishing (marginal) utility”.DeMarchi argues that for someone likeMill or Cairnes, an explana- tion ofdiminishing marginal utilitywould have to begiven interms of the association psychology,and thistypeofpsychologyran counter to “aclear conception of marginal satisfaction” (1972, 352). According to DeMarchi, adherence to thistypeofpsychology mightexplain why political economists such as Mill,Cairnes, and Cliffe Leslie were “blinded...to theclarity of ex- pression which Jevons’ mathematics imparted to the notion of themargin”. DeMarchi modifies his statement on the relationship between the as- sociation psychology and mathematics when he writes that the association psychology did not constitute an “absolute barrier” to “aclear conception of marginal satisfaction”,andhe referstoRichard Jennings’s Natural Elements of Political Economy (1855) as a case in point.But was it really only a matter of clarity of conception? Without exploring thetheme anyfurther, DeMarchi implicitly locates the distinction betweenJevonsandhisadversaries – Mill, Cairnes, and Cliffe Leslie–in developments in psychology that came to blur a distinction that provoked vehement debates inVictorian England: the distinction between the phenomena of mind and matter. White’s incisive essay on the relation of Jennings to Jevons (White 1994a) servesasahallmarkon thisissue.White makesitsufficientlyclearthatthegist of Jennings’sarguments were not derivedfrom the association psychology, but from so-calledpsychophysiological theories, such as those of William Carpenter and Thomas Laycockin which man’sactions are seen as the offspring ofhis neurophysiological constitution. Withregard to thistypeof argument, Cairnes remarked that, if “PoliticalEconomyistobetreatedin this way, it isevident it will soon become a wholly different study from that which the world has hitherto known it” (1857, 181). And that is just what happened. Developments within psychophysiology inVictorian Britaintended to blur the notorious distinction between mind and matter. When this distinction lost its relevance inthecourse of the nineteenth century, it became increasingly unclearwhereinthe difference between the physical and themoral sciences resided. As isargued at lengthin this book, it isthese very different attitudes towardsthe distinction between mind and matter that help to explainthe different viewsonthe method of

© Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org