<<

ON THE OF CHOICE A ND REGULARITY

John H. HARRIS

O. Introduction

In § I a problem is posed which suggests a need fo r a ve ry strong of choice or some extra axiom of theory. The Axiom of Regularity (REG) is the extra axiom that is usually used. In § 2 some implications of REG are given. In terms of a general definition of "set" given in § 3 it is shown in § 4 that REG seems t o be tru e f o r classical mathematical structures. But the set theoretic mode of thought and modern are not limited to classical structures. In § 5 evidence against REG is given by introducing a new construction process which can be used to construct (reasonable ?) sets contradicting REG. The construction process of § 5 is clearly open to question and is st ill o n ly at the intuitive level. But the ma in point o f the article is not to prove REG false, but to show (as is done in § 5) that REG is a questionable rather than an obviously true axiom of . So in § 6 a neutral viewpoint is adopted neither accepting REG nor its negation. However some limitation type axiom is necessary in order to eliminate such pathologies as -cycles like x (LIiM ) isx introduced and shown to be equivalent to a "no cyci les axiom". A lso L I M and REG a re shown t o be related to .each other in a ve ry natural wa y wit h L I M being a ve ry weakA and REG being a very strong limitation type axiom. Also sincen REG is no longer available to resolve the difficulty raised in A§ 1, a xsufficiently strong a xio m o f choice (A C*) is in tro - duiced too do the job. m o I. fA motivatin g problem L i mLet NBi G denote Von-Neumann-Bernays-G6del se t th e o ry (spt ecifiacally axioms A, B, C o f [4]). To NBG we need to add t i o n 274 JOHN H. HARRIS some form of the (abbrev.: AC) in order to do mathematics as currently practiced. Let us use the following form.

AC: Fo r every class X of pairwise , there exists a choice class C wh ich has exactly one point in common with each non-empty x G X: in symbols, (3C)(V x )

If some of txhe classes X formI (in NBC)[ xa *c0o llection having X Iev,e r, Xwe can gintuuitively think of such a collection. 'What if we h, aiveX an „int uitivae cosllect ion {X ) ,eo D f pairwise disjoint clas- e , l e a m r e[ enc t s ; ses ? Intuitively there exists a choice class C which has exactly h p ro o pwn e -r , onte poinht in c=oemmonn wi th e ach X ? ,. S i n c e bew proper, clee{arlyO AC is not strong enough to justify the exis- tsenccoe ofm asuceh an choice class. Let us first discuss h o w such a soitunatiofn oarise ]st ve] ry .naturally. t We hwill deefine an ordXered set to be any < x , r > o) f sets, such that r Ç x X x. We think of x as (partly) ordered byc r aond wriute " u rlv" f odr ''< u , v > G r" . For example, x could be quasi, partially, totally, o r well-or- dered b y r. The case when r = 0 corresponds to considering x a s t o t a lly unordered, i.e., considering x abstracted f ro m any ordering on it such as is done when we consider the car- dinality of the set x. Let us define two ordered sets < x , r > and < y , s>as being similar o r order isomorphic (abbrev.: < x , r > < y , s>) if f there is a bijective f:x—>y which preserves ordering, i.e.,

urv f ( u ) s f(v) f o r a ll u, v e x .

The equivalence classes wit h respect t o the equivalence re - lation " = " w i l l be called simila rity classes. Note that in the case when r = s = 0 the notion of order isomorphism reduces to that of 1:1 correspondence as used in arguments.

THEOREM 1. I f < x , r > is an ordered set with x t O , then the ON THE AXIOMS OF CHOICE AND REGULARITY 275 similarity class containing < x , r > is a proper class: in sym- bols,

{< y , s > I < x, r > < y , s > } 0 V . PROOF. Choose some u boe the set obtained fro m x b y replacing u oede xnb.o tey Tth eh ureela. tnio n oAbtalinesd foro m r b y replacing a ll p a irs lf< u oe r t r upairsao , < v , u >, o r < u , u > respectively. Then < x , r> u, . Cxlearly F, defined on V -x by F(u) = < x lav 1:u1 fuenction ont the p roper class V-x, hence x> , r u >u , i s R(F) = {f lu ) I u V - x } = < x , u i I Y u V <-x ,x r>} < y , s > , huence is also a proper class, as claimed. QED. o Consider now the intuitive collection g of all similarity clas- s>es o f well-ordered sets. We ju st showed that each such si- m, ila rity class (with the one exception (< 0 , 0 > )) is a proper colass. Thus we can't use A C to prove the existence of an NBG crlas s C wh ich has e xa ctly one point in common wit h each < But in tu itive ly the class of ordinals, denoted b y "On", isu just such a class C. Likewise we can't use A C to prove the existenceo o f a class K , called th e class o f cardinals, wh ich consist, of exactly one point from each simila rity class o r un- orderedu sets. Wh a t to do ? o In the case of the ordinals we are lucky. We can actually d>efi ne in NB C a particular (proper) class, denoted b y On, o f wr el l-ordered sets and then prove (even without the use of AC) thatb every well-ordered set is simila r to exactly one element oyf O n; p u t another way, class O n intersects each simila rity ctlass of well-ordered sets in exactly one point (cf. [9; p, 1791). hIn the case o f cardinals we are as lu cky. Using the tehe ory of ordinals we can actually define in NBG a particular c(proper) class K and prove (with the aid of AC) that every set ocan be put in 1:1 correspondence with exactly one element of Kr ;r pe us tp ao n od ti hn eg rn we aw y , c l a s s K i n t e r s e c t s e a c h s i m i l a r i t y c l a s s o f 276 JOHN H. HARRIS unordered sets in exactly one point. But what about the case of totally ordered sets, o r partially ordered sets ?

2. The Axiom of Regularity

There is a candidate for an axiom of set theory, axiom D of [41, ca lle d th e A x io m o f Regularity (abbrev.: REG), wh ic h solves o u r difficulty. On e standard formulation o f REG says that any non-empty class X contains a t least one set wh ich has no element in common with X: in symbols VX[X v l y EX and v 11 X = 01]. The implications of this not very obvious axiom are far reach- ing, but some easily understandable conclusions are now given. (Cf. [9, pp. 201-3] fo r a more detailed treatment.) First, REG implies that there are n o in fin ite ly descending

c c , e -chains ; i . e . , E E X1 E X0 t h e 'rToe p r o ve this, assume t h e contrary. L e t A = {x 0wherei x ,ixs x E iXversen o is. p rovable.) ,Tno Nehxt let us define a F:0n--*V by eAs ne b—q u F((3) = P( U a

Stage 1: The collection F(1) = P(F(0)) = to, { C M i sa s et.m a d e i n t o

Stage 13: The collection A — U OE<0 F(u ), i f m adne inotot a set. Then any subcollection of A not al- a l r ereadya d a syet is made into a set. Fin a lly a ll of a A are csollecteed and tmade into a set called F((3). i s

Thus V = H = U ccel F(u ) says that a class or collection is a set iff it is made into a set during one of these stages. Put another way, each set is constructed or built up from the empty set via iteration o f the and p o we r set operations sufficiently many times. (A ctu a lly t h e construction procedure i s mu ch easier at successor ordinals since one can show that F(13+1) = P(F((i))-) In order to prove V = H and several other consequences of REG, le t us define a n ordinal valued function g : H — *g(Ox) n= fibrst yu such that x E FM. We call g(x) the rank of the set x. In terms of our interpretation above the rank of a set x is closely related to the stage at which collection x was made into a set. To prove REGV----H, assume V—H O . Then by REG there is some x E V—H such that x n (V H ) — 0, i.e., x c H . Then {e(u) u e x } i s a set o f ordinals, hence i s st rict ly bounded above b y some ordinal 13, i.e., u E x g ( u ) < (3. Then b y de- finition of e and 13 we have

u cF(g (u ))c U a o Hence F ( u ) f o r a l l u E x x g. U a < f i hence F ( u ) ,

xE P( U Œ<13 F(a)) = F((3)1,.;EI 278 JOHN H. HARRIS contradicting

The rank function has nice properties, the important one for us being xey < e(y) for x, yEH where " < " denotes the standard ordering among ordinals. To see this, assume Q(y) f 3 . Then

xcyEF((3) = P ( U Œx y< Ic3 U Fxa (

Then we use A C to choose one element fro m each o f these disjoint sets X f t In summary, NBG +REG + AC implies the following: , h(I) en on incfineit ely descending -c h a i n s ; f(2) ar "boig-bang" theory of sets (all sets are regular); m(3) n o finite E-cycles: e(4) f oar any equivalence relation R, there exists a choice class c Ch o iemptyt R-equivalence class. f Cwonclu sions (3) and (4) are intuitively true statements of set ttheohry. On the other hand (I) and (2) — which in NBG+ AC are heachi equivalent to REG — are not so obviously true. Ma n y elogician s, however, do consider REG to be obvious (cf. [7; p. 561, R[141h)-. But to discuss whether REG is true o r not is to discuss ethe cqquesution, " Wh a t is a set ?" i vo a l en n c3. Ase def inition o f "set" c i l a Lest uss consider the following intuitive definition wh ich we swillt reefer to as the "generalized big-bang" definition of a set s(abbrev.:s . GBB). One starts wit h certain physical and/or con- ceptoual objects, called atoms. We build n e w sets b y stages. At afn y stage we form new sets by taking collections of objects (i.e.,e atoms and/or sets) formed at previous stages. Also at any stagxe we can add new atoms. We iterate this procedure over all paossible stages (one stage for each ordinal a). The collection of setsc so obtained is the collection of all sets. Ctlassically an is defined as an object which isn't a colllection (hence o f course n o t a set) b u t wh ich can be a n elementy o f a set. We adopt a broader outlook and define an atomo as an object which is discovered or formed at some stage by sno me process o t h e r th a n co lle ctin g objects fo rme d a t preveio us stages. Often atoms w i l l be objects defined b y the propeerties they satisfy. It is even possible that an atom is itself a set.l However, an atom x can't be a proper class since if x is introeduced in stage a, then x is a n element o f sets formed m e n t f r o m e a c h n o n - 280 JOHN H. HARRIS during stage a +1 . Hence proper classes a re n o t considered to be objects. One commonly seen version of GBB is to allow starting with certain atoms which are but not allow adding new atoms at future stages (cf. [13; p. 233]). One gets what might be called regular set theory if the collection o f a ll atoms is the empty set. Then the only objects are sets and GBB reduces to a vague wording of the simple "big-bang" axiom V—H, which is equivalent to REG. Thus we can conclude that REG is true for the concept of set embodied in GBB if we can show that we can assume without loss of generality that there are no atoms. In GBB we said that atoms would be physical or conceptual objects. We will also consider sets as conceptual objects. To say that object X is a conceptual object is not meant to imp ly that we are assuming X exists only in the mind of the conceiver and has no existence independent of thought. In this paper we do n o t take sides between conceptualism and platonism (o r realism). Rather we mean that a conceptual object is a non- material object whose existence has been or can be discovered by the use of pure reason.

4. Evidence for REG

One problem with using physical objects such as elementary particles or hamburgers as atoms is that it gives a time depen- dent set theory, wit h sets changing as objects are created o r destroyed. I t is better to th in k of a fixed consisting only o f conceptual objects; then if desired, one can set up a time dependent in fo rma l correspondence between p h ysica l and conceptual objects. What can be done in a set theory with physical atoms can be duplicated u p to "conceptual isomor- phism" in a set theory without physical atoms. Hence without loss o f generality we can assume that there are no physical atoms. But wh a t about atoms wh ich a re conceptual objects; e.g., what about natural numbers ? Conceptually a isn't necessarily a collection and isn 't thought o f as having ON THE AXIOMS OF CHOICE AND REGULARITY 2 8 1 any internal structure. The natural numbers are in fact good examples o f atoms wh ich are introduced conceptually a t a n early stage in GBB and are defined formally by the properties they satisfy. Thus instead of bothering with such foundational questions as " Wh a t is the number 1 ?", the mathematician will usually ju st assume that he is g ive n a collection o f objects (which we are calling atoms) satisfying the second order axioms of number theory and will proceed from there. Fo rma lly this corresponds t o extending the fo rma l theory NB G b y adding new symbols "N", " 0 " , "S", + " , "." and at least the following new proper axioms.

(i) N G ( N is the set of natural numbers) (ii) O N (iii) V x [x N --> Sx N ] (iv) (N i(N x()v, ( ) (vz[o ( v x ) Y ) (vN(ii) x + y and x.y N for all x, y N (v[[viixi)S x +z0 —= x and x + Sy = S(x + y)for all x, y N x>(xix) sx.0x — 0 and x.Sy = x.y + x for all x, y EN. —Z) , 1 — ) S•NLe tN us ccallZ thi]s extended theory NB G+ N. ysThus th e mathematician ju st leaves t h e natural numbers 0,1xx — SO , 2 = SSO, a s unspecified objects or atoms satisfying = ce*rta in properties. Whether these atoms are also sets is usual- lyy left unspecified. I f we are working in ordinary NBG where th]e0re are no urelements and X EV implies X is a set, then a ll the integers are sets, which sets however being left open. If we are working in a modified NBG where we allow urelements as well as sets and classes, (cf. [12]), then we don't even kn o w whether the integers are urelements or sets. Logicians have discovered several ways of defining an NBG set o.) and NBG set functions f , f , , f. such that if N, 0, S, + , are interpreted as u.), 0, fs, f , and f .a rer tehesorpemesc otf i(av deelfinyit,io nal extension of) NBG (cf. [9; pp. t h e n ( i ) ( i x ) 282 JOHN H. HARRIS

175-81 and [10; Ch. IV ]; (when referring to [10] we mean the results of Ch. I V translated into NBG). In fact for such defini- tions as given in [9] and [101 it is provable in NBG that w itself, the elements o f w, and the sets f s(i.e., elements o f H). Put simply, N, 0 , S, + , c a n be defined ,in tferm s, of reagulnar sdets. Thfus in summary, what can be done .in a seta theorry weit h t h e natural numbers as atoms ca n be rdupelicategd (iun falct ian mrany ways) in some definitional exten- sion o fe NBG. t s The average mathematician when studying number theory still probably works conceptually in what would be formalized as N B G + N rather than some definitional extension o f NBG. He wo u ld (o r should) lo o k a t th e wo rk o f [9] a n d [10] a s providing models f o r N B G + N in NBG, hence demonstrating that he can wo rk in NB G + N free of worries of contradiction if he already accepts NBG. It is true that anything that can be done in N B G + N can be done in a definitional extension o f NBG, but the converse is false; e.g., one can prove such "ac- cidental" properties o f the natural numbers as 1 3 in [9] o r 1e2 and 2 e 3 but 1çt3 in [10]. Let us give another example of a mathematical object which conceptually isn't necessarily a collection. Specifically, given any two sets x and y, we have in mind the ordered pair < x , y > . Even if we wanted to, we couldn't start off with a ll the ordered pairs taken as atoms at some fixed stage a: it makes sense to talk about the ordered pair < x , y > o n ly during some stage after the conceptual construction o f the sets x and y themselves. Thus if we were to treat ordered pairs as atoms, we would need to allow the addition of new atoms at every stage. Instead o f bothering wit h the foundational question " Wh a t is the ordered p a ir < x , y > ?", wh a t the mathematician con- ceptually does corresponds f o rma lly t o extending NB G b y adding a new symbol " < , > " and the following proper axioms:

( (ii) (Vx, y)[ 1 / ] X InI 1904 N. Wie n e r discovered that the ordered pair of two ; X 2 r y i , y ) t < x 1 , x 2 > < Y 1 , Y 2 > < - - - ) x i — y i & x 2 = y 2 i ON THE AXIOMS OF CHOICE AND REGULARITY 283 pure sets could be defined in simple set theory. Kuratowski's improved definition reads = ( x ) , {x, y)1. For another definition wh ich though equally a rtificia l does have many advantages o ve r Kuratowski's, consider = ( 0 , )0, (y)1. (cf. [6]). For these definitions it is easily shown that an ordered pair of regular sets is a regular set: in symbols, x, y e H < x , y > In summary: wh a t can be done in a set theory allowing the addition of ordered pairs as atoms can be duplicated (in many different ways) in regular set theory. The same has been shown to be true for other classical con- ceptual objects such as rational, real, o r complex numbers, geometrical surfaces in IV, n- and functions o f real o r complex numbers, etc.: what can be done in a set theory with such atoms can be duplicated in some definitional extension of NBG without atoms. I t is even provable in NBG that the sets u su a lly chosen t o represent such classical objects a re regular sets and the usual set theoretic operations applied to regular sets give regular sets. Thus fo r classical mathematics it seems to be true that we can wo rk in a set theory with no atoms without any loss of generality.

5. Evidence against REG

General set theory and modern mathematics, however, are not limite d to th e study o f classical structures and objects. Are there any non-classical conceptual objects which can't be expressed in terms of a set theory with no atoms ? Good can- didates f o r such objects seem to be objects x othat x ,n x GX2 GX1 EX0 . i= ,x x 2n , s u c h 1 1 f o r a l l n . T h i s g i v e s u s 284 JOHN H. HARRIS

One o f the main goals o f this paper is to describe a general construction procedure wh ich can be used to ju stify the in - tuitive existence of infinitely descending G-chains of concep- tual objects. Let us start b y discussing G-descending chains in general. If we are not excluding the possibility of infinitely descending G-chains, it seems that we must allow the possibility that for any ordinal a we can find an e-descending chain of length a. But wh a t wo u ld we mean b y a chain o f length even w + 1, denoted by

x, e x,, e ...Gx t G x The o n ly reasoonable condition seems to be to require (in ad- dition to the o?bvious condition that x„ , 1xo , bce xin, x,„ for fallo n beyondr asomel m:l in symbols, n < w ) t h a (am)t (Vn) [n m x ] . This suggests the following generalization. An - chaind e ofs lecnegthn bd isi definedn g as a { x a } (i) 3 4 , a < (i1i) f o r every limit ordinal ? s s u c h t h a t ,c xx _a< b) , t h e r e Weef sax,y tihast zt iss a t th e bottom o f a n -d e sce n d in g chain ( x„). ao G < Even i f in fin ite ly descending e -ch a in s e xist th e situation (r x3 < ? , 8 isns'at toao mu essy csince, has sho wn in the next theorem, any two o f settsl cofnnehcted bay such an G-chain are also connected b y a lfineite G-chain. tl o n a r gTHtEOREM 1. I f x + a h2 x and ending at x8, then there exists a finite se- 1 l 6} quence o f ordinals < l +a 0 ----- ao

PROOF. Assume proposition i s t ru e f o r a l l G-descending chains o f length less than b and consider a n y e-descending chain of length 8. I f b is a successor ordinal, say b = (i+ 1, we have

Xs = xt3. 1 If 8 is a limit ordinal, then for some fi<8 we have e x 5 e EXx „ fo r a ll ti--aO• BDy theoirem f1 wef can always choose ( x b . ayt8is s oshmue fcienihte rordineal n . )aet „ L, hset xUas (Z)uit o rc Ush Zx denote t t s hthe auniotn o f the sets in the class Z. bWefo then define =U" Z by in duction as follows: x , i U Z= Z. nx s U " I i= Z Ttzhe uniUon a xiom of NBG just says that if Z is a set, then so is Z henUce a lso U BZ for all ea n n d Z s ) u . b c h a i n , g i v i n g u s t h e f i n i t e 286 JOHN H. HARRIS

For a ll n?„-0 we can easily show b y induction that there exists sets xo, xi, , 1 such that x,,,, ex Fort if true for case n = k, then for case n = k + 1 we have , Xk.,4 eX1,1C X1 3C0 e<=>Xk,, 4 1,,1 Ukx x4=>X,k * T,e hus clearly z is an -a n ce st o r of a set x iff z U "X for some n?xE-0. We can now even define the ancestor function A where forU an y set x A (x) equals the set of a ll G-ancestors o f x: in symok bols , <+ A(x)I = (Unx) Unxin<00. =X TH>.EORE M 2. Assume that there are no finite G-cycles. Then forx each set x there is an ordinal 6, such that all G-descending chains starting at x are of length less than b PxR,OOF. Fo r any set x let 6, be the first greater t.ha,n the cardinality o f A (x) — in the standard development of ,NB G + AC cardinal numbers are ordinal numbers. No w con- sider any G-descending chain x . 1 „, s with x aor e1 d=iff erexnt:. fo r oAthelrwisl e the et -dehsceneding chain connecting x.x Œand „xo where x . = xo and ct c o u l d be replaced b y a finUite c-ch a in , giving us a finite e -cycle . Also each x. is an G-ancestor of x toh e"re= a re xele.me nts of A(x), hence b

Then if we denote f(a) b y x„ we have x ox x i Figuarativnely spdeaki ng we see that in constructing -a s c e n - e,ding cvhainse we nconceptually construct each x5 i n te rms o f cpr eviously completely constructed x xOrecEursive process. I n contrast, t o conceptually construct e - di( ea s

yk +I = { N ( k +1), yo, • • • Yk}• Finally, le t x„ = y N Clearly the y „ are regular sets since they are b u ilt up b y r,e cuf rsoionr starting with the regular set NI ). Hence the x„ are regular. In o u r construction o f th e same x „ b y th e simultaneous process we will use stages 0, N , N +1. We first use sugges- tive wording to aid the conceptual visualization of the process. At stage 0 we make an open necked (conceptual) balloon and label it x oby passing it through the open neck of x .so ures that we will have Om)( W(.Assume, Tewh h iwese nhac veo cownmpdleetei dt stagesi o n 0, 1, n 1 where tfiAt hsi tangne ni w-es inthrod uce and start to work with x„ and continue eawithn oul r conlstruct ion activities on the x poiwe f moarkue aino

in terms of conditions imposed on the xi„ during various stages, is as follows: Stage n?-0: require x i 1Sta gee cxo: iclosure step. That„ f f oo lr l o w s trivia lly from the definition of stages en anda to. cCleahrly a ll the x vi1ious prob lems. What is the difference between say xi °1„if ia* jnr ? edT.h esnxe otiwon o-bjects appear merely to be copies of each °rotheerg, buut lwae cra.n't prove that they are equal. For that matter, xBi u t ot For ha n y see t x r l e t A.*(x) -= x U A(x), o fte n ca lle d t h e etransit ive closure of x. We say that two sets x and y have the vsaame E-strructure if f A''(x) and ik*(y) are - • eitheres o mexois trsp ah 1:1i c fu, n ctiion. f ferom. A'K, (x) onto AL*(y) such that no b u e v f ( u ) e f (v) fo r a ll u, v A * ( x ) . s- eWe abbreviate this b y " A *(x) i k * ( y ) under f". e Intuitively one feels that two sets with the same e-structure mare equal. Strong support fo r his feeling is given b y the fo l- slo wing result, provable in NBG without REG. t oTH EOREM 3. Let x and y be regular sets. Then x and y have bthe same -s t ru c t u re iff x = y. PeR OOF. Use the proof of the Shepherdson-Mostowski theorem, acf. [3; p. 73]. Since x and y are assumed to be regular and since cREG restricted to the class H of all regular sets is provable in oNBG, the proof can be carried out without assuming REG. QED. p Now we don't know what part of our intuition or knowledge yof regular sets should ca rry o ve r to non-regular sets, i f the loatter exist in any reasonable sense. But it does seem falacious fto recognize the existence of two o r more distinct sets wh ich can'tx b e conceptually distinguished b y ju st looking a t th e ir e-structures. And we do want to construct as reasonable non- l r„eg ular sets as possible. So we propose the following axiom. STRUCTUREf A X I O M: I f two sets have the same e-structure, tohen they are equal: in symbols r a A*(x) A*(y) x y. n y n > 0 . ON THE AXIOMS OF CHOICE AND REGULARITY 291

THEOREM 4. Th e re is no sequence ( x 1 x ) n 0PR OsOFu (inc NhBG + tStruhctuare +t No G -cycles): Assume there is such a =s equence of sets. Then A*(x,) and A * (x iG-struc{ture: the G-isomorphism f is given by ) h ax v e t h e „f (x s a i m e Hence „according to the Structure Axiom x , ix = 1x k io We s}a y that x is a non-regular set if we can find sets xi, x2, ) .E suTchf hthaut s w e o= hx a cvx e rx ° 2 ni W, heneverG we construct a sequence {x.}a

Stage n,>-0: require n e x nSt agae: na):d cl osxure, . „ For1 a ny ne thex on.ly stage. at which any potential element is ad- ded to x pno tei nstia l element x ns t a x ,g e n lTnhe proofs of properties (i) - (iii) are similar to but simpler than = .t,h e Tp rohofus osf s,im ilar properties for the next theorem which we { bwa ill pyrove in detail. Q E D . n sn Out r naext tgheorem shows one wa y to construct an e -descen- , edding c hain of length 8, given any 8>0. x at ) „ wThHEOREMe 6. B y t h e simultaneous process, f o r a n y ordinal , bhe>0 theare exists an e-descending chain {x}a < 6 such that 1 vn e x„ { x }, I a

Now to discuss the regularity of the x„ for a<8. I f 8 isn't a limit ordinal, then = A.+N-F1 where A = 0 o r a limit ordinal depending on whether 8co. One then shows that

X x + are regulai r sets as in example 1. I f 8 ? is a limit orr dinal, then for any a

(3),, A * ( x ΠIf it

We have a e x„. But a ex5 for otherwise a = x, for some (3

x, e A (x. ) = f x„ I a

  • aGx, a = f(a) f ( x 4 = x5 = { ca —, xI„ fo(r 3so0 and any semi-regular set x. Then we can find an e-descending chain {x „}, 5 such that xs = x. In fact using the simultaneous construction process we can build such a sequence so that it is provable in NBG that these sets, if they exist, have the following properties: (i) x 5 Ex„, x5 c x,, not: A*(x5) = A ( x ) (ii) x „ is semi-regular for any a•-•<,_6. PROOF. Let y be the first ordinal larger than a ll ordinals in x or any of the e-ancestors of x. We now give a description of a simultaneous construction of sets x, for ett..8, stated in terms of conditions i n iStage r e q u i r e x„ e x , and y+ e x , , for all a<1.i. Also irepqouisree xd x „ . oStagne 6+ 1: closure. tOneh easeily shows that for any a b we have x (5),, x , = x U {x„ a < ) t - 6 } U (y+it a<12--'0) „ dNoteu thatr this will give x5=x. i Thatn xg5ex„ , and xo cx, for any a<13:-Çb is obvious from (5)„ vand (5a)5. To prove x5c x, we obviously have r i o e x,, u s sbut usting (5)5 we can show that a(6) y+a+1g x5. e s .In detail we have y H - y+ a + 1 (x „1 (3 < 1 1 . 6 ). a + 1 E x bFor ify 13<) 1 <6, then x , * y + a +1 since y + + 1 e x , b y (5), but dy+)e(+1f Ei yn+ ai+ 1t siince a <)); and i f )1 = b then x 6 # y + a + 1 o n o f y . A l s o 296 JOHN H. HARRIS because y+a e y + a + 1 whereas y hence y +a is larger than any ordinal in xs = x. Finally since a

    (7)„ A ( x „ ) A „ D r A(x) U {x, I a < U I lt-Y-F-6}• To show that each x„ is normal, assume otherwise. Then for some a we have x„ A (x OthisE leads to a contradiction. In particular x )afo rU 1-

    6. A neutral viewpoint One main point o f this paper is not to prove that REG is false but to show that REG is a questionable rather than an obviously true axiom of set theory. Having made an attempt to do this in § 5 we will now take a neutral viewpoint neither accepting REG nor its negation. However, some limitation type axiom is necessary to eliminate such pathologies as - c y c l e s . REG is a strong version of such a limitation axiom. We n o w introduce the weakest possible version which is equivalent to but simpler in form and more usable than the "no (finite)" cycles" hypothesis. A X IOM OF L IMITA TON (abbrev.: LIM). There exists a func- tion CI with domain V and a strict partial ordering < on Me ), the range of e , s u c h X y e ( x ) < e ( y ) for all x, y V . t h a t 298 JOHN H. HARRIS

    A ll the following theorems are provable in NBG. THEOREM 1. L I M n o finite e -cycle s. PROOF. If there were sets x i , x X1„ X2 s u c h thenh a t Q4)0 Q(x)ce(y) t r(ii)a x ny--*9 (x) g ( y ) s i t i v iPRt OyOF : Define Q : V b y p(x) = A(x) where A (x) denotes othe set of c-ancestors of x. Then (ii) just says that x g y implies fA (x)ÇA ( y) which is obviously true. To prove (i), assume x e y .

    THEOREM 4. I f we can choose 0 and < in L IM such that R(Q .is strictly well-ordered b y < , then REG holds. )PROOF. We want to show that X Q ) : , Let A = {e(x) x e X). Then A is a non-empty subclass of the : f x class ,q(e) strictly well-ordered by < hence A has a <-first ele- [ x X ment, say a a n odon't need A C since we are making o n ly one choice.) Then d . and x x Cp(uh) 0o( ox n s0QEeD. n X o)Comment: =n X T he rank function e defined in § 2 satisfied = ea = (i) xo 0 ( x ) c (y) eo l e0 (ii) R](9) is strictly well-ordered by my ee : • ntWha t t w fe can't show in NBG and need REG for is to show that xuthe domoain H of the rank function is all of V. oeSay the r e of LIM is interpreted as a function which relates each fXset to ai stage o f some kind, ma y be a stage measuring the r,comple fxity o f sets. Then LIM says that if x y then Q(x)<@(y), ochenoce xx belongs to a lower, earlier, or simpler stage than does mny. LtIM thuso says that the stages are partially ordered. REG says {rthatax then stages are well-ordered. Xd Hial vinXg reje cted REG as an axiom and chosen the weaker ecaxiot m iL0IM, we are now back to where we started in § I: how (ndo wxge j ),ustify the choosing of one element from each class in =tan inatuistive collection o f mutually disjoint (possibly proper) 0hclasses ?a Given any such w e can define an intuitive equiva- }elenc.e re yla tion R given by Wd u R(x, y) -,)•- HX [ X . 2 e x . & x X fConversoely, g ive n a n y in tu itive equivalence relation R, w e & ihave thnat R b reaks up its field in to mutually disjoint classes, y X ] . nviz., theX R-equivalence classes. Thus we have a correspondence ibetween, intu itive collections 1 t.in touiftiv et m equuivtaulenacel rel laytio ns. In general we can't wo rk with idsuchi csohllejctio nsi onf clatsse s in NBG, but we can handle many oc l ea s s e ns n oa n d f a u . 300 JOHN H. HARRIS of t h e corresponding equivalence relations. F o r a n y NB G equivalence relation R let [x1 Rde tedrmeinnedo bty ex. We suggest the following replacement for AC. tA X IhOM eA C* : RFo r- each equivalence relation R, there exists ea classq u C suchi v tahatl Ce intnerscects every non-empty R-equivalence eclas s in exactly one point: in symbols, c l a s (aC) ( V s x THEOREM 5. AC* AC ) PR[O OF. Consider any class X of pairwise disjoint non-empty set0s. Defin e Rc V X V by - - - y > R ( a w ) x [ x & y W a] The. n R is an equivalence relation on its field. (The field o f a relaution is the union o f its domain and range.) Cle a rly the R- eq[uivalence classes are just the sets w X . Q E D . InC sum mary, we have weakened the limitation type axiom fronm REG to L IM which in turn necessitated strengthening the choice[ axiom from A C to AC* in order to handle the problem raisxed in § l• Ilt seems that AC* is adequate for our purposes, resolves the difzficulti es o f § I, avoids need o f hypothesizing REG, and yet is s=t ill in tu itive ly true. There are some stronger (candidates for){ axioms of class-set theory which we now give. O STRONGE WELL-ORDERING A X IOM (abbrev.: WO*): The class V of all sets can be well-ordered.

    WEAK BIG BANG A X I O M (abbrev.: WBB): There is a func- tion F wit h domain On such that

    (i) < 0 F ( a ) g F((i), a ll a, (3c On (ii) V .= U aeOn F(a)

    The relation between WBB and GBB of § 3 is clearly that GBB implies WBB. It is easy to show that WO* imp lie s A C* and WBB. Con- versely one can show that AC W B B implies WO*, hence A ct , ON THE AXIOMS OF CHOICE AND REGULARITY 301 by using the idea of the proof that A C+RE G implies WO* as given in [11; pp. 84-7]. Thus if one accepts the GBB character- ization of a set, then one must accept WBB and hence doesn't need AC*.

    Stevens Institute of Technology J o h n H. HARRIS

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    [1] P. BERNAYS, "A system of axiomatic set theory VI I ", J ournal of Symbolic Logic, (19) 1954, 81-96. [2] M . BOFFA, "S u r l'existence d'ensembles n ia n t l e Fundierungs ax iom", Journal of Symbolic Logic, (34) 1969, 538-539. [3] P. COHEN, Set t heory and t he c ontinuum hypothesis, Benjamin, N e w York, 1966, 154 pp. [4] K. G5DEL, Th e consistency o f t h e c ontinuum hypothesis, Princ eton, 1940, 69 pp. [5] P. HAWK, ''Modelle der Mengelehre, i n denen Mengen gegebener Ge- stalt existieren", Zeitschr. f. math. Logik und Grundlagen d. Math., 11 (1965), 103-115. [6] J . HARRIS, "On a problem of Th. Skolem", Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, X I (1970) 372-374. [7] K. KURATOWSKI and A. MOSTOWSKI, Set theory, Nort h Holland, Ams ter- dam, 1968, 417 pp. [8] A . LEVY, T h e Fraenkel-Mostowski method f or independence proofs in set t heory ". Th e Theory o f Models , ed. Addis on, He n k in & Tars k i, North Holland, Amsterdam, 1965, pp. 221-228. [9] E. MENDELSON, Introduc tion t o mathematical logic , Van Nostrand, Prin- ceton, 1964, 300 pp. [10] W. QUINE, Set theory and its logic , Harv ard, Cambridge, 1963, 359 pp. [11] H. RUBIN and J. ROBIN, Equivalents of the ax iom of choice, Nort h Hol- land, Ams terdam, 1963, 134 pp. [12] J. RUBIN, Set theory for the mathematician, Holden Day, San Francisco, 1967, 387 pp. [13] J. SHOENFIELD, Mat hemat ic al logic , Addis on-Wes ley , Reading, 1967, 344 pp. [14] J. SHOENEIELD, Rev iew #2025, Mathematic al Reviews 38 (1969).