Should the Widest Cleft in Statistics - How and Why Fisher Oppos Ed Neyman and Pearson
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
F:\RSS\Me\Society's Mathemarica
School of Social Sciences Economics Division University of Southampton Southampton SO17 1BJ, UK Discussion Papers in Economics and Econometrics Mathematics in the Statistical Society 1883-1933 John Aldrich No. 0919 This paper is available on our website http://www.southampton.ac.uk/socsci/economics/research/papers ISSN 0966-4246 Mathematics in the Statistical Society 1883-1933* John Aldrich Economics Division School of Social Sciences University of Southampton Southampton SO17 1BJ UK e-mail: [email protected] Abstract This paper considers the place of mathematical methods based on probability in the work of the London (later Royal) Statistical Society in the half-century 1883-1933. The end-points are chosen because mathematical work started to appear regularly in 1883 and 1933 saw the formation of the Industrial and Agricultural Research Section– to promote these particular applications was to encourage mathematical methods. In the period three movements are distinguished, associated with major figures in the history of mathematical statistics–F. Y. Edgeworth, Karl Pearson and R. A. Fisher. The first two movements were based on the conviction that the use of mathematical methods could transform the way the Society did its traditional work in economic/social statistics while the third movement was associated with an enlargement in the scope of statistics. The study tries to synthesise research based on the Society’s archives with research on the wider history of statistics. Key names : Arthur Bowley, F. Y. Edgeworth, R. A. Fisher, Egon Pearson, Karl Pearson, Ernest Snow, John Wishart, G. Udny Yule. Keywords : History of Statistics, Royal Statistical Society, mathematical methods. -
Two Principles of Evidence and Their Implications for the Philosophy of Scientific Method
TWO PRINCIPLES OF EVIDENCE AND THEIR IMPLICATIONS FOR THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD by Gregory Stephen Gandenberger BA, Philosophy, Washington University in St. Louis, 2009 MA, Statistics, University of Pittsburgh, 2014 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2015 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH KENNETH P. DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Gregory Stephen Gandenberger It was defended on April 14, 2015 and approved by Edouard Machery, Pittsburgh, Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences Satish Iyengar, Pittsburgh, Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences John Norton, Pittsburgh, Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences Teddy Seidenfeld, Carnegie Mellon University, Dietrich College of Humanities & Social Sciences James Woodward, Pittsburgh, Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences Dissertation Director: Edouard Machery, Pittsburgh, Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences ii Copyright © by Gregory Stephen Gandenberger 2015 iii TWO PRINCIPLES OF EVIDENCE AND THEIR IMPLICATIONS FOR THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD Gregory Stephen Gandenberger, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2015 The notion of evidence is of great importance, but there are substantial disagreements about how it should be understood. One major locus of disagreement is the Likelihood Principle, which says roughly that an observation supports a hypothesis to the extent that the hy- pothesis predicts it. The Likelihood Principle is supported by axiomatic arguments, but the frequentist methods that are most commonly used in science violate it. This dissertation advances debates about the Likelihood Principle, its near-corollary the Law of Likelihood, and related questions about statistical practice. -
Statistics on Spotlight: World Statistics Day 2015
Statistics on Spotlight: World Statistics Day 2015 Shahjahan Khan Professor of Statistics School of Agricultural, Computational and Environmental Sciences University of Southern Queensland, Toowoomba, Queensland, AUSTRALIA Founding Chief Editor, Journal of Applied Probability and Statistics (JAPS), USA Email: [email protected] Abstract In the age of evidence based decision making and data science, statistics has become an integral part of almost all spheres of modern life. It is being increasingly applied for both private and public benefits including business and trade as well as various public sectors, not to mention its crucial role in research and innovative technologies. No modern government could conduct its normal functions and deliver its services and implement its development agenda without relying on good quality statistics. The key role of statistics is more visible and engraved in the planning and development of every successful nation state. In fact, the use of statistics is not only national but also regional, international and transnational for organisations and agencies that are driving social, economic, environmental, health, poverty elimination, education and other agendas for planned development. Starting from stocktaking of the state of the health of various sectors of the economy of any nation/region to setting development goals, assessment of progress, monitoring programs and undertaking follow-up initiatives depend heavily on relevant statistics. Only statistical methods are capable of determining indicators, comparing them, and help identify the ways to ensure balanced and equitable development. 1 Introduction The goals of the celebration of World Statistics Day 2015 is to highlight the fact that official statistics help decision makers develop informed policies that impact millions of people. -
The Likelihood Principle
1 01/28/99 ãMarc Nerlove 1999 Chapter 1: The Likelihood Principle "What has now appeared is that the mathematical concept of probability is ... inadequate to express our mental confidence or diffidence in making ... inferences, and that the mathematical quantity which usually appears to be appropriate for measuring our order of preference among different possible populations does not in fact obey the laws of probability. To distinguish it from probability, I have used the term 'Likelihood' to designate this quantity; since both the words 'likelihood' and 'probability' are loosely used in common speech to cover both kinds of relationship." R. A. Fisher, Statistical Methods for Research Workers, 1925. "What we can find from a sample is the likelihood of any particular value of r [a parameter], if we define the likelihood as a quantity proportional to the probability that, from a particular population having that particular value of r, a sample having the observed value r [a statistic] should be obtained. So defined, probability and likelihood are quantities of an entirely different nature." R. A. Fisher, "On the 'Probable Error' of a Coefficient of Correlation Deduced from a Small Sample," Metron, 1:3-32, 1921. Introduction The likelihood principle as stated by Edwards (1972, p. 30) is that Within the framework of a statistical model, all the information which the data provide concerning the relative merits of two hypotheses is contained in the likelihood ratio of those hypotheses on the data. ...For a continuum of hypotheses, this principle -
School of Social Sciences Economics Division University of Southampton Southampton SO17 1BJ, UK
School of Social Sciences Economics Division University of Southampton Southampton SO17 1BJ, UK Discussion Papers in Economics and Econometrics Professor A L Bowley’s Theory of the Representative Method John Aldrich No. 0801 This paper is available on our website http://www.socsci.soton.ac.uk/economics/Research/Discussion_Papers ISSN 0966-4246 Key names: Arthur L. Bowley, F. Y. Edgeworth, , R. A. Fisher, Adolph Jensen, J. M. Keynes, Jerzy Neyman, Karl Pearson, G. U. Yule. Keywords: History of Statistics, Sampling theory, Bayesian inference. Professor A. L. Bowley’s Theory of the Representative Method * John Aldrich Economics Division School of Social Sciences University of Southampton Southampton SO17 1BJ UK e-mail: [email protected] Abstract Arthur. L. Bowley (1869-1957) first advocated the use of surveys–the “representative method”–in 1906 and started to conduct surveys of economic and social conditions in 1912. Bowley’s 1926 memorandum for the International Statistical Institute on the “Measurement of the precision attained in sampling” was the first large-scale theoretical treatment of sample surveys as he conducted them. This paper examines Bowley’s arguments in the context of the statistical inference theory of the time. The great influence on Bowley’s conception of statistical inference was F. Y. Edgeworth but by 1926 R. A. Fisher was on the scene and was attacking Bayesian methods and promoting a replacement of his own. Bowley defended his Bayesian method against Fisher and against Jerzy Neyman when the latter put forward his concept of a confidence interval and applied it to the representative method. * Based on a talk given at the Sample Surveys and Bayesian Statistics Conference, Southampton, August 2008. -
Correlation of Salivary Immunoglobulin a Against Lipopolysaccharide of Porphyromonas Gingivalis with Clinical Periodontal Parameters
Correlation of salivary immunoglobulin A against lipopolysaccharide of Porphyromonas gingivalis with clinical periodontal parameters Pushpa S. Pudakalkatti, Abhinav S. Baheti Abstract Background: A major challenge in clinical periodontics is to find a reliable molecular marker of periodontal tissue destruction. Aim: The aim of the present study was to assess, whether any correlation exists between salivary immunoglobulin A (IgA) level against lipopolysaccharide of Porphyromonas gingivalis and clinical periodontal parameters (probing depth and clinical attachment loss). Materials and Methods: Totally, 30 patients with chronic periodontitis were included for the study based on clinical examination. Unstimulated saliva was collected from each study subject. Probing depth and clinical attachment loss were recorded in all selected subjects using University of North Carolina‑15 periodontal probe. Extraction and purification of lipopolysaccharide were done from the standard strain of P. gingivalis (ATCC 33277). Enzyme linked immunosorbent assay (ELISA) was used to detect the level of IgA antibodies against lipopolysaccharide of P. gingivalis in the saliva of each subject by coating wells of ELISA kit with extracted lipopolysaccharide antigen. Statistical Analysis: The correlation between salivary IgA and clinical periodontal parameters was checked using Karl Pearson’s correlation coefficient method and regression analysis. Results: The significant correlation was observed between salivary IgA level and clinical periodontal parameters in chronic -
Frequentist and Bayesian Statistics
Faculty of Life Sciences Frequentist and Bayesian statistics Claus Ekstrøm E-mail: [email protected] Outline 1 Frequentists and Bayesians • What is a probability? • Interpretation of results / inference 2 Comparisons 3 Markov chain Monte Carlo Slide 2— PhD (Aug 23rd 2011) — Frequentist and Bayesian statistics What is a probability? Two schools in statistics: frequentists and Bayesians. Slide 3— PhD (Aug 23rd 2011) — Frequentist and Bayesian statistics Frequentist school School of Jerzy Neyman, Egon Pearson and Ronald Fischer. Slide 4— PhD (Aug 23rd 2011) — Frequentist and Bayesian statistics Bayesian school “School” of Thomas Bayes P(D|H) · P(H) P(H|D)= P(D|H) · P(H)dH Slide 5— PhD (Aug 23rd 2011) — Frequentist and Bayesian statistics Frequentists Frequentists talk about probabilities in relation to experiments with a random component. Relative frequency of an event, A,isdefinedas number of outcomes consistent with A P(A)= number of experiments The probability of event A is the limiting relative frequency. Relative frequency 0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 020406080100 n Slide 6— PhD (Aug 23rd 2011) — Frequentist and Bayesian statistics Frequentists — 2 The definition restricts the things we can add probabilities to: What is the probability of there being life on Mars 100 billion years ago? We assume that there is an unknown but fixed underlying parameter, θ, for a population (i.e., the mean height on Danish men). Random variation (environmental factors, measurement errors, ...) means that each observation does not result in the true value. Slide 7— PhD (Aug 23rd 2011) — Frequentist and Bayesian statistics The meta-experiment idea Frequentists think of meta-experiments and consider the current dataset as a single realization from all possible datasets. -
Fiducial Inference: an Approach Based on Bootstrap Techniques
U.P.B. Sci. Bull., Series A, Vol. 69, No. 1, 2007 ISSN 1223-7027 FIDUCIAL INFERENCE: AN APPROACH BASED ON BOOTSTRAP TECHNIQUES H.-D. HEIKE1, C-tin TÂRCOLEA2, Adina I. TARCOLEA3, M. DEMETRESCU4 În prima parte a acestei lucrări sunt prezentate conceptele de bază ale inferenţei fiduciale. La aplicarea acestui principiu inferenţial apar dificultăţi când distribuţia variabilei pivotale folosite nu este cunoscută. În partea a doua este propusă o soluţie pentru această problemă constând în folosirea de metode bootstrap. The basic concepts of fiducial inference are presented in the first part of this paper. Problems arise if the form of the distribution of the pivot used by the fiducial argument is not known. Our main result consists in showing how bootstrap techniques can be used to handle this kind of situation. Keywords: Fiducial distribution, estimation of parameters, pivotal methods, approximation of distributions, approximate pivot. AMS 2000 Classification: 62F99 1. Introduction Commenting on Fisher’s work, [3] stated at the beginning of his paper: ’The history of fiducial probability dates back over thirty years and so is long by statistical standards; however, thirty years have not proved long enough for agreement to be reached among statisticians as to the derivation, manipulation and interpretation of fiducial probability’. Forty years later, the situation is very much the same. What is actually the fiducial theory? The fiducial model designed by Fisher leads us to objective probability statements about values of unknown parameters solely on the basis of given data, without resorting to any prior distribution. The idea that the initially assumed randomness may be preserved was one of Fisher’s great contributions to the theory of statistical estimation; the lack of acceptance arose from the fact that 1 Prof., Statistics and Econometrics, Technical University Darmstadt, Residenzschloss, D-64289 Darmstadt, GERMANY. -
Statistical Inference a Work in Progress
Ronald Christensen Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of New Mexico Copyright c 2019 Statistical Inference A Work in Progress Springer v Seymour and Wes. Preface “But to us, probability is the very guide of life.” Joseph Butler (1736). The Analogy of Religion, Natural and Revealed, to the Constitution and Course of Nature, Introduction. https://www.loc.gov/resource/dcmsiabooks. analogyofreligio00butl_1/?sp=41 Normally, I wouldn’t put anything this incomplete on the internet but I wanted to make parts of it available to my Advanced Inference Class, and once it is up, you have lost control. Seymour Geisser was a mentor to Wes Johnson and me. He was Wes’s Ph.D. advisor. Near the end of his life, Seymour was finishing his 2005 book Modes of Parametric Statistical Inference and needed some help. Seymour asked Wes and Wes asked me. I had quite a few ideas for the book but then I discovered that Sey- mour hated anyone changing his prose. That was the end of my direct involvement. The first idea for this book was to revisit Seymour’s. (So far, that seems only to occur in Chapter 1.) Thinking about what Seymour was doing was the inspiration for me to think about what I had to say about statistical inference. And much of what I have to say is inspired by Seymour’s work as well as the work of my other professors at Min- nesota, notably Christopher Bingham, R. Dennis Cook, Somesh Das Gupta, Mor- ris L. Eaton, Stephen E. Fienberg, Narish Jain, F. Kinley Larntz, Frank B. -
D 27 April 1936 Summary. Karl Pearson Was Founder of The
Karl PEARSON1 b. 27 March 1857 - d 27 April 1936 Summary. Karl Pearson was Founder of the Biometric School. He made prolific contributions to statistics, eugenics and to the scientific method. Stimulated by the applications of W.F.R. Weldon and F. Galton he laid the foundations of much of modern mathematical statistics. Founder of biometrics, Karl Pearson was one of the principal architects of the modern theory of mathematical statistics. He was a polymath whose interests ranged from astronomy, mechanics, meteorology and physics to the biological sciences in particular (including anthropology, eugenics, evolution- ary biology, heredity and medicine). In addition to these scientific pursuits, he undertook the study of German folklore and literature, the history of the Reformation and German humanists (especially Martin Luther). Pear- son’s writings were prodigious: he published more than 650 papers in his lifetime, of which 400 are statistical. Over a period of 28 years, he founded and edited 6 journals and was a co-founder (along with Weldon and Galton) of the journal Biometrika. University College London houses the main set of Pearson’s collected papers which consist of 235 boxes containing family papers, scientific manuscripts and 16,000 letters. Largely owing to his interests in evolutionary biology, Pearson created, al- most single-handedly, the modern theory of statistics in his Biometric School at University College London from 1892 to 1903 (which was practised in the Drapers’ Biometric Laboratory from 1903-1933). These developments were underpinned by Charles Darwin’s ideas of biological variation and ‘sta- tistical’ populations of species - arising from the impetus of statistical and experimental work of his colleague and closest friend, the Darwinian zoolo- gist, W.F.R. -
The Significance Test Controversy Revisited: the Fiducial Bayesian
Bruno LECOUTRE Jacques POITEVINEAU The Significance Test Controversy Revisited: The fiducial Bayesian Alternative July 26, 2014 Springer Contents 1 Introduction ................................................... 3 1.1 The fiducial Bayesian Inference. .4 1.2 The Stranglehold of Significance Tests . .5 1.3 Beyond the Significance Test Controversy . .6 1.4 The Feasibility of Fiducial Bayesian Methods . .6 1.5 Plan of the Book . .7 2 Preamble - Frequentist and Bayesian Inference .................... 9 2.1 Two Different Approaches to Statistical Inference . .9 2.2 The Frequentist Approach: From Unknown to Known . 10 2.2.1 Sampling Probabilities . 10 2.2.2 Null Hypothesis Significance Testing in Practice . 11 2.2.3 Confidence Interval . 12 2.3 The Bayesian Approach: From Known to Unknown . 12 2.3.1 The Likelihood Function and the Bayesian Probabilities . 12 2.3.2 An Opinion-Based Analysis . 14 2.3.3 A “No Information Initially” Analysis . 16 3 The Fisher, Neyman-Pearson and Jeffreys views of Statistical Tests . 21 3.1 The Fisher Test of Significance . 21 3.2 The Neyman-Pearson Hypothesis Test . 23 3.3 The Jeffreys Bayesian Approach to Testing . 25 3.4 Different Views of Statistical Inference . 28 3.4.1 Different Scopes of Applications: The Aim of Statistical Inference . 28 3.4.2 The Role of Bayesian Probabilities . 30 3.4.3 Statistical Tests: Judgment, Action or Decision? . 32 3.5 Is It possible to Unify the Fisher and Neyman-Pearson Approaches? 34 3.6 Concluding Remarks . 35 v vi Contents 4 GHOST: An officially Recommended Practice ..................... 37 4.1 Null Hypothesis Significance Testing . 37 4.1.1 An Amalgam . -
“It Took a Global Conflict”— the Second World War and Probability in British
Keynames: M. S. Bartlett, D.G. Kendall, stochastic processes, World War II Wordcount: 17,843 words “It took a global conflict”— the Second World War and Probability in British Mathematics John Aldrich Economics Department University of Southampton Southampton SO17 1BJ UK e-mail: [email protected] Abstract In the twentieth century probability became a “respectable” branch of mathematics. This paper describes how in Britain the transformation came after the Second World War and was due largely to David Kendall and Maurice Bartlett who met and worked together in the war and afterwards worked on stochastic processes. Their interests later diverged and, while Bartlett stayed in applied probability, Kendall took an increasingly pure line. March 2020 Probability played no part in a respectable mathematics course, and it took a global conflict to change both British mathematics and D. G. Kendall. Kingman “Obituary: David George Kendall” Introduction In the twentieth century probability is said to have become a “respectable” or “bona fide” branch of mathematics, the transformation occurring at different times in different countries.1 In Britain it came after the Second World War with research on stochastic processes by Maurice Stevenson Bartlett (1910-2002; FRS 1961) and David George Kendall (1918-2007; FRS 1964).2 They also contributed as teachers, especially Kendall who was the “effective beginning of the probability tradition in this country”—his pupils and his pupils’ pupils are “everywhere” reported Bingham (1996: 185). Bartlett and Kendall had full careers—extending beyond retirement in 1975 and ‘85— but I concentrate on the years of setting-up, 1940-55.