<<

Poetic WeltLiteraturen/ World Literatures

Schriftenreihe der Friedrich Schlegel Graduiertenschule für literaturwissenschaftliche Studien

Herausgegeben von Jutta Müller-Tamm, Andrew James Johnston, Anne Eusterschulte, Susanne Frank und Michael Gamper

Wissenschaftlicher Beirat Ute Berns (Universität Hamburg), Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht (), Renate Lachmann (Universität Konstanz), Ken’ichi Mishima (Osaka University), Glenn W. Most (Scuola Normale Superiore Pisa), Jean-Marie Schaeffer (EHESS ), Stefan Keppler-Tasaki (University of Tōkyō), Janet A. Walker (Rutgers University), David Wellbery (University of Chicago), Christopher Young (University of Cambridge) Volume 19 Poetic Critique

Encounters with Art and Literature

Edited by Michel Chaouli, Jan Lietz, Jutta Müller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener ISBN 978-3-11-068857-3 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-068871-9 e-ISBN (EPUB) 978-3-11-068881-8 ISSN 2198-9370 DOI https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719

This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. For details go to https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/

Library of Congress Control Number: 2020951273

Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de.

© 2021 Michel Chaouli, Jan Lietz, Jutta Müller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener, published by Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston The book is published open access at www.degruyter.com. Cover: Designed by Jürgen Brinckmann, Berlin, using a graphic by Anne Eusterschulte Printing and binding: CPI books GmbH, Leck www.degruyter.com We thank the Einstein Foundation Berlin for its generous support of the publication of this volume.

Contents

Michel Chaouli, Jan Lietz, JuttaMüller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener What Is Poetic Critique? 1

Jennifer Ashton Why Adding ‘Poetic’ to ‘Critique’ Adds NothingtoCritique 7

Michel Chaouli Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used 19

Amit Chaudhuri Storytelling and Forgetfulness 35

Jeff Dolven Poetry, Critique, Imitation 45

Alexander García Düttmann “Echo Reconciles” 57

Jonathan Elmer On Not Forcing the Question: Criticism and Playing Along 65

Anne Eusterschulte La ChambrePoétique 79

Joshua Kates The Silence of the Concepts (in Meillassoux’s After Finitude and Gottlob Frege) 105

BettineMenke Theater as Critical Praxis: Interruption and Citability 125

Walter Benn Michaels ’sForms: TheAestheticsofCritique 145

Yi-Ping Ong Poetic Criticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 155

Simon Schleusener Surface, Distance, Depth: TheText and its Outside 175 VIII Contents

Contributors 203 Michel Chaouli, Jan Lietz, JuttaMüller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener What Is Poetic Critique?

Poeticcritique – is thatnot an oxymoron?Dothese two forms of behavior – the po- etic and the critical – not pull in different,evenopposite, directions?For manyschol- ars workinginthe today, they largely do, but thathas not always been the case. Friedrich Schlegel, for one, believed that critique worthyofits name must use philologyand history not to bury the work, but to renew and intensify it.Inhis “On Goethe’sMeister,” for example, Schlegelsuggests that we need to criticize in and through poetry:The poetic critic, he writes, “ want to represent the representationanew,and form once more what has alreadybeenformed; he will add to the work, restoreit, shape it afresh” (Schlegel 2003,281). It is aliterary exam- ple thatmotivates him, namelythe discussion of the stagingofHamlet in Goethe’s novel. Still, Schlegel prompts us to envision amode of critique and of criticism (Kritik can mean either)that reflects on the poetic dimension of its own practice. Criticizing here means: rewriting, broadening, amplifying,advancing,vitalizing, valuing, and evaluatingthe wealth of meaning in literature. Schlegel suggests thatonlythis form of critique – he calls it poetische Kritik – stands achance of responding ade- quatelytoawork of art. This is not abook about Schlegel’sconcept of criticism, though his name and his ideas haunt many chapters that follow.Rather,his notion of poetic critique serves us as aprovocation to rethink and to reimagine what critique and criticism could be today. It is an invitation to examine the possibilities and limitations of such acritique in our encounters with artand literature,especiallyinview of debatesthat the prac- tice of critique has recentlycalled forth. We do not hold fast to adefinitive meaning of the notion, nor do we have aready-made idea of which practiceswould fall under the term and which would not.Yet we do find the time right to experiment with a mode of critical thought and practice that runs counter to the receivednotion of cri- tique as invariablynegative,amode that dares to bridge the gapsupposedlydividing art from critique. More than anything,the concept of poetic critique givesvoice to a desire – characteristic of Schlegel’stime and of our own – to draw close the realms of literatureand art,onthe one hand,and of research and critique, on the other,and let them mingle and affect each other. As we use it,the term poetic critique is an umbrella for the manydifferent ways of crossing the boundaries by which the poetic and the critical have often been held apart.Poeticcritique takes on manyguises: it can be amode of thinking, philological practice, poetic process, exercise in immersion, and intellectual challenge. While the gathered here approach the concept from manyangles and put it to use in a variety of periods and constellations, they have in common acommitment to reflect on how poetic critique might lead to afresh understanding of the nature and func-

OpenAccess. ©2021MichelChaouli, Jan Lietz, Jutta Müller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener,published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the CreativeCommons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDeriva- tives 4.0 License. https:// doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-001 2 Michel Chaouli, Jan Lietz, JuttaMüller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener

tion of critique. The thread running through the volume is this question: how can the idea of poetic critique shape our owncritical practice?

Critique and Postcritique

By no means are we the first to have raised the question of critique. It looms large in anumber of recent debates in the humanities.¹ Well before the publication of Rita Felski’sinfluential volume TheLimits of Critique in 2015,various authorshad begun to rethink critical practice, seeking ways of engagingwith literature and art in aless ‘suspicious,’ symptomatic, and antagonistic manner. There have been pleas for “uncritical ” (cf. Warner 2004), “reparative reading” (cf. Sedgwick 2003), “surface reading” (cf. Best and Marcus 2009), “just reading” (cf. Marcus 2007,73‒108), and “descriptive reading” (cf. Love2010), to name onlyafew.Inevi- tably, these disparate effortshavebeen diagnosed as signalingyet another ‘turn,’ this time apostcritical turn.Though their modes of transport and theirdestinations differ,these approachesdohaveacommon starting point: adissatisfaction with a form of criticism common since the 1980s, particularlyinthe Anglo-American con- text,that focuses on atext’scontext and gaps, its latent meanings, ideological impli- cations, hiddentruths, and repressed content. Against these practices – associated, for example, with some forms of decon- structive,psychoanalytic, Marxist,feminist,postcolonial, and queer criticism – the models proposed by postcritics seek to be more attentive to atext’smanifest content, aesthetic properties,and affective capacities.Their stated goal is to be more affirma- tive and open-minded towardsliterary texts and otherworks of art.This reorientation coincides with the emergence of anumber of new,orupdated, theoretical models: while critical criticism was geared to schools of thoughtthatPaulRicœur has called the “school of suspicion”–with its three “masters of suspicion,” Marx,Nietzsche, and Freud, showing the way(Ricœur 1970,32‒33) – postcritical criticism seeks its theoretical orientation elsewhere: in actor-network theory,the new , ob- ject-oriented ,affect theory,and ordinary languagephilosophy. But while the adherents of these and similar methodologies maysee, and appre- ciate, the dawningofanew postcritical era, others claim thatnow is preciselythe right “time for critique” (cf. Fassin and Harcourt 2019). Somefear thatthe hard- won practice of examining texts in their historical context and in view of their social conditions and political implications might give waytoaquietist aestheticism or for- malism, just when critical voices are desperatelyneeded. Then thereare disciplinary and methodological debates:Isliterarystudies falling backinto ? How does apostcritical approach to literatureconceive of the relationship between text

 Cf., amongothers,the followinganthologies:Jaeggi and Wesche 2009,Ankerand Felski 2017,Graw and Menke2019,and Fassin and Harcourt 2019. What Is Poetic Critique? 3

and context?And what would be the consequences of redefining this relationship as one of actorsand networks?Someofthese challenges are raised by essays in this volume. Forthe rest,the challenges form the background against which the essays unfold theirthinking.

Practicing Poetic Critique

While some essays in this volume take theirbearingsfrom the above-mentioned new methodologies,others strike out on their own;yet others go back to Ricœur’s “school of suspicion,” perhaps to go beyond suspicion. Poetic critique, as reflected in this volume, sometimes has affinities with postcritique and sometimes not,yet in no case is it prepared to forsake critique as awhole. As the editors of this volume, we acknowledge the debatesthatswirl around us, debates that shape our work and thatwe, in turn, aim to shape. At the same time, framing our project in terms of the distinction between critique and postcritique risks shortchanging poetic critique, for now we find ourselvesfaced with achoice: either we are for or against critique. Yetthis frame is tootight and toorigid to hold all that poetic critique can do. What drawsustopoetic critique is that it can jumble, even shatter,such schemas. It reveals that critique is sharpest not when it is stripped of all poetry,but,just the opposite, when it makes the vigor of the poetic impulse its own. Poeticcritique highlights the poetic dimensions of every critical act and thus urgesustoattend to the ways we engageand respond to art.Asthe essays assembled here make clear,this is not aquestion of mere presentation or rhetoric; we are not suggesting puttingold wine in new bottles. Attendingtothe poetry in critique changes both the concept and the practice of critique, and profoundlyso. Here, we name just three aspects that show what is at stake. First,poetic critique loosens the link between critique and judgment. If some of us feelbored by conventional critique,that is because critique can be apredictable affair – and it is most predictable when it dispenses its judgments. Here, once the critical routine is set in motion, it unspools likeamechanical toy.Automaticallyap- plying fixed criteria – be they aesthetic, ethical, or political – can make for dreadful reading. Worse, it can make us oblivious to the very we typicallyseek in works of art.Poeticcritique changes the game, not because it promotes alyrical sub- jectivity or an emotional response. Indeed, Schlegelstresses that it is a “necessary experience when readingapoetic work to give ourselvesupentirelytoits influence, to let the writer do with us what he will” (Schlegel 2003,273). But he also insists on the importance of goingbeyond affectiveparticipation and even demands that we “destroy what we adore” (273)tobetter understand it.Poetic critique is aplea neither for nor against moved by literature.Rather,its attitude towardsart is ambig- uous, even paradoxical. “Perhaps then we should judge it,and at the sametime re- 4 Michel Chaouli, Jan Lietz, JuttaMüller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener

frain from judging it,” Schlegelwrites about the work of art,and right away con- cedes: “which does not seem to be at all an easy task.” (275) Second, in poetic critique the relationship between work of art and work of criti- cism is realigned,changingboththe idea of criticism and of art and the temporal that prevails over them. If we take our bearing once again from Schlegel, we can see thatcritique is not abelated, supplementary phenomenon that parasitically feeds on the work of art.Rather,true works of art call for critique; they need critique. Aliterary work, Schlegel claims, always surpasses the author’sintentions. Because “every great work[…]knows more than it says,and aspires to more than it knows,” all criticism, of whatever kind, “makes suppositions and assertions which go beyond the visible work” (281). If Schlegelthus elevates the role of the critic, it is because literaryworks are meant to be understood differently, and more fully, in future ,for theirmeaning emergesonlythrough the interaction with read- ers. This idea is radicalizedbyTheodor Adorno.Hetakes the Romantic idea that the artwork is essentiallyincomplete(or fragmentary,asSchlegellikes to put it) and givesitafurther turn: critique is now seen as an agent of the work’shistorical be- coming. AccordingtoAdorno, the of works of art,atruth bothimmanentto them and in excess of them, onlyunfoldsin“interpretation,commentary,and cri- tique” (Adorno1997, 194). The practice of poetic critique therefore entails apeculiar temporality:readingisacreative engagement with the past and the present,whereas criticism is conceivedofaspoetic activity that addresses itself to the future. Third, poetic criticism undercuts the distinction between and its other. Adorno’sreadingand re-writing of romantic ideas of criticism (as filtered through the work of ) makes this especiallyclear: it remindsusthat the often- supposedalternative between an attentiveness to the formal properties of awork of art and its so-called critical content is false. Whatever the truth of an artwork maybe, it can never exist in isolationfrom its singular form. It is onlythrough form that art marks adifferencetoempirical life and becomes art,but it is also onlythrough form that art stands in relation to the social world. Hence, it is in form thatart and critique converge: “Form converges with critique. It is that through which artworks provecritical of themselves” (144,translation modified). Poetic cri- tique can take on manyforms, but it is not by accident that from Schlegeltoour own moment,poetic critics have been drawntothe genre of the essay. Forwhat “essay” (stemmingfrom the French essai)impliesisaform of writing that allows for preciselythe kind of experimentation that an effective convergence between the poetical and the critical typicallyrequires. Because of these three features,poetic critique is not in aposition to prescribe a certain mode of reading – suspiciousoruncritical,negative or affirmative – nor is it able to issue programmatic calls for ‘how we (shall)readnow.’ It is too preoccupied with the singularity of the work at hand to do that.Itneither entails post-nor anti- critique but seeks to promoteapractice of critique characterized by aspecial atten- What Is PoeticCritique? 5

tiveness to the workings of art and literature. It thus impliesareciprocal : as critique becomes poetic, literature and art become critical.²

The Philological Laboratory

Most essays published here began as contributions to aconference on “Poetic Cri- tique” that took place in Berlin in June 2019.Itwas convened by the Philological Lab- oratory,acollaborative project led by the four editors of this volume. The Laboratory is funded by the Einstein Foundation Berlin and housed in the Friedrich Schlegel GraduateSchoolfor Literary Studies at Freie Universität Berlin. At its core, the Phi- lological Laboratory is devoted to examining and exploring the past and future of critique – as atheoretical position, as apractice of speaking and writing,and as an ethos. This examination and exploration have taken multiple forms. In two semester- long colloquia, we sought to map the complex pedigree of the idea of critique. We did this not as an exercise in intellectual history,but to uncover the poetic potential in atradition tooswiftlyidentified with amoodofdistrust.Several day-longwork- shops weredesigned to direct the attention of participants, mostly advanced gradu- ate students in literary studies and related disciplines, from theory to practice, and urge them to experiment with new ways of doing criticism. Athird set of events, more public facing,approachedthe topic from the other side, as it were: here we invited , musicians, visual and other artists to reflectonwaysthat critique enters their thinking and their work. The Philological Laboratory would not exist without the generosity of the Ein- stein Foundation Berlin,nor would this volume. We are grateful to the Foundation for the trust it has placed in our project.Weare alsograteful to the Indiana University Europe Gatewayoffice in Berlin and the Center for International Cooperation of Freie Universität for supporting the conference that led to this volume. The editors also wish to thank the contributors and, for their editorial assistance, Luca Lil Wirth and Elisa Weinkötz. Andaparticularthanks to the anonymous reviewer of this vol- ume for many valuable insights and suggestions.

 In this respect,thereare clear affinities between the concept of poetic critique and anumber of contemporary currents that seek to bringart and literaturecloser together with research and critique. This tendency is most obviouslyembodied by ‘artistic research,’ an approach that highlights art’s “entanglement with theory” (Busch 2009) and the role of art in the production of .Cf., for example, Mersch 2015,Busch 2016,and Caduff and Wälchli 2019. 6 Michel Chaouli, Jan Lietz, JuttaMüller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener

Bibliography

Adorno, Theodor W. Aesthetic Theory. Trans. and ed. RobertHullot-Kentor.London and New York: Continuum, 1997. Anker,Elizabeth S., and Rita Felski (Eds.). Critique and Postcritique. Durham and London: Duke UP,2017. Best, Stephen, and Sharon Marcus. “Surface Reading: An Introduction.” Representations 108.1 (2009): 1‒21. Busch, Kathrin. “Artistic Research and the Poetics of Knowledge.” Art and Research 2.2 (2009). http:// www.artandresearch.org.uk/v2n2/pdfs/busch.pdf (14 July 2020). Busch, Kathrin (Ed.) Anderes Wissen: Kunstformen der Theorie (Schriftenreihe der Merz Akademie). Paderborn: Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 2016. Caduff,Corina, and TanWälchli (Eds.). Artistic Research and Literature. : Fink Verlag, 2019. Fassin, Didier,and Bernard Harcourt (Eds.). ATime for Critique. New York: Columbia UP,2019. Felski, Rita. The LimitsofCritique. Chicago and London: The UniversityofChicago Press, 2015. Graw, Isabelle, and Christoph Menke (Eds.). The Value of Critique: Exploring the Interrelations of Value, Critique, and Artistic Labour. Frankfurt/M. and New York: Campus Verlag, 2019. Jaeggi, Rahel, and Tilo Wesche (Eds.). Was istKritik? Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2009. ,Heather. “Close but not Deep: Literary Ethicsand the DescriptiveTurn.” New Literary History 41 (2010): 371–391. Marcus, Sharon. Between Women: Friendship, Desire, and Marriage in Victorian England. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP,2007. Mersch, Dieter. Epistemologien des Ästhetischen. Zurich: Diaphanes, 2015. Ricœur,Paul. Freudand Philosophy: An EssayonInterpretation. New Haven and London: Yale UniversityPress, 1970. Schlegel, Friedrich. “On Goethe’s Meister.” Classic and Romantic German . Ed.J.M. Bernstein. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversityPress, 2003. 269–286. Sedgwick, EveKosofsky. “Paranoid Reading and ReparativeReading, or,You’re so Paranoid, You probably Think ThisEssay Is About You.” Touching Feeling. Affect, Pedagogy, Performativity. Durham and London: Duke UP,2003. 123‒151. Warner,Michael. “UncriticalReading.” Polemic: Critical or Uncritical. Ed.Jane Gallop. New York: Routledge, 2004. 13‒38. Jennifer Ashton Why Adding ‘Poetic’ to ‘Critique’ Adds Nothing to Critique

The provocation for the June 2019 Poetic Critique conference (from which this volume originated) contains anumber of propositions:(1) that thereisadistinctive mode of critique in literary studies that differs from the discipline’sprevailing modes of cri- tique; (2)that what makes this mode special is its ‘poetic’ approach to its subject matter;and (3) thatthe approach is sufficientlydistinctivetocommand aspecial name ‒ ‘poetic critique.’ Andinsofarasthis special mode is alsounderstood to be one that,asthe conference organizers put it, “has failed to gain afirm foothold in literarystudies as it transformed itself into an academic discipline,” then at least part of what must distinguish “poetic critique” from all thoseothermodes of critique that have prevailed is simply that this one has not (Chaouli et al. 2019). These prop- ositions alsoappear to add up to ahortatory one: that poetic critique should with- draw from the margins and movetothe center of what we do. From my standpoint, however,there is little to compel the exhortation, not because Ibelievethere is some- thing wrongwith the critical practice just described ‒ certainlynot in Friedrich Schlegel’sterms ‒ but because arguing for aparticularcritical practice to prevail seems misplaced when it has never not prevailed.¹ Or to put this another way, Ican- not help thinkingthat the interpretive activitythat Schlegel describes ‒ to “present anew what has been presented,”“to shape once again what has alreadybeen shap- ed,” and therebyto“completethe work” (qtd. in Chaouli et al. 2019) ‒ also repre- sents the unstated ambition of much of the thatIread, or for that matter,muchthatIstrive to emulate myself (though Iwillreadilyadmitto being no Schlegel). Indeed, as someone who devotes most of my research to poetry, Ican barelyimagine producing acompellingreading of anypoem ‒ much less show-

 By “never” Imean in the discipline we identify with academic literary interpretation, which covers arelatively short time span in proportion to the much longer period duringwhich the works we un- derstand to count as literaturehavebeen produced. As Nicholas Brown points out in his 2013 essay “Close Readingand the Market,” (in which Schlegel makes akey appearance – indeed, Iamindebted to Brown for callingmyattention to akey passage from TheAtheneum Fragments,which Idiscuss further below): “Questions about the wayweread ‘now’ arealways beside the point,for the that the wayweread now is the waywehavealways read ‒ provided we understand that the domain of this ‘always’ is limitedtothe rather young ‘we’ of literary studies as adiscipline.[…]Tobespecific, literatureisinvented in the aftermath of the Kantian revolution ‒ particularlyinthe wakeofits ele- vation of aesthetic judgment to akeystone position ‒ at the turn of the nineteenth century,inthe circle around Friedrich Schlegel” (Brown2013,145‒146).

OpenAccess. ©2021Jennifer Ashton, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-002 8 Jennifer Ashton

ing someone else how to produce one ‒ without alsoreshaping and remaking the poem in the process.² Foracademic critics who alsoteach,ofcourse, part of our job is to help students see how to performsuch labor.Anobvious waytodoitissimply by example, to which end Isometimes assign my studentsGeorge Herbert’swell-known devotional poem “The Altar” alongsidethe AmericanscholarStanley Fish’stour-de-forceread- ing of it in his 1972 book Self-Consuming Artifacts:The Experience of Seventeenth-Cen- turyLiterature:

Abroken ALTAR, Lord, thyservant reares Made of aheart,and cementedwith teares: Whose parts areasthy hand did frame; No workman’stoolhath touch’dthe same. AHEARTalone Is such astone, As nothingbut Thypow’rdoth cut. Whereforeeach part Of my hard heart Meets in this frame, To praise thyName: That,ifIchancetohold my peace, These stones to praise thee maynot cease. Olet thyblessed SACRIFICEbemine, And sanctifie this ALTARtobethine.

(Herbert 1633,18)

In Fish’sreading, the ingenuity Herbert displays in the poem’smeticulouslysculpted form must be read as evidence not of the ’screative powers but of God’s. But to feel the forceofthe divineagency that Herbert designed the poem to promote, the reader must alsofeel the forceofthe human that it is designed to demote. The reader is able to recognize the latter,Fish argues, by the end of the very first line of the poem, and it is preciselybyrearrangingthe syntax of that line that Fish most clearlyshows us what Herbert has done:

The delayingofthe verb momentarily suspends the sense and leavesusuncertain of the rela- tionship of the threenoun phrases. Is one subject and the other object?Ifso, which one, and what of the third?Orare all three (or perhapstwo)inapposition to one another?These questions represent syntactic and semantic options which areavailable, and in their availability,pressur- ing,until the verb arrives. […]Inits position “reares” […]unmixes “ALTAR,”“servant,” and “Lord” by arranging them in syntactical relationships which arealso temporal-spatial relation-

 Ishould makeclear herethat IamaddressingSchlegel’sidea of “presentinganew” somewhat loosely, and that Iamnot tryingtosuggest that he is somehow invitingthe critic to take the place of the poet (or the scholarlyanalysistoreplace the poem). It’sthe “re” in “reshaping and remaking” that matters for the critical practice that Iamarguingisquiteprevalent. Why Adding ‘Poetic’ to ‘Critique’ Adds Nothing to Critique 9

ships of cause and effect (“I, thyservant,OLord, rear this broken altar”). (Fish 1994 [1972], 208‒209)

In settling the causal relationship among the threeentities in question, the terminal position of the verb, Fish explains,also “reaffirms the claims […]for the ingenuityof [the poem’s] author by specifying ‘thyservant’ [i.e., the human speakerofthe poem] as agent” (209). In other words, while the syntax does indeedestablish “thyservant” as the subject who “reares” the “altar,” nevertheless the initiallyunsettledrelation among subject and object and the third term, “LORD,” also sets the stagefor the poem to deliverthat third term as the maker of bothsubjectand object.But it is the final couplet of the poem that seals the deal in this transferofpower,which we do not even need Fish to help us grasp if we simplyimagine the differenceit would make werethe lines transposed: “Osanctifie this ALTARtobethine, /And let thyblessed SACRIFICE be mine.” Unlikethe syntactical rearrangement that Fish performs, this ‘reshaping’ is one we can carry out at no cost to the poem’sin- tricate form. But while the meter and the rhyme are in no wayaffected by reversing the couplet,wecan also see that the poem’sgreatest feat is all but made to disappear in thatrearrangement.For “The Altar’s” central purpose ‒ to payhomagetoGod’s sovereignty ‒ is onlyfullyachieved when what is “thine” overtakes what is “mine.” Of course, seeing how this is done is one thing and doing it is another.Tothat end we might examine arelated but somewhat different interpretive exercise involv- ing two more recent works of poetry.But Fish’sreadingofHerbert raises twomatters that Iwant to layout brieflybefore turningtothat exercise. The analysis Fish per- forms in Self-ConsumingArtifacts is also part of the history of alargertheoretical en- terprise aimed at identifying the meaning of anygiven literary work with the con- structive activity of the reader and by contrasttothe idea that the meaningofthe work might inhere in it or exist prior to the reader’sactivity.OrasFish would put it adecade later in his well-known essay “How to Recognize aPoem When You See One”: “Interpretation is not the art of construingbut the art of constructing. In- terpreters do not decode poems; they make them” (Fish 1982, 327). My use of Fish here might thereforeberead as away of presentingthat theoretical claim ‒ which flew for atime under the banner of so-called ‘reader-response theory’ ‒ as founda- tional both to what Schlegelappears to mean by ‘poetic critique’ and to the kind of remakingthat Iamarguing we are always doing in our capacity as literarycritics. But my argument will show instead whythe fantasy of our constructingthe poem is not what Schlegelhas to mean (much less what is happening) when we “shape again what has alreadybeen shaped” (qtd. in Chaouli et al. 2019). Forwemight also recall that the very sameSchlegelwho was interested in the reader’sability to reshape the poem also seemed to believethe very oppositeof one of Fish’scorollary claims, namelythat apoem (or for that matter anyobject of interpretation) has no inherent “distinguishing features”: “acts of recognition,” Fish writes, “rather than being triggered by formal characteristics,are their source” (Fish 1982,326). In other words, for Fish, whatever we might mean when we talk 10 Jennifer Ashton

about interpreting atext,includingsimplydescribingthe text,what we are reallyre- ferring to is our construction (and not our construal) of the text.For Schlegel, by con- trast,itwould appearthat poems themselves both construe and construct their own interpretations: “In all its descriptions,” writes Schlegel in one of the Athenaeum fragments, “[…]poetry should describe itself, and always be simultaneouslypoetry and the poetry of poetry” (Schlegel1991 [1798], 51). If poetry can be said to describe itself, it is hard to see how that can happen without the description being in some sense inherent in the poem, and therefore also part and parcel of the poem’s “distin- guishing features” or “formal characteristics.” Anditisthe relationship between form and meaning impliedinSchlegel’ssuggestion that “poetry should describe it- self” that is essential not onlytothe kind of critiquethat we as literary scholars can- not help but perform as amatter of course, but also to recognizing the critique that poems themselvesperform as the primary object of our study. Anyone familiar with “How to Recognize aPoem When youSee One” mayrecall that it famouslybegins with aclassroom experiment in which Fish showed his stu- dents alist of namesonareadingassignment for another class and then instructed them that it was aseventeenth-century poem they wereexpectedtoanalyze: inter- pretive labor that,ifFish’sdescription is remotelyaccurate, the studentsinproceed- ing to unearth atroveofclever prosodic devices and literaryand biblical allusions wereable to perform with spectacular success. Iwant to turnnow to avery different (but also successful) interpretive experiment that Ihad my own studentsperform; however,ifthe point of Fish’sexperiment was to show that neither alist nor a poem ‒ nor anything elsewemight call atext ‒ has anyinherent formal features, because whatever we see in it is imposed on the poem by our communal act of read- ing it,the point of my experiment is exactlythe opposite. That is, while my students’ exercise might seem to bear out both Fish’sclaim that readers make poems and Schlegel’simperative to “reshape” them, it also bears out Schlegel’sother proposi- tion that “poetry should describe itself.” The assignment is one that Igavetoafirst-yearundergraduateclass on poetry ‒ the students in which werelargely non-literaturemajors ‒ whereone of the works we read was Claudia Rankine’s2014National Book Award finalist, Citizen: An American Lyric. It is worth noting that the reworkingofRankine’spoetry thatthe exercise asks studentstodoisbasedonanaspect of Citizen that most reviewers and scholars writ- ing about it have commented on, namely Rankine’sextensive use of the second-per- son “you.”³ With few exceptions, the largely prose format of the work is delivered in this second-person voice, as we see in this passage:

Youare rushingtomeet afriend in adistant neighborhood of Santa Monica. This friend says,as youwalk towardher,You arelate, younappy-headedho. What did yousay? youask, though you

 The poet and novelist Ben Lerner,for example, devotes an extended section of his 2016 book- length essaytoananalysis of the effects of Rankine’ssecond-person address on awhite reader (Lern- er 2016,69‒74). Why Adding ‘Poetic’ to ‘Critique’ Adds Nothing to Critique 11

have heardevery word. This person has never beforereferred to youlike this in your presence, never beforecode-switched in this manner.What did yousay? She doesn’t, perhaps physically cannot,repeat what she has just said.

Maybethe contentofher statement is irrelevant and she onlymeans to signal the stereotype of “black people time” by employingwhat she perceivestobe“black people language.” Maybe she is jealous of whoever kept youand wants to suggest youare nothingoreverythingtoher.Maybe she wants to have abelated conversation about Don Imus and the women’sbasketball team he insulted with this language. Youdon’tknow.You don’tknow whatshe means.You don’tknow what response she expects from younor do youcare. Forall your previous understandings,sud- denlyincoherencefeels violent.You both experiencethis cut,which she keeps insistingisajoke, ajokestuck in her throat,and like anyother injury,you watch it rupturealong its suddenlyex- posed suture. (Rankine 2014,41‒42)

The predominant referent for the “you” here is clearlythe speaker of the poem, whom we alsoare giventoread as black, and more specifically, to identify with the poet herself. This passageisjust one of manythatcombine to depict asubject confronting arelentless barrageofmicroaggressions by whitepeople, acts that even in the short space of this passagerangefrom the oblivioustothe malicious. Moreover,insofar as the “you” mostlyrefers to the speaker herself, we can see that the second-person voice is serving afirst-person point of view.Isay “mostly” because the “you” in the question that the speaker asks twice in this passage ‒ “What did yousay?”,which also acts as akind of refrain throughout the volume ‒ clearlydoes not refer to the person asking the question. In this respect,this passage like manyothers in Citizen,also serves as abold reminderofthe second-person pro- noun’sflexibilityofreference. “Whatdid yousay?” ‒ which reads simultaneouslyas the speaker’sstunned expression of disbelief at the racialslur and apained attempt to call the friend out for it ‒ marks this capaciousness even as (or preciselybecause) we have no trouble seeing that the “you” who provokes the question is distinct from the “you” who asks it.And as aby-product of that same flexibility of reference, what also emergeshere ‒ after we are remindedofthe notorious 2007 radio broadcast wherethe American talk-show celebrity Don Imus and his guest used the same racial slur (along with string of others) discussingthe Rutgers University women’sbasket- ball team’slossinatight NCAA final against the University of Tennessee ‒ is that the speaker identifiedwith the “you” is not alone injured subject but one of manywho have suffered the effects of an identical verbal violence. The poem also reminds us, in other words, that in strict grammatical usage, the “you,” unlike the “I” that it can be usedtostand in for (and notwithstanding the kind of poetic license that might enable one, say, to use the first-person singular to “contain multitudes”), can refer either singularlyorplurally. Usingthe second-person “you” as an equivalent of the first-person “I” is hardly Rankine’sinvention,ofcourse; it is aspeech pattern that has been put to literary use not just by poetsbut also by fictionwriters,and one thatoccurs in everydayparlance as well. So an obviousquestion for us as critics, particularlywhen we consider Citi- zen’s subtitle, An American Lyric,iswhat Rankine is trying to accomplish by mobi- 12 Jennifer Ashton

lizing “you” both for its ability to stand in for the more familiar lyric “I” and its abil- ity to shuttle between plural and singular referents.Itisaquestion that,asateacher of Rankine’sbook,Ialso want my studentstotry to answer.Sotohelp them under- stand Rankine’sdecision to make the first-person “you” one of the primary cogs in Citizen’smachinery,Igave them an assignment that would help them examine the differences it would make to Rankine’slyric endeavor if the poem wereconstructed differentlyand she weretovoice it through the genre’smoreconventional first-per- son pronoun. The assignment asked students to follow atwo-step procedure: Step 1) Choose one of the shorter sections (ideallyless than apagelong) from Claudia Ran- kine’s Citizen and rewrite it,substituting afirst-person pronoun wherever asecond- person pronoun seems to refertothe speaker,and making anyother necessary gram- matical changes that follow from the substitution. Step 2) Circle or underline anyin- stances whereyou’re not sure what the right changewould be or whereitseems the original sense of the passagewould be significantlyaltered or rendered nonsensical by the changefrom second person to first person. Hereiswhat the second-person to first-person conversion looks like with the pas- sagediscussed above:

[I am] rushingtomeet afriend in adistant neighborhood of Santa Monica. This friend says,as[I] walk towardher, Youare late, younappy-headed ho. What did yousay?[I] ask, though [I] have heardevery word. This person has never before referred to [me] likethis in [my] presence, never beforecode-switched in this manner.What did yousay?She doesn’t, perhaps physicallycannot, repeat what she has just said. Maybethe contentofher statement is irrelevant and she onlymeans to signal the stereo- type of “black people time” by employingwhat she perceivestobe“black people language.” Maybeshe is jealous of whoever kept [me] and wants to suggest [I am] nothingoreverything to her.Maybe she wants to have abelated conversation about Don Imus and the women’sbas- ketball team he insulted with this language. [I] don’tknow.[I] don’tknow what she means.[I] don’tknow what response she expects from[me] nor do [I] care.For all [my/our]? previous un- derstandings, suddenlyincoherencefeels violent.[We]both experiencethis cut,which she keeps insistingisajoke, ajokestuck in her throat, and likeany other injury,[I/we?] watchit rupturealong its suddenlyexposed suture. (Rankine 2014, 41‒42)⁴

Entirelybyvirtue of the “you”’sfirst-person capacities,there’svery little changein the sense of the situation in the first paragraph except perhaps asharpening of the lines differentiatingthe speaker’swords from those of the friend. But the conver- sion alsomakes clear what the “you” can do thatthe “I” cannot,which is to cut in two directions at once, offering us the grammatical possibilityofthe speaker and the friend occupyingcommon ground even as, in the second paragraph, that prospect is made to collapse, as if the pronoun “you” itself wereatonce both “suture” and “rup- ture” between them. Forthis reason, it is alsoclear whyRankine did not attempt

 Ihavemarkedwith underscoringthose moments in this poem (as wellasinanother discussed below), whereitisunclearwhich first-person pronoun would offer the most appropriatesubstitution. Why Adding ‘Poetic’ to ‘Critique’ Adds Nothing to Critique 13

some first-person variation on the friend’scomment in this particularsection of the work, even though in manyofthe vignettes in Citizen,the white people who are given voice do address the speaker from afirst-person point-of-view,asinthis short pas- :

Because of your elite status from ayear’sworth of travel, youhavealreadysettled into your win- dow seat on United Airlines,whenthe girl and her mother arrive at your row.The girl, looking over at you, tellsher mother,these areour seats,but this is not what Iexpected. ’s response is barely audible ‒ Isee, she says.I’ll sit in the middle. (12)

But if we return to our translation exercise we can see all the better whygiving Citi- zen’s black lyric speaker (as opposed to its white ones) afirst-person pronoun will not serve, for it is preciselyaround the moment of the poem that points most explic- itlytocommon ground between its black and white subjects ‒ “youboth experience this cut” ‒ that we run up against the real challenges to our translation. That is, while “all your previous understandings” might alsopoint to something the speakerand her friend share in common, the fact that “you” cleavessoundecidablybetween the singular and the plural whenwetry to replacethe second-person pronoun with the first suggests whywemight have trouble settling on either “my” or “our.” The rupture that cuts between the speaker and her friend certainlypoints to a divide that would rule out “our understandings” as an alternative to “your” in this translation. But it is Citizen as awhole that makes acase for whythe singular “my,”“I,” and “me” might be unavailable not justtothe speaker in this particular situation, but to anyAfrican Americancitizen who would sing “An American Lyric.” Indeed until the very final poem of the book, it is onlythe white perpetrators of racism who refer to themselvesinthe first-person singular,while the speakernever uses “I” except in mentioning the pronoun, as in these lines afew pages before the end of the book: “Who do youthink youare, saying Itome? // […]Don’tsay Iifit means so little, /holds the little forming no one /[…]You are injured” (142‒143). But even if Rankine has erased the differencebetween use and mention here by omitting the customary scare quotes in these lines, we as readers have no problem recognizing the differencebetween these occurrences of “I” and the one thatbegins Citizen’s final vignette:

Ican hear the even breathing that creates passagestodreams. And yes, Iwant to interrupt to tell him her us youmeIdon’tknow how to end what doesn’thaveanending.

Tell me astory,hesays, wrappinghis arms around me.

Yesterday, Ibegin, Iwas waitinginthe car for time to pass. Awoman pulled in and started to park her car facingmine. Our eyes met and what passed passed as quicklyasthe look away.She backed up and parkedonthe other side of the lot.Icould have followed her to worry my ques- tion but Ihad to go,Iwas expected on court,Igrabbed my racket.

The sunrise is slow and cloudy, draggingthe light in, but barely.

Did youwin?heasks. 14 Jennifer Ashton

It wasn’tamatch, Isay.Itwas alesson. (Rankine 2014,159)

Upon reachingthis point in the poem readers are well prepared to grasp the lesson they have been given. If one commonplaceofthe lyric as agenre has been famously expressed in John Stuart Mill’sremark that “All poetry is of the nature of soliloquy” such that “no traceofconsciousness that anyeyesare upon us must be visible in the work itself” (Mill 1981 [1833], 349), then what Rankine’s “American Lyric” teaches us to see is the privilegethat attaches to that un-self-conscious first-person standpoint. The highlyself-conscious self-description thatthe poem Citizen enacts through its pronouns is adrama of withholding, in which self-description is exactlywhat is re- lentlessly denied to the poem’sblack speaker.Wediscover in place of the unselfcon- sciousnessofthe traditional (read: white) lyric speaker the double-consciousness (to recall W.E.B. Du Bois) of the African American lyric speaker beset by hostile projec- tions.⁵ Thus when Citizen’sspeaker summarizes the effects of this disparity in the phrase “youare injured,” we also see what would be needed to redress the injury – asubjectivity unmolested by the projections of others. In this respect,however,what we might call Citizen’s ‘poetic critique’ of the lyric also maintains the genre’sbroader contours insofar as in overturning one common- place ‒ that of the un-self-conscious solitary singer ‒ it upholds another ‒ that of expressing, to recall one of the genre’smajor Romantic practitioners, the “spontane- ous overflow of powerful feelings” (Wordsworth 1988 [1800], 246). But as the African AmericancriticKenneth Warren has observed, in embracing that commonplacein order to describe the subjective wounds of racial inequality, Citizen also actively oc- cludes adifferent form of injustice, and one thatdisproportionatelyaffects black Americans ‒ that of economic inequality:

That is, the young men depicted [as victims of racist acts] elsewhere in Citizen appear to us as victims not because (unlikeyou and me) they cannot affordtopurchase ‒ or areotherwise un- able to earn ‒ elite status tickets, but rather because they,like you, areonthe receivingend of actions and gesturesthat stem from prejudice, racism, and bias. (Warren 2016)

To show what it can looklike to perform the kind of ‘poetic critique’ that would ad- dress the economic violence that Rankine’s Citizen,whether deliberatelyorinadver- tently, occludes, Iwant to turn now to another recentlypublished work of poetry,Le- slie Kaplan’s Excess – TheFactory. The work was publishedinFrench as L’excès – L’usine in 1987, but it appeared in English translation onlydecades later,in2018, with the Oakland-based press Commune Editions (although as the remainder of this essaywill suggest,itisnot obvious thatthe choicesmade by the translators

 “The Negroisasort of seventh son, born with aveil, and gifted with second-sight in this American world – aworld which yields him no true self-consciousness,but onlylets him see himself through the revelation of the other world. It is apeculiar sensation, this double-consciousness,this sense of always lookingatone’sself through the eyes of others.” (Du Bois 2007 [1903], 8) Why Adding ‘Poetic’ to ‘Critique’ Adds Nothing to Critique 15

are all that compatible with the ostensive ideological commitments of the press’s name).Likethe speaker of Citizen,the speaker of the poems in Kaplan’sbook is also rendered in the second person, and to somewhat similar effect,inthat we wit- ness asubject grown increasinglywounded by and wearyofthe oppressive condi- tions of dailyexistence:

Youmake cablesnear the window,cables of different colors.You rollthem into coils. Light is there, spaceissoft.You come,go. Corridors,oblivion.

Youmakethe cables near the window.Extreme tension. The sky,and the cables, this shit.You areseized, gripped by the cables, the sky.There is nothingelse.

All spaceisoccupied :all has become waste. Skin is dead. Teeth bite an apple, asandwich. You absorb. The gaze sticks to everythinglikeafly.

Youwork 9hours,makingholes in parts with amachine. Youplacethe part,bring down the lever,take out the part,and raise the lever again. There’spapereverywhere.

Time is outside, in things.(Kaplan 2018 [1987], 15)

Just as with Rankine’spoem, because the second-person voice is standinginfor a first-person point of view,wecan try to gain aclearer sense of the effects of Kaplan’s use of “you” here if we see what differenceitwould make if we reconstruct the poem with the more familiar lyric “I”:

[I] makecablesnear the window,cablesofdifferent colors. [I] rollthem into coils. Light is there, spaceissoft.[I] come,go. Corridors,oblivion.

[I] makethe cables near the window.Extremetension. The sky,and the cables,this shit.[Iam] seized, gripped by the cables, the sky.Thereisnothingelse.

All spaceisoccupied :all has become waste. Skin is dead. Teeth bite an apple,asandwich. [I] absorb. The gaze sticks to everythinglikeafly.

[I] work9hours, makingholes in parts with amachine. [I] placethe part,bringdown the lever, take out the part,and raise the lever again. There’spaper everywhere.

Time is outside, in things.(15)

Herealthough most would probablyagree that the first-person voice does not quite work, there are nevertheless fewer disjunctions than in our translation of Rankine. At the sametime we can certainlypoint to the awkwardshift from “Teeth biteanapple” to “[I] absorb” in the third verse. Partlybyvirtue of the lack of an interlocutor likethe clueless whitefriend in Rankine, there are, however,almostnomoments here where the substitution of the first person for the second would raise aquestion about which pronoun to use. Of course, akey differencebetween Rankine’sspeaker and the speaker here is that the latterisdepicted grappling not with the oppressive effects of systemic racism but instead with those of capitalism. Meanwhile there is no infor- mationhere that would enable us to ascertain the race or gender of the worker whose point of view Kaplan givesus, even as we receive agreat deal of information (espe- ciallyconsideringthe short length of the poem) about the physical work being per- 16 Jennifer Ashton

formedand its effectsonthe speaker.Nevertheless, converting this poem has some similar consequences to thosewesaw with Rankine.For instance, in the strangedis- embodiment of the teeththat “bite an apple” in the third verse, we are at least invited to imagine the teethbelongingtothe speaker.Atthe sametime,the jump to first-per- son perspective in the next line, “Iabsorb,” clearlyreinforces the subjective aspects of the poem ‒ we might alsosay the traditionallyric aspects of it ‒ in ways that the “you” does not.Itisasif, in our revision, what would appear to have mattered most to Kaplan would be getting the poem to express this particularindividual’ssubjective experience of this particularlabor in this particular factory. But if we return to the original French, we begin to seeavery different picture of the poem’sspeaker, one that we need to see in order to discover Kaplan’sfull pur- pose in so vividlydepicting the factory worker’simmiseration. Both the translator’s choice of “you” and our experiment with “I” actuallydistort the original poem’s aims, and the distortion has everything to do with the fact that the poem is intended less as acritique of the laborer’ssufferingthan as acritique of what causes it,name- ly capitalism. And in this respect,Kaplan’spoems demonstrate the extent to which pursuing such acritique ‒ unlike, say, the critique of racism ‒ preciselyrequires an impersonal rather than apersonal point of view.Hencethe pronoun that prevails in Kaplan’sFrench is neither the second-person nor the first-person pronoun, but the impersonal “on”:

On fait des câbles près de la fenêtre. Lescâbles ont beaucoupdecouleurs,onles enroule en circuits. Il yade la lumière, l’espaceest mou. On va, on vient.Couloirs,oubli.

On fait des câblesprès de la fenêtre. Tension extrême. Le ciel, et les câbles, cette merde. On est saisie, tiréepar les câbles, le ciel. Il n’yarien d’autre.

Tout l’espace est occupé :tout est devenu déchet.Lapeauest morte. Lesdents mordent une pomme, un sandwich. On absorbe, le regard se colle àtoutcomme une mouche.

On travaille neuf heures, on fait des trous dans des pièces avec une machine. On met la pièce, on descend le levier,onsort la pièce, on remonte le levier.

Il yadu papier partout.Letemps est dehors,dans les choses.(Kaplan 1987, 13)

Giventhat there’saperfectlyserviceable equivalent of “on” in English, what do we discover when we read this poem in translation again, but this time with the imper- sonal “one” in place of the personal “you” imposed on it by the CommuneEditions translators:

[One makes] cables near the window,cables of different colors.[One rolls] them intocoils. Light is there, spaceissoft.[One comes, goes.] Corridors,oblivion.

[One makes] the cables near the window.Extreme tension. The sky,and the cables, this shit. [One is] seized, gripped by the cables, the sky.There is nothingelse.

All spaceisoccupied :all has become waste. Skin is dead. Teeth biteanapple, asandwich. [One absorbs.] The gaze sticks to everythinglike afly. Why Adding ‘Poetic’ to ‘Critique’ Adds Nothing to Critique 17

[One works] 9hours,makingholes in parts with amachine. [One places] the part,[brings] down the lever,[takes] out the part,and [raises] the lever again. There’spaper everywhere.

Time is outside, in things.(Kaplan 2018 [1987], 15)

There is no question here, as with Rankine’s Citizen, that the speaker is experiencing “powerful feelings,” but the effect of Kaplan’simpersonal speaker is to make them entirelysecondary ‒ by-products of an injusticethat is structural, but preciselynot in what we mean when we speak, say, of structural racism.Unlikeracism,the struc- ture of exploitation under which “one” suffers in Kaplan’s Factory,the structure that produces the ‘excess’ or surplus value that is foundational to capitalism, is astruc- ture indifferent to the individual of the laborer on the one hand and the factory owner on the other.AsWarren says in the conclusion to his critique of Citizen, “What then makes these poems ‘good’ on theirterms is their capacity to keep in the foreground the idea of injusticeasamatter of how we feel about each other and how we make each other feel, and to keep our attention away from economic injustice, which is not at all rooted in our feelings towardeach other” (Warren 2016). We might then saythat what makes Kaplan’spoems “‘good’ on their terms” (to borrow Warren’slanguage) is their ability to imagine the grounds of social changefrom the standpoint of an impersonal subject.Ortoput the point slightlydifferently, the self- description these poems perform generatesacritique of capitalismfrom the stand- point of no subject at all, acritique we can see all the more clearlyinthese poems when we see how are-makingofthem makes that critique disappear.

Bibliography

Brown, Nicholas. “Close Reading and the Market.” LiteraryMaterialisms. Eds. MathiasNilges and Emilio Sauri. New York: PalgraveMacmillan, 2013. 145‒165. Chaouli, Michel, Jan Lietz, JuttaMüller-Tamm, and Simon Schleusener. Conference: Poetic Critique. https://www.geisteswissenschaften.fu-berlin.de/friedrichschlegel/assoziierte_projekte/Philolo- gisches-Laboratorium/Tagung-Poetic-Critique/index.html (23 December 2019). Du Bois,W.E.B. The Souls of Black Folk [1903]. Ed.Brent Hayes Edwards. New York: Libraryof America, 2007. Fish, Stanley. Is ThereaText in This Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversityPress, 1982. Fish, Stanley. Self-Consuming Artifacts: The ExperienceofSeventeenth-CenturyLiterature [1972]. Pittsburgh, PA:Duquesne UniversityPress, 1994. Herbert, George. The Temple: Sacred Poems and Private Ejaculations. Cambridge, UK: Thom. Buck and Roger Daniel, 1633. Early English BooksOnline Text Creation Partnership, 2011. https://quod.lib.umich.edu/e/eebo/A03058.0001.001/ (24 December 2019). Kaplan, Leslie. L’excès ‒ l’usine. Paris: P.O.L., 1987. Kaplan, Leslie. Excess ‒ The Factory [1987]. Trans. Julie Carr and Jennifer Pap. Oakland, CA: Commune Editions, 2018. Lerner,Ben. The Hatred of Poetry. New York: Farrar,Straus and Giroux, 2016. 18 Jennifer Ashton

Mill, John Stuart. “Thoughts on Poetry and Its Varieties” [1833]. Autobiographyand Literary Essays: Volume I. Eds. John M. Robson and Jack Stillinger.Toronto: UniversityofToronto Press, 1981. 343‒365. Rankine, Claudia. Citizen: An American Lyric. Minneapolis, MN: Graywolf Press, 2014. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Athenaeum Fragments” [1798]. PhilosophicalFragments. Trans. Peter Firchow. Foreword Rodolph Gasché. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,1991. 18–93. Warren,Kenneth W. “Rankine’sEliteStatus.” LosAngeles ReviewofBooks (7 January2016). https://v2.lareviewofbooks.org/article/reconsidering-claudia-rankines-citizen-an-american-lyri- c-a-symposium-part-ii/ (23 December 2019). Wordsworth, William. “Preface to Lyrical Ballads” [1800]. Lyrical Ballads: The Text of the 1798 Edition with the Additional 1800 Poems and the Prefaces. Eds.R.L. Brettand A.R. Jones. London: Routledge, 1988 [1963]. Michel Chaouli Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used

Philological Disarmament

“Poetry,” Friedrich Schlegelwrites in afragment, “can onlybecriticized by poetry” (Schlegel1991 [1797], 14– 15). Forawhile now,Ihave thought that the line says all one needs to know about poetic criticism, what it is and how to do it,and that it thereforerequires neither commentary nor critique.Itisclear as day, and yet, like so manyofthe best aphorisms,this is an enigmatic clarity,which maybewhy I keep returningtoit.¹ Ikeep failingtofind the right wayofhearing it and responding to it.IfIknew how,then it would stop comingback to me, and before long Icould forgetit. Criticism thinksofitself as memorializing awork, but if it is done right,then it is away of overcoming it,ofdigesting and metabolizing it,and thus of forgetting it. “Poetry can onlybecriticized by poetry.” It is aplain phrase, yetright away Ifeel the urge to poke and prod its every part.After all, can Ibesure what it means by the word poetry,ifpoetry is even the right translation of Poesie,orifthe first usageofthe worddenotes the sameasthe second?AsSchlegel usesthe term elsewhere, poetry is not restricted to agenre such as the lyric nor even to verbal artworks in general, but reaches for the essence of creative making itself, whatever form it might take. Does that hold here? Then there is the word only: am Itotake literallythe assertion that poetry can be criticized by poetry alone and by nothing else? Now Inotice the pas- sive voice and find myself asking by whom – by what unnamed agency – it can only be thus criticized?And what of this criticizing?The worditself – kritisiert – rankles, as does the idea it evokes:does poetry stand in need of being criticized?These mis- givingsare further roused by the very next concept the fragment offers: “Ajudgment of art,” it reads, “thatitself isn’tawork of art […]has no right of citizenship in the realm of art.”“Ajudgment of art”:aphrase Ihavecome across athousand times, yet onlynow do Ihear how off-key it sounds, how gratingitistojoin “judgment” to “art.” Worse, this “judgment” is apt to give the aimless drift of associations that have been stirred up by “criticize” aKantian bent.And suddenlyall Iamableto see in “criticize” is “critique,” thatprosecutor that summons the accusedbefore the Tribunal of Reason to press them for answers. Before Iknow it,anair of anxiety has settled over the line, and rather than enjoying the cloudless simplicity that it had once offered, Ibecome restless and turn over each of its words.

 One response to the fragment can be found in my essay “‘We Hear That We MaySpeak’:Overtures for DoingCriticism,” Arcadia:International Journal of LiteraryCulture,forthcoming. SinceIdo not start from scratch, some passagesfromthat essayreappear here.

OpenAccess. ©2021MichelChaouli, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-003 20 Michel Chaouli

But whysuch unease? Iapproach the phrase as though in it Iconfronted abeing that speaks an unintelligible idiom whose meaning requires decipherment,when in- stead Icould begin by crediting its affinity. It is, after all, not very mysterious: “Po- etry can onlybecriticized by poetry.” Thewords show the way, by astrokeofluck more clearlyeveninthe English translation, which begins and ends with “poetry.”² Poetry is whereIset out and whereIland, my dwellingand my destination. Though I maynot know its dimensions nor the measure of its boundaries, Idonot face in it an alien object,but something with which Imaintain an unknown intimacy.Often Iap- proach it as though it wereanobscure substance to be probed from adistance with the stick of scholarlyanalysis,but then Iforgetthat Iknow it from inside, even when its meaning confounds me – forgetthat its meaning confounds me in the waythat poetry does because Iknow it from inside. Knowingitfrom inside does not meanthat it harborsnomysteries. It meansthat poetry is not an object to be studied,dissected, and decoded. It is, in fact,noobject at all. That,too, is something the line intimates:when poetry encounters poetry,the two do not occupy opposite poles – here I, the readingsubjectdeploying “poetry,” there apoetic object thatIapproach and whose meaning Iseek to parse – with cri- tique or criticism coursing between us. If criticism itself is done “by poetry,” as Schle- gelputs it,then poetry is the medium through which Imove, not athing Iholdbefore me. Even the term “medium,” recruited to dissolve the dyad of subjectand object, will not quite do. It failstocapturethe strangeaffinitythat Ihavewith poetry – and it with me – if Iamtohearitinthe right way. Forpoetry is not amedium in the sense of ameans, not atool Iwield or achannelIselect to tune into aspecial form of communication. Nor is it amedium in the more capacious sense of asetting, the stageofmyactions or the stream that carries me away.Ineither case – whether I hold it or it holds me – it remains alien to me, something Ithink of as belongingto the world rather thantomyself. Yettodocriticism by poetry names something more intimate: aform of comportment,awayofdoing things.

Hearing That We May Speak

We scholars have been readingthis fragment (along with the otherfragments,es- says,dialogues, and other writingsinthe archive of “EarlyRomanticism”)asabuild- ing block in an intricate theory of literature, when in fact it is acall to action. It pres- ents us not merelywith new thoughts,but with ademand. It asks us to “hear,thatwe mayspeak,” as Emerson says (Emerson 2001 [1837], 60). But do we need to learn how to hear and speak?Dowenot do it in our sleep?Ofcourse we do, but that is just the reason Emerson urgesadifferent mode of hearing and speaking.Every day, language passes through me without leaving aripple. Yetfrom time to time Icome across

 The original reads, “Poesie kann nur durch Poesie kritisiert werden” (Schlegel 1967[1797], 162). Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used 21

words, and something happens.The words snapmeout of my slumber and suddenly Ihearinthem acall thatdemands something of me. No longer do Iread to add to my stock of interpretations; Iread, rather,totake part in aform of making.Iremain vig- ilant about the ways of seeing – the theories – that the text unveils, yetmainly be- cause it can lead me to new ways of doing.Ichangemyposture and lean forward, readytolearn how these words set in motion something in me, rather than leaning back, content to behold the shape they reveal. So: IhearSchlegel’swordthatImight act.The wayofacting towardswhich they guide me is clear.Iam to encounter poetry with poetry,toact poeticallywhen com- ing across poetry,wherepoetry is not aspecial category of artful writing (lyrical, complex, sophisticated – what have you), but names ways of making thatoutstrip utility – call it passionatemaking.The fragment asks me to face the cominginto being of something new not with the aim of fixing its location in agrid of meanings, but rather with agesture that launches my own ways of making.Ifcriticism names my encounter with the poetic, then areal encounter,and real criticism, must itself be poetic.How do Ibring about such an encounter?The fragment does not say. Yet, in whatever wayIgo about it,mywork – criticism – no longer remains the same. It ceases to serveasthe mere occasion for assigningpraise or blame, nor does it docu- ment an arrangementofmeaningsderived from – or imposed on – asource. Some- thing different happens. Forone thing,something happens. In poetic criticism, someone speaks, someone venturesanact of speech – an act in speech. Even if it has been uttered before, such aspeech act is unheard of. Ideas that have grown flaccid gain fresh vigor,likeamus- cle that one learns to feelanew. Yetthis speaking,though new,emergesnot out of thin air,but follows upon another act,this being an act of hearing – hearing this fragment,for example – an act as fragile as the speech to which it givesrise. For to hear “that we mayspeak,” to hear poetically, demands of me to open not my ears alone, but also my self, to allow myself to be exposed to what speaks to me, un- shielded by my usual armaments – with effects Icannot foresee. Learningtobecome vulnerableinthis waylies at the coreofencounteringpoetry with poetry. What changes, then, what is at stake in hearing the fragment,ismore than criti- cism. If Isucceed in hearing the poetry in some arrangement of words (just as Imight perceive it in acomposition of images, sounds, or movements), then they rouse me from the torpor of my habits and bring to consciousness ways of encountering things that had lain dormant.Mywhole organism comes alive,and as Ilearn to hear and see and feelanew,fresh possibilities of making sense of the world reveal themselves, which turn out to be justfresh possibilities of making the world. That would change everything. 22 Michel Chaouli

Second Thoughts

Have we been readingtoo much into this line? Does it reallysay that poetry is not an object nor Iasubject, that hearing it involves knowing it from inside, that it names a form of intimacy? If so, how and where? These are fair questions. Still, it is irksome that they interrupt our reverie. Wasnot the idea to keep at baythe unease that our usual modes of readinghavetaught?Yet here we are, readytoshadowboxwith chal- lenges of our own making.And once we start,there is no stopping: behindthese questions ahundred others lurk, each readytotake aswing. When interpretation runs into trouble, we like to place the blame on the ‘difficul- ty’ of the object before us (for example, the line by Schlegel), when the real obstacle lies elsewhere. Strangethat ease does not come easilytous. Second thoughts molest us before we have come to know the first.But then, whynot simply plugupour ears and getonwith it?Are we too hidebound? No doubtweare.We know well how to vex each other with textual and historical riddles, but we are at aloss at how to go about hearing the words someone has uttered. The new,wefear,might ask toomuch of us, so we stickwith old tricks. But this timidity is not onlyaflaw. It masks another,moresignificant reason for whyskeptical questions hold our attention. If ease wereastate that we once pos- sessed, astate we had lost to the agitation that roils our lives, then shutting out ques- tions would be atechnique worth trying;itmight smooththe wavesand return us to stillness. Yetnothing we know from experience or history lends weight to this sup- position. There does not seem to be aprimitive condition in our childhood,nor in the ‘childhood of humanity,’ in which human beingsenjoy acalm that is then dis- turbed by psychic and social traffic. Even infants are plagued by disquiet.(They aim to sooth it by dreamingupgames such as fort-da.)Tranquility,itseems, is some- thing to be attained, not something to be retrieved, since the most strident voices re- verberate in our heads. Plugging our ears does not silence them, far from it; it per- mits them to echo more violently. The lament about first and second thoughts may have it backwards:what are called second thoughts in fact beset us first.Westart with ahead full of noise, and we managetoget some peace when the quarrelsome voices have lost their edge.Itisonlythen that they teach us something worth know- ing. In attemptingtohearSchlegel’sfragmentorany poetic configuration, we can- not,then, simplyshrug off challenges issued by , by history,orbycritique, hoping to return to astate of mind unmolested by questions, for we never knew such astate. Instead, the wayofmaking we seek is alsoawayofrelatingtoknowledge – knowledge derivedfrom philology, history,critiqueand other sources – that,rather than unspoolingmore and morequestions,allows us to find words adequate to our experience.Weseek aform of knowledge that allows it to lend shape to this experi- ence. Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used 23

Self-referencevs. Intensity

How do Iknow that Iamtoread the fragment poetically? Who tells me that Imust lean in to hear it,that Imust know it from inside? The answer is trivial: the text itself does – who else? If we now ask how the text tells me, we think we know whereto look. When the fragment says that to hearand understand poetry one must hear it and speak about it poetically, there is just asmall steptoconclude that it speaks not onlyabout poetry as such and in the abstract,but also about itself, about this very line by Friedrich Schlegel. Now we know what to imagine: the fragment’smean- ing forks in two, one prongraising itself abovethe other and from thatperch speak- ing about the one below.The imagecomes easily. Forsome time, scholars of litera- ture, like interpreters of otherarts, have turned our gaze from the world that the artwork evidentlyshows to the waythe artwork reflects on itself: the novel turns out to be about writing,the movieabout film making,the painting about painting. When it comes to our fragment,weare all the happier to hold fast to this imagebe- cause the writingsofFriedrich Schlegel, and earlyRomanticism generally, often use the figure of doublingthrough self-reflection to describe poetic production, some- thing thatreaders such as Walter Benjamin have noted. So at home are we with this figureofself-reflection that it takes time to notice that the fragment does not tell me to read it poeticallybysplitting itself into fragment and meta-fragment (or fragment to the power of two, as some of the Romantics like to put it). It does not announce itself as poetry in the same waythat it speaks about poetry.Weknow what goes on whenthe text speaks about poetry:itdeploys con- cepts and puts theminrelation to one another to yield aproposition. It makes an assertion, such as:poetry can onlybecriticized by poetry.The meaningofthe line maybemysterious, but thereisnomystery to the fact thatitisaproposition about some matter. What about the othercase, when Itake the words not to be issuing astatement or adirective about ways of criticizing poetry,but ademand to hear the very words of the fragment as poetry,ademand thereforetohear them poetically? Though spelled in the same letters and composed of the same words, now they do not seem to speak in the samemanner as before, and thus solicit adifferent wayofhearing.Like every poetic act,nomatter its form or the medium in which it shows itself, the fragment guides me to read it poeticallynot by splitting itself in two to supplymeta-informa- tion about itself.Itholds up no sign alerting readers that they are enteringapoetic zone. There is no about,nocleavage between words communicating ideas and words instructing readers that they are to take this communication poetically. In apoetic act,the words bring forth the thingsbychafing at conventional systems of meaning. They arrive with atension that shakes off theirordinariness and chargesthem with an unforeseen intensity.Like an electric surge,this intensity leaps from the words to the thingsthey name and lights them up. The tension is not always easy to notice. Some texts – our fragmentisanexample – keep their readers so busy with the mys- 24 Michel Chaouli

teries of the propositions they contain that their poetic intensity takes time to unfold. Their prose works likebait that distracts from their poetry,wherepoetry and prose do not name genres but degrees of vibrancy:what is conventionallylabeled prose at times pulsates with apoetry lacking in much of what is called – open anypagebyKleistorConrad, Nietzsche or Emerson.

The Intense LifeofLanguage

The Gaston Bachelard maybethinking along these lines when he writes that “poetry puts languageinastate of emergence.” How to picture this state of emergence? Hereishow Bachelard develops the thought:

The poetic image is an emergencefromlanguage, it is always alittle abovethe languageofsig- nification. By livingthe poems we read, we have then the salutary experienceofemerging. This, no doubt,isemergingatshort range. But these acts of emergenceare repeated;poetry puts lan- guageinastateofemergence, in which life becomes manifest through its vivacity.(Bachelard 2014 [1957], 11)

The passagebegins wherewetoo find ourselves, namelywith the mystery at the heart of the poetic image: poetry partakes of language, and yetstands apart from it.Tograsp this excess of poetic languageoverthe ordinary languageofnaming, Bachelard, like so manyother thinkers,reachesfor aspatial imageinwhich poetry “is always alittle above the languageofsignification.” Now he has us thinkingthat languagehas separated itself into layers,the poetic layerfloating atop the signifying layerlike oil over water. But then he catches himself, drops the spatial image, and switches to atemporallogic:heasks us to live the poems we read, and thus to live the emergence from language. Poetry now does not hover over ordinary lan- guage, regarding it from above, but names the metamorphosis of the ordinary.If readingapoem is living apoem, then the poetic emergence from languageisnot arelease from language; it offers no escape into ineffability or wordless ecstasy. This emergencefrom language, this intensity that shakes languageloose from its en- crustations, occurs in language. Poeticacts, we now see, rather than splitting lan- guageintwo, effect atransformation within language – atransformation of language by language. Which just means thatpoetry is not something that enters language from outside (thanks to amuseortogenius, for example), nor is it aspecially marked region of language, “parasitic” on its “normal” uses, as philosophersoflan- guageand linguists often assert.³ It is, rather,one of the basic thingsyou do with words. It reveals itself as aforcethat languageholds in reserve, allowing it – com-

 J.L. Austin, for example, writes apropos of poetry: “Thereare parasitic uses of language, which are ‘not serious,’ not the ‘full normal use.’” (Austin 1962, 104) Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used 25

pelling it – to emerge from itself. Hearingthe poetic edge in languageishearing lan- guageasthough it had not been heard before. We have become accustomed to finding the poetic in clearlymarked regions (the book, the classroom, the museum, the theater,and so on), but we recognize thatthis emergence can come about anywhere. As Schlegelwrites in another fragment,poetry “embraces everything that is purelypoetic, from the greatest systems of art,contain- ing within themselvesstill further systems, to the sigh, the kissthat the poetizing child breathes forth in artlesssong” (Schlegel 1991 [1798], 31). Even if there werea sign alerting me to the presenceofpoetry – the book cover,for example, might iden- tify its content as “literature”–it can at best servetosharpen my attention, the waya gallery encourages me to look, but it can never yield the exuberance of feeling “lan- guageinastate of emergence.” Has the mystery of poetic speech been lifted? If youare of ascholarlyorscientific disposition, then hardly,for then youwish to know what,precisely, propels words beyond their practical utilityinto the orbit of poetry.What does that forceconsist of and how does it unfold?You would be in your rights to ask for acatalogue of fea- tures that characterize the state of emergence, the better to identify poetry.When Bachelard then offers the thought that “poetry puts languageinastate of emergence, in which life becomes manifestthrough its vivacity,” youcannot help but be disap- pointed. Do we know how life manifests itself in its vivacity anybetter than we know how languagemanifests itself in poetry?Itseems that one mystery – thatofpoetry – has been replaced with another – life. Yetwecould also be ledtoadifferent insight. Instead of feelinglet downby Bachelard’sfailure at providinganexplanation, we mightwonder what an explana- tionofthe force of poetry mightlooklike. Areweeveninneed of explanation?Is poetry?The texture of Bachelard’smeditation – the fact that it has texture – reveals that Icannot learntograsp the force of poeticwords by launchingatheoretical inves- tigation.Icome to see,rather,thatthe accountIgive of the wayIread poetry – the accountIgive of livingit: callitcriticism – mustitself occur in languagethatisina state of emergence. Schlegel’sfragment says nothingmorethan what Bachelard’s wordsshow. One wayofcriticizing poetry by poetryistosay that in the poetic image “life becomesmanifestthrough its vivacity.” Ascholar or scientistmight,inan- other bout of scruples, insist on alistoffeaturesthatcharacterizelife(metabolism, reproduction,etc.),which would then be usedtojudge every case that presents itself. Yettosay thatlifemanifests itself through its vivacity simplymeansthat life can only be known through life, as poetry canalsobecriticizedbypoetry. The poeticedgeof the phrase lies in the audacitywithwhich it turnsonitself. And thereisanother turn worth following.Life, we begin to see, is not merelya model for poetry.Poetry showing itself through the intensity of languageisnot like life showing itself through its vivacity.No, the very waylife manifests itself through its vivacity comes about in the intensity of poetry.The quickeningwefeel in poetic intensity is amanifestation of life in its vivacity. “These linguistic impulses,” Bach- elard continues, “which stand out from the ordinary rank of pragmatic language, are 26 Michel Chaouli

miniatures of the vitalimpulse”–this being the élan vital made famous by Henri Bergson, whose vitalism Bachelard sees everywhere in poetry.The élan linguistique is not asign – arepresentation, ametaphor – of the élanvital,but one of its instan- ces.Ifwelearn to see “language-as-,” rather than “language-as-instrument,” then Bachelard promises thatwe“would find in poetry numerous documents on the intense life of language” (Bachelard 2014 [1957], 11). Here, then, is another non-definition of poetry:languagelived intensely.

What and How

“Language-as-reality”:what of this “as”?When we think of words announcing them- selves “as poetry,” we risk imaginingthe words appearing as something,asthough they wereengaged in impersonation. But words do not lead aquotidian that issues into poetry through an act of masquerade. The conjunction “as” yields another form of doubling, distinct from the self-reflection thatBenjamin and others have noted in the Romantic conception of the work of art,yet as likelytolead us off track. It opens adistance between words and poetry justwhere we want to feeltheir intimacy.Bachelard, too, seems to be led by this intuition, which is whyhespeaksof langage-réalité and langage-instrument,leaving as little daylightbetween the terms as he can getawaywith. (The spacing insinuates itself in the English translation.) If instead of asking how words appear “as poetry,” we wonder how they come to speak poetically, then we nudge ourselvesthe right way. Fornow,weare more likely to see that poetry is not an object nor aphenomenon, not abeing to which Ican point.Its center of gravity lies not in anoun, but in an adjectiveoranadverb. It is not “poetry” we seek, then, but rather the manner – the style – in which a word, agesture, or amotion comes to make itself felt poetically. Agreed, but does that bear saying?DoInot alreadyknow that Imust look to the how and not to the what? Of course Ido, yetstrangelythis wayofknowing seems to maintain its claim on me for onlyaslong as my gaze is fixed on it,and no longer.The instant my mind wanders, the insight,which onlymoments before had the clarity and cogency of self-evidence, slips into obscurity,and as Ilose my grip on it,I reach for the solidity of nouns to steadymyself: Italk of “poetry,” its features,its his- tory,its influence, its effects, its essence.The habit is hard to break, but at least I come by it honestly, for Ihavelearned it from and critics, Friedrich Schlegelamong them. To be fair,manyofthem do mention the how,but usually the wayone recommends adish for its nutritional benefits. Their duty discharged, they proceed to feast on arich spread of whats: on “poetry,”“art,”“literature,” “the absolute,”“the work of art,”“the beautiful,”“the sublime”–each concoction more elaborate than the next,each requiring years of exacting training to construct and assess. As so often, the master showing the wayisPlato, whose signatureskill lies in turning adjectives into nouns. By asking what the beautiful dress,the beautiful Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used 27

horse, and the beautifulface have in common, with each other and with all other beautifulthings, he means to direct our attention from surfaces,which,byhis lights, shimmerwith illusion, to the essence of things, imagined as restinginaremote re- gion, shielded from change. Platohas the integrity to admitfailure – at the end of the Greater Hippias,the dialogue devoted to discovering what makes beautiful things beautiful, we find Socrates empty-handed – yetthis failureturns outtobearmore fruitthanmostsuccesses do.Now thereissomething called “beauty” to be accounted for,unseen yetubiquitous,manifest in countless shapes yetunchanging, an entity filled with metaphysical mysteries in need of examination and explanation, which along roster of keen minds strive to supply: philosophers, theologians,poets, rhet- oricians, historians,psychologists,anthropologists, sociologists,biologists,and manyothers. (The most recent to try theirhand are neuroscientists, as devoted to the of beauty as anyPlatonist,exceptthat they seek to find them etched not in immutabletablets handed down from the realm of ideas, but in the soft tissue of the brain.) It is true that in Plato’swritings “beauty” maintains no especiallyclose link to “poetry” or to “art”;onlycenturies laterwill these concepts be woven into anetwork that in the Western tradition is called aesthetics. Yetwhenthe network emerges, its nodes are understood by aesthetic theorists, even by those who decline to carry the full weight of Plato’sphilosophy, accordingtoaPlatonic model. The perplexity at the heart of poetic experience is made to disappear with an elegant act of metaphysical legerdemain: the poetic forceofwords is taken to be caused by their “poetry,” the how by a what. (Nietzsche debunks the process by doing what good debunkers do: he shuts out the magician’spatter and keeps the eyes fixed on his hands. An expert of this technique can be observed in the first few pages of his essay “On Truthand LyinginanExtra-Moral Sense.”)

The Knot of Experience

The question thatled us here was how something – how aconfiguration of words, sounds, colors,shapes – can come to make itself felt poeticallyand in turn elicit a poetic reception: how poetry can be criticized by poetry,how it can be heard so that we mayspeak.Wewould be barking up the wrongtree(the treeofphilosophy and of science) if we sought the answer to this how in a what: in atechnique, agenre, aconvention, an essence, an object belongingtothe genus “art,” or in other such conceptual determinations. The poetic is the how. It is how language-reality emerges from language-instrument. We won’tbeable to undo the knot at the coreofpoetic experience, nor would we wish to, for then the experienceitself would unravel. Yetwecan follow the twists and turns that make up the knot,the better to see what kind of grip the experience has on us. The first twistofthe thread seems to pull away from the objective world and into subjectivity.That is because of the sort of thing apoem – which just means: anything 28 Michel Chaouli

poetic – is. And we know what sort of thing:itisasingular thing.One waythe power of the poetic manifests itself,wesaid, lies in its being singular.But singular in what way? Is the poetic something utterlynew,something never before seen or heard?Yes and no. An image, aphrase in aworkofreflection (take Bachelard’s), the pause an actor makes in delivering aline – when they arrive with poetic intensity,then Iam led to think thatthey have not been invented or written or performedbefore. But their novelty is not exhausted by the fact that anew phenomenon has appeared on the horizon.Asolareclipse or astock market crash too maybesingular: it maybetrue that in our lifetimes there has not been an eclipse or acrash quite like this one. Yetthe event has not thereby become apoetic singularity,and not be- cause eclipses and crashes are not poetic or artistic, but because apoetic singularity cannot appear in ageneral guise.Acknowledging it is not amatter of scientific ver- ification or collective consensus.This includes ascholar’sassurance, backed by his- torical evidence and formal analysis,that some phenomenon – Schlegel’sfragments, say, or Manet’s Olympia – breaks new ground. The scholar’sinsight mayevenper- suade me, but unless Imake it my own, it is just something Iread in abook.The poetic must not onlyhavebeen made singularly, but also experienced as having been made singularly – here, now,byme. What if Imiss the poetic forcethat others have felt in awork, because Iamdis- tracted or adunce? That will be my loss. Imay feel shame for having failed where others have succeeded, yetIwould be mistaken to conclude that what continues to elude me is something hard and real whose presencecould be demonstrated by objective means. The idea that aesthetic experience remains deaf to the forceofcon- cepts is not new;itlies at the heart of Kant’saesthetic theory. “If someone reads me his poem or takes me to aplaythat in the end fails to please my taste,” Kant writes,I am moved neither by famous critics trying to swaymenor by rules that supposedly govern asuccessful work. Quite the contrary:

Iwill stop my ears,listen to no and arguments,and would rather believethat those rules of the critics arefalse or at least that this is not acase for their application than allow that my judgment should be determined by means of apriori grounds of proof. (Kant 2000 [1790], 284–85)

Coming upon this one image – ImmanuelKant himself plugging up his ears against arguments, an obstinate child shutting out the voice of reason – is fair recompense for the hours spent navigating the long,cheerless corridors of the Critique of Judg- ment.⁴ But its drollness should not mislead us about how far-reachingthe idea is for the enterprise of criticism. Criticism thatoperateswith “reasons and arguments,” Kant is saying,has no authority over aesthetic experience – none. The reasons may

 Iexaggerate. One of the wonders of readingKant is that these corridors can suddenlybecome the sites of intense joy and illumination. My Thinking with Kant’sCritique of Judgment (2017) seeks out such moments. Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used 29

be airtight or specious and the arguments well supported by evidence or not: it makes no . By the sametoken, apiece of scholarship thatplaces awork in aconceptual frame – ahistoricaltrajectory,agenre, aphilosophical truth, apo- litical program, asocial tendency, atechnique – can be right onlyatthe cost of crushing what is poetic in apoetic work. Which means thatmost of what passes for critical scholarship of poetic works (literary studies, art history,film studies, mu- sicology,and so on), whatever elseitdoes that might be of value, misses the poetic coreofthose works.The thoughtmay seem insurrectionary to professional critics; everyone else knows thatifIfail to pick up the poetic forceofawork because I am inattentive or tone-deaf, then no amount of formal or historical analysis can make up for my failure, just as little as ameticulous studyofthe words someone has uttered is able to disclose their seductive or sarcastic overtones. Following the thread leading into the knot seems to have landed us in the thick of subjectivity.Now it sounds as though the poetic is whatever Isay it is. Is that what we are saying?Again, yesand no. We said that acknowledging the forceofthe poetic cannot happen in general, not in the “we” of science,scholarship, or common opin- ion. (Another question crowds in: Is the snake devouring its own tail here? The “we” of science and scholarship is being rebuffed by none other than …“we.” Is this sen- tencenot sufferingfrom an acute caseofperformative contradiction?Itwould be if all “we”swerecreated equal and if the “we” speaking here had effaced itself to chan- nel the disembodied voice of science.) To acknowledge the poetic,asharplycon- toured “I” is required. This “I” need not be confined to an individual: the audience in atheater,the crowdinastadium, or,indeed, We the People of the United States, seeking to establish amore perfect Union, can become such an “I.” But the poetic has not thereby become arbitrary.Icannot,led by aflight of fancy, simplydeclare athing poetic and be done with it.That is because the experience of poetic singularity – and here is another loop in the knot – is not mine alone, walled off from others by the boundaries of my person, by my particular tastes and distastes. In its very makeupand quite apart from my intentions and my place in the social order,itopens to others and calls on others. Society is woven into it.The experience is social,and essentiallyso, even if it takes place on adesertisland or in the solitude of my skull, yetnot social in the sense that it must align itself with the acclaim of others. Itsvalidation lies not in market value or in market share. Nor is it social be- cause it typifies asocial position. Poetic experience,evenatits most intenselysingu- lar,exceeds myself not because sociologyhas revealedittobeshared with agroup or to exhibit awell-defined marker of identity (myclass, my nation, my sexuality,my geography, and the rest). It is true thatmyexperiencecannot help but emerge from the welter of ways of knowing,feeling,judging,making,acting,speaking, imag- ining,daydreaming, even hallucinating that have pressed on my life. And how could it? “There is no delirium,” has written, “thatdoes not pass through peoples, races,and tribes, and thatdoes not haunt universal history” (Deleuze 1998 [1993], 4). What goes for my feverish reveries alsogoes for my experience of the poetic. Yettobehaunted by history and to haunt it does not mean thatmyexpe- 30 Michel Chaouli

rience adds up to the sum totalofhistoricalforces and no more. It means, rather, that,having passed through them, it surpasses them. The experience registers the singularity of the poetic just when it lays bare not the commonalities of shared life but the impersonal in my person, the place whereanopacity keeps me distant from my quotidian self. We have been tracking the loops in the knot of poetic experience. Hasitbrought us anything but more entanglement?Recall how we came upon the knot.Wesaid that encountering the poetic –“criticizing” it,asSchlegel likes to say, hearing it “that we mayspeak,” in Emerson’swords – has ashape thatdiffers from my expe- rience of ordinary objects. To hear and feel the poetic impulse – the élan poétique – means hearing and feelingthingsinawaythat takes them beyond their ordinary ways of signifyingand functioning.Familiar things – words, colors,materials,move- ments – now have an intensity that jolts them out of known circuits of meaning and into something unknown, something singularlynew.That was our first description of the knot.Infollowing the thread that leads into it,wewereled from into subjectivity – from an account of the singularity that would characterize the poetic thing to the singularity with which Ireceive it.Then we sawhow this subjectivity loops backout of the subject and opens to the public. But we have not gone in one end of the knot onlytoemerge from the other into the sameobjective world. Rather,the waymyexperience of the poetic relates to the thing Iencounter and to myself deforms the conceptsofobjectivity and subjectivity beyond recognition.We are better off without them, since they lend afalse familiarity to what is unfamiliar.Kant’snotion of “subjective universality” is an attempt at cap- turing this dimension of poetic experience with receivedphilosophical terms.Its un- gainliness acknowledgeswhat Kant’sanalysis of aesthetic judgment in the reveals,namely that in these judgments bothsubjectivity and universality are profoundlyaltered by the experience. Is asubjectivity “not grounded in anyin- clination of the subject(nor in anyother underlying interest)” (Kant 2000 [1790], 211) still worthyofits name? Andwhat about auniversality so toothless that it can only issue demands for assent without means of enforcing it?Kant has zeroed in on are- gion of experience,flagrant in the encounter with an aesthetic object,wherethe sub- ject,byreaching apoint that exceeds subjectivity,achievesanegative universality.It is the same point Emerson has in view when he says of the poet that “the deeper he divesinto his privatest,secretest presentiment,tohis wonder he finds this is the most acceptable, most public and universallytrue” (Emerson 2001 [1837], 64). The knot,then, does not lead us out of the dimness of subjectivity back into the daylight of the objective world, but urgesusfurther into knottiness,aplace whereIno longer feel my known self, but,tomywonder,find something public and universallytrue. Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used 31

Making Freedom

The poetry that Schlegelhas in mind, the poetry to be criticized and the poetry criti- cizing,isnot exhausted by markers of genre or convention, we have said, not con- fined to lyrical or elevated language. It is amoregeneral phenomenon. In one of his lectures,Schlegeldescribes it as akind of thinking. “There is […]akind of think- ing that produces something,” he notes.Hecalls this productive thinking “the mak- ing of poetry [das Dichten],” which “creates its material itself” (Schlegel 1964 [1804– 1805], 371). Understood this way, the key characteristic of poetry is not beauty,not truth, not pleasure, nor is it its ability to engagemoral or political quandaries, but acreativity in thinking. Creativity must then also be the mark of anyform of criticiz- ing that wishes to maintain its citizenship in the realm of art. But whyprize creativity?Why pursue it?What does creativity create?Suppose youheed Schlegel’swordand find ways of respondingtopoetry poetically: what does this response convey? When youlearn to hear thatyou mayspeak, what do yousay?Well, manythings. The themes, methods, and goals of criticism practiced in Schlegel’sorEmerson’svein are endlesslyvaried, as are its forms. Your speech maybeverbose or terse, highflying or modest.Oritmay cease. Whatyou hear maysodumbfound you, that youfallinto astutter or muteness. Yet, however varied content and form maybe, your speech – your silence included – is apoetic act.That maynot sound like much, but if youmanagetoperform such an act,then – besides whatever the “content” or the “message” of your act maybe–youhaveenlargedthe space of what youallow yourself to sayortodo. By venturing something new,you surprise yourself. Youdosomething that youdid not know youknew how to do. This bit of extraelbowroom givesyou space for new ways of acting (towards others, towards things, and also towards yourself), ways youcould not have foreseen. Now the world has become wider and deeper.Thisenlargement does not merely augment the known world, but changes its very make-up. Foryou have done more than to add this one new possibility of speaking and acting stimulated by asolicita- tion; what has also been introduced is the very possibilityofproliferating the possi- bilities that the world affords.True, the quantum of new wiggle room maybeminute and in itself hardlymomentous;inthe grand scheme of things, how significant could the words be that youutter in response to the fragment?Yet your actions betoken a profound freedom. Forwith even the humblest poetic act youalter the very textureof the world: it is no longer simplythere as the sum total of what presses on youand what must be administered. No longer are youlimited to responding to demands is- suing from the environment,the wayanimalsdo, or the wayweimagine animals do. The world turns out not to be exhausted by what is given, but is now immeasurably enlargedtoinclude what it could become, and become through your doing.Itistrue that apoetic act – hence poetic criticism – cannot become apractice; it will never entirelybegovernedbyatheory or shoehorned into amethod. There is something in this wayofdoing thatsurpasses the capacities and competences of asubject. 32 Michel Chaouli

Still, poetic making is not counterfeit making,asWestern philosophykeeps charg- ing.⁵ Itsway of making is as real as anyaction. In poetic acts, the world, and not its semblance,istransformed. In this way, it reveals itself as something youcan form. (Or, if youare aHeideggerian, youmight justsay:itreveals itself.) Even if youmanagetovaryits shape by onlyasmall degree, bending acorner here and flex- ing an edge there, youface aworld whose physiognomyhas softened: what was once an unyielding arrangement of circumstances beyond your reach, younow find to be pliable – something given, yes, but giventobemade. What is more,the freedom to make something of this world – the freedom to say and do what youdid not know could be said and done, which is the freedom to make poetically – this freedom has not been ceded to youbysome agency,nor does it rest in youasasilent reserve(a“natural endowment”)into which youmay tap, nor has it fallen to youbychance. Rather,the freedom to speak and act poeticallycomes about in the very saying and doing.Inshapingthe world in some way – putting together words or soundsorgestures “in which life becomesmanifest through its vivacity”– youmake not onlysome object but also the very freedom needed to make that object. Youmay not be able to recount the steps exactly, but thereisnodoubt that it was you who shaped the added elbowroom. This elbowroom was not there all along,apocket of vacant spaceofdefined dimensions waitingtobeoccupied, but itself has come into being thanks to an act of poetic making.When youspeak poeticallyinthe face of poetry,the freedom youfeel in your bones is not the freedom of speech that asovereign has bestowed on you; if challenged, it would not help holding up alicense youhavebeen issued. Speaking poeticallybringsforth the freedom that en- titles this speech. When yousurprise yourself, youdosonot just with what yousay (its propositional content), but with the fact of speaking:before doing it,you didn’t know it was permitted or possible. And that is not all. It can happen thatwhen youmanagetohear and to speak – if youmanage – others hear your words, and hear them that they mayspeak.Soyou surprise not just yourself, but others too, me perhaps,spurring me to make my own elbowroom, by my own lights and in my own way. My movemight in turn rouse oth- ers, youfor example, to attempt theirown moves, and before long the freedom to make the worldhas spread like acontagion of fresh possibilities. What communicates itself from utterance to utterance is not amessagenor an idea, but away of relating to the world and to myself, and it is this that provides the sharpest thrill. Foronlyinthe actions of others does it begin to dawn on me that Imyself have acted, and not because they “reflect back” to me what Ihave done; if Ifound in others merelywhat Iknew from myself, Iwould feel flattered, no more. But what Ifind is that they have taken my act – my words – in their

 Even Theodor Adorno, as constant an advocateofthe aesthetic sphereasone is likelytofind amongphilosophers, considers their “semblancecharacter” to be an essential featureofworks of art (Adorno 1997[1970], 103). Schlegel’sWords, Rightly Used 33

own wayrather than in mine, just as Iused Schlegel’swords for my own purposes rather than his. And if they hear in my words avoice that was alien to myself, then it is in these departures from my ownwaysthat Imay see how,when Iacted, Itoo departed from my habitual ways and ventured – or juststumbled – into a new situation. It is in acknowledging what is alien to me in what others have done that Iamapt to gain an intimacy with the stranger that Iamtomyself.

Respondingtopoetry with poetry;hearing that we mayspeak;feeling the vivacity of language – these gnomic formulas reveal themselvesaswaysofreaching for the same idea, embarrassing almostinits plainness: they urge me to saysomething new,something that might startle me with its newness. And, again, this urgency lies not mainlyinthe messagethey carry,inarequest or exhortation, but in alan- guagechargedwith enough intensity thatitthrows off sparks, which, with luck, kin- dle poetic acts in those gatheredaround them. We might put it this way: poetic acts do not just bring forth products, which by convention we call works of art (though who can saywherethe edgesofthis group of thingsrun?); they are rather acts that,inbringingforth products, bring forth other poetic acts. And poetic criticism is not amode of speaking and writing thatmakes assertions about objects; rather it is amode of speakingand writingthat, in making assertions, engenders more criti- cism. Youknow the feeling:you read an essayorjust afragment,and youfeel en- couraged – no, urged – to sit and write. Youwrite not to playuporplaydown what youhaveread, nor to amplify or object,but because something youread – the twistinanidea or an adjectivethat had no business being there – wokesome- thing up in you. “Books are the best of things, well used; abused, among the worst,” Emerson writes in the essaywehavebeen going back to. “What is the right use?” he asks, and provides his own answer: “They are for nothing but to inspire.” And just as we are getting comfortable with the thought,reachingfor the pencil to mark it,he adds: “Ihad better never see abook,thantobewarped by its attraction clean out of my own orbit,and made asatelliteinstead of asystem” (Emerson 2001 [1837], 59). The pencil hesitates.Are we readytoundersign this last thought?Havewenot said that we go to books to lose our wayand not to keep to the path?When reading abook, do we know when we are satelliteand when system?Dowewhen not reading abook?But now we see thatwehavelet Emerson’sline warp us clean of our orbit and put us on asatellite’scourse, even though he has just told us its right use.We read to be inspired. If that is toomawkish, then we can sayinstead: we hear so that we mayspeak. And if that sounds too oracular,then we can say: we read – we look, we listen, we feel – to learn to do thingswedid not know we could or would or should do. Or just: to act with more freedom. 34 Michel Chaouli

Bibliography

Adorno, Theodor. Aesthetic Theory. Trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor.London: Continuum, 1997 [1970]. Austin, J.L. How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press,1962. Bachelard, Gaston. The Poetics of Space. Trans. Maria Jolas.New York: Penguin, 2014 [1957]. Chaouli, Michel. Thinking with Kant’sCritique of Judgment. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press, 2017. Chaouli, Michel. “‘We Hear ThatWeMay Speak’:Overtures for Doing Criticism.” Arcadia: International Journal of LiteraryCulture,forthcoming. Deleuze, Gilles. “Literature and Life.” Essays Critical and Clinical. Trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael A. Greco. London: Verso, 1998 [1993]. Emerson, Ralph Waldo. “The American Scholar.” Emerson’sProse and Poetry. Eds. Joel Porteand Saundra Morris. New York: Norton, 2001 [1837]. Kant, Immanuel. Critique of the Power of Judgment. Trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversity Press,2000 [1790]. [The pagination used is thatofthe Akademie edition, supplied in the margin of thisedition.] Schlegel, Friedrich. Die Entwicklungder Philosophie in zwölf Büchern [1804–1805]. Kritische Friedrich Schlegel Ausgabe [=KFSA]. Vol. XII. Ed.Jean-Jacques Anstett. Paderborn: Schöningh, 1964. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Kritische Fragmente” [1797]. KFSA. Vol. II. Ed. Hans Eichner.Paderborn: Schöningh,1967.147–163. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Critical Fragments” [1797]. . Trans. Peter Firchow. Foreword Rodolph Gasché. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,1991. 1–16. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Athenaeum Fragments” [1798]. PhilosophicalFragments. Trans. Peter Firchow. Foreword Rodolph Gasché. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,1991. 18–93. Amit Chaudhuri Storytelling and Forgetfulness

Years ago, Ibegan to run into the claim that we are all storytellers.¹ Storytelling was evidentlyaprimal communal function for humanity. Iwas assured that we have been tellingeach other stories since the beginning of time. Ifelt achurlish resistanceto these proclamations,possiblybecause one might decide that being human does not mean one should subscribe, without discomfiture, to everything the human race is collectivelydoing at anygiven point.Storytelling should not be guaranteed an aura simply because humans have been at it from the beginning of history.Of course, part of my unease emanated from the fact that the ‘beginning of history’ is even more of awishful invention thanthe ‘end of history’ is. It occurs to me that we probablybegan to hear ‘we are all storytellers,’ as an utterance, from the late 1980s and early90s onwards.From the moment one first heard this utterance, one was told it had been made from the beginning of time.Aswith various thingsthat happened in the ageofglobalization, radical shifts in our understanding(of value, for instance) quickly acquired an immemorial air.So, for example, it became increasinglydifficult to conceive of aperiod in history thatvalued thingsdifferently from the waythe freemarket does. Middle-class ideologymay have concerned itself with appropriatingthe universal; the ‘now’ of the free market appears to have been more preoccupied with recruitingeternity.Asaresult, the popular- term ‘all time’ gainedanew meaningwith globalization; like the assertion ‘We have always been storytellers,’‘all-time’ lists and ‘all-time greats’ often go back over periods, and are applied to categories (like rock guitarists), that are actually thirty years old. The disciplinary shifts in the humanities privileging ‘storytelling’ are toonumer- ous to go into here: Iwill onlygiveone example. Ahistorian recentlytold me thatshe asks her studentstoliberate themselvesfrom the constraints of theirpedagogyby thinking of the novel and behaving like ‘storytellers.’ As Isaid to her,this interpre- tation of the novel of course inadvertentlymakesimaginative writing,especiallyfic- tion, synonymous with storytelling: it is as if looking outside the bounds of scholarly work towards fiction or imaginative proseasamodel for loosening constraints must privilegenarrative,rather than other aspects of fiction, as being constitutive of the liberations of imaginative writing. Asurfeit of ‘We are all storytellers’ made me realize that this was not reallya primary utterance at all. Theprimary utterance, if there must be one, is praise or ac- knowledgement of what makes stories and other thingspossible: existence; life. By ‘life’ Imean not what narrative is ‘about,’ but what lies on narrative’speriphery. What the earliest texts seem to do is to attempt to find alanguagewith which to

 This article was first published in the Los Angeles ReviewofBooks (September 20,2019). See here for the online version: https://lareviewofbooks.org/article/storytelling-and-forgetfulness/.

OpenAccess. ©2021AmitChaudhuri, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-004 36 Amit Chaudhuri

both come to terms with and acknowledge – even celebrate – the contingency of the fact of existence. The story,with the human or anthropomorphized animal at the cen- ter,emergesinthe aftermath of existence, but,paradoxically, has an air of being re- counted and apriori, of alreadyhaving happened.Existenceisneither apriori nor originary;itisamoment of possibility. In the spirit of investigating whether we werealwaysstorytellers, Iwent back to a canonicaltext.Itisfrom the first millennium BC: the Kena Upanishad. It felt impor- tant to go back to it because storytellinghas been almost dutifullyconflated with non-Western ,which themselvesare often conflated with orality. Writing and inscription are, on the otherhand, an Enlightenment project.Outside the West,inthe lap of orality, our mothers and grandmothershavebeen telling us stories from when we wereinthe womb. Story,for us, has been an autochthonic method of nutrition. While not denying anyofthis, it was important to check out aprimary text from an incorrigiblystorytelling culture. ‘Kena’ in the Kena Upanishad means ‘why,’ connected to the whys and wherefores of the universe. This poetic statement is from the brief openingsection of this Upanishad (note that is not to be confused with Brahma,Brahmin,orother similar-sounding words):

Who sends the mind to wander afar?Who first driveslife to start on its journey?Who impels us to utter these words? Who is the spirit [‘spirit,’ as the Sanskritist Heeraman Tiwari pointed out to me, is aJudeo-Christian translation of what he calls,inhis translation, an all-pervasive ‘ele- ment’]behind the eyeand the ear?[…]What cannot be spoken with words,but that whereby words arespoken, know that alone to be Brahman.

What cannot be thoughtwith the mind, but that whereby the mind can think, know that alone to be Brahman the spirit and not what people here adore. What cannot be seen with the eye, but that wherebythe eyecan see – know that alone to be Brahman. What cannot be heardwith the ear,but that whereby the ear can hear; what cannot be withdrawn with breath, but that whereby breath is withdrawn, know that alone to be Brahman. (TheUpanishads 1965, 51)

This comes across not so much as anarrative of creation as an instance of self-reflex- ivity that is at once curiouslytortured and liberating.Its meaning cannot be para- phrased, but it can be rephrased as aseries of questions and replies. ‘What cannot be thought with the mind?Whateveritisthat makes the mind think.’‘What cannot be seen with the eye? Whatever it is that makes the eyesee.’ It is an account that abjures progression on behalf of the self-reflexive,ofthe assertionthatturns upon itself. Hereisanexcerpt from the third section:

The Brahman oncewon avictory for the Devas. Through that victory of the Brahman, the Devas became elated. They thought, “This victory is ours.This gloryisours.” The Brahman perceived this and appeared before them. They did not know whatmysterious form it was.

They said to Fire: “OJataveda (All-knowing)! Find out what mysterious spirit this is.” He said: “Yes.” Storytelling and Forgetfulness 37

He rantowards it and He (Brahman) said to him: “Who art thou?”“IamAgni, IamJataveda,” he (the Fire-god) replied.

Brahman asked: “What power residesinthee?” Agni replied: “Ican burn up all whatsoever ex- ists on earth.”

Brahman placed astrawbeforehim and said: “Burn this.” He (Agni) rushed towards it with all speed, but was not abletoburn it.Sohereturned fromthere and said (to the Devas): “Iwas not able to find out what this great mystery is.”

Then they said to Vayu (the Air-god): “Vayu! Find out what mystery this is.” He said: “Yes.”

He rantowards it and He (Brahman) said to him: “Who art thou?”“IamVayu, IamMatarisva (traveller of Heaven),” he (Vayu) said.

Then the Brahman said: “What powerisinthee?” Vayu replied: “Ican blow away all whatsoever exists on earth”

Brahman placed astrawbeforehim and said: “Blow this away.” He (Vayu) rushed towards it with all speed, but was not abletoblow it away.Sohereturned from there and said (tothe Devas): “Iwas not able to find out what this great mystery is.” (52–53)

Although similar in shape and tone to Judeo-Christian parables about miraculous strength, like the one about Samson bringingdown the columns, this is reallyapara- ble about delicacy.After all, what is at issue here is not moving mountains, but a straw.You do not need strength to moveastraw:what is it that youneed,then?Del- icacy is non-narrative;aswith writing apoem,you cannotcoerce its workings.Nar- rative and story by themselves are neither the same thing as,nor aguarantee of, movement; this is what writers,likethe mystified Devas,need to learn quickly.Oth- erwise the straw staysinert.

Inever liked readingnovels. My growingupwas spent consumingcomic books and poems. Iwas eventuallydrawn to novels through exceptional paragraphs cited in es- says:bymylate teens,Iwasprobablymore likelytoread apiece of criticism about a work rather than the work itself. One such paragraph occurs in AHouse for Mr.Bis- was by V.S. Naipaul, whereBiswas in his earlylife takesanew job as asign painter after having been abus conductor;Iencountered it in my earlytwenties in acritical piece about the book in an anthologyon‘commonwealth literature’.Biswas must re- produce the edict, “IDLERS KEEP OUT BY ORDER.”

[H]is hand became surer,his strokesbolder, his feelingfor letters finer.Hethought Rand Sthe most beautiful of Roman letters; no lettercould express so manymoods as R, without losingits beauty;and what could comparewith the swing and rhythm of S? With abrush, large letters wereeasier than small […]. (Naipaul 1969, 76)

Iwas transfixed by this paragraph, and felt it was ashame thatIhad have to read the novel. Iwas content,instead, to reread the paragraph endlessly. Thisisbecause the paragraph presented me with apossibility.The possibility was the novel. The novel I was presented with was not the telling, the recounting,that Iwould purportedlyhave 38 Amit Chaudhuri

to read. That act of readingthe narrative,the recounting,would, in asense, diminish the possibility generated by this encounter with the paragraph. Where, then, are we likelytofind this moment of possibility in apiece of writing;in, say(since we are talking about storytelling), awork of narrative fiction?Tomeitseems it resides in the sortofstandalone paragraph such as the one Ihavequoted, which belongsto astory but is also independent of it,inthat it seems equallylocated in an irreducible life and textuality outside that novel as it is in the life narrated and contained within it. The moment of possibilityresides especiallyinthe opening paragraphs of awork of fiction, or anyparagraph that has the irresolution, the air of open-endednessand lifelikeness,the lack of recountedness,that opening paragraphs have.The para- graphs in the first pageofanovel (sometimes in the second and third pages too) have not been bound yetbythe telling,but are opening out on to something.Myam- bition, always,was to write novels composed entirelyofopening paragraphs and then to put them in some kind of order.The order would be asequence that was part- ly illusory.Ofcourse, we are experts at creatinganillusion of continuity, both as readers and writers,and Ibelievethat if yougivesomebodyatext without anynar- rative,they will imposecontinuity on it.Mysubterranean aim – so subterranean that it is taken me twodecades to see what Iwas up to – was to createanassemblageof opening paragraphs,toexpand as much as possible, without introducing asense of development,the vivid lack of resolution of the first three or four pages. What kind of text is producedbyanartistwho does not want the moment of pos- sibility to be closed down by the compulsion or the need to tell?Once youcommit to telling, the moment in the opening paragraph is over.Weknow for afact that many writers have wonderful opening pages whose magic is sacrificed to higher causes, such as observances to do with the syntax of realism, and the responsibility of por- traying the arc of the existenceofcertain human or ‘characters’:the novelist “must /Become the whole of boredom itself,” says W.H. Auden, who was in aweof, and slightlybewildered by,this voluntary taking on of the depiction of social milieu almostasaform of social responsibility (Auden 1962).This loss of the abandon of the opening pages is characteristic of the human compromise,the deepmaturity,that the novel represents, when the writerknowingly assents to being shackled by the need for narrative and telling. Naipaul himself is afundamental example of awriter who sometimes begins with astonishingpassages of lifelikeness, but then not so much loses the plot,orloses himself to aplot,but takes on upon himself fetters that are clearlyunwanted. Joan Didion recognizes this and expandsonthe peculiar sensoryexcitement of the first three pages of Naipaul’s Guerrillas,which she confess- es to compulsively rereading, almost as if the rest of the novel did not reallymatter (Als 2006). In the novella In AFreeState,Naipaul translates,with extraordinary vi- tality in the opening section, an intuition of possibility into astory about aEuropean man and woman who must journey urgentlyand impulsivelyout of an African coun- try in the time of acoup (Naipaul 1971). Then, like his two characters,heseems not to know what to do except see the journey through.Asthe syntax of narrative takes Storytelling and Forgetfulness 39

over,not onlydoes the representation of the journey feelincreasinglyentrapping, but – as is often the case with Naipaul when he feels unhappy – by most standards mo- rallyand politicallypeculiar, turgid, and alienating. Something similar happens in his travelogue An Area of Darkness (Naipaul 1964). Towards the beginning,aperiod of waitingisdescribed: the ship,onits waytoIndia, has stopped at the port in Alexandria. Nothinghappens; horse-drawncabsare await- ing fares. Fewarrive,and melancholysettlesin. This melancholyisaform of excite- ment,just as the waiting-for-something-to-happen is akind of energy unmatched by the events laternarratedinthe book, the actual encounter with India, which is the book’slegitimate subject.For Naipaul, as possibility recedes (and possibility,for him, as the chapter on Alexandria shows, has little do with optimism), questionable moral judgement begins to dominate: this is his response to the cost of succumbing to narrative propriety – not so much ‘becomingthe whole of boredom itself,’ but an alienated chafing. AHouse for Biswas opens with ashort prologue, whereeverything is indetermi- nate and proleptic. It begins, “Tenweeks before he died,MrMohun Biswas,ajour- nalist of Sikkim Street,StJames, Port of Spain, was sacked,” and then goes on to dwell, for five pages, on Biswas’shouse, ahouse that is “flawed” and “irretrievably mortgaged”: “during these months of illness and despair he was struck again and again by the wonder of being in his own house, the audacity of it” (Naipaul 1969, 7). We are suspended here, in the prologue, with Mr Biswas,between arrival and de- parture. Naipaul manages to staythroughout with this sense of the possible, and he does this by constantlyreturningtoBiswas’sdisbelieving conviction, even at the end of the novel, thatthe house on Sikkim Street is ahousehehas justbegun to live in: “In the extraspace Mr Biswas planted alaburnum tree” (583). In my edition, 583of 590 pages have gone by when this sentence appears; and yet, despite all that has ensued and is now finished,weare still absorbingthe prologue’s “wonder” and “au- dacity” (7) of arrival. Arrival, like existence, and unlike story,lacks the air of the apriori and the nar- rated. In TheEnigma of Arrival,the ship that paused at harbor in An Area of Darkness appears again, but this time in adeChirico painting that givesboth its title and its atmosphere of lapsed expectancy to the book.Midwaythrough the novel, the narra- tor reflectsthat the painting is about aship that sailed into acity,and aman who got off at the port and intended to go back, but forgotto: “The antique ship has gone. The traveler has livedout his life” (Naipaul 1987, 92). The inadvertent forgetting of the matter of going back, rather thanthe creation of anew existence,becomes this per- son’sstory,asitdoes the narrator’s. Forgetting and possibility become, then, inter- changeable; the life is never reallyrecounted. It – the novel; the painting – does not contain the tale of an immigrant;itrepresents an attempt at immersion in abe- ginning,what Naipaul calls ‘arrival,’ involving an action endlesslypostponed, which the narrator encapsulates with the words, “The traveler has livedout his life.” 40 Amit Chaudhuri

How do we construct apagecomposed of opening paragraphs?One is reminded, of course, of Walter Benjamin’sambition to write abook composed entirelyofquota- tions. Aquotation for him, as in his essays on Franz Kafka, is alsoaparagraph; for my younger self, for reasons Imentioned earlier,and maybefor my present self too, aparagraph is aquotation. Anovel is an assemblageofparagraphs or quo- tations, which both belong to the narrative and outside it.Aquotation in an imagi- native work – say, an essay – causes unsettlement.Itisthere not as evidence, to le- gitimize aclaim, as it might in ascholarlywork, but to remind us that the narrator is distracted, thatthey have made an association, and have been momentarilyled from the text to another text outside it.The quote is not whollypresent in the narrative;it is partlyelsewhere. So the quote does not just further an argument; it leads to an opening up. The paragraph, as Iunderstand it,must have the same sense of not being whollypresent thatthe quotation, in Benjamin’ssense, does. When Benjamin speaksofhis ambition to write abook composed entirelyofquotations, he is speak- ing of amethodofbuilding thatbringstogether units thatbelong,but alsodonot whollybelong,tothe argument or narrative.Aquoted paragraph for him is astand- alone paragraph, because it comprises apossibilitythat makes recounting – that is, the rest of the narrative – redundant. If the paragraph is at least doublylocated in fiction,then one location lies in fiction’spurported task, the recounting of alife; the other lies outside it,inacknowledging what is more powerful than ‘story’– the present’scontingency.

Ihavenot forgotten that this piece has to do with ‘forgetfulness and storytelling,’ for which reason Iwish to look at the opening section of Kafka’s Metamorphosis in Mi- chael Hofmann’stranslation:

When Gregor Samsa awokeone morningfromtroubled dreams,hefound himself changedinto a monstrous cockroach in his bed. He layonhis tough, armoured back, and, raisinghis head a little, managedtosee – sectioned off by little crescent-shaped ridgesinto segments – the ex- panse of his arched, brownbelly, atopwhich the coverlet perched, forever on the point of slip- ping off entirely.

“What’sthe matter with me?” he thought.Itwas no dream.There, quietlybetween the four fa- miliar walls, was his room,anormal human room, if always alittle on the small side. Over the table, on which an array of cloth samples was spread out – Samsa was atravellingsalesman – hungthe picturehehad onlyrecentlyclipped from amagazine, and set in an attractive gilt frame. It was apictureofaladyinafur hat and stole, sittingboltupright,holdinginthe direc- tion of the onlooker aheavy muff into which she had thrust the whole of her forearm.

From there, Gregor’sgaze directed itself towards the window,and the drab weather outside – raindrops could be heardplinkingagainst the tin window ledges – made him quitemelancholy. “What if Iwent back to sleep for awhile, and forgotabout all this nonsense?” he thought, but that proved quiteimpossible, because he was accustomed to sleepingonhis right side, and in his present state he was unable to find that position. […]

“Oh, my Lord!” he thought. “If onlyIdidn’thavetofollow such an exhaustingprofession! On the road,day in, dayout.The workissomuch morestrenuous than it would be in the head office, Storytelling and Forgetfulness 41

and then there’sthe additional ordeal of travelling, worries about trainconnections,the irregu- lar,bad meals,new people all the time, no continuity,noaffection.Devil take it!” He felt alight itch at the topofhis belly[…].

He slid back to his previous position. “All this gettingupearly,” he thought, “is bound to take its effect.Thereare some other travellingsalesmenIcould mention wholivelikeharemwomen. […] If Ididn’thavetoexercise restraint for the sake of my parents, then Iwould have quit along time ago; Iwould have gone up to the directorand told him exactlywhat Ithoughtofhim. He would have fallen off his desk in surprise!That’sapeculiar wayhehas of sitting anyway,uponhis desk, and talkingdown to his staff fromonhigh, makingthem step up to him very close because he’ssohardofhearing[…].” (Kafka2007, 75 – 76)

What is striking is how bothGregor and the narrator have forgottenwhat the central predicament and theme are, or are incapable of grasping their centrality.Gregor is more concerned with the difficulty of turning on his side in his present state, adif- ficulty that impedes his plan to sleep abit longer; he is made melancholy by the sound of rain; he will soon become aware of the unfairness of train schedules;in the meantime, he is incensed by the memory of his boss’sposture. Another writer, alesserwriter,would not have permittedthis losing sight,soearlyon, of the immen- sity of what has happened. But the liberation of the opening pages of Metamorphosis comes from their inability to be absolutelypresent,their vacillation between being in the story of aman who has become agiant insect and their forgetting of this story and their leakage into something outside it: the matter of living,with its timetables and trains, which is supposed to feed its experiencesinto the story but also competes with and is unconscious of it. There is another kind of forgetfulness here: thatofobjects, or what in literary works we call ‘detail’.The picture of the woman “sitting bolt upright”;the gilt frame; the coverlet; the tin window ledges; the rain – these seem not to be fullycon- scious of beingpart,asbackground, of astory of aman who findsheisagiant in- sect.Their role is not even ironical, as, according to Auden, the role of the animals and humans in Breughel’spainting of Icarus’sfall into the ocean is: “how everything turns away /Quite leisurelyfrom the disaster” (Auden 2007,87). In Metamorphosis, detail is not so much indifferent to the disaster as it to being in astory about adis- aster;its locationisboth in the story and independent of it.Soanarrative with an easilyparaphrasable centrality of focus becomes,instead, an example of multiple and dispersed openingsout.Its details have their counterpart not in Breughel’s Ica- rus,orinrealist fiction, or in period or genre cinema, but in Abbas Kiarostami’smov- ies, wherenon-professionals are often not playing characters but themselves, and are not fullymindful thatthey are in alargerstory.They are in the film and outside it. The same can be said of animals, air,water,and trees in aTarkovsky film, or in afilm like TheNew World by TerenceMalick: that all these are non-professional actors un- aware of playing the role of the characters ‘animal,’‘air,’‘water,’ and ‘trees’ respec- tively, butare,inadvertently, themselves. They emanate, if younotice them, an innate forgetfulness of the story they are in, as do the paragraphs Ihavementioned. In this regard, the details Iamdiscussing are quite unlike those in period or sci-fi films, 42 Amit Chaudhuri

whereobjects, horses, elephants, and thingsexude, like the protagonist,anaware- ness at every point of being either in history or in the future, two easilyrecognizable categories thatembodyfurther modulations on the recounted air of storytelling.

Jean Paul Sartre was intrigued by the ideaofthe adventure. An adventure, of course, is another name for story:for children, ‘adventure story’ is atautology.HereisSar- tre’snarrator in Nausea:

[F]or the most banal event to become an adventureyou must (and this is enough)begin to re- count it.This is what fools people:aman is always ateller of tales,[…]hesees everythingthat happens to him through them; and he tries to live his own life as if youwere telling astory.But youhavetochoose: live or tell. (Sartre1964,56)

In other words, we do not,cannot,know we are in an adventure or in astory.The same can be said of history:nooneisreallyaware of living in ahistorical epoch. Conversations with people who have participated in historic situations, whether it is aperformance by John Coltrane or the partition of acountry,confirm this unknow- ingness:all they recall is what it was like to be present at thattime. But forgetfulness is absent from historicalnovels or films, as it is in films about the future; both the past and future are assembled by bringingtogether markers of history – turbans, togas,orforelocks – or the future: spaceships and space. Even space lacks forgetful- ness in films like 2001: ASpace Odyssey,whose story is already, apriori, being nar- rated as the ‘future.’ Space, in Stanley Kubrick’sfilm, becomes ametaphor for the ‘homogenous empty time’ of history that Benjamin says makes the idea of man’s progress possible: the historicism that imbues our notionsofthe futuristic and his- torical is enacted succinctlyinthe film’sopening:anape from aprehistoric epoch flingsabone into the air which, ascending in ‘homogenous empty time,’ becomes aspaceship. Yet, both Kubrick in BarryLyndon,and certainlyTarkovskyinhistorical films like Andrey Rublov,orinhis science fiction-based cinema, Stalker and Solaris,reject the notion of the ‘adventure.’ The ‘background’ in these movies adheres,onone level, to what Sartre calls “the most banal event”;for instance, one of the first signals we re- ceive in Solaris of dissonance does not have to do with science fiction appurtenances, but ahorse wandering outside ablock of sixties’ houses; the second signal, which also comes early, occurs when atunnelaman is driving through takes inordinately long to end: the tunnel, avery recognizable urban feature (this bit,set in Russia, was apparentlyshot in Japan, testimonytoacertain kind of mid-century urbanization available in various cultures), seems to loop in upon itself without in anyother waybeing remarkable. The horses, spaceships, horsemen, and stretches of grass or space in Tarkovsky’sfilms, and in BarryLyndon,possess not identifiable charac- teristics that mark them out as futuristic or historical, but adisorganized banality,a forgetfulness of the role they’re playing in the setting.Asaresult,both the past and Storytelling and Forgetfulness 43

the future are, in these movies, undifferentiated from the non-homogenous present in which we live.

What is the relation between living and tellingonthe one hand,and between living and writingonthe other?The prevalentmodel for life’srelationship to telling is that we live,gather material, and then pour or transform that material experience of liv- ing into something that comesout of it: the story we consequentlytell. In my understanding,however,the moment of writing converges with living ran- domly. There is no decision about transforminginto astory material that has been previouslyexperienced or collected; instead, one arrivesatajunctureatwhich there is an unexpected sense of possibility for the writer:Iincludeall of us when Iuse thatword. Thissense of possibilitycomprises what Iamcalling ‘writing,’ which need not involveputtingpen to paper or sitting down to write an inaugural sentence – as the act is portrayed in Hollywood films, wherethe ‘writer’ might be afictional character or HemingwayorFitzgerald, poised significantlyatthe typewrit- er to start anovel. The physical act of writing,ormaking that break from life when one sits down to commit oneself to embarkingonawork is areification, areduction of the actual intimationofabeginning,apossibility that writing actuallycontinually constitutes. Let me give youanexample of what Imean. Youare looking at the cover of a book and want to own it,tobuy it.You study the cover,transfixed by it,and then youdonot read the book.You are transfixednot onlybecause youwant to read what is contained within, but because youhavebegun in asense to compose or write what is within.The story that is giventoyou by the book has become secondary to the story youhavebegun to write.This is the moment of writing.But youhavenot written anything;you are arrestedbywhat yousee on the cover.You buy the book;in fact,you buy manysuch books, transfixed by them for one reason or another – it could be the jacket or title; it could be your reading,inthe bookshop, of the first page – and then youput them on the shelf, as acovert gesture towards the perpetual imminence, the possibility,ofwriting.Your sense of ownership has to do with own- ing the story,but the story is not to be reduced by recounting, by telling: the story is always to be apossibility,which is whythe books on our bookshelvesthat we do not read outnumber the booksthatwedo. Our bookshelvesare largely made up of books that we do not read. These are our ongoingmoments of writing – aself-generated accumulation of writing as possibility.

Bibliography

Als, Hilton. “Joan Didion, The Art of Nonfiction No. 1.” The Paris Review 176 (Spring 2006). https://www.theparisreview.org/interviews/5601/the-art-of-nonfiction-no-1-joan-didion (14 July 2020). 44 Amit Chaudhuri

Auden, W.H. “The Novelist.” The Mentor Book of Major American Poets. Eds.OscarWilliams and EdwinHonig. New York: Signet, 1962. 514. Auden, W.H. “Musée des Beaux Arts.” Selected Poems. New York: Vintage, 2007. Kafka,Franz. Metamorphosis and other stories. Trans. Michael Hofmann. London: Penguin, 2007. Naipaul, V.S. An Area of Darkness. London: AndréDeutsch, 1964. Naipaul, V.S. AHouse for Mr Biswas. London: Penguin, 1969. Naipaul, V.S. In AFree State. London: AndréDeutsch, 1971. Naipaul, V.S. The Enigma of Arrival. London: Penguin, 1987. Sartre, Jean-Paul. Nausea. New York: New Directions Publishing, 1964. The Upanishads. Trans. Juan Mascaró. London: Penguin, 1965. Jeff Dolven Poetry,Critique, Imitation

Hereisaninvitation; or,toput it alittle more suspiciously, an interpellation:

Come live with me and be my love, And we will all the pleasures prove, That valleys,groves, hills,and fields, Woods,orsteepy mountains yields.(England’sHelicon 1887, 229)¹

The words of the passionate shepherd, as he has come to be known, werefirst print- ed in 1599 in averse anthologyattributed to William Shakespeareand titled ThePas- sionate Pilgrim. They had alreadybeen sung in aplay, Shakespeare’s MerryWivesof Windsor,two years before, which mayhaveencouraged the Pilgrim’seditor in his fraud. (Itwas no honest mistake: the book is full of other poems Shakespeare didn’twrite,and would likelyrather have died than write.) Much later,in1653, Izaak Walton’smeditative angler heard amilkmaid singing, and gotthe attribution right,recognizing “that smooth song which was made by Kit.Marlow,now at least fifty years ago” (Walton 2014,58).² In between, the lines weretranscribed into countless commonplacebooksbyadmiring readers;transcribed, and often al- tered, adapted, reimagined, under various names, or no name at all. In that first printing,and also in the second, the anthology England’sHelicon,they are followed by apoem in response:

If all the world and lovewereyoung, And truth in every Shepherd’stongue, These pretty pleasures might me move, To live with thee and be thylove. (England’sHelicon 1887, 231)

In Pilgrim,thereare onlythese four lines; in Helicon,whereMarlowe’sname first ap- pears, the printer includes what is now usuallygiven as the full text of bothpoems, which acquirethere the titles under which they have mostlytraveled since, “The Pas- sionate Shepherd to HisLove” and “The Nymph’sReplytothe Shepherd.” Scholars attribute the second to Sir Walter Raleigh, ten years older than Marlowe, acourtier who had enjoyed, in the course of long service, both high favorand dangerous scorn from Queen Elizabeth. His poem is acounterargument; whether to call it acri- tique is aquestion to which Iwill return. Forthe moment,Iwill observe that in mak-

 Iquoteboth poems from England’sHelicon. Forthe texts in ThePassionate Pilgrim,see Shake- speare2002, 365–366.  Walton’stranscription includes asixth stanza added to the second edition which,ashis editor Mar- jorie Swann relates, “otherwise survivesonlyinthe Thornborough CommonplaceBook and abroad- side in the Roxburghe Collection” (Walton2014, 249–250).

OpenAccess. ©2021Jeff Dolven, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-005 46 Jeff Dolven

ing his answer,Raleighfollows his original closely: he adopts the form of Marlowe’s tetrameter couplets,and he echoes the language, the constellations of words and also phrases, especially “live with me and be my love.” His poem is an answer, and also an imitation. In carrying over such phrases, Raleighanticipates Schlegel’sadvice to the poetic critic in the review of Wilhelm Meister thathas giventhe present discussion its basic terms:

The poet and artist […]will want to represent the representation anew,and form once morewhat has alreadybeen formed; he will add to the work, restore it,shape it afresh. He will onlydivide the whole intoarticulated parts and masses [Glieder und Massen], not break it down into its orig- inal constituents,which in respect of the work aredead things,because their elementsare no longer of the same natureasthe whole […]. (Schlegel 2002d, 281; Schlegel 1967, 140)

As Iunderstand Schlegel, aphrase like “poetic critique” can stand for anynumber of tense antitheses that animate his philosophy – Iamnot sure we should call them dialectical; probablybetter to say, as he would, ironic, meaning that each term stands off slightlyfrom the other and sees it from acertain distance, even as they are compounded in asingle concept. “Ironyisthe form of paradox,” he claims in his Critical Fragments,and adds, with characteristic enthusiasm for the topic, “para- doxiseverythingsimultaneouslygood and great” (Schlegel2002a, 241).³ Another such tense pairing is thatofpart and whole. “In poetry too,” he writes in his Critical Fragments, “every whole can be apart and every part reallyawhole” (239). Part and whole are perspectives, and to perceive bothsimultaneouslyistoattain to a “clear consciousness of eternal agility,ofaninfinitelyteemingchaos” (Schlegel2002c, 264). The ironic multiplication of perspectivesisanopening onto the infinite. Such claims do not exactlyamount to amethod, but the Meister essayhas apractical rec- ommendation for splitting the difference. Thepoetic critic should divide the whole into “articulated parts and masses.” Not,however,all the waydown to its original, simplest constituents;into molecules, we might say, but not into atoms.Whatisat stake is the survival of the original in the text thatcritiquesit. Cutawork into its sim- ples, and you “destroy his living unity” (Schlegel 2002d, 281), which is exactlywhat the ordinary,scalpel-happy critic habituallydoes. The poetic critic, by contrast,will work with parts large enough, articulated enough – parts with parts – that the design of the original, the voice, the style, the genius, remains alive and active.Inwriting about the object of his criticism the poetic critic is willingtobelike it,toadmit its principles of organization, its musteringofparts, into his ownmaking. Perhaps such an account captures something of Walter Raleigh’srelation to Christopher Marlowe. But Idonot want to read Marlowe and Raleighfrom the stand-

 Irefrain from callingSchlegel’santithesesdialectical because though the terms provide perspec- tive on each other,and the resultisanincreasinglycomprehensive understanding, that relation does not develop in the specificallyhistorical waythat Hegelwould describe. Poetry,Critique, Imitation 47

point of Schlegel; my project here is to read Schlegel, and to read us, Schlegel’sin- heritors,from the standpoint of Marlowe and Raleigh. That will mean taking up that earlymodern, rhetorical concept of imitation, which is alien to Schlegel’sphilosoph- ical poetry – alien because imitation is the practice basic to the rhetorical regime that Schlegel’sRomanticism rejected; and to some extent,alien to contemporary literary studies, too.⁴ Marlowe and Raleighwereexceptionallygifted students under that hu- manist regime, in the version thatprevailed in Elizabeth’sEngland. Both learned, at school and at university,towrite an oration like Ciceroand to write verse like Horace,orOvid. To studywas always to studymodels,the practice known as imi- tatio. The analytic technologyofrhetorical theory was at their fingertips, but the cri- teria of success were, first,sounding likeyour original (not standing back from it, stylisticallyoranalytically), and second, and ultimately, turning the rhetorical free- dom such studycultivates to the work of persuasion – whether in academic dispu- tation or,ifyou found favorthere, at court.⁵

So, imitation: this mode of composition after models, pedagogical and makerly: what wayofwriting,what wayofknowing,isit? In amoment,Iwill return to the passion- ate shepherd, but let me make some very general proposals first.The most funda- mental is from Aristotle, that ahuman being is an imitative animal, and “learns first by imitation.”⁶ Imitation is basic to us. Present-day neuroscientists make the point on their own terms,describing the circuit of our mirror neurons,which fire sympatheticallywhen we observethe actions of others, as though we wereperform- ing thoseactions ourselves.⁷ To understand,onsuch accounts, is to imitate. This kind

 Stephen Halliwell discusses the “undoubtedlywidespread Romantic rejection of mimesis” in The Aesthetics of Mimesis (Halliwell 2002,360); though he givesasubtle account of how the concept was preserved, at the expense of its technical, skilled aspect,distinguishing, as Schegel’sbrother August Wilhelm did, between “‘imitation’ [Nachahmung]asexternal ‘aping’ [nachäffen]and, on the other hand, imitation, in aless than transparent formulation, as the adoption or appropriation of the prin- ciples of human action” (Halliwell 2002,361). The classic studyofthe problem in English poetry is M.H. Abrams, TheMirror and the Lamp:Romantic Theoryand the CriticalTradition. See also note 8below.  The classic essayonimitatio remains G.W. Pigman’s “Versions of Imitation in the Renaissance.” David Riggs givesanexcellent description of what this trainingmeant for schoolboysinTheWorld of ChristopherMarlowe (Riggs 2004,25–77). See also my own Scenes of Instruction in Renaissance Ro- mance (Dolven2007, 15–64).  According to Aristotle, imitation is “natural to man from childhood, one of his advantages over the lower animals beingthis, that he is the most imitative creature in the world, and learns first by imi- tation” (Aristotle 1984,1448b5).  Thereisanactive scientific debateabout the roleofmirror neurons in social life, especiallytheir relation to empathetic understanding,but evidenceisclear that some neurons fire both in action and when in observingthe same action in someone else. Mark Johnson discusses the humanisticpossi- bilities of the idea that “understanding requires simulation” in TheMeaning of the Body (Johnson 2007,164). AlfredGell, in his Art and Agency,approaches the same question as an anthropologist. 48 Jeff Dolven

of understanding – and thereisalong,sturdytradition stretchingbetween Aristotle and the MRI – is not the product of an adjustment of range, as in close or distant reading, analysis or overview.⁸ It is an identification, adopting the actions, the behav- ior of another,discovering the how of it by doing it.Not aquestion of far and near, but of outside and inside; and so much of the outside is inside, alreadyimitated, al- readyinour bodies, before we begin to reflect upon it.Which is to saythat imitation is not always,orevenprimarily, deliberate. The rhetorical discipline of imitatio can thereforebeunderstood as an effort both to exploit and to regulate an imitative ap- petite for the ways of others. Imitation, in writing,ismediated for the student of rhet- oric by the terms of art that crowdthe field of rhetoric, but the model, and its cha- risma, are stillforemost.Imitation is afeedback loop, in which the maker is constantlyadjustingthe made thing accordingtothe criterion of the object,conform- ing the text she makes to the text she reads.What she makes is an imitation of the maker,too, one made out of herself. The dangers of such amodel of knowledge are obvious enough, in acritical age: is this not apedagogyofconformity?Ifimitation requires immersion, absorption, ar- guablysubmission, what becomes of critical distance? Is such athing as critical imi- tation possible? In makingananswer,let me turn back to Marlowe and Raleigh, and then to John Donne, who is one of manypoets to continue the little tradition Marlowe started. The original poem is acharming pastoral enticement.Itisalso,itshould be said, alreadyself-skeptical.Itpiles gift on gift,agenerous,rustic copia – but the gifts tend towardmanufacture, starting with abed of roses and acap of straw and ending up with gold buckles and amber studs. Innocenceturns graduallytoartifice.The poem has apeculiardouble ending,too, bringingthe first line back to close the pe- nultimatestanza, then doing it again, as though against some implicit resistance:

Abelt of straw and ivybuds, With coral clasps and Amber studs; And if these pleasures maythee move, Come live with me, and be my love.

The shepherdswains shall dance and sing Forthy delights each Maymorning:

“To see (or to know) is to be sensuouslyfilled with what is perceived, yieldingtoit, mirroringit–and hence imitatingitbodily” (Gell 1998, 100).  Walter Benjamin is atwentieth-century touchstone, and he takesalong retrospect: the imitative faculty,heargues, is somethingmodernity has eroded; the analytic powertorecognize similarity is “nothingbut arudiment of the oncepowerful compulsion to become similar and to behave mim- etically. Thereisperhaps not asingle one of his higher functionsinwhich his mimetic faculty does not playadecisive role” (Benjamin2004–2006,2.720). Michael Taussig’s Mimesis and Alterity is an influential recent accountofhow “the practice of mimesis in our day” is “inseparable from imaging and thinkingitself” (Taussig1992, 70). Idiscuss the basis of styleinimitation,and its relation to a history of maker’sknowledge,inmySenses of Style (Dolven2018, 110 –121). Poetry,Critique, Imitation 49

If these delights thymind maymove, Then live with me, and be my love. (England’sHelicon 1887, 230)

Has she said no, the first time? There is asubtle hardeningofhis stance from invi- tation, “if […]come,” to amore strenuous,not to saycoercive logic, “if […]then.” In this internal doubling,ortripling,the poem anticipates its successors, returningto that pristine original invitation under increasing suspicion. Is it therefore already self-critical?Aninstance alreadyofpoetic critique?Self-imitationdoes open up adis- tance inside the poem, when the reader measures ending against beginning,the dif- ferencebetween imitation and mere repetition. But for auniversity manlike Mar- lowe, such asubtle show of , and still subtler threat,would find aready audience among his sophisticated peers. The poem stands onlysofar away from it- self. Raleigh’sresponseiscloselystudious of its model. It tracks Marlowe’slist-mak- ing,his syntax, the structure of his argument,including the double ending.The work it wants to do, it does from the inside. His intervention – the objection of his nymph – is to point out that the shepherd has forgotten about the passageoftime.Ihave al- ways wondered if Raleigh’snymph does not hear the clock ticking even in Marlowe’s first line, “Come live with me and be my love,” where the transit from “live” to “love” is almostaconjugation, from present to past,as‘drive’ to ‘drove,’ or even ‘tick’ to ‘tock.’ Be that as it may, the imitation makes the problem explicit.Notice the beau- tiful diminuendo of the fourth stanza:

Thygowns,thy shoes, thybeds of roses, Thycap,thy kirtle, and thyposies, Soon break, soon wither,soon forgotten, In follyripe, in reason rotten. (231)

Six gifts become threeverbs of damageand loss, resolving finally to the two halvesof an open-and-shut maxim. It is awonderfullyartful undercuttingofMarlowe’ssea- sonless bounty,one thatunsettlesthe more because it accepts so manyofthe terms of its original. Is this, then, poetic critique? Thelikenesses are indexes of dif- ference, measured from the inside looking out,rather than the outside looking in. That said, such revenges against the carpediem tradition are their own kind, which Raleighinhabits as amatter of conventional counter-convention. He inquires somewhat less into the motivesofhis nymph thanMarlowe does of his shepherd. What then of John Donne? Here is “The Bait,” in its entirety:

Come live with me, and be my love, And we will some new pleasures prove Of golden sands,and crystal brooks, With silkenlines and silverhooks.

There will the riverwhisperingrun, Warmed by thyeyes, morethan the Sun; 50 Jeff Dolven

And thereth’enamoured fish will stay, Beggingthemselvesthey maybetray.

When thou wiltswim in that live bath, Each fish which every channel hath, Will amorouslytothee swim, Gladder to catchthee, than thou him.

If thou to be so seen be’st loth, By SunorMoon, thou dark’nest both, And, if my heart have leave to see, Ineed not their light,havingthee.

Letothers freeze with angling-reeds, And cut their legs with shells and weeds, Or treach’rouslypoor fish beset, With stranglingsnareorwindowy net.

Letcoarse, bold hands fromslimynest The bedded fish in banks out-wrest, Or,curious traitors, sleeve-silk flies Bewitch poor fishes’ wand’ringeyes:

Forthee, thou need’st no such deceit, Forthou thyself art thine own bait; That fish that is not caught thereby, Alas,iswiser far than I. (Donne 2010,134–136)

Donne likelywrote this poem duringhis miscellaneous years as apersonal secretary and minor official in London, in the very late sixteenth, perhaps earlyseventeenth centuries;hemust have seen its predecessors in manuscript,orheread acopyof England’sHelicon. He takes up Marlowe’sopening lines, but alreadywith asmall perversity:the modulation from meadow to brookside, and the barb of the silver hook danglingatthe end of the last line. (That pun on “line” is active throughout.) The tetrameter and the rhyme scheme are inherited, and handledwith equal skill. The catalogue of gifts is inherited, too, but altered, not just,asinRaleigh, negated. Donne’sspeaker lists not objects, but features of the waterscape flatteringtothe ad- dressee, how her eyes will warm the cold water,and how the fish will come to pay amorous tribute. (Forsaking their freedom as they come: Donneadmires the latitude of afish, that “every channelhath” in the three-dimensionalmeadow of deep water; it is this freedom they will give up for her.) If she is reluctant to be seen, fear not,her beauty will so outshine sun and moon that they will be darkened by the contrast, and he will see her by her ownradiance. Flattery,flattery,flattery,evenasthe invi- tation has shifted, from “come live with me,” to “strip and bathe for me.” Raleigh’s time-lesson has been learned by someone. But onlytacitly. With the fifth stanza, Donnechanges tack. (Perhaps because his line of persuasion is not working? – the labile rhetoric of the poem invites us to imag- ine it as an act of seduction in real time, adaptingtoits targetthroughout.) “Let oth- ers freeze with anglingreeds,” he says;let those other fishermeninjurethemselvesin Poetry,Critique, Imitation 51

the chase, deceiving the fish with snares and nets and lures. “Forthee, thou need’st no such deceit,/For thou thyself art thine own bait.” The passionatefisherman’sar- gument has been pointingtoward this moral, if “moral” is the word, as he tangles his own admiration with that of the amorous fish – the fish thatcorrespond with the shepherd’ssheep in the original, yes? – and it feels like anaturalconclusion, afinal act of flattery decorouslytransposed out of pastoralfor sheer variety’s sake. But alittle tugonthose lines drawsupthe snare. Whatdoes it mean, to be your ownbait?This woman, to whom he is speaking – she must be afisherman too, but one who needsnolure,needs no mediation; who need neither labor,nor lie; her beauty perfectsher agency.Then again, recall that she is the object of the fishes’ attention, too, each fish “Gladdertocatch thee, thanthou him”;and of course, it is she for whom the speaker is fishing,perhaps with the bait of the poem. If she is the catch, and also her own bait – how is that different from the de- sirability of the object of desire? Is not beauty always its own bait?Donne’sbait and switch, if youlike, has dangled the promise of afisherman’sagency before his catch, but the poem catches the flickeringlight we read by like afly tied from asilken sleeve. Youcould say, in the languageoftwentieth-century ,that Donne’s poem is an exercise in immanent,rather than transcendent,critique; it is involved with the languageofits object,usedasleverageagainst itself; it looks for no fulcrum elsewhere. As Adornoputs it,inhis essay “Cultural Criticism and Society”: “Asuc- cessful work, accordingtoimmanent criticism, is not one which resolvesobjective contradictions in aspurious harmony,but one which expresses the idea of harmony negativelybyembodying the contradictions, pure and uncompromised, in its inner- most structure” (Adorno 1997, 31). Agood poem, that is, is critical by being complicit. ForAdorno,this is true of the object of study(the poem), and it will necessarilybe true of the studyitself. Donne’sstudy establishes between itself and its predecessors aset of analogies – shepherd to fisherman, sheep to fish, nymphtoboth; analogies, not to saycomplicities – in order to examine the contradictions thatemerge.There is the collapsing triangulation of the nymph as her ownbait; and the more stubborn triangulationwith the other fisherman, who are her competitors, or are they his? (Atall events they,not she, would seem to be the audience for the mock-abjection of the final lines.) Such ingenious permutations make for askeptical anatomyof the tradition into which “The Bait” is entered, as acritical intervention of exceptional rigor and determination. The question is, what is the gain of imitation, imitatio – of the specific skill by means of which Donnemakes his entry? There is something to be learned from comparison with amuch latercontribu- tion to the chain of replies, William Carlos Williams’“RaleighWas Right”:

We cannot go to the country for the country will bringus no peace What can the small violets tell us 52 Jeff Dolven

that grow on furry stemsin the long grass among lance-shaped leaves?

Though youpraise us and call to mind the poets whosung of our loveliness it was long ago! long ago! when country people would plow and sow with floweringminds and pockets at ease— if ever this weretrue.

Not now.Loveitself aflower with rootsinaparched ground. Empty pockets makeempty heads. Cure it if youcan but do not believethat we can live todayinthe country for the country will bringus no peace. (Williams 1991, 2.88–2.89)

Williams’ poem maybeananswer – or ataking sides – but it is no imitation; not rhythmically, not in diction,not even in the “Come live” tag thatisthe poem’ssecond name.⁹ And though its own anti-pastoral sentiments are sympathetic, it stands far enough outside its original that it has little power to critique its tradition. There is no real feeling for what the genre meant,nor how it might have been transmuted, over time, nor for the specificity of Raleigh’sresponse; and though the poem betrays acertain obdurate longing, Williams’ speaker acknowledgesnocomplicity,noentan- glement.Itishistoricallysymptomatic of its own moment – how could it not be – but it does not attempt historical understanding;and if thereissome pathos in its rejec- tion of history (“long ago!”), still, the rejection itself is largely successful. Perhaps Williams’ poem is something like an instance in poetry of what for Schlegelwould be ordinary critique;the kind of critique Adorno might call transcen- dental, for standingapart from its object,setting up criteria that are removed, un- compromised. It has resolved its object into primitive parts for analysis that carry with them no risk of contamination. Imitation is an alternative to such transcenden- tal detachment.Still, it is not,infact,the alternative that Schlegel has to offer,and I

 Though John Beer,who heardmepresent this paper at the Poetic Critique conference, observed afterward that the lines “but do not believe/that we can live today” reprise Marlowe’slive/lovecon- jugation, and that Williams might be takentobeexploringsomething likethe seductions of disen- chantment; the speakerisenjoininghis own listener to ashared cynicism that the poem wants to expose, rather than endorse. So read, the poem is still no imitation, but takesacritical attitude to- wards its anti-pastoral attitude (and the title, “Raleigh WasRight,” comestoseem calculatedly, ex- aggeratedlyperemptory and defensive). Poetry,Critique, Imitation 53

want to conclude by sharpening that difference,inorder to suggest that there is a specific critical power in imitationthat is not to be derivedfrom the post-Romantic critical tradition; adistinct version of poetic critique that Schlegel mayglimpse, but cannot follow.Isaid earlier thatimitation, as abasic practice, was alien to him. Here he is, in the Athenaeum Fragments of the same year,discussingthe translation of the .

393. In order to translate perfectlyfromthe classics intoamodern language, the translator would have to be so expert in his languagethat,ifneed be, he could make everythingmodern; but at the same time he would have to understand antiquity so wellthat he would be ablenot just to imitateitbut,ifnecessary,recreateit[zugleich aber das Antikesoverstehn, daß ersnicht bloß nachmachen, sondern allenfalls wiederschaffen könnte]. (Schlegel 2002b, 257; Schlegel 1967, 239)

That re-creation recalls his sense of the poetic critic’spower to “add to the work, re- storeit, shape it afresh.” Translation soundsagood deal like imitation. But it is im- portant thatunderstanding, verstehen,and imitation, nachmachen,come in that order,both in his sentence, and in the career of the translator.¹⁰ “Where we should exercise to know,weexercise as having known” (Sidney1973, 112), says Philip Sidney in 1580,inhis great Defense of Poetry. By exercise, he means imitate, and it is natural to him to think of imitation and translation as modes of comingtoknow,from which understanding should be derived. That is not how Schlegel thinks, nor is it native to the critical tradition, poetic or otherwise. So, while his poetic critic refuses the de- tachment of analysis –“Why,” he asks, “should we not bothbreathe in the perfume of aflower and at the same time, entirelyabsorbed in the observation, contemplate in its infinite ramifications the vein-system of asingle leaf?” (Schlegel 2002d, 273) – the perfume and the vein-diagram are both modulations of areceptive sensibility. They are not maker’sknowledge,let alone impersonation. They are interdicted from imitation. But here is Schlegelagain, justayear later,inhis Critical Fragments:

55.Areallyfreeand cultivated person oughttobeable to attune [stimmen]himself at will to beingphilosophical or philological, critical or poetical, historical or rhetorical, ancient or mod-

 Schlegel makes the same point,insistingonthe same priority of understanding to imitation, in his On the Study of Greek Poetry,which he wrote in 1795: “Onlyhewho thoroughlyknows [ganz kennt] Greek poetry can imitate[nachahmen]it”(Schlegel 2001,77; Schlegel 1979,331), he says,and again: “One cannot properlyimitate[nicht richtig nachahmen]Greek poetry as long as one does not actually understand [gar nicht versteht]it”(Schlegel 2001, 84;Schlegel 1979,347). Schlegel’sattitude in that text towardimitation is complicated, but his references to imitationasatechnical skill, to “slavishly imitative artists whoonlyimitatethe particular” (Schlegel 2001,58), areunfailinglydisparaging. His ideal of imitation is directed not at the work but at the spirit it conveys:the genius does not allow himself “to be restrictedbythe peculiarity that the outwardform, the husk of the universal spirit, maystill yetcarry with it” (Schlegel 2001,47). Halliwell discusses this attitude in TheAesthetics of Mimesis (Halliwell 2002,360 –363). 54 Jeff Dolven

ern: quitearbitrarily, just as one tunes an instrument, at anytime and to anydegree. (Schlegel 2002a, 242; Schlegel 1967, 154)

Attunement is not imitation. But there is something in this ideal person of the rhet- orician’sversatility,the cultivated skill of the imitator,the student who can tune what she makes to the objects of her study. If Schlegeldenouncesthe “countless legions of derivative imitators [nachahmende Echokünstler]” (Schlegel 2001, 30;Schlegel1979, 239) in his own moment,heshares some of the humanists’ ideals of attunement. There is agreat and,atthe present moment,neglected pedagogicalpower in the ex- ercises that build that capacity;one might say, cooptingSchlegel’sargument,that imitation,intaking over contiguous words and thoughts, might keep the original alive in the hand and mouth of the student.That is no small thing in itself,atamo- ment when the humanities are struggling for enrollments. (And when creative writing is thriving.) There is aspecial critical potential in imitation, too. Donne manipulates lyric structures from the inside, immanently, exposing otherwise invisiblecontradic- tions. Imitationhas apower to open up the differencefrom the original as an exem- plary contradiction, by its variances, and by its exaggerations, the strategic hypertro- phyofthe imitator’sskill. (Hal Foster has discussed astrain of contemporary art that practices critique by “mimetic exacerbation” [Foster 2017,Ch. 3]; John Donne might find himself in good companythere.) And that is askill that comes onlybyits prac- tice. And then again – with all that said, there is, in the provisional self-surrender of the imitator,inthatabsorbingfeedback between maker and model, something that resists assimilation to post-Romantic critique; at least,tothat variety of critiquethat depends for its power on strict differencefrom its object.Itisaresistance that makes imitation amore provocative alternative to such critique than description, say, or sur- face reading, the critical opposites for which so much contemporary literary argu- ment has reached, in its search for other ways of reading.¹¹ “Come live with me and be my love” is an ideal test of imitation’spowers and its risks, for it is just what we are afraid of: that the poem will interpellateusinto its form of life; that in loving it we will lose our ability to think freely, objectively. But to be atruly free and cultivated person – and here, let “cultivated” refertothe practical, learnable skills of poem-making;skills anyone can learn – to be atrulyfree and cultivated per- son means youcan choose when to imitate, when to step back, and not demand that the contradiction be reconciled in advance.

 It strikes me as acontemporary blind spot that critics discontent with critique as amode of en- gagement have not lookedtothe long pedagogical tradition of imitation; it speaks to the institutional separations between faculties of creative writingand literature. The touchstones for the current de- bateintheUnited States areRita Felski’s TheLimits of Critique (2015), and the series of responses to it published in PMLA;also influential has been Stephen Best and Sharon Marcus, “SurfaceRead- ing:AnIntroduction” (2009). Poetry,Critique, Imitation 55

Bibliography

Abrams, M.H. The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, 1953. Adorno, Theodor W. “Cultural Criticism and Society.” Prisms. Trans. Samuel and ShierryWeber. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997.17–34. Aristotle. The Complete WorksofAristotle. 2vols. Ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UniversityPress, 1984. Benjamin, Walter. “On the Mimetic Faculty.” Selected Writings. 4vols. Eds.Marcus Bullock and Michael Jennings. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press,2004–2006. 720–722. Best, Stephen, and Sharon Marcus. “Surface Reading: An Introduction.” Representations 108.1 (2009): 1–21. Dolven, Jeff. Scenes of Instruction in Renaissance Romance. Chicago: University of ChicagoPress, 2007. Dolven, Jeff. Senses of Style. Chicago: UniversityofChicagoPress, 2018. Donne, John. The Complete Poems of John Donne. Ed. Robin Robbins. Harlow: Longman, 2010. England’sHelicon. Ed.A.H. Bullen. London: John C. Nimmo, 1887. Felski, Rita. The LimitsofCritique. Chicago: University of ChicagoPress,2015. Foster, Hal. Bad New Days: Art,Criticism, Emergency. London: Verso, 2017. Gell, Alfred. Art and Agency: An Anthropological Theory. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press, 1998. Halliwell,Stephen. The Aesthetics of Mimesis. Princeton: PrincetonUniversity Press,2002. Johnson, Mark. The Meaning of the Body. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,2007. Pigman, G.W. “Versions of Imitation in the Renaissance.” Renaissance Quarterly 33.1 (1980): 1–32. Riggs, David. The WorldofChristopher Marlowe. New York: Holt, 2004. Schlegel, Friedrich. Kritische Friedrich-Schlegel-Ausgabe. Vol. 2. Ed. Hans Eichner.Munich, Paderborn, and Vienna:Schöningh,1967. Schlegel, Friedrich. Kritische Friedrich-Schlegel-Ausgabe. Vol. 1. Ed.Ernst Behler.Paderborn, Munich, and Vienna:Schöningh,1979. Schlegel, Friedrich. On the StudyofGreek Poetry. Trans. Stuart Barnett. Albany,NY: SUNY Press, 2001. Schlegel, Friedrich. “From ‘Critical Fragments’ (1779).” Classical and Romantic German Aesthetics. Ed.J.M. Bernstein. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversityPress, 2002a. 239–245. Schlegel, Friedrich. “From ‘Athenaeum fragments’ (1798).” Classical and Romantic German Aesthetics. Ed.J.M. Bernstein. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversityPress, 2002b.246‒260. Schlegel, Friedrich. “From ‘Ideas’ (1800).” Classical and Romantic German Aesthetics. Ed.J.M. Bernstein. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversityPress, 2002c. 261‒268. Schlegel, Friedrich. “‘On Goethe’s Meister’ (1798).” Classical and Romantic German Aesthetics. Ed. J.M. Bernstein. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversity Press,2002d. 269–286. Shakespeare, William. The Complete Sonnetsand Poems. Ed. Colin Burrow.Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, 2002. Sidney,Sir Philip. Miscellaneous Prose of SirPhilip Sidney. Eds. Katherine Duncan-Jones and Jan vanDorsten. Oxford: Oxford University Press,1973. Taussig, Michael. Mimesis and Alterity. London: Routledge, 1992. Walton, Izaak, and Charles Cotton. The Compleat Angler. Ed. Marjorie Swann. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, 2014. Williams, William Carlos. The Collected Poems of WilliamCarlos Williams. 2vols. Ed. Christopher McGowan. New York: New Directions, 1991.

Alexander GarcíaDüttmann “Echo Reconciles”

If one asks: what is poetic critique, or criticism, can one then avoid raising afurther question, namely: whyshould there be such athing as poetic critique,orcriticism, in the first place? Perhaps it is onlybytrying to answer this question, and in so doing echoing the answer to the initial question before it is given, that one will find the grounds on which to provide an idea of poetic critique,orcriticism. Onlyifone can feelthe urgency of poetic critique, or criticism, the urgency,the need, perhaps even the necessity,and communicate this feeling to others in apersuasive manner, can one develop aconvincing idea of such critique, one that proves less vulnerable to the objections of arbitrariness and abstraction, futility and gratuitousness. It maybehelpful in this context to restrict oneself to the domainofart rather than attempt auniversal justification. Indeedone could arguethat in the caseof art the critique or criticism that elucidates it,orsome of its aspects, requires the qual- ification that the adjective ‘poetic’ supplies, simply because without it thereisarisk of missing something important about art, namelyand triviallyits resistancetoprop- ositionalspeech or communicative discourse. Foraslongasthereisart and we wish to engage with it,nomatter how unlikelyits existencemay seem or preciselybecause its existenceseems so rather unlikely, what calls for some kind of poetic critique, or criticism, is the enigmatic natureorthe enigmaticalness of artworks,that which can- not be rendered intelligible and comprehensible by wayofaseries of propositions about art,orabout the artwork as agiven object.Inother words, unless one takes art to be enigmatic in asense to be established, poetic critique will hardlybe more than afanciful endeavorfor aesthetes,oradiversion for academics not so keen on being treated as serious professionals. It is art itself, whose enigmaticalness extends into the unlikeliness of its ownex- istence, it is the artwork as the enigmatic and enigmaticallyunlikelyresultofanin- tentional activity,thatgenerates the need for poetic critique and at the sametime suggests what it is that such critique must achieve.Art,aproduct of the mind and the bodyand not afact of nature, to put it in old-fashioned terminology, must appeal to the mind, to spirit,onthe basis of its enigmaticalness, which perhaps exceeds the very distinction between art and nature. This appealgives birth to poetic critique or criticism and begins to clarify its idea. Poeticcritique or criticism must partake in art; it must echo the artwork, by showing the limits and limitations, the insufficiencyofpropositional speech, or com- municative discourse.Ofcourse this demonstration has to be inseparable from the performance itself. To call critique poetic, to saythat it must partake in art and its engimaticalness, means to acknowledge the inseparability of demonstration and per- formance that is broughtabout by the artwork itself. It is by performing apoetic cri- tique of art thatthe limits and limitations, the insufficiency of propositional speech or communicative discourse are highlighted, not by demonstratingthem in the ab-

OpenAccess. ©2021 Alexander García Düttmann, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the CreativeCommons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-006 58 Alexander García Düttmann

stract or in amerelyconceptual manner. Insisting on the performativeaspect of po- etic critique means that such highlightingcannot take place in propositional speech or communicative discourse. The idea of poetic critique as acritique of artisthe idea of aparticipation in an enigmaticalness that bindstogether inextricablyperformance and demonstration, existenceand non-existence, as if each echoed the other.Poetic critique does not proceed to solve the riddle so as to relievethe artwork’sbeholder of the burden enigmaticalness places upon him. It is the idea of asemblance: in critique demonstration, conceptual elucidation is meant to prevail, and the poetic is supposedtoserveit, to servepropositional speech or communicative discourse. In truth, however,the performance of poetic critique renders the demonstration just as enigmatic as it appears to be in the work of art. One maybetempted to assert that this cannot be so in the instance of poetic critique because of its relianceonthe concept and the critical powers it bears. Yetisitnot often the case thatartworks seem bereft of enigmaticalness onlybecause one expects them to stagesome subtle or ostentatious mystification which critique is meant to strip away,laying bare what they are all about? But surelypoetic critique’s acknowledgement of the inextricability of perfor- mance and demonstration, existenceand non-existence, to be found in art, is not the sameasthe inextricability itself?Itflagsadifferencethat is often considered to indicate aself-reflexivity of art.Art becomes self-reflective when elevated to,or taken up by,poetic critique. Poeticcritique awakens art to an awareness of itself, acognitive awareness that determines,sublates,potentiates it aboveand beyond its ownlimits. Andifpoetic critique is to participate in art when cognizing it,then either art must come to an end, reveal aconceptual nature that eventuallyallows cri- tique to shed the poetic guise it has to adopt,oritmust inscribe itself in aboth re- ceptive and productive connectedness, in acontinuity of ever higher,more reflected formations thatithelps to establish and that willcarry art to the absolute. Yetultimatelyenigmaticalness and reflexivity must remainincompatible with each other since nothing trulyenigmatic can become aware of itself, grow sufficient- ly self-aware for cognition to solve the enigma in the course of an absolute, or infin- ite, reflection. Thedifferencebetween art and poetic critique – between, on the one hand, the inextricability of performance and demonstration, of existenceand non-ex- istence, and, on the other hand, its acknowledgment – is the uncertain difference that lies in an echoing.For it belongstothe definitionofanecho thatits effect can- not be reduced to passivity,and that its passive and active moments can never be told apart.Anecho thatdoes not fool the one who hears its sound or its voice, an echo that is not areminder of something more powerful, of areverberating other- ness, an echo thatdoes not double the simulacrum it produces, ceases to be an echo. , acontemporary master of poetic critique,though perhaps one who would have had reservations about using this expression,repeatedlystress- es the othernessofechoing.When referringtothe myth or legend of Echo and Nar- cissus in the Metamorphoses,hespeaks of echoing as a “junction” (Derrida 2003a, 10;translation A.G.D.) where repetition encounters the “unforeseeable.” He also pla- “Echo Reconciles” 59

ces the otherness of echoing at the very coreofone’srelationship to oneself, as an othernessthat complicates the alleged sameness of this relationship, and the narcis- sism inherent in it (Derrida 2003b, 204; translation A.G.D.). In the wake of such remarks,one could speculate that the idea of poetic critique entails asimilar complication. It affectsthe work of art’sself-sufficiency from within, as it were. Foristhe work of art not an achievement thatseeks to be self-sufficient?If so, then it generates more than just one kind of enigmaticalness, the enigmaticalness of an echoing of performance and demonstration that keeps disrupting its unity and that calls for poetic critique. It does so to the extent that self-sufficiency must always come across as enigmatic. The othernessofpoetic critique is, then, not to be sought in its conceptual scope or in its critical powers,inwhat its judgement mayreveal about the work of art, about its truth or its worth, but in its own undecidable echoing of the undecidability that the artwork’secho establishes between performance and demonstration. Doubt- less poetic critique creates its echoing with other means than the work of art.Itcre- ates it with the means of concepts thataccomplish critical work. In poetic critique, however,the otherness of means remains subservient to the otherness of an undecid- able echoing that, as such, must defy conceptuality. The idea of poetic critiqueisthe idea of an echoing that captures and reproduces an echoing.Performance and demonstration, existenceand non-existencekeep echoing each other undecidably in the artwork, and it is this strangeechoing,the echoing of conflictingtasks – the task of performance and the task of demonstration – and the echoing of nothing – the nothingness of non-existence – that is echoed in poetic critique.Asanechoing of an echoing,the idea of poetic critique becomes also perfectlysuperfluous.Paradoxically, then, poetic critique is all the more superfluous the more the need for it makes itself felt. It would fade away if the otherness of the artwork’secho, of the echoing of per- formance and demonstration thatproduces what is perceivedasessentiallyenigmat- ic about an artwork, let itself be captured and reproduced. And it would fade away if, conversely, the otherness of poetic critique’secho could not surprise the artwork in its turn.However,such surprise is onlytobehad if poetic critiqueadmits its super- fluousness. The enigmaticalness of artworks is due to the inextricability of performance and demonstration thatresistspropositional speech and communicative discourse.Itis due to aradical finitude that makes art hover between existenceand non-existence, as if its intrinsic reluctance to identification and instrumentalization, its enormous difficulty and disarmingsimplicity,kept it constantlyemerging from, and receding back into, non-existence.But the enigmaticalness of artworks is also due to the need art createsfor poetic critique,for participating critically and poeticallyinthe artwork, and to the sensation of shamethat must overcome whoever experiences such need,asiftouchingupon the enigmaticalness of the artwork wereasymptom of incontinence, acomportment utterlyalien to art.One cannot feel the need for po- etic critique without feelingthat it is asuperfluous and possiblyharmful undertak- 60 Alexander García Düttmann

ing,anintrusion thatwill proveunable to participate in the artwork and,asacon- sequence,will precipitateits destruction. Shame delays the satisfaction of the need for poetic critique but also protects it against acompulsive denial of the fact that, with each creation of an artwork, spirit, Geist,accomplishes something,independ- entlyofhow enigmatic and unlikelythis accomplishment maybe. Ashort passagefrom Adorno’sposthumously published Aesthetic Theory¹ can put to the test the idea of poetic critique developedsofar,especiallysince it places some emphasis on the effect of echoing.Thispassage, the onlyone in the book in which the author quotes an entire poem and comments upon it,opens with arejec- tion of the conventional distinction between hermetic and non-hermetic artworks, which is then, with agesture characteristic of Adorno’sthought, reintroduced in a radicalizedfashion.The hermeticism of so-called hermetic artworks,artworks that are deemed almost incomprehensible,isonlyanindication of the enigmaticalness that defines art in general, Adorno states. Hermetic artworks are, comparatively speaking, more comprehensible than artworks that are traditionallyand commonly considered to be easilyaccessibleand thatunder closer scrutinyturn out to be pro- hibitively intricate. Hidden “behind their galvanized surface” (Adorno 1970,186), a surface of universallyshared opinion that is meant to preservethem, they withdraw into themselvesand will not come out again. The echo has stopped resounding.To stress enigmaticalness by creatingapurposefullyhermetic work of art is an attempt to tame the enigma’sintractability.But to conjure it away by relating to awork of art as if it had been understood once and for all is unmistakable evidence of the enigma remainingasintractable as it must be. If, consequently, hermetic art can never attain the same hermeticism to which non-hermetic art aspires,then there is perhaps al- ways something slightlydisappointingabout it,something that does not quite mea- sure up to art’schallengeand worth, something that misses the enigmaticalness of art.Adorno does not saythis in so manywords, yethis observations on the dynamics of hermetic and non-hermetic art seem to point to such aconclusion. He then givesafirst account of the enigmaticalness of art,ofits irreducible though not unvaryinghermeticism. It is supposedtoresultfrom the transformation concepts undergo when they enter art’sdomain. Adorno resorts to an example and asks: what happens when Georg Trakl uses the word “sonata” in his poems?His an- swer to this question is startling because it seems to implythat the transformation the concept of “sonata” undergoes when it enters the domain of art,ofpoetry,of Trakl’spoems, when it ceases to function in “communicative discourse” (187) and be- gins to contribute to art’sconstitutive enigmaticalness,isthat it is no longer usedin the samemanner in which it is usedintechnical musical language. Surelyamusi- cologist’sdiscourse is arather special instance of “communicative discourse.” Surely the word “sonata,” as rare as its usageinordinary speech maybe, tends to be em-

 In the following, Iwill refertothe page numbersoftheGerman edition of Ästhetische Theorie, while using – and from time to time modifying – the English translation (see Adorno 1997, 122–124). “Echo Reconciles” 61

ployed in amuch vaguer fashion when it is not aspecialist who is speaking.Infact, it tends to be employed quite similarlytothe mannerinwhich it is usedinthe poem, so that this example proves astrangeone for the linguistic transformation, the trans- formative “borrowing” of terms art is supposedtoaccomplish, a “borrowing” that renders enigmatic what seemed comprehensible in the first place. In the poem, Ador- no observes, sonata no longer designates an “entity,” a “construct,” or a “formation” that is “highlyarticulated, motivicallyand thematicallywrought, and internallydy- namic.” (186) It no longer designates amusical “entity” whose “unity is aclearlydif- ferentiated manifold, with development and recapitulation.” Rather the concept turns into an evocativename, as if “sonata” in the poem came much closer to reveal- ing its essence than in the discourse of the musicologist, fulfilling acommunicative function rather than fostering the enigmaticalness of art – unless, of course, it is self- evidence that is trulyenigmatic in the end. But what transpires from the musical ex- ample and alsofrom the other examples giveninthe text,isthat the workofart op- eratesasort of deactivation of unambiguous or obvious meaning.The semantic force that the usageofthe word “sonata” obtains in Trakl’spoemsderives from the impos- sibility of saying exactlywhat it means. It is this forcethat must be regarded as enig- matic. At times it has astabilizingeffect,creatingapowerful “imago” (186), acom- memorative or unconscious representation endowed with acertain autonomythat summons, deepens, and intensifies comprehension. But it can also have adestabiliz- ing effect,making meaning in an artwork, and the meaningofthe artwork itself, un- certain and ambiguous, ungraspable in terms of aproposition or aconstative utter- ance. Thus, the poetic usageofthe copula “is” maydrawitnear to its own negation despite anegative particle not beingadded to it.The copula acquires an enigmatic forcethatstems from the undecidability as to whether it is actuallyusedaffirmative- ly,asapositive “existential judgement.” This forceproduces “pale afterimage[s]” (187) that let the initial meaningturn into its very opposite, or dither between the original and the simulacrum, as if its echo infused it with otherness. Perhaps one could saythat it is the forceofatrace, atrace that is never apresenceoranabsence. Before quoting Mörike’s “MousetrapRhyme” (Mausfallen-Sprüchlein), apoem that is asort of spellsince it acts as amousetrap,Adorno pointsout the similarity and the dissimilarity between an artwork and ajudgement. He speaksofananalogy: artworks and judgements are similar in that they are bothdetermined by asynthesiz- ing power.While ajudgement attributes apredicate to asubject, bringssubjectand predicatetogether conceptually, or cognitively,byidentifying them, awork of art gathers all its different and heterogeneous elements mimetically so thatthey can be recognized as belongingtoit. Yetworks of art do not judge;they do not state something or carry amessagethat would conveytheir meaning.They are, as it were, judgements without judgement,judgements thathavebeen deactivated but not erased, judgementsthat preservetheir form and at the same time remain empty.Adorno writes, “[w]hat works of art amount to,that which establishes their unity,cannot be formulatedasajudgement,not even as one that they maycontain, that they issue explicitlyorstate in words and sentences” (187; trans. modified). That 62 Alexander García Düttmann

critique,, must be poetic in view of art’senigmaticalness, means, as can be gauged from Adorno’sargument about the transformation that elements, linguis- tic elements, undergo whenart appropriates them, that it needs to payattention to the echoing such appropriation causes. It needs to prolongand reinvent an echoing that can consist in a “yes” reverberatingasa“no,” or a “no” reverberatingasa“yes,” without,however,affirmationsimplycollapsing into negation, or,conversely, nega- tion into affirmation. The “discursive content” of the “MousetrapRhyme” reproduced in the passage on the hermeticism, the enigmaticalness, the transformative forceofart,restricts the poem, as Adorno remarks,toa“sadistic identification with what civilized custom has done to animalsdisdained as parasites” (187, trans.modified). In truth, this con- tent,the meaningofthe child’senticing and taunting of the mouse, with whom it wishestoperformadance after dinner, in the moonlight,adance in which its old cat is supposed to join, is suspended at the very moment the poem enounces it. So rather than celebratingaritual of liquidation, the poem is said to denounce it, and to do so by keeping the gistofadeadlyritual, by following its rules and never exiting the “gapless immanence” of the celebration. Subordination does not confirm this “abominable” and “socially conditioned ritual” (188) but transcends it through its unflinching linguistic reflection, or repetition, as if artconsisted in turning the “gesture” that takes something for granted against itself. “Sadistic iden- tification” no longer has “the last word” in apoem thatseems to be entirely consti- tuted by it,that does not simply refer to apreceding social condition but thatcreates this condition within itself, performance and demonstration being inseparable though not identical: “Form, which shapes verse into the reverberation of amythical spell, suspends its disposition” (187). Yet, having reached this insight into the enigmaticalness of art, the reader of Aes- thetic Theory maywell wonder about two claims that pertain to the argument Adorno puts forward. Forcould the poem ever produce its echoing effect,could it ever link performance and demonstration in an inextricable and undecidable manner, if it did not partake in “sadisticidentification” at all, in the staging of aritual that does not simplyexist outside it,regardless of how much this ritual is “socially conditioned”? Must the forceneeded to overcome “sadistic identification” not be broached from the identificatory forceitself, at least if alogic of repetition, of echoing,istobeatwork in the poem Adorno examines?Isthere not an irreducible ambiguity to echoing in- asmuch as art “borrows” from reality,orbetter still from “communicative discourse,” and thus cannot avoid recreatingreality and drawingon“communicative discourse?” And if it is preciselyart’sabstention from judgement thatresults in judgement,inan act of holding court and indicting,asAdorno maintains, is one statement not then replaced by another,astatement that contradicts it but astatement nonetheless, no matter how tacit the critical denunciation remains?Does the inverting repetition of statements not submit the echoing effect to “communicative discourse” and re- duceart to one of its manifestations, amanifestation bereft of enigmaticalness? Can the blinding “mythical” spell that identification perpetuates, “sadistic identifica- “EchoReconciles” 63

tion” and the identification distinctive of judgements, ever be broken by adiscourse of critique, or negativity? At the exact junctureinthe text wherethese questions arise for the reader,Ador- no inserts agnomic phrase: “Echo reconciles.” (188) How does one read this phrase? How does one listen to it?Can the reconciliatoryforcethat Adorno bestows upon Echo, upon the echoing effect,reconcile the conflictthat traverses and disruptsit, the conflict between echoing as standardized, as deceptive,asevidence of aspell, all forms of echoing to be found in the work of the philosopher,and echoing in art,echoing as that which prompts reconciliation, bringsconsolation, and defines love? “There is no lovethat is not an echo” (Adorno 1980,248/217), Adorno writes in his MinimaMoralia. If one takes echoing to be standardized, deceptive,orevi- dence of aspell, one will probablyhear the gnomic phrase “Echo reconciles” as an apodictic statement,astatement thatdoes not allow for anykind of objection or appeal, hesitation or uncertainty.One will hearitasastatement that does not mean what it says.If, however,one takesechoing to be an effect indistinguishable from acause and capable of promptingreconciliation, bringingconsolation, and de- fining love, then one will probablyhere the same phrase differently, as an infinitely discrete, tenuous and receding utterance. In his reading of Mörike’spoem, Adorno recalls the “involuntarilyfriendlyimage of child, cat,and mouse dancing,the two animalsontheir hind legs” (Adorno 1970, 188). Reconciliation lies here in the divergence between what is willed, “sadistic identification,” and what is suggested, “friendliness.” It is as if the reconciliatory forceofechoing,ofthe echoing that takes place between two images that exist onlyasand in one single poem, that are the same and yetdifferent,that have both reinforcing and releasingqualities, depended upon adeactivation of the will because reconciliation is not something that can be willfullysought.The reconcilia- tion Echo, or echoing,achieves has nothing to do with avoluntary process. Echo’s otherness, the otherness of anoun that might be aproper name, is not the otherness of an intention aiming at reconciliation rather than at identification, whether in the sense of an identificationwith violence or in the sense of aviolent identification of a subject. Adorno’sreadingofMörike’spoem is apiece of poetic critique inasmuchas the gnomic phrase “Echo reconciles,” this phrase whose succinctness functions as an author’ssignatureand whose elliptical reservedness escapes authorship altogeth- er,echoes the echoing of performance and demonstration in the “Mousetrap Rhyme.” Nothing and no one can guarantee that aperformative forceofreconciliation emergesfrom the artwork, from its echoing of performance and demonstration, least of all the artist,the author,the poet.Henceitisreconciliation as aperformative forcethatmakes art fundamentallyenigmatic. Thedifficulty of poetic critique called forth by the enigmaticalness of artisthe difficulty of lovethat Adorno emphasizes in MinimaMoralia: “All is over if what one finds for the other [was man fürihn findet] no longer reaches him” (Adorno 1980,248/217). Inasmuchaswhat lovefindstogive to the otherisalways an echo thatcomes from the other, poetic critique that can no 64 Alexander García Düttmann

longer reach the artwork, the artwork’sotherness, has lost its feel for the echoing ef- fect,its ability to love. It looks for meaningsormessages conveyedbythe artwork, ignoringthe fact that the artwork has absorbedand transformed them, and that they are not essentialbut accidental features of art.Itmisses out on the “infinite” (Adorno 1970,188) thatartworks harbor within themselves, the true “infinity” that Echo and echoing alone disclose.

Bibliography

Adorno, Theodor W. Ästhetische Theorie. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1970.[English translation: Aesthetic Theory. Trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor.London: The Athlone Press,1997.] Adorno, Theodor W. MinimaMoralia. Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. 4. Ed.Rolf Tiedemann. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1980.[English translation: Minima Moralia. Trans. E. Jephcott. London: Verso, 1999.] Derrida, Jacques. Voyous. Paris: Galilée, 2003a. Derrida, Jacques. Chaque fois unique, la fin du monde. Paris: Galilée, 2003b. Jonathan Elmer On Not Forcing the Question: Criticismand Playing Along

1

Critics are contemptible. How else can we explain the stream of taunts and mockeries directed at them?Critics are, first of all, wannabes:they wish they were artists, but they aren’t. Thisleadstoapervasive envy,captured well in ’ssummary judgment: “Interpretation is the revengeofthe intellectual upon the artist” (Sontag 1990 [1966], 7). Critics wish to share in the glory of the artist,but they don’t: “Ihave been all over the world and Ihavenever seen astatue of acritic.” (This gibe is var- iouslyattributed to or Leonard Bernstein.) The more exorbitant the ar- tistic ambition,itseems, the greater the contempt for those who merelyinterpret. Gustave Flaubert,aman with ambitions, implies that the creative defect in critics is analogous to the moraldefect of spies: people “write criticism because they are unable to be artists, just as aman unfit to bear arms becomes apolicespy” (Flaubert 1979,xv). Elsewhere, Flaubert makes his moral point differently: “Criticism occupies the lowest place in the literary hierarchy; as regards form, almostalways; and as re- gards ‘moral value,’ incontestably. It comes after rhyming games and acrostics,which at least requireacertain inventiveness.” (xv) Incompetent,resentful, underhand, policing – such is the standard litany of the critic’sfaults.Inthese attacks, the critic is always in aderivative relation to the artist and the artwork; he is aparasite, akind of tick. This attitude toward critics is neither new nor rare; Icertainlycould have chosen other examples. WhatIwant to empha- size is the intensity of feeling that animatesthis current of thought,and the grandi- osity of its terms. Astatue for the artist! Greatness lies with the artist,paltriness with the spying critic. The whole relationship seems colored by very basic, even primitive, experiencesand fantasies, as if “His Majesty,the Baby (Artist)” felt constantlyhem- med in, controlled, misunderstood, or disciplined by some witnessing or surveilling presence – the critic as a never “good-enough” minder. In anycase, thatisthe direction Iwant to travel in this essay. Iwish to consider the problem of ‘poetic critique’ as encompassed in this scenario of acreative actor and awitnessingother.The twinning of creator and witness is, in one sense, existen- tial: every human act,creative or otherwise, is born into aworld in which others have come before. The witnessing other mayenable this creative act,like oxygen helping the spark to flame, or might disable it,awet blanket thrown over that spark toosoon. But as is signaled by my riffing aboveonpsychoanalytic mottos –“His Majesty,the Baby” (Freud) and “good enough mother” (Winnicott) – Ialso take psychoanalysis to be aprivileged discourse for anyinquiry into the question of poetic critique.That is

OpenAccess. ©2021Jonathan Elmer, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-007 66 Jonathan Elmer

because the work of analysis is always a joint production of patient and analyst. What is brought forth through the complex weave of unconscious materials,transfer- ence effects, and interpretation is new meaning that is also always old: it is both poi- esis and critique.The psychoanalytic situation suggests that while the creative and the interpretive are necessarilyco-present dimensions, they are not co-incident – just twonames for the samething – nor,for thatmatter,are they fullyseparable. Iwill argue, in fact,that the question of the relation of the creative and the critical, of that which bringsnewness into the world – poiesis – and that which works on what is found in the world, maybenefit from not beingbroached at all. My warrant for such an approach is the work of psychoanalyst D.W. Winnicott. Hereisperhaps the best-known statement of his influential ideas about the transi- tional object,about illusion and play, and the witnessing presencenecessary to such play:

The transitional object and the transitional phenomena start each human beingoff with what will always be importantfor them, i.e. aneutral area of experience which will not be challenged. Of the transitionalobject it can be said that it is amatter of agreement between us and the baby that we will never askthe question: ‘Did you conceiveofthis or was it presented to you from with- out?’ Theimportant point is that no decision on this point is expected. Thequestion is not to be formulated. (Winnicott 1991 [1971], 12)

Winnicott remains focused on this “neutral” or “intermediate” (11,13, 105) area of experience for his entire career.Itis, he , the very ground of creative “expe- riencing” (2,6,14) in all of life (he often uses this odd gerund to keep our eyeonproc- ess rather than product). If this passagethrough the “experiencing” of azone of “il- lusion” (3,11) – the wordillusion, we should point out,derivesfrom in-ludere,in play; – if this zone is not happilytraversed, it is likelythe child will have troubles in life, will find it hard to consider life meaningful. These transitional phenomena in which the relation between subjective and objectiveisnot broached are, Winnicott believes, essential for human being in its totality:

It is assumedherethat the task of reality-acceptance is never completed, that no human beingis free from the strain of relating inner and outerreality,and that relieffrom this strain is provided by an intermediateareaofexperiencewhich is not challenged(arts, religion, etc.).This inter- mediateareaisindirect continuity with the playareaofthe small child whois‘lost’ in play. (13)

The swiftness and the unobtrusiveness with which Winnicott jumpsfrom the minu- tiae of child analysis to the furthestreaches of “culture” can make it hard to grasp the claim he is making.The child “lost” in play, the child with whom the interpreting other has atacitagreement not to forcecertain questions, is in “direct continuity” with any grown person participating in the aesthetic and religious dimensions of life.What we learn from child psychoanalysis,inother words, maybefruitfullytrans- posed to analyses of the arts. This is hardlyanew idea. Psychoanalysis has never shied away from extendingits interpretive domain beyond the consulting room; On Not Forcing the Question: Criticism and PlayingAlong 67

Freud himself was very interested in using the tools of psychoanalysis to interpret artists, artworks,and aesthetic experience more generally. But there is something in Winnicott’swork – in his style of presentation as much as in the content of his ideas – that is unique in the psychoanalytic canon, and thatsuggests otherlessons than Freud’smight be available. Adam Phillips argues that the “genre of simplicity in which Winnicott writes, a wry version of pastoral, is in fact akind of elusiveness. But the shrewdingenuous- ness of his writing, unprecedented in the psychoanalytic tradition, is consistent with one of his therapeutic aims: to protect the privacyofthe self in the making of person- al sense and,bythe same token, personal non-sense” (Phillips 1988, 14). This seems right,and also complicated: on the one hand, the explanatory reach claimedbyWin- nicott’sidea of this unforced “neutral zone”–“arts, religion, etc.” [emphasis mine] – is exorbitant, and Winnicott might thereby be said to displaysome of the grandiosity Iwas flagging above. On the otherhand, this grandiosity is displayedinsuch are- cessive and “elusive” manner that it is hard to know if one has understood it correct- ly.Some of this is duetoWinnicott’sstrongpredilection for the passivevoice: “Of the transitional object it canbesaid”; “The important point is that no decision on this point is expected”; “The question is not to be formulated.” Passivity is so charged for Winnicott that,asBarbaraJohnson has remarked, objects themselvesare invested with agency so that their own pathos can be registered: the transitional object’s “fate is to be graduallyallowed to be decathected […]Itisnot forgotten and it is not mourned.Itloses meaning” (Johnson 2008, 100). When Phillips writes thatWinni- cott’sstyle “is consistent” with his “therapeutic aim” to “protect the privacyofthe self,” it is both the patient’sself and his own that Winnicott has in mind: “The need of the self to be both intelligible and hidden that he found in his patients is reflected in his style.” (Phillips 1988, 14) At the same time, Winnicott’selusiveness, his desire to remainhidden, is curi- ouslyvulnerable and exposed.¹ It is this simultaneouslyrecessive and vulnerable posture towardthe work of psychoanalytic interpretation that sets Winnicott apart. In one paper,heinvokes the proverbialarmchair philosopher onlytosuggest that if the philosopher gets out of his chair and on the floor with the playing child things would look different.Winnicott’selusiveness is deployed from aposition on the floor, as it were. Compare this to Freud in his famous analysis of the child’sgame of fort-da in Beyond the Pleasure Principle. Doing everythinghecan to keep adistance from the context of his observation, Freud refers to his grandson drilyasa“little boy of one and ahalf” (Freud 1961[1920], 8); and perhaps to keep at bayany worries that his familyrelationship to the child has led him to impute cleverness wherethereis none, Freud makes clear that the “child was not at all precocious in his intellectual development” (8). How,finally,does Freud come to understand that the “loud, long- drawn-out o-o-o-o” is in fact the word “fort”?Hedoes not tell us; he merelyreports

 On the importance of “self-exposure” in criticism, see Chaouli 2013. 68 Jonathan Elmer

that the child’s “mother and the writer of the present account wereagreed in think- ing” (9) that it was so. Reading this passagewith Winnicott in mind, we might re- mark that here, too, we have akind of exhibition of hiddenness. But thereisacrucial difference: in Freud’scasethe severallayers of recessiveness – an obscured family relation, avoidance of the I, passive voice – are in service to analytic power rather than the kind of “vulnerability” we find in Winnicott. “One dayImade an observa- tion that confirmed my view” (9), Freud writes,and goes on to describe the famous playwith the spool. “The interpretation of the game then became obvious” (9). Case closed. Child analysis was never acentral concern of Freud’s, even as his foraysinto this practice (think of “Little Hans”)foreshadowed important developments in the psy- choanalytic tradition. Winnicott was apediatrician before he was an analyst,but even if he had not been, he might well have steered towardthe interpretation of chil- dren, since the two dominant schools of psychoanalysis in Britain,those of Anna Freud and Melanie Klein, relied so fundamentallyonchild analysis.Winnicott was amajor figure in what has come to be called the “Third Way,” along with Marion Mil- ner,Masud Khan, and others. In “Playing:ATheoretical Statement,” Winnicott sig- nals his divergence from Klein, in particular: “in so far as she was concernedwith play,” it was “almost entirelywith the use of play” (Winnicott 1991 [1971], 39). She moves too efficiently,Winnicott suggests, from observation to interpretation, as Freud for example moves from the fort-dagame to the “obvious” interpretation that this game meant “mastery.” The “psychoanalyst has been too busy using play content to look at the playing child,” Winnicott writes, “and to write about playing as athing in itself. It is obvious that Iammaking asignificant distinction between the meaningsofthe noun ‘play’ and the verbal noun ‘playing.’” (40) What,exactly, is Winnicott’sdisagreementwith Klein?What’sthe difference be- tween “play” and “playing”?Klein’sclinical acumen was much celebrated, and her innovations in the technique of child analysis werewidelyinfluential. It is also true that Klein took an extremelyactive interpretive posture, something that,from her earliest papers,she argued was necessary:

As soon as the small patient has givensome sort of insightinto his complexes – whetherthrough his games or his drawingsorphantasies – Iconsider that interpretation can and should begin. This does not run counter to the well-tried rule that the analyst should wait till the transference is therebeforehebegins interpreting, because with children the transference takesplaceimme- diately. (Klein 1949[1932], 47)

With small children, Klein explains, separation between conscious and unconscious behavior is onlytenuouslyinplace, with the resultthat manydefenses (such as those inhibiting transference) are not present.Atthe same time, anxiety is much more dis- ablinginmanychildren than in manyolder patients. Thisanxiety also calls for early intervention. Agirl of threethat Klein calls Trude “exhibited […]much anxiety at her very first coming.” Klein tells us that “in such patientsprompt interpretation was the On Not Forcing the Question: Criticism and Playing Along 69

onlymeans of lessening anxiety” (53). Children present special problems calling for swift and vigorous interpretive intervention. Reading Klein can be aharrowingexperience, not onlybecause the clinical ma- terial from small children is so oftenviolent and florid, but alsobecause her own in- terpretive vigilanceissounrelenting. Klein’slastpublication was adetailedcase studyofaten-year-old boy,Richard, whom she treated during the war.Hereisa taste of what it is like:

Richard[…]often fearedthat anasty man – akind of tramp – would comeand kidnapMummy during the night,[…].

Mrs K. askedhow he thoughtthe tramp would getinto Mummy’sroom.

Richardsaid (aftersome resistance)that he might getinthrough the window:perhaps he would break in.

Mrs K. askedifhealso wonderedwhether the tramp would hurt Mummy.

Richard(reluctantly) answeredthat he thought the man might hurt her,but he, Richard, would go to her rescue.

Mrs K. suggestedthat the tramp whowould hurt Mummyatnight seemed to him very much like Hitler whofrightened Cook in the air-raidand ill-treated the Austrians.Richardknew that Mrs K. was Austrian, and so she toowould be ill-treated. At night he might have been afraidthat when his parents went to bed somethingcould happen between them with their genitals that would injure Mummy.

Richardlooked surprisedand frightened. (Klein 1961, 20–21)

This exchangecomes from the first session. The analysis continues in this vein for another four hundred pages. At ten years of age, Richard is more verballyfluent thanmanyofKlein’syounger patients. But playwith toysisasswiftlyreduced to its unconscious meaning as Ri- chard’sverbalmaterial: “[I]n the first hour,” Klein writes of Peter,not quite four years old, “his knocking together of the two carriages and horses had been followed by his remarkingthathehad gotanew little brother.SoIcontinued my interpretation and said: ‘Youthought to yourself thatDaddyand Mummy bumpedtheir thingummies together and thatmade your brother Fritz be born’” (Klein 1949,42).Whatever the efficacy of Klein’sclinical work – and there seems to be lots of evidence thatshe helped her young patients very much – her interpretive method cannot help seeming aggressive.There is, in the end, aknown code to which fantasies can, and must,be reduced: the code of oedipal feelings, primal scenes,the entire Freudian armory that is unquestioningly invoked even as it is constantlybeing revised and reshaped by Klein’sclinical experience. Toys bumping =thingummies bumping. “In so far as she wasconcerned with play,” Winnicott had remarked about Klein, it was “almost entirelywith the use of play” (Winnicott 1991 [1971], 39). The child’suse of play, and hers. The idea that play, as an act of creativity,would express the “need of the self to 70 Jonathan Elmer

be both intelligible and hidden [emphasis mine]” (Phillips 1988, 14), is not aconcern of Klein’s. Inoted earlier Winnicott’sstrangepreferencefor “experiencing” wherewemight expect “experience,” and his choice of “playing” over playcomes from the same dis- position: namely, to avoid relapsing, for as long as feasible, into interpretive abstrac- tion –“play” (abstraction) serves or means “mastery” (abstraction);or, toysbumping means thingummies bumping.But interpretive abstraction can also lead to over-es- timation of the objectivedimension itself, of the toy,game, or creation, understood as separate from, even if revealing,the secrets of the child. Thisversion of interpre- tive abstraction loses sight of the mystery of creativity itself: “When psycho-analysis has attempted to tackle the subject of creativity it has to alarge extent lost sight of the main theme,” Winnicott writesin“Creativity and ItsOrigins.”“It is possible to take Leonardo Da Vinci and make very important and interesting comments on the relationship between his work and certain events that took place in his infancy” (Winnicott 1991 [1971], 69). But:

It is inevitable that such studies of great men tend to irritateartists and creative people in gen- eral. It could be that these studies […]are irritatingbecause they look as if they aregettingsome- where,asifthey will soon be abletoexplain whythis man was great and that woman achieved much, but the direction of inquiry is wrong.The main theme is beingcircumvented, that of the creative impulse itself. The creation stands between the observer and the artist’screativity.(69)

Let me pause here and gather up some threads. Ibegan with the tradition of spleen directed at the critic. Winnicott understands such rage,though he calls it,more mild- ly, “irritation,” and suggests it might be due to interpretation (or what Iamalso call- ing criticism) “looking like it is gettingsomewhere.” Interpreters might “getsome- where” by recoursetoacode, but also – and this is more strange – by letting “the creation [stand] between the observer and the artist’screativity.” Critical methods that over-invest the object in this latter wayare in fact over-investing their method, they are eager to “getsomewhere,” to basically takeovercontrol of the playing.But what would it mean to stayfocused on the artist’screativity,not ignoring the crea- tions but understanding them as emblems of aprocess that should be allowed to be ongoing,not swiftlyresolvedinto meaning? This is whereWinnicott’sinsistence on “not forcingthe question” becomes his central technicalcontribution. To forcethe question – to require an answer to the question of whether this object is made up or found – is, finally, to over-value the object.Itistoossify it to the extent that it be- comes an object in the interpreter’sown itinerary, like abaton being passed. But if the child or artisthas passed the baton, he or she is no longer playing.Inworrying about the ontological status of the object,playissuspended, or ruined. On Not Forcing the Question: Criticism and PlayingAlong 71

2

Iwant now to pull the focus out from child analysis to ask some questions about in- terpretation and aesthetic experience more broadlyconstrued. What Winnicott is so intent upon – not forcingthe question, leaving the intermediate space unchallenged, its paradoxesunresolved – can sometimes look familiar,and sometimes strange. Granting for the moment the possibility of “direct” continuity between infantile playand “arts, religion, etc.,” we could arguethatthe tacit compact between creative behavior and its witness (who might now,inour wider focus, be areader,ortheater- goer) not to ask certain questions goes by some familiar names: the “suspensionof disbelief,” for example. HereisBill Watterson, the creator of the Calvin and Hobbes comic strip, on this topic:

The so-called ‘gimmick’ of my strip – the two versions of Hobbes – is sometimes misunderstood. Idon’tthink Hobbes as adoll miraculouslycomes to life when Calvin’saround.Neither do I think of Hobbes as the product of Calvin’simagination. The natureofHobbes’sreality doesn’t interest me, and each story goes out of its waytoavoid resolvingthe issue. (qtd. in Groensteen 2013 [2011], 129)

This is satisfyingly Winnicottian in its staging:achoice is there – animated stuffed tiger,orimaginary projection? – and that choice is refused. “The nature of Hobbes’ reality doesn’tinterest” Watterson, and if we are readingthe strip in aWinnicottian spirit,itwon’tinterest us either.We’dbenincompoops if we worried too much about Hobbes’ reality,just as we would be if we worried the problem of Hamlet’sreality when we go to the theater.IfWatterson was playing with areal child named Calvin, then this readiness not to ask aquestion would be in service of continued play. Cal- vin is not real of course, but Watterson’streatment of the Calvin/Hobbes relationship works as if he is, and in anycase is in service of keepingthe playproceeding,and the strip open-ended: “each story goes out of its waytoavoid resolving the issue.” This interest in keeping playproceeding,what Winnicott calls an interest in “playing” rather than merely “play,” is one result of not forcingthe question. One wayinwhich creator and interpreting witness come together to produce something that we might call “poetic critique,” is by understanding the playing involved as part of aprocess that both precedes and succeeds the objects created and interpreted. There are some kindsof“playing along” that have,strictlyspeaking, no beginning or ending,merelyaseries of resting-places and way-stations. , a special kind of “play,” oftenhas this feeling;and perhaps philosophy, concerned as it is with fundamental problems thathide their origins and ends, has aspecial closeness to our problem of playing along.(If so, it is not without paradox: not forc- ing the question by forcingamultitude of questions!) In the intricate final movement of ’s TheClaim of Reason,there are afew curious pages on dolls. Cavell has been asking questions about identity,about bodies, about our idea thatbodies 72 Jonathan Elmer

are living,and so on. He has justfinished ruminating on the relationship between a statue and the stone of which it is made.Suddenly, anew theme is introduced:

Astatue has aspects.Bywalkingaround it,bythe changinglight,inyour changingmood, the figure can be seen as vulnerable, as indomitable, as in repose, as if in readiness. Adoll has oc- casions.Iam thinkingofaragdoll. It can be happy or sad, fed or punished. In reposeithas aspects,for example it can be seen as sleepingordead or sun-bathing. But onlyifyou do not know which is true. (Cavell 1979,401)

The distinction between “aspects” and “occasions” Cavell develops here points to two different kinds of life we are prepared to impute to non-living things. Aspects are, as it were, snapshots of the “life” of the statue, always traceable to our changing visions: “the figure can be seen [emphasis mine] as vulnerable,” etc. “Occasions,” by contrast,implyanongoingness, an insertion of the figure in ahistory thatdeter- mines the “truth” that onlyyour not knowing would allow youtosee the doll as merelyamatter of aspects – as “sleeping or dead or sun-bathing.” But wheredoes this “truth” beyond aspects come from? The simple answer is this: “There is onlyone who knows which is true, the one whose doll it is” (401). We’re backatthe relation between the one who knows – the child – and the one who wishes to know,the observer,the player-along,here the phi- losopher.(Of course, in the psychoanalytic version, the child both knows and does not know.) Cavell describes aseries of exchanges about the doll between its “owner”–he questions that wordtoo – and the observer.The point of these ex- changes is thatevenifthe observerdefers –“At some point my saycomes to an end. Idefer to the one whose doll it is” (402) – the “truth” of the doll’s “occasion” is nevertheless ajoint production.

There arecriteria in terms of which Isettle judgments about the (other’s) doll. To know whether aconcept appliesIhave to look – at the doll. Ihavetodetermine if Ican see it in this way, get that occasion for it to dawn for me. Otherwise Iamonlyhumoringthe one whose doll it is. Per- hapsIamtired, or have ahead-ache. Icannot in anycase experience the meaningofthe words about the doll. The doll seems rags.Istill know what adoll is; but at the moment Iamdoll- blind. (401–402)

The fact that youcan know what adoll is and be doll-blind says something about the kind of knowledge we are dealing with. This knowledge of what adoll is does not help us see the doll, does not help us overcome doll-blindness, when it hits. Knowing what adoll is does not help us “enter into its history,achieve the spirit in which con- cepts of life are applied to it” (403). To “enter into its history,” if Iunderstand correct- ly,isneither to denythe doll – to sayitisjustrags – nor merelytodefer to the one whose doll it is; it is to “getthatoccasion to dawn for me.” Notice here that Cavell is describingasituation in which too restricted afocus on the object – on “what adoll is”–will fail in understanding the reliance of thatobject on aprocess, an “occa- sion,” thatexceeds it.Getting an “occasion to dawn for me” is akind of imaginative On Not Forcing the Question: Criticism and Playing Along 73

investment that is neither “poetic” nor “critical,” or rather is both, but neither at the expense of the other. Such imaginative investmentextends the “history” of the doll in the waywe might hope sensitive criticism allows its “occasions” to continue their histories. It does not,inany case, make too much of the form, or “reality,” of the doll, knowing that its life does not exist there. It does not hijack its history either.Toward the end of these penetratingpages on the “occasions” of the doll’slife, Cavell forwards his own unforced question: “What is the doll?(Iwould like to answer that question because I feel Iknow everything there is to know about dolls. But Iwould like not to have to answer it since of course Iknow absolutelynothing about dolls that others do not know)” (404). Some questions, the answers to which everyone knows but no one knows differently, are better left unanswered. Cavell’smethod – at once poetic and critical – tacks between the urgency of answering and the urgency of not answer- ing;his genius is in his ability to ask questions for which such tacking is the best response. It is not incidental that child’splay – with an other,since there always is an other,one hopefullyfendingoff “doll-blindness”–provides such apowerful occasion to turn away from the too-quick answer in favorofopen sailing on asea of questions. It is child’splay, in anycase, that here provides Cavell with an “occa- sion” to exercise and exemplify his unique method of poetic critique, amethod for which, as his book’sepigraph from RalphWaldo Emerson has it, “it is not instruc- tion, but provocation, thatIcan receive from another soul” (iii).

3

The English literary critic William Empson was well acquainted with the contempt in which critics were held: “Critics, as ‘barking dogs,’ […]are of twosorts: those who merelyrelievethemselvesagainst the flower of beauty,and those, less continent, who afterwards scratch it up” (Empson 1947, 9). But he remains unfazed:

Imyself, Imust confess, aspiretothe second of these classes;unexplained beauty arouses an irritation in me, asense that this would be agood placetoscratch; the reasons that makealine of verse to give pleasure, Ibelieve, are likethe reasonsfor anythingelse; one can reason about them; and while it maybetrue that the roots of beauty ought not to be violated, it seems to me very arrogantofthe appreciative critic to think that he could do this, if he chose, by alittle scratching. (9)

At first blush, the “appreciative” critic, who eschewsscratchinglikeabarking dog, might seem more Winnicottian in his interpretive restraint than Empson. But it has never been aquestion of not asking questions at all;Winnicott’sconcern is with the kind of digging thatlooks too much “like it is getting somewhere,” as if it reallywerepossible to getfullyatthe root of things(about which Empson is skep- tical). LikeCavell, Empson practices poetic critique as akind of interpretive errancy, getting all kinds of places but perhaps nowhereinparticular. 74 Jonathan Elmer

Empson’sfirst book was Seven Types of Ambiguity,awork about which one could well ask whyitbegins whereitdoes or ends whereitdoes. In the Prefacetothe sec- ond 1947edition of his book, Empson considers some of the criticisms he received after the publication of the first edition. The prevailing moodofthe critics seems to have been exasperation. And it is an understandable response: Empson’s ‘meth- od,’ if it is one, is to unspool avariety of meanings from apiece of verse like aped- dler unpacking his wares for visual effect; to consider how these shades of meaning might unite to produce the power of the poetry;tobrieflyadmire the array again; and then move on to another example. In reply, Empson focuses his response on one re- view by James Smith, who had argued that Empson fails miserably in what is the “first business” of the critic, namely “the passingofajudgment on value” (xii).Emp- son admits that Smith is correct in this charge: “Even in the fuller examples, whereI hope Ihavemade clear what Ifeelabout the poem as awhole, Idon’ttry to ‘make out acase’ for my opinion of its value” (xiii). This is because Empson understands the role of judgment to be not some one-off conclusion or ruling,but rather astruc- tural assumption of the work of interpretationitself: “The judgment indeedcomes either earlier or laterthan the processwhich Iwas trying to examine. Youthink the poem is worth the trouble before youchoose to go into it carefully, and you know more about what it is worth when youhavedone so” (xiii). The judgment of value is impliedinthe work of interpretation itself, in other words; it both precedes it as the notion that interpretationisworth undertaking right here, with this poem, and extends beyond anydelimited act of practical criticism: youthen know more about “what it is worth,” but not perhaps everything. The question of value judgmentsgets entangled, through Empson’sgenerous quotation of Smith’snegative review,with aversion of the Winnicottian question that must not be forced. Winnicott had written that “it is amatter of agreementbe- tween us and the baby that we will never askthe question: ‘Did you conceive of this or was it presentedtoyou from without?’” (Winnicott 1991 [1971], 12)Inthe present context,wemight paraphrase this as follows: “Is this poem athing in the mind or athing in the world?” Mr.James Smith has decided in advancehow he answers this question, as it regardsthe ambiguities analyzed by Empson:

Is the ambiguity referredtothat of life – is it abundle of diverse forces,bound together onlyby their co-existence? Or is it that of aliterary device – of the allusion, conceit,orpun, in one of their moreorless conscious forms?Ifthe first,then Mr.Empson’sthesis is whollymistaken; for a poem is not amerefragment of life; it is afragmentthat has been detached, considered, and judgedbyamind. Apoem is anoumenon rather than aphenomenon. If the second, then at least we can saythat Mr.Empson’sthesis is exaggerated. (qtd. in Empson 1947, xii)

“Apoem is anoumenon rather than aphenomenon,” athing in the mind, detached from the world by the mind, which also makes ajudgment about it.This is Smith’s position. Empson is less sure. He bringsupthe widelyshared position thatanartist’s judgment about his or her own work “maybewrong” (Empson 1947, xiv). On Not Forcing the Question: Criticism and PlayingAlong 75

As Iremember,one of the best-known short poems by Blake is actuallycrossed out in the note- book which is the onlysource of it.This has no bearingonany ‘conflict’ theory;itisonlypart of the difficulty as to knowingwhether apoem is anoumenonoraphenomenon. Critics have long been allowed to saythat apoem maybesomethinginspired which meant morethan the poet knew.(xiv)

The “difficulty” here is thatthe poem is both anoumenon and aphenomenon, or neither onlyone or the other.Itisnot irrelevant to an interpretation of the poem that Blake crossed it out; it is just that the poem is alsoathing in the world, larger and more lasting than Blake’sjudgment of its merits. Others have come along and judgeditquite good, and for them, too, the poem is both and phenomen- on, afact thatmakes their “judgment” in Smith’ssense just as relevant and just as revisable as Blake’s. Practical criticism takes place in the space in which judgments are deferred: “the point Iamtrying to make is that this final ‘judgment’ is athing which must be indefinitelypostponed” (xv). After the example from Blake, Empson bringsupanexhibition of Constable then showing in which a ‘study’ thatConstable clearlyconsidered inferior to his finished canvas is in fact the more prized work at that moment. “WouldMr. James Smith saythat the ‘study’,which is now more ad- mired than the finished work, was anoumenon or aphenomenon?Ido not see anyway out of the dilemma which would leave the profound he wasexpress- ing much importance for apractical decision” (xv). Profound truths without much importance for the practicalitiesofinterpretation: it is from this perspective that it seems not just desirable, but necessary,toleave aquestion unbroached and unan- swered, “indefinitely.” Iconclude with another snippet from Empson, this one from SomeVersions of Pastoral,first publishedin1935. Adam Phillips had seen Winnicott’sapproach to an- alytic interpretation as answering the “need of the self to be both intelligible and hid- den” (Phillips 1988, 14). And when he came to describe how that stance toward the self showed up in Winnicott’sstyle, he reached for the “pastoral”: “the genre of sim- plicity in which Winnicott writes, awry version of pastoral, is in fact akind of elu- siveness. But the shrewdingenuousness of his writing […]isconsistent with one of his therapeutic aims: to protect the privacyofthe self in the making of personal sense and, by the sametoken, personal non-sense” (14). Interpretation here is the vehicle of an , one seeking understanding but respectingfirm limits to it. But what does this have to do with “pastoral”?Empson suggests an answer:

The feelingthat life is essentiallyinadequatetothe human spirit,and yetthat agood life must avoid sayingso, is naturallyathome with most versions of pastoral; in pastoral youtakealim- itedlife and pretend it is the full and normal one, and asuggestion that one must do this with all life, because the normal is itself limited, is easilyput into the trick though not necessary to its power.Converselyany expression of the idea that all life is limited mayberegarded as onlya trick of pastoral, perhapschieflyintended to hold all our attention and sympathyfor some lim- itedlife, though again this is not necessary to it either on grounds of truth or beauty;infact the suggestion of pastoral maybeonlyaprotection for the idea which must at last be taken alone. The business of interpretation is obviously very complicated. Literary uses of the problem of 76 Jonathan Elmer

free-will and necessity,for example,may be noticed to give curiously bad arguments and I should think gettheir strengthfromkeeping youindoubt between the two methods. Thus Hardy is fond of showingusanunusuallystupid person subjected to very unusuallybad luck, and then amoral is drawn, not merely by inferencebut by solemn assertion, that we areall in the same boat as this person whose story is strikingpreciselybecause it is unusual. The effect maybevery grand, but to makeanotherwise logical reader accept the process must depend on givinghim obscurereasons for wishingitso. It is clear at anyrate that this grand notion of the inadequacyoflife, so various in its means of expression, needs to be count- ed as apossible territory of the pastoral. (Empson 1974,114– 115)

Reading this extraordinary passage, one cannot help agreeing that “the business of interpretation is obviouslyvery complicated.” There are,Ithink, two intersecting problems or levels: the question of “the inadequacy of life” and the question of how pastoral works.Taking the example of Hardyisperhaps the easiest wayin: Har- dy’sgrim texts are pastoral, thinks Empson, because the story of “an unusually stu- pid person subjected to very unusually bad luck” is somehow made to suggest that “we are all in the sameboat as this person whose story is striking preciselybecause it is unusual.” We can see how it works – Empson likes to call it the “trick” of pastoral – but we cannot reallysay why it works:theremust be “obscure reasons” in the reader “for wishing it so.” And Empson’shunch is that thosereasons are obscure, are made to remain obscure, because they touch on the “feelingthat life is inadequate to the human spirit,” that our own puny, mortal life is hopelessly “limited” with respect to all that our spirit mayencompass. We are all living a “limited life” pretending to be “the full and normalone.” Pastoral, it turns out,isatried-and-true method for simul- taneously expressingand hiding aself thatisboth limited and unlimited. Life is “es- sentiallyinadequate to the human spirit” but “agood life must avoid saying so” [em- phasis mine]. It is this circumspection, this essential reserve, thatpastoral addresses by offering “reasons” that remain “obscure.” Interpretation here proceeds through a syncopation of expression and opacity.The individual both knows and does not say that life is inadequate to his spirit.The pastoral writer both knows, and does not say, that his audience has “obscure reasons for wishing it so.” The literary critic both un- derstandsand remains puzzled by the “trick” of pastoral. All this succeeds onlyif certain questions are not forced. Agood life must avoid saying certain things. The business of interpretation is obviouslyvery complicated.

Bibliography

Cavell,Stanley. The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, ,and Tragedy. New York: Oxford University Press,1979. Chaouli, Michel. “Criticism and Style.” New LiteraryHistory 44 (2013): 323–344. Empson, William. Seven Types of Ambiguity. New York: New Directors, 1947 [1930]. Empson, William. Some Versions of Pastoral. New York: New Directions, 1974[1935]. Flaubert, Gustave. The Letters of Gustave Flaubert, 1830‒1857. Ed.and trans. Francis Steegmuller. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,1979. On Not Forcing the Question: Criticism and PlayingAlong 77

Freud, Sigmund. Beyond the Pleasure Principle. Trans. James Strachey.New York: Norton, 1961 [1920]. Groensteen, Thierry. Comics and Narration. Trans. Ann Miller.Jackson: University Press of Mississippi, 2013 [2011]. Johnson, Barbara. Persons and Things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,2008. Klein, Melanie. The Psycho-Analysis of Children. Trans. AlixStrachey.London: HogarthPress,1949 [1932]. Klein, Melanie. Narrative of aChild Analysis: The Conduct of the Psycho-Analysis of Children as seen in the TreatmentofaTen-year-old Boy. New York: The FreePress, 1961. Phillips,Adam. Winnicott. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversityPress, 1988. Sontag, Susan. AgainstInterpretation. New York: Anchor Books, 1990 [1966]. Winnicott,D.W. Playing and Reality. London: Routledge, 1991 [1971].

Anne Eusterschulte La ChambrePoétique

No, Iwon’tleave the world – I’ll enter a lunatic asylum and see if the profundity of insanity reveals to me the riddles of life. (Kierkegaard: Journal 1836–1837)

Shadow Plays

What is a chambrepoétique? First,anallusion to Roland Barthes’ La chambre claire. Notes sur la photographie and its reference to the cameralucida. Let’sfollow this trace. A cameralucida is an auxiliary instrument for drawing. Usingaprism that is at- tachedtoadrawingboard with atripod, the artist can sight the object through an eyehole and alsosee aprismatic projection of the same object directlyonthe paper.But it is not apurelytechnical achievement that makesthis divided view pos- sible. The cameralucida is, in afigurative sense, amediation between an external object of perception, the projected appearance on the paper,the mental imagination, and the somatic recording process. In the gaze,the external object translates itself into apictorial reflection on the object whose appearance the artist’shand captures as an outline. We remember the myth of the origin of painting:skiagraphy. Plinyreports that the daughter of the sculptor Butades, to capturethe imageofher beloved, framed his shadowinlines on awall by the light of alamp (Plinius Hist.Nat.XXXV151). The shadow is atestimonyofaperson, paradoxically, both present and absent,a genuine expression of ephemerality.The draftswoman looks at afaint echo, the shadow,and translatesittoanother level of presence, the silhouettedrawn on the wall. Within the contours, the picture is empty,merelyadark surface like asheet of paper not yetwritten on. ForBarthes, the photographic projection of light guarantees areference that is somehow present in the picture, yetwithout by anymeans losing its intangible na- ture. The object is there – without it therewould be no projection – but it is equally absent.Each picture offers amomentary record that extracts something from the flow of time and captures it photo-graphically, i.e., as alight drawing.Photography bringssomething to light: it is an art of light and shadow,itcreates apictorial sphere of appearances.But what of ahuman being can be experienced through apicture? In his phenomenological observations on photography, Barthes starts from an experi- ence of loss. It is asadness (chagrin)that is evoked by the image, likeafleeting shad-

OpenAccess. ©2021 Anne Eusterschulte, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-008 80 Anne Eusterschulte

ow from another world. The external picture can thus almost evoke adesire, adeep love, or cause pain.Ittears open awound in the self-reflection of the viewer.¹ The relationship between interior and exterior views, their translation into apro- jective,poetic room of reflection, and the material representations shall guide us in the following to room situations. In the figurative as well as in the literal sense: to poetic chambers as places of ashadow theaterand thus to aspecific form of poetic imagery,self-reflection, and criticism. But can images – those in language, painterly, photographic or performative – communicatesomething of the inner life of asingular person?

Poetic Shadow Casting

It is Søren Kierkegaardwho, using shadow silhouettes(Skyggerids), considers the possibilityofdepictingthe interior.There are movements of the soul thattake place on the surface: they are written on the face, as we say. Forinstance,moods such as joy or immediate sadness might be read off the facial features and included in apicture.² Kierkegaard, however,isconcerned with invisible, existential forces hiddendeeplyinthe abyss of the soul, something which he calls ‘reflective sorrow’ (reflekterede Sorg).³ The Iisaware of this inner sorrow but is unable to completely understand it and therefore constantlystruggles with itself. These inner struggles do not manifest themselvestothe outside world and remain under cover. The ‘reflective sorrow’ is constantlyinmotion and does not understand the rea- son for its sadness, and thus wanders around searching. It refuses adirect depicta- bility.⁴ Thisirreducible obscurity is one dimension of poetic critique. It is directed against physiognomic character studies that claim to analyze the interior of the soul. Barthes has emphasized that the evidence of the photographic image, as far as human beingsare concerned, is always accompanied by agenuine enigmaticalness, an ambiguous présence-absence (Maurice Blanchot). Forevenifthe photographic imagecertifies the existenceofaperson, a “croyance fondamentale” (Barthes 1980,44, 165), some inaccessibilityremains nevertheless. And this is wherethe shad- ows come into play. What emergesinthe representation is amode of expression

 “Iwanted to exploreitnot as aquestion (a theme) but as awound: Isee, Ifeel, henceInotice, I observe, and Ithink.” (Barthes 2006,8,30)  Kierkegaardknew the Physiognomic Fragments of Lavater,who illustrated his studies with silhou- ettes(see Liessmann2017, 133).  The Danish term sorg has awide rangeofmeanings,includingsorrow,grief, worryingabout,caring for (omsorg), and thus lovingattention. We can interpret sorg here as an existential restlessness in relation to another person or challengingcircumstances of life.  “The exterior pallor [ydreBleghed]is, as it were,the interior’sgood-bye, and thoughtand imagi- nation [Tanken og Phantasien]hurry after the fugitive,which hides in the secret recesses.” (Kierke- gaard 1988, 169; Kierkegaard 1920,170) La Chambre Poétique 81

(“air”), or,toput it more accurately, aunique aura⁵: “The air (air)isnot aschematic, intellectual datum, the wayasilhouette is. Nor is the air asimple analogy (analogie) […]. No, the air is that exorbitant thing (cette chose exorbitante),which induces from bodytosoul – animula,little individual soul […]. Thus the air is the luminous shad- ow (L’air est ainsi l’ombre lumineuse) which accompanies the body; and if the photo- graph fails to show this air,then the bodymoves without ashadow,” i.e., if the pho- tograph is not able to “supplythe transparent soul its bright shadow (donner àl’âme transparenteson ombre claire),the subjectdies forever” (Barthes 2006,45, 109–110; Barthes 1980,45, 167–170). Kierkegaard’sreflective sorrow is aconstant back and forth, like the restless up and down in the smallest of spaces.Itisnot written on the face but onlyhints at it- self. It givesawink (Vink)orlaysatrace (Spor). Because of its restlessness it is acon- stant becoming (bestandig iVorden). There is no fixed state thatcould be labeled with awordand so the reflective sorrow is left to poetic or psychological treatment (“po- etiske eller psychologiske Behandling” [Kierkegaard 1920,173]). We will follow Kierkegaard’spoetic path, which maystand for the reflection on a blind spot of the self, confronting itself with shadows cast by itself. The dynamics of reflective sorrow make an artistic representation impossible. Nevertheless, it is poetic images that by means of spatialization and temporalization layatrace.

Like asquirrel in its cage,itturns around in itself, yetnot as uniformlyasdoes that animal, but with acontinual alternation in the combination of the interior elementsofsorrow (iCombina- tionen af SorgensindreMomenter). […]Just as the patient in his pain tossesfromone side to the other,soreflective sorrow is tossed about in order to find its object and its expression (Ud- tryk). (Kierkegaard1988, 170; Kierkegaard1920, 170)

It seems as if this ineffable sadness has closed up within itself and retreated against the outside world into an enclosure, the existenceofwhich onlyacareful observer would even suspect.Kierkegaard creates poetic images that involvethe reflection of the reader,who is quite familiar with such scenarios of the troubled self. The re- flective sorrow almost rushes inwards,withdraws into the invisible.

By withdrawinginwardinthis way, it finallyfinds an inclosure(Indelukke), an innermost re- treat,where it thinks it can remain, and now it begins its uniform movement.Like the pendulum in aclock, it swingsback and forth and cannot find rest.Itcontinuallybegins from the begin- ningand deliberatesanew,interrogates the witnesses,checks and examines the various state- ments,somethingithas alreadydone hundreds of times, but it never finished. In the course of time, the uniformity has somethinganesthetizing about it.Just as […]the monotonous sound of aman pacingback and forth with measured steps on the floor above[…]and deep within, in its little nook, grief (Sorg)lives likeawell-guarded prisoner in an underground prison

 In French, air (wind, breath) refers also to alook, afacial expression of grace or charisma, and thus to somethingimmaterial, somethingadded, an aura,sotospeak (ancient Greek: αὔρα,inthe sense of abreath of air), the je ne sais quoi in relationtoanunmistakable person. 82 Anne Eusterschulte

[…], walkingtoand fro in his cubbyhole (Aflukke), never weary of travelingthe long or short road of sorrow.(Kierkegaard1988, 170 – 171; Kierkegaard 1920,171)

This maysound like totalseclusion, but this wandering in reflections (vandre frem og tilbage iReflexionen)ispoeticallyexpressed in pictures (Billeder). Kierkegaardcalls them shadow cuts (Skyggerids). On the one hand, these silhouettes are something that comes from the dark side of life; they are, as it were, shadows that lie on the soul, whose dark reasons cannot be expressed in language, like atrauma that appears in shadows in reflection (Kier- kegaard 1920,172–173). On the other hand, these poetic shadow cuts are like outline drawings takenfrom the depths of the soul, in analogytomaterial silhouettes,like a scissor cut from black paper.But to bear witness to the subtle interior picture (det fine indere Billede)ofthe soul, the silhouettemust first be brought to light.Itmust become visible in the medium of aprojection. Here, the poetic mediation in spatial scenarios of inner movement becomes relevant (Kierkegaard1920, 174).

If Ipick up asilhouette, Ihavenoimpression of it,cannot arrive at an actual conception of it; onlywhenIhold it up towardthe wall and do not look at it directlybut at what appears on the wall, onlythen do Isee it.Soitisalso with the pictureIwant to show here,aninterior picture that does not become perceptible until Isee throughthe exterior.(Kierkegaard1988, 173)

The soul’sconstant turmoil is transferred into the spatial movement of silhouettes that can be imagined cinematographically, like ashadow theater.Wemoveinto aper- formance. The light of reflection, i.e., the interaction between the poet or the poetic languageand the reader stages the shadows and lets them act as if they werealive. The wayoflooking and the mediationthrough light are decisive for the silhou- ettes in poetic words. Onlywhen they are set in motion and held against the light so as to create aprojection on the wall does something become perceptible or at least foreshadowed. This, however,onlysucceedsfor thosewho have sympathyfor the sorrow in its secrecy (Sympathien nemlig med Sorgens Hemmelighed), because it in- deed lurks about the world in secret (Kierkegaard 1920,174). It is dialecticalcorrelations of pictorial expression, external perceptions, and no- tions of the interior that Kierkegaardaddresses,and here the manner of poetic rep- resentation and the interpretation of the reader playaconstitutive role.

One walks down the street; one house looks likethe other.Onlythe experienced observer sus- pects (prøvede Iagttager ahner)that in this particular house things are quiteotherwise at the midnight hour;then an unhappy person paces about,one whofound no rest; he goes up the stairs,and his footsteps echo in the stillness of the night.People pass one another in the street; one person looks just like the next,and the next one is likealmost everyone else. Onlythe ex- perienced observer suspects that deep within that one’shead residesalodger[Indsidder]who has nothingtodowith the world but livesout his solitary life in quiet home-industry work. (Kier- kegaard1988, 174; Kierkegaard 1920,175) La Chambre Poétique 83

The uniformity of the streets, buildings,people – as it were, atypeface of external life and its standardization in an eraofurbanization, industrialization – the monotonyof life’srhythms, the anonymity of the individual in the masses, the indifference to- wards one another,and the apparent silence of anight that seems to absorb every- thing individual, all this is onlyfacade (lat. facies), i.e., the outwardlyturned face of inner life. Forthe sympathizers of secrecy,onlysuch messages of the hidden(e)mo- tion deep down become perceptible. If we look at the world with the gaze of poetic sensibility, then what echoes outwardly, i.e., poetic picture-writing,isable to convey tuneful written or pictorial signals from adistance, like a ‘tele-graphic message’ (“tel- egraphisk Esterretning” [Kierkegaard1920, 175]).

Poetry as telegraphy.These material telegraphies are always also ways of critically reflectingonthat which sorrow has forced into its lonelycell. Kierkegaard’schamber plays of the soul are not simplystagings of inwardness as aretreat from the world in locked rooms.Although Theodor W. Adorno criticizes Kierkegaard’sinteriors as expressions of an objectless inwardness,healso points out anegative aesthetic in Kierkegaard’spoetic language(Adorno 1979,57). As we will see, the chamber scenes are not simplyarefuge in the face of aworld of social alienation and massification, or an exclusion of real-world events under the illusion that one can withdraw into oneself unaffected by exterior influences. Indeed, the world is always inscribed in the intérieur. We encounter here neither places of longing for intimacy,nor retreats of abour- geoisie into the shells of privacy(Benjamin), nor enclaves of an inspired artistic ex- istence. However,Kierkegaard plays with all these implications. But broken projec- tive spaces are the result, stagings of tough processes of reflection, overshadowed by fleeting time and the dark voids of the soul. He goes to court with the illusionary stages of the privatesphere. Indirectly, the poetic reflections on the discordofthe self are indicators of the conditions of the outside world as experienced. Thepoetic-philosophical treatment of all the inner stagingtakes up aliterarytopos (Becker 1990;Lange2007; Schür- mann 2015;Stiegler 2010) to poeticallyreformulate and criticize it,not least with aview to romantic approaches. By means of these translations,Kierkegaard performs poetic criticism in the sense of Schlegel, because “poetry can onlybecriticized through poetry.Anart judgment which is not itself awork of art,either in the mate- rial, as arepresentation of the necessary impression in its becoming, or through a beautifulform,and aliberal tone in the spirit of the old Roman satire, has no civil right at all in the realm of art” (Schlegel 1967[1797], 162[fr.117]).⁶ Let us try to see how the poetic chambers create, as it were, light-writings of both areferencetothe self and the world, and recall Kierkegaard’s fine indere Billede, which casts vivid shadowsonlyinpoetic representation – not in fixed silhouettes,

 Throughout the text, all translationsofSchlegel’stexts aremyown. 84 Anne Eusterschulte

but by making an appearance in its movement and giving us aglimpse of the inner life of the soul. What is needed is alight thatbringsthe shadow to life by throwing them against the wall. This happens in the medium of poetry.

Emigration of imagination, so that the legs can never come along⁷

Kierkegaard subjects Schlegel’sconcept of aromantic universal poetry and the aes- thetic wayoflife to rigid criticism. He shares the romantic impetusagainst the nar- row-mindedness and conventions of aphilistine bourgeoisie.⁸ But he confronts with existential questions the romantic liberation of the poetic spirit and the idealization of an independent practice of freedom. appears to him as an escape from the world, an “emigrationfrom reality,”⁹ and as the illusion of poetic art as- cendingtoarealm of fantastic infinity,thereby losing sight of the ground of reality under the feetoffinite life. Kierkegaard counters such forgetfulness of the self and the world, includinga lack of historical awareness, with an ethical paradox. The individual is confronted with existential challenges, struggling with contradictions and the intricacies of free- dom, which always bear the risk of failure. This does not mean that the aesthetic ap- proach is obsolete, but it should not simplybeaflight of fancy.Ithas to be trans- posed into the realm of ethics,i.e., poetical languagehas to be reconnected with ‘real life’ in order to fight the constant battle between finitude and infinite possibil- ities, temporality and eternity.Attempts to suspend these existential tensions by making reference to idealized worlds or the support of philosophical systems¹⁰ ap- pear as deceptions,which do not hold true from the perspective of the “doghouse.”¹¹ The leap of faith promises the onlymoment of hope for the desperate.For Kier- kegaard, we cannot survive the paradoxofour fragile, worldlyexistencewithout be- lieving in an event of grace, thatis, an apriori of God and of reconciliation.

 Kierkegaard1905,177.  Kierkegaardhas no primary socio-critical concern. But the invectivesagainst the conventionsof the bourgeoisie, the strategies of escape through business and routines, and finallythe doctrinaire paralysis of – all this forms the background of his thematization of the individualthat exists in the tension between the finiteand the infinite, beingconfronted with decisions that cannot be met with literary escapades. Implicitly, this is always acritique of socio-historical .  See Schreiber 2014,402.  This is also directed against Hegel’sidea of a “self-reconciliation of the spirit” (Glöckner 1998, 143 – 144).  “Athinkererects ahugebuilding, asystem, asystemembracing the whole of existence, world history,etc. and if his personal life is considered, to our amazement the appallingand ludicrousdis- covery is made that he himself does not personallyliveinthishuge, domed palacebut in ashed alongside it,orinadoghouse, or at best in the janitor’squarters.” (Kierkegaard2013,43–44) La Chambre Poétique 85

Let us consider the leap, beyond theological reassurance: Freedom requires de- cision-making and has to constantlydeal with strongaffections, impulses of the will, and agonizing existential doubts. It dwells with all the hesitation and indecision, fur- nishesitself with the fear of taking guiltupon itself. Can such adareoflife hope for a changeability of the world?Whatcan takethe place of reconciliation under the aus- pices of loss or doubtoftranscendental shelter in the 20th century? Here, what needs to be introduced is Kierkegaard’s poetic telegraphy,which aims to return to life such indissoluble questions, placing them as actors in apoetic echo chamber.

Hiking on the Wallpaper – actiones in distans

In Kierkegaard’sdiaries, we are taught that the poetic imagination can try to escape from the soul’swearyinghome. But the effort to leave the gloomystate behind can lead to aloss of self-relationship. The self is not at home with itself; it is almost on the run.

Between my melancholyand my intimate ‘Thou’ therelay awhole world of fantasy.The world it is that Ihavepartlyexhausted in my pseudonyms. Just likeaperson whohasn’tahappy home spends as much time away fromitaspossible and would prefer to be rid of it,somymelancholy has kept me away from my own self while I, makingdiscoveries and poetical experiences, trav- eled through aworld of fantasy.[…][T]hat is how Ibehavedinmelancholytowards possibility. (Kierkegaard 1938, JP,No. 641)

But when poetic imagination temptsustofree the self from grueling emotions and to embark on fantasticjourneys,this can cause afeeling of terrible worldlessness. Yet, while speakinginmanytongues, this very self simultaneouslydiscovers and experiencesitself poetically. Thispointsustoanother dimension of poetry.Itisthe indirect poetic telegraphs, i.e., the speakinginpseudonyms or divided roles and epi- sodes – elements of Romantic poetry – that become the medium of apoetic critique in voiced shadows. The poetic polyphonyevokes pictorial scenarios which, like ashadow theater, give an inkling of the fine inner imageofthe soul and the unspeakable sorrow. Like an aesthetic game of hide-and-seek,itbringsthe reader out of his shell, con- frontinghim with modes of self-deception. Poetry stages self-questioning that does not provide an agenda, but engages asympathetic reader who knows about the shal- lows of the soul. The ethical challengeofexistenceappears on apoetic stageorina rehearsal room of decision (see Feger2007, 543). Prototypically, this is playedout in Repetition,and, here too, the crystallization of poetic criticism is reflected in aroom scene. 86 Anne Eusterschulte

Fig. 1: Etienne de Jouy: L’HermitedelaChaussée-d’Antin, ou Observations surles mœursetles usagesparisiens au commencement du XIXesiècle. Paris 1814. The book’sfrontispiece shows the scholar in alibrary, his hand holding the pen on the sidetable rather casually set up for writing, seated reclined in the armchair,completely concentrated on in- tently gazing through alorgnette, which hereprojects the light of the imagination likealens onto acurtain that coversthe windowofthe darkroom. The inner eventofthe imagination is shown in acircle of light, which makes abusy street scenevisible. Just as if one could look out through the window, the interior extends perspectively into the imagined exterior space. It is like acinema situation. Yet, thisisnot amatter of afantasy world but of contemplating reality as it is experi- enced: “My chamber is like a cameraobscura,inwhich the external objects canretracetheir traces” (Ma cellule est comme une chambreobscureoùviennentseretracerles objetsextérieurs). Aparadoxdraws attention to the wayinwhich inner imagination and perception staged externally arehere intertwined: The light of the imagination, which is laid on the curtainlike acircular open- ing, is projectedback into the scholar’sroom, whereitcreates shadows. Walter Benjamin refers to thistitle engraving in his Arcades Project [Passagen-Werk](see Haug 2017,42‒43).

Let us imagine atraveler returning to acity and staying exactlyinthe same boarding house and the same room, just as he did on aprevious trip. An attempt to repeat a happilyrememberedexperience. Let us sayitisBerlin on the DayofPrayerand Re- pentance and the whole city seems to lie under athick layerofdust,seeming to bear La Chambre Poétique 87

witness to ashes to ashes, dust to dust,being thus overshadowed by agrey veil of transience. And now to the room:

When afellow has settled himself cosily and comfortably in his quarters,whenhehas afixed point (fast Punkt)likethis fromwhich he can rush out,asafe hidingplacetowhich he can re- treat and devour his booty in solitude (for iEensomhed at fortrære sit Bytte) – somethingIes- peciallyappreciate, since,likecertain beasts of prey,Icannot eat when anyone is looking on – then he familiarizeshimself with whatever notable sights theremay be in the city.(Kierke- gaard 1983, 153)

Acarnivore cave of poetic reflection. Astarting point to capturebootyinthe world, to hide and disembowel it.The room maynow be the point of departure for taking walks through the city or at least for hearing about it,orafixed point for embarking on imaginary journeys and for onlyimaginingpossibleexperiences.Either way, the self runs away from itself. In anycase, these are scenarios in which the explored possibilities turnout to be aphantasm. They do not become active decisions but remain mere eventualities. The booty willalwaysbecaptured from reality,depending on the interest or attention with which someone wanders through the streets,hurries, promenades,orstrides purposefully. It is the poetic imagination thatbringsthe bootytolife. Let us imagine the poetic room like atheater stageofthe imaginingself, ashadow theater. It is like in areal theater performancewhereespeciallyayoung person will be enraptured by the magic of the “artificial actuality in order like adouble to see and hear himself and to split himself up into every possible variation of himself, and nevertheless in such away that every variation is still himself” (Kierkegaard 1983, 154). Adissociation and multiplication of the self: While the bodyrests, the imagination experiencesamultitudeoffacets of the self, which are not onlyvisible but become audible as voiced shadows and sounds (lydende Skygge). These maynow be mere fantasies, as they come over ayoungperson who, on the threshold of awak- ening,isdreamingabout his personality.Kierkegaard designs ashadow theater in which the egomeets poetic refractions of itself.

In such aself-vision of the imagination, the individual is not an actual shape but ashadow,or, morecorrectly, the actual shape is invisiblypresent and thereforeisnot satisfied to cast one shadow,but the individual has avariety of shadows (men Individet har en Mangfoldighed af Sky- gger), all of which resemble him and which momentarily have equal status as beinghimself. (Kierkegaard 1983, 154)

Kierkegaard uses romantic motifs – we maythink of the doppelgangerinE.T.A. Hoff- mann or the shadow of Peter Schlemihl, of night scenes and dream visions. But he focuses on apre-reflexive,dreamlikeconsciousness of the self, which stages its pos- sibilities. The consciousness is not yetawake, it wanders between its possibilities. But these possibilities must be givenshape and voice so that the dreamingIcan be- come aware of them. “Each of its possibilities is an audible shadow (Enhver dets Mu- lighed er derfor en lydende Skygge)” (Kierkegaard 1983, 155). The dreamingsoul is still 88 Anne Eusterschulte

hovering over the abyss, not wanting to disentangle the crush of inner voices of fear, lament,anxiety,exuberance, not wanting to decide. And before one knows it,the individual has woken up from this dream state again and the voices of the night fall silent (Nattestemmerne forstumme). If the voices do not fade, then thereisanother strategy,toflee from the challenge of freedom and to dance in sheer possibilities. “The stageisthat kind of setting,and thereforeitisparticularlysuitable for the Schattenspiel [shadow play] of the hidden individual (En saadan Omgivelse er den sceniske,som derfornetop egner sig for det krypteIndivids Schattenspiel)” (Kierkegaard 1983, 156). Now shadows move onto the stage, acting in different roles,inwhose voices the individual rediscovers its own voice, as in amirror image(“spellbinding”)orecho chamber,and perhaps the individual puts itself in the role of arobber captain and goes through wild adventures (156). We are still in the chamber,but the imagination is drawing wider circles,has expanded into atheater space. It is apoetic meansof demonstratingthe existential questioning of the self and bringingitback into the world from the sleep of reason, which sometimes givesbirth to monsters. What is audiblyand visiblystaged in dreamlikeimaginations of the youthful, childlikeconsciousness is the foil of areflection into which the matureconscious- ness can dive,though not in weightless reverie, but when the soul at amatureage gathers itself in earnest,i.e., concentrates (157). Apoetic undergoing of ethical chal- lenges. To experience this, the reflective soul must look at thingsasifitwerea child.¹² Therefore, the “more mature individuality who satiates himself on the strong food of actuality (Virkelighedens stærke Føde)” (158) does not turn to highart, such as painting,inparticular, but to everydayart,the picture sheet,proceeding like achild who, in cutting out something concrete, revitalizes with this piece of paper ageneral existential question with adizzying intensity.Again, it is about im- ages thatset the imagination free, silhouettes or cut-out pictures that come to life instantly and reflect something general in very concrete detail – and in this concrete- ness reach adepth of questioning thatrejects all conventions, something which only the unbiased, and at the same time deeplyserious, gaze can do.

In the days of childhood, we had such enormouscategories that they now almost makeusdizzy, we clipped out of apieceofpaperaman and awoman whowereman and woman in general in amorerigorous sense than Adam and Evewere. (Kierkegaard1983, 158)

 Kierkegaardherealso alludes to aromantic motif of childhood, i.e. asometimes mythologically idealized interpretation of childhood as apre-rational and supra-rational stage that is characterized by the soul’sinclination to dream and miraculous or almost prophetic insights into the future (for instanceinWackenroder or ). But Kierkegaarddoes not romanticize aretrojected childlikefe- licity in terms of amythological golden age. Rather,hefocuses on the pre-conscious abilities of the child’splayful soul, which resurfacesinthe psyche of the adult, i.e. aforebodingmemory of past sufferingoranintuition or sentimentofpain and loss that foreshadowafuture. La Chambre Poétique 89

The cut-out picture’sreduction of objectstoavery simple, popular form (as in the picture sheets of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries) raises fundamental ques- tions arising from the outlinesofthese pictures that call up memories or collective and carry them into the present.Itisthe gaze of the child that,beyond conventions, uncovers this deepquestioning.¹³ Perhaps the words from Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata now become more lucid.

My sorrow is my baronial castle, which lies likeaneagle’snest high up on the mountain peak amongthe clouds.Noone can takeitbystorm. From it Iswoopdown intoactuality and snatch my prey,but Idonot staydown there.Ibringmybooty home, and this booty is apictureIweave into the tapestries at my castle. Then Iliveasone alreadydead. EverythingIhave experienced I immerse in abaptism of oblivion unto an eternity of recollection.Everythingtemporal and for- tuitous is forgotten and blotted out.Then Isit like an old gray-haired man, pensive,and explain the pictures in asoft voice, almost whispering, and beside me sits achild, listening,although he remembers everythingbeforeItell it.(Kierkegaard1988, 42)

This can be read as apoetic procedurethattransposes experiences of reality into im- ages that cover the space of consciousness like wallpaper,asheet of pictures that clad the walls. Whereas early(oriental) wallpapers were woven carpets, and then hand-painted or printed paper coveringsofthe walls, industrialization (around 1830) introduced aprocess of printing wallpapers with serial patterns on paper webs.But despite industrial production, connectingpoints and acertain unevenness in the print always remain visible. The wallpaper is, as it were, amontage. It covers the chamber with paper webs on which ornamental segmentsjoin togethertoform recurringpatterns of pictorial writing.These are oftenstylizations of the floral world, such as abstractions of tendrils and plants. But it is preciselythis translation into re- petitive patterns that opens up aspecific variability of forms for the imagination, that comes alive for the poetic spirit.The eyemay follow the seams, can look for breaks and fractures; it knows each particularirregularity and,like achild, bringsthe pat- terns to life, sets them in motion, and thereby allows them to grow.

In Berliner Kindheit,Walter Benjamin describes how the bed rest prescribed by the doctor leads the fevered child to movefrom the bed to the interior: “Just as aman in afrenzy sometimes calculates and thinks, just to see: he can still do it,Icounted the circles of sunlight that swayedonthe ceilingofmyroom, and Iarranged the loz- enges of the wallpaper into ever new bundles.” (Benjamin 1972,GSIV, 272)

 With reference to the childlikepower of imagination in dealingwith sheets of pictures, i.e., pop- ular single-sheet prints whose pictorial motifs have been collected, cut out and pasted in, Walter Ben- jamin highlights the wayinwhich traces of acultural-historical manifest themselvesin simple outlines and break into the present.See Benjamin1972, GS IV,280 –282(“Das Pult”)and 115 (“Unordentliches Kind”). In “Ichpackemeine Bibliothekaus” (GSIV, 389–390), he emphasizes that the childlikenatureofcollecting is constitutive for the aged collector,too. Children areable to achievearenewal of the given: they paint objects,cut them out,take them off, develop ascale of revivifications. 90 Anne Eusterschulte

ForKierkegaard, it is about questions of memoryand renewal, about breaking out of the regimes of visibility and breakingupexperience, which is translated into poetic imaginations.The child and the old man can do this,but all of this is not an internalization that is alien to the world. On the contrary,itstarts with the experience of the world, extracts something from the empirical, i.e., focuses on de- tails, reformulates these extracts into literaryimagery,and the images learn to walk and pose questions for reflection. And does this not require adistancedperspective or literaryprocedures that Kierkegaard calls actionesindistans?¹⁴ In these literary forms abstracted (subtracted) from the realm of life, the reader is confronted with challenges that life abandons. The poetic shadow playputs these questions at areflective distance. In “Das Fieber,” Walter Benjamin tells of the childlike tendency to see everything as if it werecomingtowards him from far away (Benjamin 1972, GS IV,269). Silhou- ettes are projected onto the wall. They onlyappear lively from adistance. They come towards the self or,like areflection or vocal echo, come back to it.Anactio in distans that opens aspace for reflection. Thus, it is the child who, in the evening,bythe light of alamp,with the playofits fingers, projects shadow figures on the walls and brings stories to life.

Iused my tranquility and the proximity of the wall Ihad in my bed to welcome the light with shadowy images. Now all those gamesthat Ihad let my fingers playcame back on the wallpa- per. “Instead of beingafraidofthe shadows of the evening”,assaysmyplaybook, “funnychil- dren rather use it to have fun.” (Benjamin 1972,GSIV, 272)

The bodilygestures and finger plays createashadow theater,adistanced observa- tion of one’sown bodyand mental movements, which now run across the wallpaper as shadow figures and become the object of observation in the poetic room.¹⁵ What interests us here is not the childlike playthat projects figures onto the walls, but in afigurative sense, the literary processthatKierkegaard develops with the shadow plays. We are investigating procedures of a poetic actio in distans,which does not rep- resent empirical reality,but rather bringsittolife telegraphically,i.e., in projective narrativeforms, figures,and gestures, and allows them to act as shadows in apoetic space, so that the producer, as well as the readers, become spectators and interpret- ers of the poetic staging. Did not Schlegelemphasize this invigoratingpower of poetic criticism?

 Kierkegaard1988, 311. The actio in distans adapts as aliterary method ascientific theory of the remote effect of forces (e.g., magnetism,gravity), according to which bodies can triggeraneffect, change movement etc. without touching each other (see Tajafuerce 2000 and Blumenberg2007).  Benjamin refersto‘Spielbücher’ of the nineteenth century,hereLeske 1914. See Brüggemann 2007,49–67. La Chambre Poétique 91

Fig. 2: Illustriertes Spielbuch für Mädchen. Ed.Marie Leske(1914), 99 (detail).

Fig. 3: Illustriertes Spielbuch für Mädchen. Ed. Marie Leske(1914), 102 (detail).

On the wings of poeticreflection hoveringinthe middle

ForFriedrich Schlegel, poetic representationarticulatesnot onlyanaesthetic refer- ence to the worldand the self but also acritical reflection on the prerequisites of po- etic articulation. The role of the poet and his mode of representation, and,ultimately, the role of the sympathetic reader,are intertwinedinamaterial, artistic language: “every [art and science] that does not find its essence in the words of language has an invisiblespirit,and that is poetry” (Schlegel 1967[1800],304).¹⁶ The movement of the poetic spirit,accordingtothis programmatic claim, bears witness to an artistic individual, manifests itself as amirror of the world, or rather,of the ageand its respective spirit,and continuallyrelates itself to the surroundings.

 Concerninglanguageasthe prototype of all artistic media, see Chaouli 2004,138. 92 Anne Eusterschulte

Nevertheless,poetry “can hover most between the portrayedand the depicting,free of all real and ideal interest,onthe wingsofpoetic reflection in the middle, poten- tiating this reflection again and again and multiplying it as in an endless series of mirrors.” Here too, poetry is conceivedasanoptical projection of repetition and var- iation in multiplication. It is aprocess that takes place in an interplaynot only “from within, but also from without,” as acontinuous becoming(Schlegel1967[1798a], 182 [fr.116]). We mayrecall Kierkegaard’sfigure of the ceaseless movement of the wearyself. The romantic ideal of mediation of all disciplines and the concept of mediating art and life are reversed in aradicallyexistentialist turn of this hovering,which is hence subsequentlymodeled on the poetic room. It functions as aprojection space of iterative reflections and moving imagescenes,poeticallyinterweaving inner and outer worlds and thus simultaneouslyaddressing the status of poetry. But while Schlegel is concerned with “indulg[ing] oneself completelytothe impres- sion of apoem, letting the artistdowith us what he wants,” and, aboveall, with “be[ing] able to abstract from all the individual, to grasp the general in asuspended state,” with Kierkegaard it becomes atask not to relyonthis high “sense of the uni- verse” or “to be able to rise aboveour ownloveand to destroy what we worshipin our thoughts” (Schlegel 1967[1798b], 130 –131). Rather,this romantic soaring is to be poeticallycriticized and reflected in terms of the concrete dizziness of the self in in- dividual everydaylife. Kierkegaard takes up approaches of poetic criticism and turns them against what he considers to be aworld-forgottenunderstandingofpoetry.AccordingtoSchlegel, poetry as an art can onlybecritically assessed by poetry itself. Itsrealm is thus a cosmopolitan one, wherecitizenship is attained by sympoets and symphilosophers.¹⁷ Poeticcritique cruciallyinvolvesthe role of readingorreadership, i.e., the participa- tion of alivelyand resistant counterpart. It unfolds in adynamic of interaction and inventions that set in motion aprocess of becoming. As poetic poetics (Schlegel 1967 [1798a], 170[fr.28]), it is acritiquethat is presented in apoetic way. Why? Because “every excellent work, of whatever kind, knows more than it says,and wantsmore than it knows” (Schlegel 1967[1798b], 140), thus holding potentials that are unspo- ken and yeteffective as implicit knowledge.Inaddition, there are those that cannot be gathered by the poet himself and yetare drivenbyasubliminal will. This requires an engagement with poetic texts that give ample reason for assumptions, interpreta- tions, readings, and ways of understanding.But poetic criticism does not produce meaningsinorder to state,like “amere inscription, onlywhat the thing actually is, whereitstands and should stand in the world” (Schlegel 1967[1798b], 140). The poet and artist is at the same time apoetic and critical reader,i.e., ‘translator,’

 The synthetic writer creates acounteractive (entgegenwirkend)reader(see Schlegel 1967[1797], 161 [fr.112]). La Chambre Poétique 93

philosopher,rhetorician, and philologist.These readings and translations give new life to historicalformsofrepresentation and expressions. Kierkegaard takesupproceduresofromantic, poetic criticism, butitisthe individ- ualthatistobebrought into focus, withoutabandoning theexistingreality.Itisnec- essary to winoverthe readersassympathizers or symphilosophersand sympoets to lead them to the intimatestages of theselfbymeans of indirect aesthetictransmission. Theseare stagings in whichthe struggle with realityispoeticallyarticulated. The reader must have sympathyfor sorrow in its secrecy.Then ashadow theater stagingthe broken self within its worldlycircumstances is created. It theatricallyre- flects existenceinaworld that cannot be reconciled poetically. But in these refrac- tions – whether in terms of the illusory character of the promises of happiness,or of the stagings of tristesse, desire, or doubt,i.e., in negative aesthetics – alonging is expressed. It refuses anyconciliatory tone and thus points dialecticallytothe un- redeemed.¹⁸ Let us take up this poetology of self-mirroringand critical growth, as well as the demand for arevitalizing language. We enter areflective, poetological cabinetofmir- rors with awealth of material refractions and turn to interior scenes in various media of poetic imageformationtoexemplify how they become the site, or Schauplatz (Ben- jamin), of poetic criticism.

“Poemsare paintedwindow panes” (J.W.v.Goethe)

We are looking at two paintingsbyVilhelm Hammershøi (1864–1916), among alarge number of interior paintingsbythe Danish artist. They provide insights into his pri- vaterooms in Copenhagen. The chamber scenes are held in color nuances of grey and white, which vary in soft bluish, ochre, and greenish color values.Particular fur- nishingsorobjects are givenahaptic emphasis in the colors of their material (wood, glass,porcelain). The objects frequentlyappear entangled in an interplaybetween light and shadow as well as mirror reflections.The frugality of the indoor situations evokes the atmosphere of an extended period of temporalpersistenceaswell as of a peculiarabandonment.However,the paralysis disappears when the viewer contin- ues to contemplate the paintings. Asubtle playofmovementsbecomes evident, re- acting to the outside,inmomentary shots of the incoming light,which, despite the apparent standstill, points to the passingoftime. The interiors manifest themselves as very sparselyfurnished, almost empty,but not uninhabited. Often they are desert- ed likeHammershøi’slandscape and cityscape paintings, which are mostly without people.

 See Feger2007, 543. On the of the faintinglonging,see Adorno 1970,199. 94 Anne Eusterschulte

Fig. 4: Vilhelm Hammershøi, Interior. “The Four Rooms”,1914 (Oil on canvas,33 1/2 ×274/5 inch; 85 ×70.5cm), Ordrupgaard, Kopenhagen

Repeatedly, afemale figure can be seen in the interiors,for which the painter’s wife oftenacted as amodel, always in ablack floor-length dress,her hair tiedina knot,almost likeablack silhouette.Ifwewant to speak here of silence, then in the sense of taciturnity,which seems to exclude the hectic noise of the world. In the sparse rooms,traces of everydaylife appear with the greatest sobriety. The outside world appears as sunlight that causesareverberation of shadows, light projections,and reflections.Onmanypaintings, windows – some of which are shown open, others closed and subdivided – draw attention to the exterior of the interior.Light breaks in through the window crosses or the multiplyframed panes; panels of light and crosses of shadow thus fall into the room. But the win- dows do not afford the gaze aplain view or anyclear sight of the vastness of the sky,which is at best seen rather vaguely. If we are able to see what is happeningout- side the windows at all, this requires,for example, that we look at the window fronts of the opposite facades. Here, no (romantic) view into the open is granted. Rather, framed interior and exterior views intersect as apalimpsest of window crosses or framingsinthe gaze (fig.5). An inner courtyard view:The depiction of windows and framings always carries an allusion to painting or framed pictures,which exhibit themselves(Hemkendreis 2016). Beyond that,windows suggest athreshold or opening between inside and out- La Chambre Poétique 95

Fig. 5: Vilhelm Hammershøi, Courtyard.Strandgade 30,1899 (Oil on canvas, 65,7 ×47,03 cm), Toldeo MuseumofArt.Ohio side. The series of windows running across acorner here pointstosomething behind it,but the windows do not allow adeeper insight; they indicate shadedrooms or cor- ridors, absorbed in darkness, but there are also light projections thatfall into the in- terior. Some of the windowpanesremainopaque and reject the spectator’sview.Then again, they become mirror surfaces on which architectural elements and apiece of the skyare reflected. Aray of sunlight falls into this courtyard area and hits an open window wingonthe first floor.The interweaving of reflections, framings, and architectural elements constitutes atransition area between interior and exterior worlds,reflecting, in both the literal and figurativesense, how exterior and interior areas are seen blending into one another.The courtyard area enclosedbywindows becomes itself an interior space, the impression of asortof‘cagedworld,’ a Gehäuse- Welt (Simmel). Repetitions, series of framing structures,light projections,shadows, and reflec- tions come into view.This blending of framingsoropenings that do not lead into the open, of reflections and light effects that create projections in the interior through a 96 Anne Eusterschulte

window,and of the iteration of structures is impressively staged in Four Rooms (fig.4). We look into asuite of four rooms.They are obviouslyhigh-ceilingrooms, but they can onlybeseen in acut-off view.Adoor leaf stands out into the room, the outermost edge of the door touches the edge of the painting and divides the space of the picture.Light is reflected on the door and enters from the left through awindow,which is not visible but is hinted at by alight curtain. Behind the door,in its slipstream,asmall side table can be seen, on which stands an empty bowl with light reflections. Aboveitonthe wall, there is adark-framed mirror in which areflec- tion is visible, too, even though it is located in the shadow. It drawsthe eyeinto a perspectival depth of space – as if it werereflecting an opposite window,though it seems to mirror the door. Like asmall window in the wall, the mirror creates the impression that it leads outside. It strangelycorresponds with what can be seen through the large open door: asuiteofrooms.The incidence of light is always accentuated by shading and the prominenceofthe whitelacquered doors. One might also think of mirror cabinets in baroque castles, which work with such optical illusions. The successive rooms are separated from each other by door frames, thresholds, and differentlyangled doors. Thick wooden planks draw perspective lines to the last room, but always with slight misalignments, and lead to adark canapée and apaint- ing on the wall, which is again cut off. Time and again, it is cut framingsthat dominate this parkours of iteration and alteration. Alreadyinthe room in the foreground, this is pointed to by the opened door.Acut profile on the door leaf drawsattention to the back of the door,which, if closed, would fit into ahalf-height wooden paneling. And the dark-framedmirror also hangsonaframing board. The interlockingofborders and cut framingsdeter- mines the perception of the suite of rooms.Itbecomes acabinet of mirrors or anest- ing of rooms. Hammershøi owned some writingsbyKierkegaard.¹⁹ His paintings, likeKierke- gaard’sroom scenes of poetic criticism, involvethe viewer in multiple perspectives, operating with iterations, reflections,refractions of light,and situation variations. Let us recall Kierkegaard’s actionesindistans,i.e., apoetic, image-generatingpro- cess that lets us envision aspectrum of different situations which are being played through. The impression of the realistic representation is captivating, but the painter operates with compositional shifts and reflections.Objects are varied, figures are placed differently, thus modifying the viewer’sperspective of view.Poetic reflection and micrological investigations of reality enter into adialecticalrelationship. The room as aprivateretreatand expression of an attitude towards life is shown in dif- fering compartments and framings, i.e., from prismaticallyvaryingperspectives. Repetition, recurringsituations, and,again and again, edgingsand framings stand out.Time seems to have come to astandstill in these frames, even when the

 See Alsdorf 2016,269. La Chambre Poétique 97

suite of rooms is seriallyextended, allowing the gaze to wander into the depths of the room, or when the incidence of light refers to an external time determined by the changingposition of the sun, or when figures in unchangingposes testify to se- quences of formermovement.Hammershøi’sstagingofrooms maybeinterpreted as poetic reflection chambers, as spaces of painterlypoetry and criticism. But at best, they give ahint or layatrace. Is the world dense and, as it appears,timelesslyfrozen in the face of the ragingmonotonyofindustrial capitalist seriality?Does it denyboth the past and the future? As unfathomable as the lines of the room is the “doubling of the room, which appears to be mirrored withoutbeing mirrored: likethese rooms,all the appearances of history mayperhaps resemble each other, as long as they them- selves, in bondagetonature, persist in appearances” (Adorno 1979,69; trans. A.E.). Is this an implicit critique of acollective consciousness that neglects the past, because everything or the ever new that happens passes, as it were, as aconstant repetition?Does the experience of time standing still criticallytestify to an ahistori- cal perception of the world of modernity and to the perpetual recurrenceofthe same, which makes of modernity aKafkaesque hell of eternity,asBenjamin states,sothat the perception of space (or of aroom)inwhich this experienceoftime is expressed constitutes atransparencyofpenetration, overlaying and covering?(Benjamin 1982, GS V.2, 676[S1,5]; 678‒679[S2,1]) All this maybealluded to here. Let us return to another episode of Kierkegaard’s Repetition,wherepreciselythe impossibility of stealingout of time becomes the object of poetic criticism. And in- deed, models of the perception of time here correspond with the representation of aparkours of interiors and suites of rooms.

One climbs the stairs to the first floor in agas-illuminatedbuilding, opens alittle door,and stands in the entry.Tothe left is aglass door leadingtoaroom.Straight ahead is an anteroom. Beyond aretwo entirelyidentical rooms, identicallyfurnished, so that one sees the room double in the mirror.The inner room (inderste Værelse)istastefullyilluminated. Acandelabrastands on awritingtable; agracefullydesigned armchairupholstered in ared velvet stands beforethe desk. The first room is not illuminated. Here the pale light of the moon blends with the strong light from the inner room(indreVærelse). Sittinginachair by the window,one looks out on the great square, sees the shadows of passersby hurryingalong the walls (Forbigaaendes Skygger ile hen over Murene); everythingistransformedinto astage setting(sceniskDecoration). Adream world glimmers in the background of the soul. (Kierkegaard1983, 151–152)

But here, too, the comfort of aretreat concealed in the moonlight is deceptive.The dreamyhope “as if the end of the world had alreadycome” (152),²⁰ the attempt to approach the world in adreamilydistancedway like a “sceniskDecoration,” and the endeavortofind distractionin(actual) theater performances provemore and more illusory for the protagonist – and in the end, he wishes to shatter to pieces the backdrops of the bourgeois world and the props of the writing room (“Ialmost

 This ambiguouslyalludes to the end of earthlytime, that is, in theological terms, the time of ful- fillment and redemption, but also the time of final judgment. 98 Anne Eusterschulte

smashedittopieces”). “Half-awake,half-dreaming,” the redvelvetchair becomes a foreign object in ahome that has become uncannyand the chair is thrown forcefully into acorner. “My homehad become dismal to me simplybecause it was arepetition of the wrong kind.” Therepetition of aromanticized remembrance proves to be just as impossible as the escape into an open future. “There is no repetition at all.” (Kier- kegaard 1983, 169) It is again poetictelegraphs that Kierkegaard makes literarilyeffective.For in- stance, when in Sickness unto Death he tells us the story of amurderer,who tries to escape the scene of his crime by train (a sequence of chambers on rails,one might say), but as circumstances dictate, atelegraph is active in one of the cabins and reports that the criminalisonboard. Thus, when the wanted man arrivesat the next station, he bringsthe news of his conviction himself.²¹ Adorno has referred to this episode as aparable of civilization in the sense of areality of the court,which dissolves, and at the sametime fulfills,deceptive appearances (Adorno 1979,67–68). There is no escape from one’spersonal life. The individual past,asacrystalliza- tion point of acollective history,accompanies us every single moment,evenwhen we take atrain in order to escape. This is not , and it does not interest us here in the theological sense of ahigher justiceorjudgment.What it represents, however,is the problematization of adeceptive sense of security.The attempt to escape from the world and from one’sown personal and collective history by seeking to settle down in the cavesofprivate comfort fails, because this very historicalworld is present ev- erywhere and always surroundingus. As Adorno has often stated with regard to cin- ematic fiction: The scene is speeding towards us like an express train.²² As atopos of consciousness or self-awareness – Nietzsche’schamber of con- sciousnessthat we never enter but are onlyable to seethrough asmall gap – ascenic world is revealed in these inward chambers.Inthem, however,modes of subjection to an overpoweringouter world are perpetuated. And this becomes even more insist- ent in the twentieth century. Allthese poetic chambers operatewith alanguageoffurnishing (Einrichtung), whichisinterwoven with the experienceofthe social world. Yet, this visual language entails apoetic enigmaticalness,i.e., apoetic criticism that is articulatedinparadoxical figures. We do notescapethe noise of athreatening outside worldbyentrenchingour- selves. On the contrary, it becomes even louder.Let us listen to apassage from Kafka, whose intense, ambiguous involvement with Kierkegaard has beenwidelydiscussed.

Everyone carries aroom about inside him. The fact can even be proved by means of the sense of hearing. If someone walks fast and one pricks up one’sears and listens, sayinthe night,when

 See Müller 1995, 67– 75.  As Adorno emphasizes with regardtoKafka, aesthetic distancehas become impossible – some- thingwhich is prototypical for . The contemplative comfort of the readerisshattered, be- cause the catastrophic world does not allow for an uninvolved spectator (see Adorno 2009 [NS], IV, 418). La Chambre Poétique 99

everythinground about is quiet,one hears,for instance, the rattlingofamirror not quitefirmly fastened to the wall. (Kafka1991,1)

Anight scene – and we do not know wherethis supposedencounter between the one hurrying through the night and the one hearing the sounds of awall mirror in the silence takes place. The poetic stagingalludes to an inner self-reflection, aclattering self-reflection which has turned into adiscordant state and which is betraying its in- stability through movement;atthesame time, it also alludes to abourgeois interior with wall mirrors,furniture, and social conventions. Listeningtothe silence within oneself, to the echo spaceofthe inner telegraphs,may remind us of Kierkegaard’s soundingshadows. The world seems locked-out,and yetitechoes in the imaginative space of poetic writing,virtuallycrowding into consciousness and undermining any possiblecalm. The poetic chamber is by no meansobjectless.Inits indifferencetoworld events, it suspendsany direct relation to the sphere of empirical activities. It negates purpos- es of self-preservation belongingtolived routinesand thus indirectlyreflects upon the (im)possibility of another practice. But this happens in aesthetic idioms of distor- tion, interruption, deformation. Poetic procedures make us susceptible to being at the mercyofthe living world at an aesthetic distance.But this distance requires mo- bility,paradoxical actions, i.e., actionesindistans as arestless back and forth be- tween inside and outside. The poetic chamber becomes astageonwhich the world in its absurdconstitu- tion begins to resound. In his reflections on the musical-erotic,Kierkegaard has de- scribed the deep layers of the soul’smovement as an underlying urge,beitpainful or rapturous. This urge ties itself to anyeverydayexperience, is an indicator of the ego’s experience of the world, and it requires silence to listentothis interweaving of expe- rience and memory.Can silence, in particular,not bring along an immense volume? Does not the roar of the world sometimesreveal itself through enervating signals or a deafening silence?Will it be the noise of an inner telegraphy, disturbed from the slumber of ignorance? Let us listen to Kafka again:

It is notnecessary foryou to leavethe house. Stay at your tableand listen.Don’tevenlisten, just wait. Don’tevenwait, be completely quietand alone. Theworld will offeritselftoyou to be un- masked,itcan’tdootherwise,inrapturesitwillwrithebeforeyou.(Kafka2012, 200; NSFII140)²³

Separated from the individual’srestless activity,the historicalcontext and the exter- nal social world push themselvesevenmore intenselyinto the enclave of the ego, infiltrating its inner voices and becomingacrystallization point of critical reflection. As we have alreadyseen and heard: poetic rooms do not offer vantage points for comfortable contemplations. They do not allow us to lean back in pleasurable, unin- volved self-reflection, as in ared velvet armchair.Instead, they draw the reader into a

 See also Kleinwort 2004,224–225. 100 Anne Eusterschulte

maelstrom and do not leave the sympathizer of secrecy alone,but expose him to in- dissolubility. Where reality has taken on the character of hostility,rejection, and inhumanity, or the appearance of an irrational totality,aretreat into inwardness is preciselythat which cannot guarantee liberation. Rather,itbecomesaprison. The chamber scenes discussed earliermake this unmistakablyclear with all their features of abandon- ment,loneliness, rebellion, and the destructive parodyofeverydayworlds.They also mirror modes of domestication, asubjection of the self to the norms and habits of bourgeois life: indoor situations thus mirror the outdoor world. This also happens in ambivalent stagings.The following scene will perhaps (at first) evoke the impres- sion of happy fantasy journeys under the father’scare.²⁴

When at timesJohannesasked permission to go out, his requestwas usuallyrefused;but occasion- allyhis father,byway of compensation,offered to take hishandand go forawalk up anddownthe floor […]. They walked throughthe citygatetothe countrypalacenearbyortothe seashoreor aboutthe streets – accordingtoJohannes’swish, forhis father wascapable of everything.While they walked up anddownthe floor,his father wouldtellabout everything they saw. They greeted thepassers-by; thecarriages rumbledpast, drowning outhis father’svoice;the pastry woman’s fruits were more tempting than ever.[…]Ifthe pathwas unfamiliar to Johannes,hemadeassoci- ations, whilehis father’somnipotent imaginationwas able to fashioneverything, to useevery child- ishwishasaningredientinthe dramathatwas taking place. (Kierkegaard 1985, 120)

This scene has often been read biographically. But the promenade through the room, which transposes structuresofthe outside world into the illusory worldofthe inside, can not onlyberead as aprotected flânerie at the father’shand. Kierkegaard’sinte- riors are neither comfortable nor always inviting.Itisthe aesthetic form – the antag- onism of moments, repetitions, and paradoxical situations – that strivesagainst illu- sionary arrangements and allows for boththe experience of life’sdestructive forces and an awareness of the deceptive illusion of comfortable inwardness.The poetical chamber,i.e., the furniture of aesthetic language, makes these distortions tangible.

Youmust push your head throughthe wall. It is not difficulttopush it through because it is made of thin paper. But what is difficultisnot to let yourself be deceivedbythe fact that thereisalreadyanextremelydeceptive paintingonthe wall showingyou pushing through the wall. It tempts youtosay:Don’tIpush it throughall the time? (Kafka 1954,303)

We takeuphere onlysome flashlights from Kafka leading us to apoetic chamber of the late twentieth century.Weare now in avideo installation by the artist Gary Hill. The audience has to enter adarkened room,ablack cube, within which it is confront- ed with avideo projection on one of the walls, aprojectionthat repeatedlypops up

 Implicitly, we can again think here of the entanglement of the imaginative roles of child and aged man. This might prompt us to think about standardized images of reality that are, literally, cut out here. La Chambre Poétique 101

and then disappears again, cut-off, exhibiting onlyshattered sequences:acinemato- graphic shadow play. With the flashing light constantlyflickering, we can see for a moment amale figure that seems to throw itself against awall, as if seeking to break through it.Atthe same time the projected figure on the wall seems to jump against this imaginary borderline time and again, we can listen to the chantingof apoetic text that is just as shattered, as breathlesslyflashing as the light reflections – anever-ending loop.

Fig. 6: GaryHill. Wall Piece, 2000.Single-channel video/sound installation

Aword is worth .001 pictures. To be transfixed is no longer an option. Iaminawayblind. Ilive time throughasuccession of pictures I’ve known since when. But it’spreciselythis when that haunts – it eats out the lookingcavities and smiles inwardlike aCheshire cat.What Imight name as “the immediatesurroundings” has all but vanished. Ihavenoplace. No feet.I’ve lost the vagueidea of limbs.Legsfeel morelikelogsarranged for afire. Iremember adream of holdingthe other’sheart in my hand; for amoment Ilivethe pulse of another being. […] This is not me. I’mnot accountable. It wasn’tthoughtout.Ithas no relation to thought. This is that hole that everythingmust pass through.[…]Itburrows itself in, blows up and begins againplural—–Points. Cells.²⁵

An inversion of the borderlines between inside and outside. Cabin, cell, prison – or blasting cap of language? The paradoxical inside-out and the endless attempt to es- cape one’sshattered self-perception maybeseen as aradical stagingofpoetic criti- cism. We leave the lastwords to Kafka:

Der Kampf mit der Zellenwand ______Unentschieden (Kafka,NSF II, 383)²⁶

 http://garyhill.com/work/mixed_media_installation/wall-piece.html  “The war with the cell wall”–“Undecided” (qtd. in Corngold 2011,14). 102 Anne Eusterschulte

Bibliography

Adorno, Theodor W. Ästhetische Theorie.Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. VII. Ed.RolfTiedemann, assistedbyGretel Adorno, Susan Buck-Morss, and Klaus Schultz. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1970. Adorno, Theodor W. Kierkegaard. Konstruktion des Ästhetischen. Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. II. Ed. RolfTiedemann. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1979. Adorno, Theodor W. Nachgelassene Schriften (NS). Section IV,Vol. 3. Ästhetik (1958/59). Ed. EberhardOrtland. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2009. Alsdorf, Bridget. “Hammershoi’sEither/Or.” Critical Inquiry 42.2 (Winter 2016): 268–305. Barthes, Roland. La chambreclaire. Note surlaphotographie. Paris: Gallimard, 1980. Barthes, Roland. Cameralucida. Reflections on photography. Trans. Richard Howard. New York: Hill and Wang, 2006. Becker, Claudia. Zimmer-Kopf-Welten. Motivgeschichte des Intérieurs im 19. Und 20. Jahrhundert. Munich: Fink, 1990. Benjamin, Walter. Kleine Prosa. Baudelaire-Übertragungen. Gesammelte Schriften (GS). Vol. IV.Ed. Tillmann Rexroth. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1972. Benjamin, Walter. Das Passagen-Werk. GS. Vol. V. Ed.RolfTiedemann. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1982. Blumenberg, Hans. Theorie der Unbegrifflichkeit. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp 2007. Brüggemann, Heinz. Walter Benjamin. Über Spiel, Farbe und Phantasie,Würzburg: Königshausen &Neumann, 2007. Chaouli, Michel. Das Laboratorium der Poesie. Chemie und Poetik bei Friedrich Schlegel. Munich et al.: Schöningh,2004. Corngold, Stanley. “Special views on Kafka’scages.” Freedom and ConfinementinModernity. Kafka’sCages. Eds. Kordela A. Kiarinaand Dimitris Vardoulakis. New York: Palgrave Macmillian 2011. 9–28. Glöckner,Dorothea. KierkegaardsBegriffder Wiederholung. Eine Studie zu seinem Freiheitsverständnis. Berlin and New York: De Gruyter,1998. Haug, Steffen. Benjamins Bilder: Grafik, Malerei und Fotografie in der ‚Passagenarbeit‘. Paderborn: Fink, 2017. Hemkendreis, Anne. Die monochromen Interieurbilder Vilhelm Hammershøis. Paderborn: Fink, 2016. Kafka,Franz. Dearest Father.Stories and Other Writings. Eds.Ernest Kaiser and Eithne Wilkins. New York: Schocken, 1954. Kafka,Franz. Nachgelassene Schriften und Fragmente in der Fassung der Handschriften. Vol. II (NSFII). Ed.Jost Schillemeit. Frankfurt/M.: Fischer,1992. Kafka,Franz. The Blue Octavo Notebooks. Cambridge, MA: Exact Change,1991. Kafka,Franz. AHunger Artist and Other Stories. Trans. JoyceCrick.Oxford:Oxford UniversityPress 2012. Kierkegaard, Søren. Enten – Eller. Kopenhagen: Gyldenrdalske,1920. Kierkegaard, Søren. Kierkegaard’sWritings. Eds.EdnaH.Hong and HowardV.Hong. Vol. III/1: Either/Or (1988); Vol. VI: Fear and Trembling/Repetition (1983); Vol. VII: Philosophical Fragments (1985); Vol. XIX: Sickness Unto Death. AChristian PsychologicalExposition for Upbuildingand Awakening (2013). Princeton, NJ: PUP,1983–2013. Kierkegaard, Søren. The Journals of Soren Kierkegaard [JP]. Ed and trans. Alexander Dru. New York: Oxford UniversityPress, 1938. Kleinwort, Malte. Kafkas Verfahren: Literatur,Individuum und Gesellschaft im Umkreis von Kafkas Briefen an Milena. Würzburg: Königshausen &Neumann,2004. La Chambre Poétique 103

Leske, Marie. Illustriertes Spielbuch für Mädchen. Unterhaltende und anregende Belustigungen, Spiel und Beschäftigungen für Körperund Geist, im Zimmer sowie im Freien. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer,1914. Liessmann, KonradPaul. “Schattenrisse. DasTagebuch des Verführers: Im Schattendes Eros.” Sören Kierkegaard: Entweder – Oder (KlassikerAuslegen 67). Eds. Hermann Deuser and Markus Kleinert. Berlin: De Gruyter,2017.131–150. Müller,Ernst. “‘Der Einsame, der die Fahrteines Eisenbahnzuges gestörthat.’ Wahrnehmungs-, Kommunikations- und Bewegungstechniken bei Kierkegaard.” Wahrnehmung und Geschichte. Markierungen zur Aisthesis materialis. Eds. BernhardJ.Dotzler and Ernst Müller.Berlin: De Gruyter,1995. 43‒82. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Kritische Fragmente” [1797]. Kritische Friedrich-SchlegelAusgabe (KFSA). Vol. II. Ed. Hans Eichner.Paderborn et al.: Schöningh,1967.147–163. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Athenäums-Fragmente” [1798a]. KFSA. Vol. II. Ed. Hans Eichner.Paderborn et al.: Schöningh,1967.165–255. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Über Goethes Meister” [1798b]. KFSA. Vol. II. Ed.Hans Eichner.Paderborn et al.: Schöningh,1967.126–146. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Gespräch über die Poesie” [1800]. KFSA. Vol. II. Ed.Hans Eichner.Paderborn et al.: Schöningh,1967.284–362. Schreiber,Gerhard. Apriorische Gewissheit. Das Glaubensverständnis des jungen Kierkegaard und seine philosophisch-theologischen Voraussetzungen (KierkegaardStudies 30). Berlin: De Gruyter,2014. Schürmann, Uta. Komfortable Wüsten. Das Interieur in der Literatur des europäischen Realismus des 19. Jahrhunderts (Literatur – Kultur – Geschlecht. Studien zurLiteratur-und Kulturgeschichte65). Vienna: Böhlau, 2015. Stiegler,Bernd. Reisender Stillstand. Eine kleineGeschichte des Reisens im und um das Zimmer herum. Frankfurt/M.: Fischer,2010. Tajafuerce, BegonyaSaez. “Kierkegaardian seduction,orthe aesthetic actio(nes) in distans.” Diacritics 30.1 (Spring 2000): 78–88.

List of figures

Fig. 1: Etienne de Jouy. L’Hermite de la Chaussée-d’Antin, ou Observations surles mœurs et les usages parisiens au commencementduXIXesiècle. Tome Ier (4ème édition) &Tome IIIème (5ème édition), revue, corrigéeetornée de deux gravures. Paris:Pillet, Imprimeur-Libraire, 1814. (Photograph A.E.) Fig. 2: Marie Leske. Illustriertes Spielbuch für Mädchen. Unterhaltende und anregende Belustigungen, Spiel und Beschäftigungen für Körper und Geist, im Zimmer sowie im Freien. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, 1914. 99. (Photograph of detail: A.E.) Fig. 3: Marie Leske. Illustriertes Spielbuch für Mädchen. Unterhaltende und anregende Belustigungen, Spiel und Beschäftigungen für Körper und Geist, im Zimmer sowie im Freien. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, 1914. 102. (Photograph of detail: A.E.) Fig. 4: Vilhelm Hammershøi. Interior. “The Four Rooms.” 1914 (Oil on canvas, 33 1/2 ×274/5 inch; 85 ×70.5cm).Ordrupgaard, Kopenhagen. Hammershøi und Europa. Ed. Sven Bjerkhof. Statens Museumfor Kunst, Kopenhagen; Kunsthalle der Hypo-Kulturstiftung. Munich, London, and New York: Prestel Verlag, 2012. 107 [panel 83]. (c) Statens Museumfor Kunst, Kopenhagen. Fig. 5: Vilhelm Hammershøi, Courtyard. Strandgade 30. 1899 (Oil on canvas, 65,7 ×47,0.3cm). Toledo MuseumofArt,Ohio. L′Univers poétique de Vilhelm Hammershøi. 1864–1916. Eds. 104 Anne Eusterschulte

Anne-Brigitte Fonsmark, Mickael Wivel, and Henri Loyrette. Paris: Réunion des musées nationaux, 1997.73. (c) Ordrupgaard, 1997; Réunion des musées nationaux, 1997. Fig. 6: GaryHill. Wall Piece,2000.Single-channel video/sound installation. (Film-Still. Photograph: A.E.) Joshua Kates The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s After Finitude and Gottlob Frege)

The confidencethat truth can be found through thinkingisthe inevitable precondition for all investigating. (Hermann Lotze)

The call for the conference on which the present volume is basedinvites reflection on poetic critique ‒ on criticism that would alsobepoetic. Citing Schlegel, it advances the notion thatsuch critique might also be art, that criticism would add its own art to the work of art.Without wishing to disavowthis possibility,abook project Ihavejust finished suggests thatthe relation between criticism and art is atwo-way street:not onlymay criticism be poetic, roughlyinSchlegel’ssense, but,asSchlegel himself al- readysuggested, literature, includingpoetry,would alreadybecritical – by which I intend that literature, too, would have asubject matter,beabout something,and strive for insight,understanding,ortruth, albeit not always on the assertoric terms that usuallyframe these accomplishments.¹ To be clear,sochangingthe equation and reinflecting our conception of what literatureand criticism are would not entail that literature ceases to be fanciful and becomes asequence of veiled assertions or statements;nor,however,has this ever reallybeen true of interpretation, criticism, or thinking.Infact, “the silence of the concepts” namesanew view concerning what happens when we read or write anytext.Onthis account,the understanding of what we say, our expressions’ meaningfulness and references,comes to pass in an operation that unfolds across time, taking in stretches of discourse necessarilylargerthanthe wordand even the isolated sentence. Such an event of understandingisnot graspable in terms of anypre-existing frameworks ‒ givens, such as words, language, signifiers,forms, ge- neric rules. Instead, what is at issue in writing and speech ‒ what they have to say, and what they talk about,aswellashow they sayit‒would recur to asingle, every- whereidentical operation, occupyingaheretofore neglected middle ground: aregion greater thanthe wordorsingle sentence, yetsmaller than thoseformationsthought to combine discourse and its objects en bloc,such as, on some views, genres,orWitt- genstein’slanguagegames.Tobesure, open-ended habits or practices,informed by what Icall traditionalities or historicities, would still shape our expectations when

 Forthis project,see my ANew Philosophy of Discourse: Language Unbound (Kates 2020). Moreover, see Yi-Ping Ong’s “Poetic Criticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee” in this vol- ume for aniceexploration of the possibility indicated by Schlegel of literary works commentingon (or “critiquing”)other works.

OpenAccess. ©2021Joshua Kates, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-009 106 Joshua Kates

approaching different sorts of discourse, or “talk!,” as Itermit.² Confrontingshop- ping lists, for instance,different uses are anticipated thanwhen regardingthe peri- odic table. Nevertheless, nothing fundamental or structural separates anyofthese instances;hybrids or variants are always possible, specimens such as “shopping lists of the stars” ‒ shopping lists not thrown away,but preserved, like the periodic table ‒ or BenLerner’snovel, 10:04,which is also an exercise in art criticism. In the present essay, this middle ground will be fleshed out,and what is at stake in it indicated, by using Quentin Meillassoux’swork as springboard and provocation. Meillassoux’sspeculative realism, and other recent initiativeswith which it is often allied (such as Graham Harman’s, ’sorKaren Barad’s) share aconcern that animates the present work, while being marked by amajor differenceinhow that concern is addressed. An anxiety about science, which mayalso take the form of afascination with it,arguablymotivates these programs. The resurgence of humanistic (geisteswissenschaftliche)practices afforded by the , structuralism,poststructuralism,and in the post-WWII erahaving collapsed, what this moment had held at bay – namely, the apparentlyunparalleled power and authority of modern scientific discourse with its power to reshapeexis- tence – now returns to the fore. The approach Iammapping here, to be clear,also entails the rejection of godlike structures of knowledge,arguably pushing still further that ontological flattening that marks Action Network Theory (ANT) or Barad’swork, as well as surface reading, though seemingly not Meillassoux’sendeavor.³ The denial of scientificdiscourse’s exceptionality,however,bynomeans discredits its claims to truth, which, often, though not always,are compellingwhen examined in their specificity. Truth’spur- view is insteadbroadened and diversified. Truth, on my account,pertainstoall talk!, to all discourse, including criticism and literature,aswell as political theory, lawand, at moments, philosophy. Every discourse, as discourse, speaks, comments, describes, articulates,orinsome other mannerlatches on to something otherthan itself and articulatessomething concerning it,albeit on different terms and often with respect to different types of subject matters. To propose that all discourse touches on the world and maybecapable of insight necessitatesthatall talk!, every discourse, has referencepoints, topics,and subjects, concerning which it tenders such apprehensions. In respect to this possibility,the present project registers its most significant differencefrom the ones previouslymen- tioned, although this difference, too, varies in degree. The above-named endeavors, especiallywhen it comes to theorizing their matters of concern, but also more gen- erally, devalue, even while incorporating,ahermeneutic dimension. Their own dis- course, bothinrespect to how they present their subject matter,aswellashow

 Iprefer the neologism “talk!” to “discourse,” sincethe latter is tooassociated with the program of expandinglanguage’srule-bound character to languageinuse, as in “discourse theory” or John Searle’sversion of speech-acttheory.  On such “flattening” as ageneral trend in the contemporary humanities,see Bennett 2010,254. The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s AfterFinitude and Gottlob Frege) 107

that matter takes shape, recurs to arelatively straightforwardstyle of theorizing and argumentation, of which Meillassoux offers perhaps the most extreme example. In contrast to some phases of poststructuralism, the hermeneutic and the theoretical moment come asunderinthese works. By contrast,inthe present undertaking,because this middle ground’soperation entails the appurtenance of even asingle sentencetoothers in implicit series, it re- tains both insight into some subjectmatter and ahermeneutic axis. The interpretative register,implicitlyeverywhereatwork, but explicitlysoinhumanistic contexts, is foregrounded in the present instance, though this by no meanscancels these or the present undertakings’ ability to referand to render insights or truths. Indeed, in every instance, along with our expressions or related stretches of talk!, ultimately something non-verbal, different from talk!, remains up for grabs,which can come to the fore on different terms thantalk! or discourse,inpart because terms themselves here are never fixed once and for all nor function in isolation. Instead, both what talk! says and the disclosure of those non-talk!-matters it engages take shape as events, along acontinuum of familiarity and novelty,with some topics and some ex- pressions ‒ for example, in certain contexts, “pass the salt” ‒ being more readily parsedthan others, such as the first chapter of Das Kapital. Yet, all instances remain eventful, both in their production and their reception; their expression and under- standing takeplace on occasions and in contexts and are never preprogrammed nor signify autonomously. Nevertheless,atthis moment, “in walks Quentin,” as jazz aficionados might put it,since for Meillassoux and manyofhis readersany retentionofahermeneutic di- mension will seem aversion of his great bugbear, “correlationism,” the term with which his thinkingtodayismostoftenassociated, albeit for his attack on it.Accord- ingly,for the remainder of the present discussion what Ipropose to do is to sketch Meillassoux’spositioning in After Finitude,with one eyeonthe thinkingofGottlob Frege, to clarify correlationismboth in my own work and in Meillassoux’s. So pro- ceeding, Iwill set out the middle ground here in question, contrasting it with Meil- lassoux’sway of working, while also exemplifying this region’soperation in practice. The consequences of this middle ground for literarystudies then will be brieflydis- cussed by wayofconclusion.

1The Middle Ground’sLower Bound

The middle ground here conceivedoperates neither on the great scale of genres nor the more minute one of words. The former,genres and other such totalities that would at once prescribe what talk! says,and the objects it talks about,such as Fou- cault’s or Niklas Luhmann’ssystems, instantiatethe upper reach of this middle region. Words,concepts, signs,and othersubsentential units, furnish the middle ground’s lower bound.Neither of these, Iamabout to suggest,function as their proponents imagine; neither close on themselvesand neither can be effectively 108 Joshua Kates

traced nor affirmed, as supplying conditions for expression, understanding,and in- sight.Revealing Meillassoux’sthought’slimits in light of Frege, and then Frege’s theory’sown shortcomings, exhibits whythis is so, and thus how this middle ground actuallytakes shape, as well as ultimatelyhow this middle ground avoids correla- tionism, by dint of the real’sroleinit. The real as here understood, in turn,grants leewayfor literature, criticism, and the other humanities to consort with truth on their own terms. Whythe lower boundsofthis middle zone lack closure, and thus whywords or signs as such effectively playnorole in literaryorany other expression and their un- derstanding, maybegrasped by examining correlationism itself ‒ the term, or word, or sign “correlationism” ‒ and its fate in Meillassoux’sown thinking.Asweare about to see, one striking paradox or ironyinMeillassoux’swriting is that while his specific arguments, of which there are manyinAfter Finitude,conform to Aristotle’solder syl- logistic logic of subject and predicate,Meillassoux’spresentation as awhole deviates markedlyfrom this format.His is not an extended deductive exposition even in the very loose style of Kant’sfirst Critique. Instead, Meillassoux’saims repeatedlyalter, and, with that, what each of his terms sayormean changes, especially “correlation- ism.” Whatbefalls “correlationism,” upon its introduction in AfterFinitude,thus it- self, perhaps unintentionally, exhibitsthis middle ground’sfunctioning. That logic, essentiallyAristotle’s, to which Meillassoux has recourse, is likelyfa- miliar to most.For it,words or terms and their definition are key. This logic’sunit, more specifically, is the syllogism, such thingsas: “All women are mortal; Cleopatra is awoman; Cleopatraismortal.” The crucial moment in this figure of the syllogism, called Barbara ‒ thereare others ‒ is the second clause, wherethe grammatical sub- ject Cleopatraturns out to have aproperty and fall under apredicate, treated univer- sallyinthe first: here, “being awoman.” This second step, the so-called “minor premise,” lets the other property and predicate in question, mortality,betransferred on to Cleopatra, thereby arriving at the assertion expressed in the conclusion: “Cleo- patraismortal.” In Aristotelianlogic, consequently, terms and their definitions are decisive.What women are; theirdefinition; whether beingmortal is part of it; who or what Cleopatra is ‒ all must be clear and previouslyknown for this or anyinstance of syllogistic rea- soning to operate. Meillassoux, who also proceeds syllogisticallyor, as it is sometimes put,deduc- tively, earlyoninAfter Finitude offers the following definition of correlationism. Cor- relationism consists in the claim that “we onlyeverhaveaccess to the correlation between thinking and being,and never to either term apart from the other” (Meillas- soux 2008, 5). Correlationists assert no being without thinking,nothinkingwithout being.Shortly, at what more this definition aims will become clearer. At the moment, it can be noted that this formulation arguablyisalreadycontroversial, since it ap- pears to be aversion of Parmenides’ famous saying about thinking and being, The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s After Finitude and Gottlob Frege) 109

voein and einai,being the same, to auto. YetMeillassoux deems correlationism aspe- cificallymodern development.⁴ Meillassoux, in anycase, almostimmediatelytransforms this notioninamanner that,though not in line with Aristotle’stemplate, is at least not excluded by Frege’s. Frege’slogic, it must be underscored, is not syllogistic but propositional. ForFrege, the statement or assertion ‒ the judgment,not the term ‒ is the unit of expression and of whatever truth it mayaccess.Hence, earlyoninhis career,Frege counseled against seeking definitions and advised instead to looktoward the use of words in statements,wherealone what the words express maybegrasped.Thisinjunction, “never to ask for the meaning of awordinisolation, but onlyinthe context of aprop- osition,” came to be known as Frege’scontext principle (Frege1980,x). Owing to Frege’scontext principle, concepts, terms,and words begin to slough off their grammatical, but alsotheir ontological and categorial,identities. Concepts are neither properties nor predicates; they cannot be identifiedwith anysingle word, nor can they even be defined directlyorgrasped as such. Concepts are essentially incompleteorunsaturated portions of statements and maybeidentified onlyby wayoftheir extension: the different objectstowhich anygiven concept applies or that the concept “takes.” Frege, more specifically, came to understand concepts as functions, which per- form operations on arguments, the objects that fill them in. Their definition by wayoftheir extensions entails that the concept or function, as,for example, ex- pressed by “…is ahorse” is identified thanks to all the different instanceswhen “x is ahorse” turnsout to be true: “Secretariat is ahorse,”“Bucephalus is ahorse,” and on so on. Yet, even the workaround just employed is not reallysatisfactory;a different concept,for Frege, would be expressed in the lyrics from the old TV show Mr.Ed,which seems to possess the sameverbal schema: “ahorse is a horse…of course of course.” Here “…is ahorse,” despite possessing what seem to be the samewords and format,expresses a different concept owing to the different work it performs in the context of the present sentence, namely, that of expressing an identity. Frege’sscheme, it should be noted, harbors the profound possibility thatthere can be both speech and truth about agiven subject matter ‒ “Secretariat is a horse” ‒ without that subjectmatter,orthe terms that capture this truth, being trans- parent or known in anyfinal way. Talk! in this respect operates in precise contrast to

 Moreover,assoexpressed, it actuallydoes not applytoKant’sprogram in his first Critique,though this is Meillassoux’sprimary instanceofthis failing(Meillassoux2008, 4, among others). What Kant calls transcendental knowledge,that is, knowledge of the conditions of genuine empirical knowl- edge,isitself apriori. Hence, for Kant there can be knowledge on the part of thinkingorreason of itself,apart from knowledge of what is. This misprision of Kant,itshould be noted, is in line with Meillassoux’sunderstanding of Kant’scategories as factical, herelater discussed,and his assignment to Kant of what he calls Hume’sproblem. Kant’scategories, though indeed otherwise unexplained, for this same reason cannot be “factical,” being apriori. 110 Joshua Kates

its presentation in Aristotle’slogic. ForFrege, one can say, “heatisfound in bodies,” without reallyknowing what heat is or what abodyis, how the two interact,orthe precise notions these words purport to express. This fact,aswell as the concepts’ in- ability to be directlynamed, are two ways in which concepts provetobesilent in Frege’streatment.Others will emerge,albeit not always in amanner Fregehimself would have expected. Hence, when approached from aFregean perspective,rather than Meillassoux’s definition of correlationism being decisive,what Meillassoux does with this term in other sentences and parts of his discourse is of primary importance. Moreover,this is fortunate,since Meillassoux’sexposition, as alreadyremarked, ringsarather diz- zying set of changes on his leading notion. Meillassoux initiallyhighlights correla- tionism’sabandonment of realism,ofthe ability to grasp things, indeednature, in itself, without filters of anysort ‒ in the wild, so to speak. To be against correlation- ism, consequently, is to insist that knowledge grasps nature raw, if not necessarily red in tooth and claw.⁵ Through aseries of steps,Meillassoux’sprogram, however, morphs quite considerably. It turns into the project that his text’ssubtitle presents: the affirmation or establishment of “the necessity of contingency.” Meillassoux’scru- sade against correlationism culminates in the imputation to nature of aradical and unprecedented style of contingencyorchance (yet one somehow still necessary)that Meillassoux in part employs set theory to sketch, here being inspired by Alain Bad- iou. Neither such contingency nor its necessity,ofcourse, on their face immediately answer to what correlationism as first defined aims at: aradical realism, or nature in the wild, which Meillassoux exemplifies by what he ironicallyrefers to as the “arche- fossil” (Meillassoux 2008, 10).⁶ The problem, however,ofwhich Meillassoux himself is aware, is that,assoconceived, his embrace of nature as non-correlated, as in the wild, yetasstill known, runs the risk of returning us to thatnaturallight or sovereign reason said to holdswayinthe earlymoderns, such as Descartes,aswell as their predecessors.⁷ With nature in the wild, being itself absolute, as Meillassoux has it,

 Meillassouxspeaks of “agreat outdoors” that he fears contemporary philosophyhas lost in respect to nature(Meillassoux 2008, 17). Christian Thorne also citesthis remarkinhis “OutwardBound: On Quentin Meillassoux’s After Finitude” (Thorne 2012,274). Thorne’sconcerns and mine at times over- lap, though,ofcourse, he makes no reference to Fregenor does he movetowardthat middle ground ultimatelyhereset forth.  The existenceofthe fossil, accordingtoMeillassoux,embodies atime beforehuman beingand beforethought (Meillassoux 2008, 14); thereby,the fossil, by his lights,directlyrefutes the correla- tionist affirmation of thinkingand being’smutual dependence, although neither Kant,who gave an earlyaccount of planetary genesis,nor anyother philosopherMeillassoux cites, actuallydoubts the existenceofapre-human past.  In fact,Meillassoux initiallyillustrates the difference between the correlationist and non-correla- tionist standpoints in terms of Descartes’ separation of so-called secondary from primaryqualities. The differencebetween secondary qualities,liketaste and color,and primary ones,likeextension and shape ‒ the latter beingmathematizable, the former not ‒ for Meillassoux exhibits the difference The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s After Finitude and Gottlob Frege) 111

yetalso an object of knowledge,the knower and her knowledge themselvesmust possess asimilarlyabsolutestatus. (This problem, by the way, seems to me to affect almostall of the new materialisms insofar as they appeal to .) Hence, in Meillassoux’scase, the terms on which he initiallyset forth his project will change; in the place of that initial and ultimately “naïverealism” in respect to nature that he first depicts, Meillassoux, correspondingly,next affirmsacontingency thatinvests nature as an object of scientific knowledge (Meillassoux 2008, 27). As suggested above, afundamental anxiety about science and its achievements may, then, subtend Meillassoux’sprogram in After Finitude,though this worry takes the form of restoring science’sabsolute authority at almost anycost.Indeed, the high price Meillassoux’sendeavorpaysmay alreadybeplain, since the conundrum he faces initiallyappears insoluble on the terms that he takes up. Meillassoux, to be clear,will try to reason his wayout of this impasse, to find in argument,and thus in reason itself,aflight from reason’shegemony. Onlyinthis manner can he hope to maintain some approximation of realism alongside knowledge in the modern sci- entific style of laws expressed in mathematical formalisms, without making the ca- pacity for knowing itself absolute. To balance what would otherwise mark areturn to reason’straditionalsover- eignty and presumption to know the in-itself, Meillassoux, accordingly, asserts adif- ferent absoluteonthe side of the object: asupposed absoluterandomness, aradical chance or contingency,somehowalso still necessary,and also still purportedlycom- patible with modern scientific knowing.⁸ At this moment,moreover,inthe service of this first detour or transformation of his project,Meillassoux’sAristotelianism re- turns full throttle, bringing anumber of fairlyobviousfallacies in its wake, some of which would be recognized in Aristotle’sidiom, though they are much clearer in Frege’s. Indeed, to square this circle, to accomplish his embrace of an absolute, wild, object thatnevertheless does not reinstate asovereign reason, Meillassoux turns again to Kant,formerlythe poster child for correlationism, now in apositive vein. Meillassoux himself avows aversion of Kant’stranscendental turn, launched against the earlymodern vantage point,despite its correlationist tendencies.Specif- ically, Meillassoux embraces what he calls, anachronistically, and arguably wrongly, a “facticity” thatKant’stwelve categories in the first Critique purportedlyexemplify (Meillassoux 2008, 53‒54). Meillassoux thus returns to Kant,but also to Kant’ssuccessors, to mount his ar- gument for radical contingency.Meillassoux would follow both Kant and those ab-

between an anthropomorphized and correlationist access to nature, and that tapping intowild na- ture,nature in itself, that he wants to defend (Meillassoux 2008, 3).  It should be notedthat Meillassoux himself by his lights never fullyaccomplishesthis task; he never explains how the mathematization of natureand his new contingencyare related,why knowl- edge of such aradicallycontingent natureshould take the form of mathematicallyexpressed laws. Afterposingthis problem at the end of his penultimatechapter(Meillassoux 2008, 111), he recurs to it againonthe last pageofhis work, assertingthat it is an issue yettoberesolved(124). 112 Joshua Kates

solutists who followed after Kant,the idealists. Like them, Meillassoux willraise an aspect of Kant’sthinkingtothe absolute; Meillassoux’sown absolute, however, bears on the object,not the subject.Meillassoux choosestoabsolutize the so-called “facticity” of Kant’scategories, afacticity which he claims withstands the idealist turn. Facticity,onMeillassoux’sview,harbors an otherness, an absolute “absence of reason,” one which he assigns,not like Kant,tothe understanding, but to its ob- jects (Meillassoux 2008, 53).⁹ Fixingonthe seemingly unmotivated status of Kant’s categories, to which Hegel and the other idealists of course also attended, Meillas- soux’saim at this moment,accordingly,becomesto“convert facticity into the real property whereby everything and every world is without reason, and is thereby ca- pable of actuallybecomingotherwise without reason” (53). In this way, Meillassoux would substitutefor the realism earlier sought,now lost sight of in all but name, a novel and entirelyspeculative,yet somehow still necessary,contingency. Whatever else maybesaid about this new aim, whereMeillassoux’sown dis- course onlymomentarilyrests, reasonbyitself clearlyispresented as accessing such aradicallycontingent nature ultimately devoid of reason;aworld so determined can appear in no actual science, nor even, as we shallsoon see, in anyactual object. Meillassoux’sstance at this moment is in fact still more contorted thanitmay seem, in that what resultsfrom this imputationtonatureofaversion of aradical facticity, yielding what he himself at one point labels “chaos,” even in this form must remain consistent with modern science and its findings(Meillassoux 2008, 63). Accordingly, Meillassoux conjures not onlyanon-correlationist real, now such solely insofar as it is absolutelycontingent; moreover,this absolutelycontingent real, this chaos is also non-contradictory,and thus stillknowable by modern knowledge. To square this seeming circle, then, Meillassoux argues both syllogisticallyand counterfactually, thereby allowing for the fateofconcepts, terms, and words in his own exposition to be grasped, and, with that,the sketch of this middle ground’s lower bounds to be completed. In particular, Meillassoux claims that wereabeing inconsistent in itself, acontradictory nature, to exist,such abeing would be incapa- ble of change, and,since unchangeable, it would not be contingent or random. Hence, his chaos, his purportedlywildnature, since it must be alterable, subject to change, must also be consistent, non-contradictory. Accordingly,nature can, in- deed must both be achaos and consistent,thereby remainingavailable to scientific inquiry. The sophistry of this argument,which Meillassoux himself seems to acknowl- edge at one moment,isperhaps not blindingly self-evident,onlyowing to its syllo- gistic form; this form and its implications, in anycase, are here finally more of inter-

 “Thought,far from experiencingits intrinsic limits throughfacticity,experiences rather its knowl- edge of the absolute through facticity,” he writes (Meillassoux 2008, 52). The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s After Finitude and Gottlob Frege) 113

est than the sophistry as such.¹⁰ As regards the latter,however,itmay be quickly noted that it is axiomaticinboth Aristotle’sand Frege’slogic that anyand every con- sequence follows from acontradictory premise (or condition); all outcomes are pos- sible, none prohibited. Thus were nature in contradiction with itself, as Meillassoux posits, it follows that nature so determined could as well not changeasthat it could. Both consequences are similarlyand equallyentailed; Meillassoux’sargumentation, accordingly, by no means establishes his chaos’ necessary consistency.¹¹ More importantly, however,iswhy the type of logic Meillassoux employs may somewhat mask this fallacy.For Frege, rather than being apredicate or aproperty of some being,existenceisalways asecond-order concept or function. To saysome- thing exists is to affirm that some first-order concept possesses at least one object that agiven concept ranges over ‒ that the lower order concept in question yields the value true in at least one statement in which it is used. Forexample, to saya horse exists, for Frege, is to claim that there is at least one true judgementthat some- thing,Secretariat or Bucephalus, is ahorse. If this is so, thatahorse existsistrue. On Frege’stemplate, then, before reasoning can occur about what follows from a contra- dictory nature, it would have to be determined whether in the first place thereissuch anature,orindeedany contradictory objects, anything answering to “xisacontra- dictory being.” Not so proceeding,Meillassoux instead argues in amanner thateffectively ren- ders him the St.Anselm of . In bothAnselm and Meillas- soux, argument proceeds from definitions, and existenceistaken as but one possible predicateamong others. ForAnselm, God by definition exists, since, owingtoGod’s definitionasthe most perfect being,the predicateexistencecannotbedeniedtohim, existing,after all, being moreperfect than non-existing.¹² ForMeillassoux,similarly, an object the existence of which is assumed to be possible, thanks to its possessing the predicate “contradictory” could not be changeable, and thus must be consistent with scientific knowledge,its actual existenceapparentlybeing simplyanother pred- icate it mayhappen to bear or not.The definition alone in both instances yields con- clusions about what must be the case, anyacquaintance with such entities and their genuine being rendered beside the point. The lower reaches of the middle ground here in question, then, are reached with this brief surveyofthe logic of subject, predicate,and existence, in Aristotelian log-

 “Philosophyisthe invention of strangeforms of argumentation,necessarilyborderingonsoph- istry,” Meillassoux at one point states, presumably commentingonhis own practice (Meillassoux 2008, 76).  In syllogistic logic this can be shown throughthe disjunctive syllogism; in Frege’s, through the conditional, where,ifthe premise is false, the consequent is always true. In the former,ifIsay “whales areeither mammals or fish,” and “if they arefish Iwill eat them,” if the premise embodies acontradiction (whalesare fish and whales aremammals),then both my eatingthem and not eating them follows.  Foravery different view of Anselm, see Levene 2017,especiallychapterfive. 114 Joshua Kates

ical garb, though their instability in Fregehimself has yettobeaddressed.¹³ Never- theless, in contrast to Anselm’sand Meillassoux’sreasoningthatbegins from terms or names and theirmeanings,itcan now be seen whyitmatters that Fregeap- proaches conceptsthrough their appearance in entire statements,ultimatelygiving pride of place to reference or significance (Bedeutung), not sense or meaning (Sinn) ‒ albeit as becomes clearerbelow,Fregealso, of course, has adoctrine about the latter.Correspondingly, what is, and even what can be said, finally derives from apprehensions of the world ‒ Secretariat is ahorse ‒ rather than what is true about the world and our knowledge of such truths deriving from our ideas and no- tions, as in Meillassoux’streatment of nature or Anselm’sspeculations on the idea of God. At the lowest level of this middle ground thus stand statements,sentences and the references that in part make up their understanding.

2The Middle Ground’sUpper Bound

Frege’slogic thus represents an advanceonthe Aristotelian one, at least as the latter is employed by Meillassoux; in aFregean context,the argument Meillassoux makes for the consistency of aradicallycontingent naturecould not be countenanced. Frege himself, however,inhis own fashion, attempted to stabilize his logic’slower bound, to fix such references and thus his concepts’ identities, through ahigher order regi- mentationofthese concepts’ objects.¹⁴ By attending to this facet of his project,the limits of the upper reach of this middle ground emerge,and, with them, ultimately the instability of both bounds. Frege’sattempt indeed fails; in its wake, it leavesmul- tiple conceptualizations and apromiscuity of references thatneither can be fixed once and for all, nor have need of being such in order to operate. Instead, what is being said (“is ahorse”)ultimatelycan onlybegrasped in relation to what is being talked about ‒ Secretariat,this part of acarousel, Mr.Ed‒by wayofimplicit prior historiesoftalk! and of commerce with things, permitting them, talk! and things, to emerge.Things, talk!, and theirhistory,functioning together, allow all dis- course, all talk!, ultimatelyfrom poetry to physics,toreferand to mean, with no sin- gle aspect ever being stabilized or fixed on its own distinct terms.

 In Aristotle’sown thinking, it should be noted, these issues aremorecomplicated, in part owing to his categories,which have adifferent function than Kant’s, and his treatment thereand elsewhere of the upokeimenon (subject) and the todi ti (sometimes translated as the individual), as wellasul- timatelyhis handlingofthe notion of ousia (beingness or essence). Forthe former two, see Aristotle 1962, 15‒31.  As discussed below,Frege also thoughtthat the senses of sentencesorpropositions had their in- herent stability as senses,orthoughts,ashecame to term it.Nevertheless,his attempttoidentify concepts by wayoftheir extensions proceedswithout callingonthis register and thus can be fol- lowed out in its own right. The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s After Finitude and Gottlob Frege) 115

Amoreprofound, because more moderncorrelationism, it should be noted, un- derpins Meillassoux’sstance in After Finitude,ineffect identical with that he criti- cized above, in addition to the more classical correlationismMeillassoux evinces when he reasons his waytohis chaotic nature’sconsistency as just sketched. This second instance of correlationism is critical, since the limits of Frege’sthinking ap- pear in it,aswell as those of Meillassoux’sown.Meillassoux’sversion of amore moderncorrelationism ultimatelyexhibits whynoupper bound to discourse or talk! can be maintained, no decisive regimentation of talk! and its subject matters promulgated, now thatthe fate of the lower,the wordorthe concept,has begun to appear.Accordingly,its treatment completes the presentation of the middle ground here in question by further depicting the concept’ssilence. In the wake of the foregoing,Meillassoux’sdiscussion of nature takes astill more unexpected turn. Not onlymust that absolutechaos, radicallycontingent na- ture, be consistent ‒ non-contradictory enough to be known. Nature must also not appear to be actually changing,since genuine changewould not just damage, but en- tirelyundermine, science’sclaim to knowledge.Were natureactuallytobeevident “becomingotherwise without reason,” to use Meillassoux’swords, obviouslyno knowledge of nature in itself would be possible, assuming such aturn of events is even conceivable (Meillassoux 2008, 53). Accordingly, to resolve this tension, after arguingfor radical chaos’sself-consistency,Meillassoux takes another step along his presentation’scareeningaxis; this twist involves fendingoff what Meillassoux calls Hume’sproblem, albeit Hume does not make use of this consideration in the manner Meillassoux indicates, and it has nothing to do with Kant,towhom Meillas- soux alsoimputes it. What Meillassoux dubs “Hume’sproblem” asserts that were nature contingent this fact must necessarilyhaverevealed itself within afinite time (Meillassoux 2008, 85). Non-lawfulness would have had to become evidentinthe course of the nearlyinnumerable experiences of nature had by human beings, basedonaproba- bilistic calculation. Hence, the argument as statedaffirms nature’sconformity to . The supposition that nature’sinconsistency, did it exist,would stand forth, is turned round by Meillassoux, then, to accomplishtwo goals. First,heuses it to ex- hibit the character of his own notion of contingency,which will be more radical than anyrandomness probability can calculate. Secondly, Meillassoux turns to Hume’s framework to defuse the worry that naturemight actually be encountered as varying and thereby elude knowledge.Meillassoux, in engaging with Hume’shypothesis, thus will coin acontingency supposedlysoradical that,when assigned to nature, the latter has no need, nor even chance, of appearingascontingent at all. To capturebothcharacteristics of his absolute, which in every other context would seemingly be in tension, Meillassoux turns to Cantor and set theory.Probabil- ity,asMeillassoux pointsout,insofar as it is quantified, clearlymakes reference to a totality of possible instances:one out of ahundred, two out of tenthousand and so on ‒ includinginthe thought experiment upon which Hume and Kant purportedly rely. Accordingly, Meillassoux appeals to Cantor’stheorem, specificallyasityields 116 Joshua Kates

atransfinite number as the power set ‒ or number of subsets ‒ of the first order in- finity of the rationals. Cantor famouslyshowed that the set of the reals so derived (includingnumbers such as pi, the decimals of which expand without repeating) consists in ahigher-order infinity than the infinity of the integers, one thathe deemed “transfinite.” Meillassoux suggests that the randomnessofnature would be of this second, uncountable, non-totalizable order.¹⁵ Nature’scontingency thus corresponds not to anypossible count,not even the first order infinite of the integers, but to the next infinity up, atransfiniteinfinity,onthe order of the real numbers, themselvesintrinsicallyuncountable. With contingency conceivedinthis fashion, as answeringtothe transfinite, it then becomes thoroughlypossible, in effect necessary,thatthe randomness applica- ble to nature would never appear.Numerous,paradoxical results, afterall, can be derivedfrom the transfinite,such as the ability to construct from asingle sphere two spheres of the exactsamesize with nothing missing from either.¹⁶ Natural events for Meillassoux would be similarly transfinitelyrandom, and thus would have noth- ing missing from their consistent appearances.Their randomness, conceivedinterms of the transfinite, would not appearevenwithin the sum of thingsand events belong- ing to the knowable spatio-temporal known universe, since the latter is at most countablyinfinite like the rationals. Now the most important feature of Meillassoux’sargument,inthe present con- text,isthat his entire construction hinges on an historical divergence between set theory and Frege’sproject,inwhich the limits of Frege’sproject,aswell as set theo- ry’s, make themselvesfelt.That differencealsolets Meillassoux’sown correlation- ism, identical to that he otherwise denounces,begrasped. The ability of set theory,ofmathematical logic to build on itself, to spawn these infinities upon infinitiesofdifferent orders,inthe manner Meillassoux exploits, in- deed stands in contrast to the fateofFrege’slogic and his nascent philosophyoflan- guage. As is well-known, Frege’sprogram, his attempt to forge alogical formalism able to generate the totality of modern mathematics with the exception of geometry, raninto what become known as Russell’sparadox. In the face of Frege’sregimenta- tion of functions, his attempt to movefrom first to second-order functions and their corresponding extensions, and consistentlyonup, Russell invented anovel higher- order function, or concept,rangingoverlower-order extensions:that of extensions that do not include themselvesasmembers. The extension of this samefunction would fall under this concept,then, onlyifitdid not fall underit, and vice versa ‒ an outcome obviouslynot sustainable within alogical deductive system. Though seemingly technical and even contrived, Russell’sparadoxshowed that extensions

 “We will retainthe followingtranslation of Cantor’stransfinite: the (quantifiable) totality of the thinkable is unthinkable. Accordingly, the strategyfor resolvingHume’sproblem can now be stated” (Meillassoux 2008, 104).  Forarelatively deep, yetaccessible “dive” on this possibility known as the Banach-Tarski para- dox, see Kaseorg2007. The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s After Finitude and Gottlob Frege) 117

could not always be made into objects, into arguments of other functions, as Frege had supposed, nor could one, then,freelygenerate new higher-level functions and “moveupthe ladder,” in the wayFregeenvisioned to laythe basis for his definition of the numbers.¹⁷ Now what tends not to be recognized in contemporary philosophicalappropria- tions of set theory,inparticular Meillassoux’s, is that the very same paradoxthat Fregeconfronted and failed to resolve,aswell as some others, also affected the first versions of set theory that Cantor framed. Russell in fact had studied Cantor’s work, and initiallyestablished his paradoxwith an eyetohis theory.Moreover, Ernst Zermelo, of Zermelo-Frankel (or ZF,the now standard formalization of set theo- ry), discovered virtuallythe same issue as Russell in his own examination of Cantor’s earlywritings. Zermelo’saxiomatization of set theory,later fine-tuned by Frankel, was thus designed to avoid preciselythe same paradoxestowhich Frege’slogicism fell prey.Though Zermelo’sattempt is widelyconsidered successful, nevertheless, to achievehis goals, Zermelo had to payaprice. To avoid the issues Fregeand Russell confronted, Zermelo’saxiomatization of set theory made it impossible to generate sets in some situations wherethatpossibility intuitively should be available (for ex- ample,when all the members in question, originallyfound in different sets’ subsets, fall under asingle function,thus disallowing sets, such as Russell’s, composed of sets not members of themselves).¹⁸ Similarly,itisimpossibleinZermelo’stheory to speak of all sets, the set of all sets or the so-called universal set.There is not one function or concept underwhich all set theory’ssets fall. Accordingly, the set as such cannot be defined within settheory itself (which was also true of Russell’s formalisminhis Principia,asGödel noted). Axiomatized set theory indeed by design cannot provide aunivocal notion of aset.Instead, its axioms define what counts as a set and what does not by wayofthe operations that can be performed upon it,re- maining silent about what this notioneverywheredesignates, as well as the original collections,afforded by broader domains of discourse, from which sets are first gen- erated. With an eyetothese stipulations and restrictions, Meillassoux’sway of proceed- ing at the moment he turns to Cantor and settheory is, then,correlationistinhis own original sense. In the formalismonwhich Meillassoux depends, “set” itself has no

 Russell’sown revision of Frege’sproject,inhis PrincipiaMathematica,written with Whitehead, used what was called the theory of types to avoid these difficulties ‒ types beingassigned to concepts and to value-ranges to restrict them to their own levels.This strategy, in turn, encounteredGödel’s proof, based on the Principia’sformalism, that both consistencyand completeness werenever attain- able in complexlyorderedlogical systems,thereby bringingthe logicist program in mathematicstoits end. Chapterseven of Joan Weiner’s Frege Explained givesastrong and accessible account of the problems Frege’sphilosophyofarithmetic encountered(Weiner 2004,115‒126). See also chapters five and six of Hans Sluga’s Frege: TheArguments of the Philosophers (Sluga 1999,102‒148).  This feature follows from Zermelo’sAxiom of Separation; for adiscussion of it and the following claim, the paradoxesattendant upon the positingofa“universal set,” see Hallett 2013. 118 Joshua Kates

isolatable semanticvalue, no single meaning, concept,orfunction belongingtoit. At the same time, nature in itself as purportedlytransfinitelycontingent can onlybe spoken about at all thanks to this otherwise empty scheme. The nature Meillassoux has in mind cannot be designated as such apart from this formalization. Accordingly, neither nature (being)nor thought (the set) at this moment have anystanding apart from one another.Neither access to radicallycontingent nature in itself nor to the set as such is available in Meillassoux’saccount,onlytotheircorrelation ‒ in conform- ity with the definition of correlationismMeillassoux himself initiallygives. Meillassoux at this moment in After Finitude,then, practices correlationism ex- actlyashedefines it,something which Iwould argueisalso true of ’s work.¹⁹ Accordingly, the question posed of whether correlationismcan be imputed to the present paper’sstance returns. If Meillassoux cannot avoid correlationism, both of apre-Kantian variety (as in the first,syllogistic, instance)and apost-Kantian one (as just reviewed), no alternative to some version of this position mayexist.Atthe same time, adifferent arrangement mayperhaps better retain Meillassoux’soriginal commitment to realism than Meillassoux’sown thinking,and to this extent no longer deservethe correlationist label. To sketch this alternative possibility, the limits of Frege’sproject thathavebegun to be glimpsed must be further set forth and this middle ground more fullylaid bare. The paradoxthat Fregestumbled over,and that set theory subsequentlyfound ingen- ious ways to circumvent,shows how this middle region is open-endedonits upper, as well as its lower bound. In fact,neither extreme being possessed of stable, defin- able elements, the two openingsultimatelyare one. Concepts or functions, inherentlyincompleteand unsaturated, are to be identi- fied for Frege, as has been noted, by their extensions,through all those instances that fall under them, all the arguments that make them true. This confidence, which impliesavertical construction of higher-order functions and value-ranges, cannot be whollysustained, as has just been witnessed. The inherent instability of functionsand concepts, in turn, ripples back on to the statements wherein they op- erate,ultimatelyleading to the demand that something other thanexpression, some thing or worlded subject matter,buttress each sentence’soperation. Statements are all the more unstable, and some sort of worldlyfactor are thus required to support them, moreover,since statements encounter problems of their own with maintaining their identity as construed by Frege. Fregedeems statements closed,complete, and autonomous,ashealsodoes the namesfound in them. For

 Badiou’s Being and Event,ofcourse, rests on asustained appropriation of set theory.That work never appears to me to aim at genuinelymathematical, set-theoretical rigor,but to use set-theory in- steadasakind of philosophical ,asattested by Badiou’sunorthodoxtreatment of the null set,and it is thus correlationist from the ground up. (Onthe null set,see Badiou 2005,68and 90). Ricardo L. Nirenbergand David Nirenberghave, in anycase, contested Being and Event’sclaims to rigor,wereittomakethem, in their “Badiou’sNumber:ACritique of Mathematics as Ontology” (Nirenbergand Nirenberg2011). The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s AfterFinitude and Gottlob Frege) 119

Frege, both the statement and the name possess reference (what would make the statement true, and in the case of the name, the object named) and asense (which Fregelater called the “thought”). Fregecould treat concepts as he did in part because the statements in which they function are understood in terms of these supposedlyautonomous meaningsand senses, and thereby viewed, to this ex- tent,asindependent.²⁰ Statements and names possess self-subsistent ideal senses for Frege, anotion Meillassoux surprisingly at one moment himself credits.²¹ Thisconstrual, which later is overtaken in analytic philosophybythe attempt simply to formalize the se- mantics of statements,inboth versions ultimatelyproves unsuccessful, however. Forone thing,indexicals, such as “I” or “here” or “now,” with their inherent seman- tic incompleteness, theirlack of stable meaning in respect to what they designate, are never able to be entirely subtracted from the equation; no construal of the state- ment can whollyfactor out their operation, especiallywhen it comes to naming and names.²² “I” or “this” always involves an expression’s context and thus provides no meaningsthat can simplybelifted out of it and stand alone,eveniftheremay be rules for generatingother sorts of significations (turning “I” into “Josh,” for exam- ple). In addition, statements mayappear in what are called indirect contexts, within reports about aspeaker’sbeliefs or other attitudes.The truth of the latter,however, vary from the truth or falsityofthe statement when it stands alone, thus raising the question of how their ownsemantics are to be understood. “Johnnybelieves Flipper is afish,” to takeanexample, obviouslymay be true even when “Flipper is afish” is false. Frege, accordingly, attempts to distinguish ref- erences and sensesinthe twocases. Specifically, he claims that the embedded state- ment (“Flipper is afish” appearingin“Johnnybelieves thatFlipper is afish”)has for its reference the meaning of this samestatement when it standsalone. In this case, when embedded, the reference of “Flipper is afish” is not Flipper and his possible fishiness, but the meaning of the statement that speaksofsuch. But if this is so, what this statement’sown new meaning is in this context (what “Flipperisafish” means when it appears in “Johnnybelieves thatFlipper is afish”)seems inexplicable. If its old meaning becomes its new reference,what meaning can this expression now em- bedded in the new statement have?Alternatively,ifithas no meaning,assome com- mentators suggest that Fregecame to believe, how can astatement contain referen- ces without meaning,yet still be capable of independentlybeing adjudicated true or false?²³

 Forthe relationship between sense, reference, and “thought,” see, respectively,Frege 1997a and Frege1997b.  Meillassouxaffirms that “generallyspeaking, statements areideal insofar as their reality is one of signification” (Meillassoux 2008, 12).  On indexicals and these issues morebroadly, see Kates2015.  Slugasomewheresuggests that Fregeeventuallycame to believethat they lacked all meaning ‒ how that suggestion would work, however,clearlypresents aconundrum (Sluga 1999). 120 Joshua Kates

In Frege’saccount,then, the instability of concepts ultimatelycombines with the instability of statements,the latter being the contexts in which concepts themselves are found.Asaresult, statements do not close on themselves, nor can namesbeas- signed fixed senses and references. No regimentation can organize once and for all concepts, extensions, and their various levels. Accordingly, the project of treating what is said, discourse, in separation from its background, from the actual contexts it operatesin, includingthosethingsand subject matters talked about,cannot itself be maintained. Frege’smodel at both its upper and its lower reaches frays, yielding a continuum of understanding and insight,wherein not just concepts, but sentences and names must recur to other instances of theiruse to articulate what they say and mean, in afashionthat also requires attention to the referents in question, to these expressions’ subject matters. Indeed, it follows from Frege’sfailurethat ultimatelyneither what astatement says nor whether it maybetrue can be known without acquaintancewith other in- stances of talk!, as well as with what is being talked about,instances which neces- sarilyinpart recur to the speaker’sand the hearer’shistory.Once Frege’sstipulations cease to holdsway, to understand bothwhat “Flipper is afish” expresses,aswell as whether it is true or false, attention must be paid at once to the fact that it is little Johnnywho says it,and to the matter being talked about (“Flipper” in context could be the name of his dog who has justjumped in afountain), as well as other related expressions (“sushi is fish”)and topics (whales,porpoises, tuna,theirhabits and habitats), yielding not an intentionalism, but atriangulation across differing di- mensions, all of which are in motion. In asimilar vein, at the present juncture, phys- icists can identify and generate new subatomic particlesonthe basis of particle physics’ current theorizations, though these theories includeproblems,the resolu- tion of which maychangethe contents and character of these observations them- selves. Both aspects, what is observed and what is theorized, are correlated with con- texts,and hence also with whereresearchers stand within this discursive middle ground. What Fregewould call the concept and the world are both in play, and with them come what is said and what is being talked about and their history. Leeway, to be clear,remains for truth, ultimatelyconstrued as an irruption from elsewhere, since these statements’ very articulations, theirability to express any- thing at all, are deemed impossible in isolation from referents and the world. Hence, no construction of what exists by thought or speech is here in question. As aresult, the present conception, unlike his own, avoids what Meillassoux calls cor- relationism, at least to this extent.While no “view from nowhere” here takes hold ‒ that pre-Kantian correlationismtowardwhich Meillassoux at timesbackslides being rejected, indeed owingtounderstanding’sfinitude ‒ on the present account things and their determinations can and do meet us from unexpected directions of their own devising.Thinking and being follow different careers,evenasthey also inter- sect. Having arrivedatthis middle ground, some of its implications for literary stud- ies, finally, maybebrieflyunfolded. This ground and its corresponding hermeneutic The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s AfterFinitude and Gottlob Frege) 121

view of truth (hermeneutic solelyinthatthings’ unfoldingsand their understanding and expression are always preceded by prior episodesofeach), bothimplyfacticity, not in some perhaps fanciful Kantian sense, but in Heidegger’s. Facticity indicates that world ‒ understood as apre-existing nexus of thingsand understanding ‒ pre- cedes each individual instance of expression and anyencounter with specific exis- tents.Onexistence and existents holisticallyconceived, agenuinely wild, because never fullyapparent,real, in turn, will have alreadyleft its mark. Owing to facticity, persons have always alreadybeen handed over to aworld alreadythere in away that entails thatthe finitude of understanding has asupra-finite, or indeed in adifferent sense than Cantor’s, transfinite real as its correlate. While thought has always been tethered to aworld in Heidegger’sholistic and practical sense, atransfinite real ‒ the ultimatereference of what Fregecalled the true ‒ has also previouslyleft its mark on this arrangement. Facticity thus pertains not justtothe individual persons who come upon the scene, but to this entire matrix. The backgroundingthereby afforded, in which the real has always alreadybeen taken up, in turn, lets the differencebetween what is and what is said be maintained, while honoring their mutualyet differing intelligibility,yielding at once aconfluence and divergence of thought and things. Facticity,inshort,onthe present account,enables a(non-naïve) realism.²⁴ In turn, as so conceived, reality and the real provecapacious enough for literature,lit- erary criticism, the arts, and the humanities to field insights and truths on their own terms.Any final, stable one-to-one correspondence between statements and their subjectmatters having ceased to be in question, while the statement as such is no longer privileged, multiple modes of expression and their corresponding insights can now be seen to operate. In these instances,too, the real precedes anygiven ar- ticulation, it overflows every context,while also giving itself in them. Accordingly, literatureand criticism, as well as the arts and humanistic disciplines can have an eyetotheir subjectmatters and pursue their concerns with an aim at some sortof truth, while drawingontheirown various traditionalities or historicities, articulating understandingsintheir specific fashions, albeit these are never determinative in ad- vanceofwhat transpires in anygiven instance. Indeed, statements, descriptions, and reports never speak apart from their im- mersion in largercontexts of utterance and understanding,owing to their appurte- nance to the middle ground here in question. Literature, criticism, and the human- ities, however,regularlybring just such largercontexts forward and explicitlymake them parts of their own talk! The complex dimensionality inherent in this middle ground, which allows for,rather thanchecking,insight (without feigningtoescape its own temporallyconditioned existence) in our disciplines explicitlyenters into un- derstandingtexts,posingproblems, disclosing truths, and/or generatingnew feel-

 Hence on the present view,fossils,totake Meillassoux’sexample, can be, and also can be fossils. That fossils would have existed had human beings not sprunguphundreds of millions of years or even billions of years after their formation, no one actuallydoubts.The understanding that fossils exist,however,would not,ofcourse, itself exist under these same circumstances. 122 Joshua Kates

ingsand sensibilities. Humanistic instances and their understandinguniquelyfore- ground their own embeddedness and implicit traditionality,though the possibility for this sort of scrutinyinheres in all discourse or talk! On the present account,inquiry and truth, are not onlybroadened, then, extend- ed to the arts and humanities, but turn out to be filiated, funiculated, organized in strings, temporaland historical. Thismiddle ground’slack of closure entails that every insight or problem or achievement emergesinadiscourse alreadybegun, mak- ing possiblegoing back over its articulations, in respect to its subject matters and its expressions. Accordingly, in question can never be “science,” or “nature,” but some develop- ment (information theory,gene splicing) broached from out of an ultimatelytempo- ralaggregate of sayings, texts,and subjectmatters that can be gone over with an eye to aquestion and afuture understanding.Similarly,what is necessary for the sorts of truths the humanities and literarycriticism usually conveyare not considerations pertainingtostructures and forms (as surface readingand other contemporary crit- ical moments also suggest), nor even networks or zones of interpenetration and in- determinacy.²⁵ Instead, attention must be paid to the relevant historicities, by wayof discursive threads themselves convened on occasion and oriented by situated prob- lems, questions, affects, and other styles of understanding.Literature and criticism and otherhumanistic disciplines must pursue questions and discoveries (as here concerning the relation of set theory to semantics, or in other instances, evolving types of narration or the formation and understandingofraceorgender)bygiving due weight to the different traditions of understandingatplayinsuch talk! In these contexts, themselvesreconvened with reference to the questions at issue, and thus in their own fashion in part always novel and unprecedented, such prob- lems and subject matters, as well as others, can be explored; onlythereand then can insights about our situation, and perhaps also at times remedies for it,bedis- cerned. Inquiry and insight always occur at concrete crossroads, at once both not,and of, the critic’sown making.Discovery/invention of this type, moreover,operates alike in poetry and science,philosophyand literarycriticism, mathematics and legal scholarship, whereresearchers at once understand and innovatefrom within asituation both intellectual and worldlythat they must alsoinpart project,owing to their work’sultimatelyfutural orientation. Of course, the view here on offer of such achievementsisnot necessarilythe one found in such sayingsthemselves: poems, theories, theorems, literary criticism and so on. This middle ground, entailing the historicity of all understanding,nevertheless can be traced at workinall of these and other discursive achievements, and thus the silence of their concepts.

 On surfacereading,see Best and Marcus 2009;Latour,ofcourse, is the prime progenitor of actor- network theory,orANT.For an interrogation of his program, see Kates 2017. The Silenceofthe Concepts (in Meillassoux’s After Finitude and Gottlob Frege) 123

What does all this concretelyimplyfor literature and literarystudies, then?Nei- ther the uppernor the lower boundholding,the middle ground here sketched being all thereis, in the end, it is fair to saythat all speech effectively is literary speech: all talk! involves anew sighting,anattention to some,asinpart still undetermined, subjectmatter,along with inviting,ifnot always necessitating, an eyetothe means and medium of thatsubject matter’sarticulation on agiven occasion. Other- wise stated, judgement,critique, is poetic; it inevitably involves poeisis,akind of making,not of its subjects,but their understanding.The reverse, however,alsois the case. To affirm that all speech is literary, afterall, equallyimpliesthat none is, that neither literature nor literarycriticism ultimatelystand apart from anyother sort of talk! Schlegelhimself perhaps had in mind asimilar collapse of these distinctions when he spoke of poetic critique. At the very least,Schlegelindicates that literary speech maycomment on other speech. The context of his remark concerns the ca- pacity of one work (in this caseGoethe’s Wilhelm Meister)tospeak about another ‒ here Shakespeare’s Hamlet (a discussion and then production of which is presented in Books III and Vrespectively of Goethe’snovel). ForSchlegel, however,unlike in the present instance, such retroactive potentiatingofone work by another,ultimately givesaccess to the aesthetic in its specificity, in its purported differencefrom the re- mainder of understanding. It makes available aso-called literary absolutedescended from, but not identical to Kant’ssetting out of the free playofour faculties in his Cri- tique of Judgement. In the present instance, however,aesthetic experience is no more subjective or objective than anyother; correspondingly,the distinction between that experience and other sorts, and thus between literature and other discourses is not structural or fundamental in Schlegel’ssense nor an alternative one. The differencebetween literarytalk! and other sorts is instead amatter of quantity,pertaining to the degree, not to the kind, of attention paid to how what is said is said and to who is speaking, alongside what is beingtalked about and the insertion of all three into an ongoing sequence or tradition or historicity. Accordingly, for the present approach, innovations in media (in lyric poetry, drama, or the novel), which Kant took to be the work of genius, can never be sepa- rated from their subject matters. As is readilyevident in Thomas Pynchon’searly works or in some of Gerhard Richter’spaintings, new views of asubject and new means of presentingitmutuallyenable one another.The medium drawsattention to some phase of existenceand presents it anew,inPynchon’sand Richter’scase this aspect often being an historical occurrence (in fact sometimesthe same one, the second world war). In turn, concern with grasping that occurrenceorsome other subject matter permits innovations to be forgedwithin their respectiveartistic traditions ‒ as in Richter’sblurred paint,orPynchon’sdiscovering in the molecule responsible for abanana’saroma anew model for his prose. Poets, literature,the literaryand the aestheticare thus neither the antennae of the race, nor atranscendental clue to human existenceand its self-understanding. 124 Joshua Kates

They do not accede to arealm apart,whether painted paradise or hell. These dis- courses and endeavors instead work with the same tools of which the rest of us dis- pose. Thisfact has never,nor does now,however,prevent literatureand the other arts from unearthing valuable nuggets,providingflashesofillumination at once on what is and how we understand it ‒ insights that critics, thinkers,readers,and society must both potentiateand heed.

Bibliography

Aristotle. The Categories. Trans. Harold P. Cook. Cambridge, MA: Harvard, 1962. Badiou, Alain. Beingand Event. Trans. Oliver Feltham. London: Continuum, 2005. Bennett, Tony. “,Aesthetics, Expertise.” New Literary History 41.2 (Spring 2010): 253‒ 276. Best, Stephen, and Sharon Marcus. “Surface Reading: An Introduction.” Representations 108.1 (Fall2009): 1‒21. Frege,Gottlob. The Foundations of Arithmetic. Trans. J.L. Austin. Oxford: Blackwell, 1980. Frege,Gottlob. “On Sinn and Bedeutung.” The Frege Reader. Ed.Michael Beaney.Oxford: Blackwell, 1997a. 151‒171. Frege,Gottlob. “Thought.” The Frege Reader. Ed. Michael Beaney.Oxford: Blackwell, 1997b.325‒ 345. Hallett, Michael. “Zermelo’sAxiomatization of Set Theory.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2013). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/zermelo-set-theory/ (25 September 2019). Kaseorg, Anders. “The Banach-TarskiParadox.” 18.504Seminar in Logic (17 May 2007). web.mit.edu/andersk/Public/banach-tarski.pdf (25 September 2019). Kates, Joshua. “Semanticsand Pragmatics and Husserl and Derrida.” Philosophy Compass 10.12 (December 2015): 828–840. Kates, Joshua. “Neither aGod nor ANT CanSaveUs: Latour,Heidegger,Historicity,and Holism.” Paragraph 40.2 (July 2017): 153‒173. Kates, Joshua. ANew PhilosophyofDiscourse: Language Unbound. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2020. Levene, Nancy. Powers of Distinction: On Religion and Modernity. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2017. Meillassoux, Quentin. After Finitude:AnEssayonthe Necessity of Contingency. Trans. Ray Brassier.London: Continuum, 2008. Nirenberg, Ricardo L., and David Nirenberg. “Badiou’sNumber:ACritique of Mathematics as Ontology.” Critical Inquiry 37.4 (Summer 2011): 583‒614. Sluga,Hans. Frege: The Arguments of the Philosophers. London: Routledge, 1999. Thorne, Christian. “OutwardBound: On Quentin Meillassoux’s AfterFinitude.” SpeculationsIII. Eds. Michael Austin, Fabio Gironi, RobertJackson, Paul J. Ennis, and Thomas Gokey. Brooklyn, NY: Punctum Books, 2012. 273‒289. Weiner,Joan. Frege Explained. Chicago: Open Court, 2004. Bettine Menke Theater as Critical Praxis:Interruption and Citability

In this article, Iwill reflectonaquestion that was posed in the announcement of the conference, on which this volume is based(“Poeticcritique – is that not an oxymor- on?”)byshifting (it) to the field of theater,wherethe intersection between the “po- etic” and “critique” takesplace in aspecific way, and in each of the ‘elements’ of the question, the poetic and critique.Inwhat follows, Iwill consider theatrical practice that takes adistance from itself, is divided in itself, and thereby,asthe critical reflec- tion on theatrical (re)presentation, interrupts it and allows for “critical stances” (kri- tische Stellungnahme[n]) (Benjamin 1939,538).¹ Iwillmake use of concepts from Wal- ter Benjamin, referringtonotionsfrom his essays on Brecht’stheater (Benjamin 1931b and 1939), and, whereitseems apt or necessary,Iwill alsoaddress Friedrich Schlegel(as well as Benjamin’sreadings of Schlegel). In readingBenjamin’sessay(s) “Wasist das epische Theater?” (“What is Epic Theater?”) – one version of which was stopped in print in 1931 and the second of which waspublishedanonymouslyin 1939² – Iwill focus in particularonthe notions of ‘gesture,’‘interruption,’ and ‘cit- ability.’³ These terms mark central tenets of Benjamin’sphilosophy, that is to sayof his readings, and they have aparticularrelevancefor theater (and not onlythat of Brecht). Benjamin explicitlyrelates what he sees Brecht’stheater to achievetothe con- cept of romantic-ironic self-distancing (of form) and thereby to critique as the (self‐)reflection of form in/on itself. Benjamin does this, on the one hand, when he accounts for epic theater’s “awarenessofbeing theater” in interruptingits (re)pre- sention with the old phrase: “an actor should reservefor himself the possibilityof falling out of character artistically” (Benjamin 1939,538).⁴ Thus, Benjamin brings

Note: Translation by Jason Kavett

 All translations of Benjamin’sand of other texts aremodified where necessary.Throughout the ar- ticle, the references usuallylist the pagenumbersfor both the original edition and for the translation. The first page number refers to the original.  In 1931, Walter Benjamin wrote “Wasist das epische Theater?Eine Studie zu Brecht,” invited by Siegfried Kracauer to be published in the journal Frankfurter Zeitung. It was stopped while being printedbythe editor BernhardDiepold (cf. Benjamin GS II, 1374, 1379–1381;printingproof and docu- ment in Wizisla 2017,71–80). Benjamin wrote asecond version, “Wasist das epische Theater?,” to be published anonymouslyinthe bimonthly magazine Maßund Wert 2/6(1939).  Thereissome overlaphere in wording and ideas with my article “Gestureand Citability:Theater as Critical Praxis” (Critique: TheStakes of Form. Eds.Sami Khatib, HolgerKuhn, Oona Lochner,Isabel Mehl, and BeateSöntgen. Berlin: diaphanes, 261–296).  “Der Schauspieler soll sich die Möglichkeit vorbehalten, mit Kunst ausder Rolle zu fallen.” (Ben- jamin 1939,306–307)

OpenAccess. ©2021Bettine Menke, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-010 126 Bettine Menke

the concept of parekbasis and thereby the paradigmatic figure of ‘romantic ’ into play, which he, on the other hand,immediatelyrejects as aflawed analogy for the epic/gestural theater. AccordingtoBenjamin’sdoctoral dissertation, Der Begriff der Kunstkritik in der deutschen Romantik,the “critique of awork [die Kritik des Werkes]is[…]its reflec- tion” (Benjamin 1920,78/159), which “drives[its form] out of itself” (73/156).⁵ This is the case, because the form of the work ‘is’ self-limitation, and therefore ‘is’ not, but rather remains bound to what is excluded, what is external to it (Benjamin speaksofthe ‘contingency’ [Zufälligkeit]tobeexcluded). Therefore, in order not to remain ‘limited,’ it must relateitself to its ownconstitution and refertothe formless- ness from which it has emerged, which it excludes while delimiting itself. Thus, the “criterion” (Maßstab)of“immanent critique/criticism” is the “immanent tendencyof the work,” the reflection of its form on its form(giving) (77/159). “Critique fulfills its task by”“resolving […]the original reflection” of its form (form as “the work’sown reflection”) “into ahigher one and continuingitinthis way,” since this deferral out of itself always attains form again (73/156).⁶ Tieck’scomedies are well known as ex- amplesofthe romantic ironyofform.⁷ His Puss in Boots,towhich Benjamin explicitly refers in the second text from 1939,isacaseofreflection of the playin/on itself. The playperforms what Benjamin refers to as the most ‘evident’“technique” of a “play within the play” in TheOrigin of the German Trauerspiel: “the stageitself”“is set up on the stage, or the spectators’ space is incorporated within the space of the stage,” which mirrors or folds the playand its framework into the occurrences on stage(Ben- jamin 1928a, 261/69). In this play, the actors,in‘falling out’ of character,assert them- selves ‘beside’ the dramatic figures,thereby establishingaduality between actors and dramatic figures. Parekbasis as gesture, with which afigure on the stageturns away from the dra- matic scene, had traditionallybeen chalked up as afailureofancientcomedy, be- cause it interrupts the dramatic illusion of what is taking place on the stage⁸ in ad- dressingthe audience.Friedrich Schlegel not onlyre-evaluated this gesture of speech⁹ but also defined romantic irony tout court as “apermanent parekbasis.”¹⁰ The reflection of the play – this is what makesitparadoxical – performs the consti- tution of what maybecome presented by means of its delimiting(folded into the play

 “[T]he unity of the single work” is “continuallybeingdisplaced [from itself]intoironyand criti- cism.” (Benjamin 1920,86/164)  “Formal irony[…]presents aparadoxical venture: to build on the formation even through demo- lition [am Gebilde noch durchAbbruch zu bauen]” (Benjamin 1920,87/165).  See Benjamin1920, 84/163;also Benjamin 1939,538/307;cf. de Man 1996,178.  See de Man 1996,178,177–180.  See Schlegel 1794 [1979], esp. 30.  “Die Ironie ist eine permanente Parekbase” (Schlegel 1797 [1963]: KFSA, XVIII, 85 [Fr. 668]). De Man reformulates this ‘permanence’ of the parekbasis of romantic irony as aself-disruptive turn- ing-away, which can occur or mayhaveoccurredanytime, everywhere,and at everymoment (de Man 1996,178 – 179). Theater as CriticalPraxis: Interruption and Citability 127

and its framework)¹¹ in thatitpresents the processes of constitution, which must con- tinually be carried out as figural separations between thatwhich belongs, between form, between what is ‘actuallypresented,’ and the digressions, additions, or mar- ginal occurences, what is merelycontingent or not meaningful: without reachinga conclusion and thereby aground or aseparation of form or figure from the formless or (the figure’s) ground. In the potentiated (potenziert,aconcept from earlyGerman )¹² displacement or transgression of delimited form and its framework in/to play, the limit/border that decides about form becomes always again and still uncertain,¹³ becomes always again and still unrecognizable, its contours diffuse in an undecidable manner. But Benjamin states with unusual clarity that it would be “erroneous” (irrig)to recognize the “old Tieckian dramaturgy of reflection” within the Brechtian praxis of theater (Benjamin 1931b,529/11, cf. 522/4; 1939,538–539/307). The latter performs the theatrical presentation’staking adistance (from/toitself)inadifferent way, as its interruption taking place in presentation: as “gestural theatre” (Benjamin 1931b, 521/3).¹⁴ The theatrical presentation’s “awareness of being theater” is indeed atheat- rical one: manifesting in gestures,its citability,and the interruptions they open up. AccordingtoBenjamin, epic theater thereby withdrawsitself from ‘professional’ criti- cism and contests it and its failed standards.¹⁵ It does so with the distance the play takes from itself, by letting “intervals” into itself, which are to incite the audience to take a “critical stance” (kritischeStellungnahme):

Thus,intervals emerge which rather underminethe illusion of the audienceand paralyze its readiness for empathy. These intervals arereserved for the audience’scritical stancetoward the behavior of the persons and the waythey arepresented. (Benjamin 1939 [trans. 2006], 306)

So entstehen Intervalle, die die Illusion des Publikums eher beeinträchtigen. Sie lähmen seine Bereitschaft zur Einfühlung.Diese Intervalle sind seiner kritischen Stellungnahme (zum darge-

 When (limited) form interrupts itself ironically and reflects itself,itstill does not escape what is limited, the conditionality of theater,inthe “paradoxical reflection of playand illusiveness” (para- doxen Reflexion von Spiel und Schein)(Benjamin 1928a, 261/69).  What this potentiation refers to hereisan‘irony of irony’:the ironizing turning(away)ofthe rep- resentation from and out of itself does not allow somethingelse to be understood as what is (really) meant but rather suspends about the position of speech, its object,and its addressee, in favorofits potential deferrals (cf. Schlegel 1800,KFSAII, 368).  In the potentializationofthe foldingofwhat presents into what is represented, it is uncertain where the contour between the ‘inside’ and the ‘outside’ is: does the puss in boots fall out of his rolewhen he climbs up atree in fear?Ordoes the actor fall out of his roleinto the roleofthe puss in boots?Orsomethingelse? In this falling out of the role, what is shown in Tieck’scomedies, according to Szondi, is not the actorsbut rather the “role,” which takes distancefromtheir “dramatic existence” (Szondi 1978,28–31/68 – 75).  See also Benjamin 1939,536/305;cf. his drafts “Studien zur Theorie des epischen Theaters” (Ben- jamin GS II, 1380 –1382).  The critics have to become aware: “ihrenAgentencharakteraufgedeckt und zugleich außer Kurs geraten” (Benjamin 1931b, 527– 528/9 – 10). 128 Bettine Menke

stellten Verhalten der Personen und zu der Art,inder es dargestellt wird) vorbehalten. (Benja- min 1939,538)

Through his acting/playing,the actor has to demonstrate (in seinem Spiel auszuweis- en [538]) the “intervals” as interruptions let into the theatrical presentation, in the action on the stage, opened up to give the audience space for their “critical stance”: in the self-distancing of acting from what is represented and from its own presenting. There is no place for aposition of authority,nocertain ground for critique (or criti- cism).¹⁶ Epic theater,asgestural (gestisches)theater is constituted, as Benjamin puts it, by the “Vorstellung des ‘Theaterspielens’” (Benjamin 1939,538/306).Whatthis refers to is not the idea of theater-playing but,roughly,the presentation, or the ‘putting on ashow’ of “‘theater-playing’” itself, taking place in the praxis of acting/playing (schauspielen). Benjamin accounts for this explicitlywith the old phrase for parekba- sis: “falling out of character artistically/artfully” (538/306–307). As agesture of speech, parekbasis is an act: aturning away,aninterruption and asuspension. But in Tieck’s Puss in Boots,this act of turning,interrupting, and addressing the spectators in the theater is contained in anew frame, the playinthe theatrical play. Thus, parekbasis and the reflection of the theatrical play inside the playbecome dramatic action (again). The interruptingturning away,which drivesthe form beyond itself, thus is included in “Tieck’sold dramaturgy of reflection,” which would pro- ducearather dull satire of the philistinesinthe theater.But,eveninthis case, the presentation is not homogeneous and is always onlyprovisional,¹⁷ because it is always again undecidable what and where its frame actuallyis; the distinction be- tween form and its being shifted from/out of itself is, in this manner,always unde- cidable. In parekbasis,inthe speakers’ turning away from the represented action, out of the contours of the dramatic person and out of the scene of dramatic speech, the speakers address those others who do not belong to the represented action and who, accordingtoDiderot,should be made forgotten by what is represented and by the actors who represent – for the sake of illusion and empathy. Diderot’sfictive fourth wall represented the closure or containment of the playinitself. Benjamin refers to this self-containment by speakingofthe “pit” (Graben)into which the “abyss” (Ab- grund), “which separates the actors from the audience as the dead from the living,” and which “bears the most indelible traces of its sacral origin” (Benjamin 1939,539/ 307), had then been transformed, and which thereby becomes obsolete. It is decisive that,accordingtoBenjamin, “[t]he aims of theater (today) ([w]orum es heute im The-

 According to Benjamin’s “Memorandum” to Krisis und Kritik (Benjamin 1930,619), the journal conceivedbyBrecht and Benjamin in 1930 and 1931 (with obvious reference to the events of the times), critique cannot “relyonauthorities” ([sich] im Ganzen nicht auf Autoritäten stützen). It is nec- essary to draw “radical conclusions from the unfoundedness and untenability of authoritiy” (Müller- Schöll 2002,310). Formoreonthe journal project,see “Konzeptgespräch” (in Wizisla 2017,102– 104).  On provisionality and its incompatibility with drama, see Szondi 1978,26/1986,68–69. Theater as Critical Praxis: Interruption and Citability 129

ater geht)can be defined more preciselyinterms of the stagethan in terms of anew form of drama” (Benjamin 1931b, 519/1;1939, 539/307) – thus through its relatingoth- erwise to the stagethathas been transformed into a “podium,” whereas the ordinary old theater business continues to operate an ‘obsolete’“stageapparatus” (Benjamin 1939,539/307).¹⁸ Benjamin’sreservation that the gesture, the taking distance of the actors in ges- tural theater,should not “remind” us of romantic irony (538/307)isnot onlyanob- jection against its restrictiveperformance in terms of Tieck’s “old dramaturgy of reflection.” In his book on romantic criticism, Benjamin had alreadypointed out the insufficiency of the romantic concept of critique. As “medial,continuous trans- position” of the reflection of form (Benjamin 1920,70/154), the romantic critique of art that “drives[form] out of itself” (73/156)should be both: “on the one hand, the completion, consummation, and systematization of the work and,onthe other hand, its resolution in the absolute” (78/159).¹⁹ If thereby the “unity of the individual work” shall “continuallybedisplaced in ironyand criticism/critique,” then in this wayacontinuum of artworks and the “idea” of art is conceived(86/164),²⁰ without the conflict between the work (of art) and (the idea of)art actuallybecomingman- ifest.AccordingtoBenjamin – contrary to Friedrich Schlegel – it is not that critique/ criticism should be poetic, but poetic form is (“immanent”) critique/criticism of itself; critique does not process the “continuity” of the work (of art) and shift in(to) art,but rather sets acaesura. Benjamin invokes the “caesura,” the “inexpressive” (das Aus- druckslose)as“critical violence,” which has to impede and shatter the work’s “false totality.”²¹ And in an explicit revision of the romantic concept of critique/criticism as reanimation – or to quote again Friedrich Schlegelonthe poetic critic, who will “add to the work” and “rejuvenate” it (ergänzen, verjüngern)(Schlegel 1798, 140/281) – Benjamin,inTheOrigin of the German Trauerspiel,defines critique as the “mortifica-

 “Aufdiesem Podium gilt es sich einzurichten. Das ist die Lage.Wie aber vielen Zuständengege- nüber,sohat sich auch bei diesem der Betrieb ihn zu verdecken vorgesetzt,statt ihm Rechnungzu tragen” (Benjamin1931b, 519/1; Benjamin 1939,539/307). As Benjamin postulates in “Der Autor als Produzent”:No“apparatus of production” (Produktionsapparat)should be supplied without chang- ing it or givingitanew function (Benjamin 1934,691–692/774–775).  “[E]inerseits Vollendung,Ergänzung,Systematisierungdes Werkes, andererseits seine Auflösung im Absoluten” (Benjamin 1920,78). “Both of these processescoincide in the end” (Benjamin1920, 78/ 159). “Formal irony […]presents aparadoxical venture: to build on the formation even through dem- olition, to demonstrateinthe work itself its relationship to the idea” (Die formale Ironie […] stellt den paradoxenVersuch dar,amGebilde noch durchAbbruch zu bauen: im Werkeselbst seine Beziehung auf die Idee zu demonstrieren)(Benjamin 1920,87/165).  See also Benjamin 1920,87–91/165 – 167.  The conclusion of Der Begriff der Kunstkritik in der deutschen Romantik alludes to this with refer- encetoGoethe (Benjamin 1920,111–115). The work, aconcept for which Goethe stands,needs, as Benjamin has it in “Goethes Wahlverwandtschaften,” the caesura as the expressionless (ausdruck- slose)interruption, the “critical violence” that applies to the mistaken mythical supposition of whole- ness, that “completesthe work, which shatters it intoabroken piece[Stückwerk], intoafragmentof the true world” (Benjamin 1924–1926,181–182). 130 Bettine Menke

tion of works,” as which critique takes effect in complicity with the duration in which the works decayand endureasdébris.²² Benjamin claims that “for all its skills of reflection, the Romantic stagenever succeeded in doing justicetothe […]relationship between theory and praxis” (dem Verhältnis von Theorie und Praxis gerechtzuwerden)(Benjamin 1931b, 529/ 11–12). Tieck – that is Benjamin’sreservation – merelydemonstrates his being “phil- osophicallysavvy” (seine philosophische Informiertheit): “the world mayultimately provetobeatheater” (Benjamin 1939,538/307).²³ In contrast,gestural theater copes with the relation between theory and praxis “with the ongoing setting-apart [Auseinandersetzung]ofthe action which is shown on the stage[Bühnenvorgang] and the behaviorofshowing on the stage[Bühnenverhalten]” (Benjamin 1931b, 529/11). Quoting Brecht,Benjamin characterizes the relatedness and division of both actions in the play-acting as the actors’“showing athing” and “showing them- selves”:

The actor must show athing, and he must show himself. He naturallyshows the thing by show- ing himself, and he shows himself by showingthe thing. Althoughthese twotasks coincide, they must not coincide to such apoint that the contrast (difference) between them disappears. (Brecht,cit.inBenjamin 1931b [trans. 1998], 11)

Der Schauspieler muß eine Sache zeigen, und er muß sich zeigen. Er zeigt die Sache natürlich, indem er sich zeigt, und er zeigt sich, indem er die Sache zeigt.Obwohl dies zusammenfällt, darf es doch nicht so zusammenfallen, daß der Gegensatz (Unterschied) zwischen diesen beiden Auf- gaben verschwindet.(Cit.inBenjamin 1931b, 529) ²⁴

‘Showing athing’ would “coincide” with the actors’‘showing themselves’ in playing (as acting) (Vorspielen); thus, precisely, the playissplitand doubled in itself (in sich entzweit): The “ongoing setting-apart of the action which is shown on the stageand the behavior of showing on the stage” (Benjamin 1931b,529/11) is what constitutes gestural theater.This is taking place in theatrical performance, in playing and putting on an act,inthe playing’s/acting’s practice,turning it to – im-plicating – theory. The text from 1939 continues: “The extent to which artistic and political interests coincide in the epic theater can be easilyseen in its mode of playing” (die Art des Spiels)(Ben- jamin 1939,538/307). This is not (so much) because of its political content,but rather due to preciselythe ongoing process of setting-apart: the Auseinandersetzung in act-

 See Benjamin1928a, 357/193. Critique/criticism is amode of the “living-on of works,” wherethese no longerbelongtoart,which is “merelyatransitional stage of great works.” This is analogous to the status of translation in Benjamin’snotesoncritique/criticism in the context of Krisis und Kritik in 1931 (Benjamin GS VI, 174, 170 – 172).The scopeofBenjamin’sconcept of critique/criticism is thus indicat- ed (see Steiner 2000).  See also Benjamin 1931b, 529/11–12. With this, the presupposed givenness of both “world” and “theater” would merelybeconfirmed. And the counterpart to this (which is merely inverted) is the stage as “‘the planks,which mean the world’” (520/2).  In the text’ssecond version, see Benjamin1939, 538/306. Theater as Critical Praxis: Interruption and Citability 131

ing/playing (Vorspielen), which allows “the one showing – the actor as such – [tobe] shown” (Benjamin 1931b,529/11). Thereby,inepic theater, “the awareness that it is theater”“is incessantlyasserted,” something which the naturalistic theater must re- press in order to “devote itself,” without being “distracted,” to the supposed repre- sentation of the supposed real (522/4). And this “awareness” is politically relevant. This can be argued by referringtoBenjamin’sessayon“historicaldrama,” writ- ten close in time to (and in thematicproximity with) TheOrigin of the German Trauer- spiel.²⁵ Here, Benjamin presents the “historical drama” as a “problem,” since it as- sumes a “meaning of the determinateness” (Sinn der Determiniertheit)ofthe dramatic action, for which the recoursetocausality would be insufficient: history can “only”“claim dramatic truth” as “fate”;itmust present “history as fate” (Benja- min 1923,276,250).²⁶ But it can onlydothat as the “play” thatdrama is. “When the drama of play[Dramatik des Spiels]isconfronted with historical subject matters,it finds itself compelled to unfold fateasplay. It is preciselythis cleavage [Zwiespalt] that constitutes the ‘romantic tragedy’” (260). The play-character,which the “fate” of the “drama of fate” inevitablyhas (and exhibits), requires the “romantic,” that is, “paradoxicalreflection of playand semblance [Spiel und Schein]” (Benjamin 1928a, 261–262/69). If the “world of fate,” or rather,ofthe “dramas of fate” is “closed in itself” (in sich geschlossen)(Benjamin 1923,267;1928a, 262/71), this worldisnone other than the stage,the “strictlydelimited space” of the theater-play(Benjamin 1923,272): Fate is presented “as play,” as the play(Schauspiel)and its framings are ‘playfully’ reflectedasaplay, mirrored inside of its constitutive delimitations, “minimizing” (verkleinernd)and “framing” it (umrahmend)(Benjamin 1923,268– 269; 1928a, 262/70).²⁷ In contrast, when taken seriously,when “fate is postulated as real” (das Schicksal schlechthin real […] gesetzt [werde]), that is, “onlyinthe bad, un- romantic tragedies of fate” (Benjamin 1923,272), such “historical dramas” that pre- sent history “as fate” must fail.Without the exposition of the playthat it is – that is to say, without the disruptiveentry of theater into what is represented – the play of fate (which cannot be other than adeliberate assemblage) will be forgotten or repressed. Thus, “unromantic historicaldramas” fall prey to a “realistic” misunderstanding of “fate” or of the necessity of reality (or history).

 In makingthis reference to Benjamin’s TheOrigin of the German Trauerspiel and its contexts, we also recall that,onthe one hand, the awkwardGerman baroque Trauerspiel (not closed in itself)re- fers to the coming “most recent experiments in drama” (neuesten Versuchen)(Benjamin1928a, 390/ 235). And, on the other hand, according to the text’sinquiry into the Brechtian theater,this theater emergesfromanon-linear tradition, travellingonsmuggler’spaths and mule’stracks,ofawhole dis- orderlyclan (Sippe)ofanti-dramatic theater forms,towhich the baroque Trauerspiel belonged(Ben- jamin 1931b, 523/5). On the relations between Benjamin’stexts on epic theaterand the Trauerspiel (book), see Müller-Schöll 2002,50–52,110 –112, 139.  Here and in whatfollows, see also B. Menke2005.  It is the “Verkleinerung des Reflektierten” in the play(im Spiel)(Benjamin 1928a, 306,260 –262/ 126, 68–71. 132 Bettine Menke

Against the “naturalistic” confusionofthe events on the stagewith the extra- theatrical world,²⁸ ‘epic theater’ preciselydoes not perform withoutbeing distracted, but rather,has a “productive awareness”“incessantly” that “it is theater” (Benjamin 1931b,522/4). In Brecht’stheater, “historical incidents” (Vorgänge), accordingtoBen- jamin citing Brecht (Benjamin 1931b,525;1939, 533/303),resist,precisely, the Dra- matik des Spiels (Benjamin 1923,260), the dramatic conception of the theatrical play. Since the course they follow is known, they do not preoccupy spectators with comprehendingly following (Nachvollzug)the course of action. Therefore, ac- cording to Benjamin (but not Brecht), they allow theater “to loosen the […]joints of the plot []tothe limits of the possible” (bis an die Grenzedes Möglichen) (Benjamin 1931b, 525/8; 1939,533/303).²⁹ Hence, what is “incommensurable” to the plot,what is not along the “lines of expectation” (Fluchtlinien der Erwartung)(Ben- jamin 1931b, 525), is allowed to come to the fore, with its known and presupposed connections being “loosened.”³⁰ Instead of presupposing the given “state (of things)” (Zustände)astobeimitated, theater as theater is handledasaVersuchsanordnung, that is, as an “experimental disposition” (522/4) which always also refers to its re- spective framing – wherethe Zustände that maystand “at the end” of the experiment are possible (522/4) – and thereby refers beyond the particularframe and the Zustände it reveals too. This kind of theater-playing,then, makes the contingency of theater “productive”–in taking this basic attitude (Grundhaltung): “‘It can happen in this wayorinacompletelydifferent way’” (“Es kann so kommen, aber es kann auch ganz anders kommen”;quotation marks are Benjamin’s) (525/8).³¹ “Where someone experiments, there reigns no necessity;rather,possibilities are obtained,” states Christoph Menke (2005,145/117). “At the end,” that is, retroactively,orbelatedly, what is shown in “the experimental disposition” (Versuchsanordnung)may be (re) cognized as the “real state of things” (die wirklichen Zustände)(Benjamin 1931b, 522/4). Then not onlythe events on the stage, but also die wirklichen Zustände are cognizable as not necessary,that is, as possibleotherwise:They could not be,or be different,and are always accompanied by the shadows of other possibilities.³²

 See Benjamin 1939,539/307.Benjamin’stext from1931finds the traces of the interrelation between ironyand criticism in Strindberg’shistories,which have “pavedthe wayfor the gestural theater” (Benjamin 1931b, 526/8).  Benjamin’smetaphor “wie ein Ballettmeister der Elevin” (Benjamin 1931b, 525; 1939,533/303) would have to be read as very specificallygendered. The Brechtian theory of theater is bound to plot or Fabel (cf. Lehmann 2002,219–237; see also Lehmann 2016,147– 164,esp. 157–159).  On the “epic extension” (Streckung)of“historical incidents” (geschichtliche Vorgänge) “by apar- ticular mode of acting, by placards, and by onstage captions,” see Benjamin1939, 533/303;1931b, 524– 526).  See Lehmann 2002,368.  The abandonment of the illusion of the reality of ‘how it reallywas’ is decisive for Benjamin’s concept of historiographyand its relation to its ‘subject matters,’ which arenot to be conceivedas pregiven(cf. especially Über den Begriff der Geschichte,1935 – 1940). Theater as CriticalPraxis: Interruption and Citability 133

While what constitutes gestural theater is the “presentation of play-acting [Vor- stellung des Theaterspielens]” (Benjamin 1939,538/306), this is not to be read as aref- erencetoa(Brechtian) theoretical concept (Vorstellung)but rather with respect to the “presentation of playing” in acting. What is emphasized is the practice of play-act- ing,³³ the playing itself – which is doubledand divided in itself and thereby is de- pendent on and engenders insight.Playing (in) theater (Vorspielen)brings “the rela- tion of the performed actiontothat,which is givenassuch in the performance,”“to expression” (Benjamin 1931b, 529/11),³⁴ since it unfolds the relation of bothasdivi- sion of both, and at the same time exposes, in both “actions,” theirnon-identity, their difference from themselves. Thus, theater-practice is divided in and from itself: it is never one, never identical with itself: it is foreign to itself. Brecht’stheater,ac- cording to Hans-Thies Lehmann (2002, 231), referred “to aradicalized self-foreign- ness,oraninternal otherness, alterity […]from which Brecht – in theory – always shrinks away in fear.” “[T]he relation of the performedaction to the action giveninthe performance as such” is brought “to expression” (Benjamin 1931b, 529/11) insofar as the relationship between the twoisblocked in the gesture;thus, they do not collapse into one anoth- er.The gesture is not the expression of something that supposedlyprecededit;³⁵ it is not aform of expression,whether involuntarilyorhistoricallyconventionalized; it contradictsthe representational model and asserts itself as an act in its dynamis in- transitively against anything that it would ‘carry.’³⁶ It is an “element” of astance (Haltung)asahalt,aninterruption of the courses of events that “retards” them,³⁷ and sets itself apart,incompatible with anyinterest in the coherenceofaction.³⁸ In agesture of casualness, Benjamin highlights the “interruption [as] one of the fundamental procedures of all form-giving,” bringing in citation: “To cite atext also

 Thereby ‘practice’ does not applytothe ‘real’ reality outside of theater as opposed to the illusion- ary theatrical play. The relation between playand world is put differentlybyChristoph Menke,who distinguishes the action of playingsomethingtosomeone [Handlung des Vorspielens]fromthe (con- cept of)praxis (derivedfrom prattein), which is aim-oriented and completesitself in the achievement of the aim (C.Menke2018, 45;2005,123–125, 128–129/98 – 100,103–104).  “[D]as Verhältnis der aufgeführten Handlung zu derjenigen, die im Aufführen überhaupt gegeben ist,zum Ausdruck zu bringen” (Benjamin 1931b, 529). See Benjamin 1939,538–539/306–307.  Regarding the common understandingsofgesture as asign bound to semantics,see Meyer 2004, 61.  See also, very close to Benjamin, Giorgio Agamben, “Notes on Gesture” (Agamben 1993, 133–140/ 49–54); on gesturesbecomingintransitive (with reference to Bergson and Barthes), see Meyer 2004, 56–57.  See Benjamin 1931b, 521– 523/3 – 5. In the second text: “‘one waited until the crowd had laid the sentencesonthe scale.’ In short the playwas interrupted.” (“‘abgewartet wurde, bis die Menge die Sätze aufdie Waagschale gelegt hatte.’ Kurz das Spiel wurde unterbrochen.”)(Benjamin 1939,535 – 536/305)  “Until now it was missed” that “there might be an even unbridgeable discrepancy between what Brecht‘sidea of gestureisaimingatand his concept of the plot [Fabel]” (Lehmann 2002,231, also 214–216; Lehmann 2016,159). 134 Bettine Menke

means: to interrupt its context” (Benjamin 1939,535 – 536/305).³⁹ The epic theater, “which is organized by interruption, [is therefore] acitable [theater] in aspecific sense” (das epische Theater,das auf die Unterbrechung gestellt ist, [ist] ein in spezifi- schem Sinne zitierbares); not onlyinthe sense of the “citability of its texts,” but rather with respect to the “gestures thathavetheir place in the course of the play” (536/305).⁴⁰ With gesture, there is no form specified that critique could assume; rather,itisan‘entry of form’ and as entry it is disruptive,form-giving,but not an es- tablished form. It is an act of giving that is suspended before its becomingpresent (as something),⁴¹ not something that could be stated, but in the very process held out before this. This must also be opposed to conceptsoftheory as a ‘content’ to be learned or taught.⁴² Thereby the ‘position’ of theory as such is affected. Benjamin conceptualizes “the actor’smost important accomplishment” to “‘make gestures citable’” [“‘Gesten zitierbar zu machen’”]bymaking astunning com- parison: “he must be able to space out his gestures as the typesetterspaces out words [seine Gebärden muß er sperren können, wie ein Setzer die Worte]” (Benjamin 1931b,529/11). Theater is thereby thoughtofaccording to the spatial arrangement of letters and the typeface of books.⁴³ Gestures are not onlyproduced by meansofthe interruption of an action; rather,they interrupt the course, setting themselvesoff as an extended – retarding – interruption, likethe typesetter, who spaces out words by expanding the spaces between letters into interstices, which in turn separate the let- ters (from each other)insuch away thatthe words spaceout (sperren)orblock the course of the sentencebyinserting intervals in themselves, and setting themselves

 In “Karl Kraus,” Benjamin sets the task of “unbinding” the “force” (Kraft)incitation: “to expur- gate, to destruct,the only[force]that giveshope [zu reinigen, zu zerstören;die einzige [Kraft],inder noch Hoffnung liegt]” (Benjamin 1931a, 365); this relates to the status of citation in Benjamin’sconcept of historiographyasexpoundedinhis Passagenwerk (Benjamin 1934–1940,595 [N 113]).  At around 1931, Benjamin defined criticism/critique as amode of citation (cf. Benjamin’snota- tions [Fragmente zurLiteraturkritik], GS VI, 169–171[Fr.135 and 136], 161–162, [Fr. 32]).  This is how Jacques Derrida conceivesofthe gift.See Derrida 1992, 12–15,23–27,38–42,100 – 102, 111–112; see also (referringtoNancy) Lehmann 2002,367– 368.  The “relation between theory and practice” refers to the “dialecticthat reignsbetween teaching and learningcomportment” (Benjamin1931b, 529/11–12). “What the Lehrstück promises to teach con- sists not in the transmissionofcontent, but rather in an attitude of experimentalaction and interpre- tation [einer Haltung des versuchenden Selbermachens und -deutens]” (C.Menke2005,145/117). Lehrstücke, “Dichtungfür Übungszwecke” (Brecht,citedinMüller-Schöll 2002,325), insteadof usingthe production of gestures merely as ameans to an end, makethem “one” of their “most im- mediateends” (Benjamin1939, 536/305).  Benjamin characterizes the baroque mourningplays (Trauerspiele)inasimilar way: “daß die Situationen nicht allzu oft,dann aber blitzartigwechselten wie der Aspektdes Satzspiegels,wenn man umblättert” (Benjamin 1928a, 361/198). The ‘literalization’ of theater connects there: “‘Auch in die Dramatik ist die Fußnote und das vergleichende Blättern einzuführen’” (Brecht,quoted by Ben- jamin 1931b, 525/7). Instead of “scenery sets” (Dekorationen zu Szenen), surfaces of presentations are assembled: “inscriptions” (Beschriftungen), “placards” (Plakate), relatingtothe several “numbers” (Nummern)ofthe program (Benjamin1931b, 524–525/6 – 7; 1939,533/303). Theater as Critical Praxis: Interruption and Citability 135

off from it,dissociating it in itself.⁴⁴ Gestures are made “citable” insofar as they are spaced out or barred, as adamming-up of the course of action, exposing the “rela- tion” of the “action giveninperforming” to “the performedaction” (Benjamin 1931b, 529/11; 1939,538–539/306–307). Gesperrt and sperrend: spaced out,barred, and blocking,they set themselvesoff as “citable.”⁴⁵ Converselythey are as such given onlythrough their repetition or citation, and that means preciselywhereand insofar as they are not themselves.⁴⁶ As Benjamin emphasizes with regard to Brecht’s Mann ist Mann: “One and the same gesture summons GalyGay,first to changehis clothes, and then to be shot,against the wall” (Benjamin 1931b,530/12).Set off in the repe- tition as gesture, that is, as citable, preciselythere, whereit(always already) will not have been able to be ‘one and the samething,’ it interrupts,byreferringback and potentiallyahead to what is to come (a repetition elsewhere, sometime); it is citable as other (to itself). In Brecht’s Die Maßnahme,one of his Lehrstücke,gestures are cited in avery specific kind of “playwithin aplay,”⁴⁷ thatis, accordingtoBenjamin, “not onlythe report from the communists,but through their acting [Spiel]alsoase- ries of gestures of theircomrade whom they acted against [des Genossen, gegen den sie vorgingen]are broughtbefore the party tribunal” (Benjamin 1939,536/305). In the acting/playing of what has happened before the tribunal and before the spectators, one of those who have returnedateach time acts/plays (spielt vor)the absent one, whom they killed, and for whose effacing they seek ajudgement.⁴⁸ In this (doubled) Vorspielen of Vorspielen (playing/actingofplaying/acting) – ex-citing,asitwere, the dead, the absent one⁴⁹ – the actors (as those who returned acting the absent dead, whose ‘part’ they play) citehis gestures: citing them and making themcitable, per- forming them as citable by showingthem as gestures. ‘Making gestures citable’ is here the “action performed” itself. The entry to the stage, which in drama must be integratedasatransition into the performeddramatic person, (here) is hindered as aproblematic – provisional – passage into the performance: in these cited ges-

 Benjamin cites Karl Kraus whospaces out in his citation: “die dort im Granatbaumsaß” (Ben- jamin 1931a, 363); thereby the citation that calls out of the context is both destroying(the context) and saving(the cited).  See also Meyer 2004,60–61.  On the foreignness of the gesturetoitself, insofar as it is repeated or lends itself to imitation, see also Henri Bergson: “We […]become imitable onlywhenwecease to be ourselves. […]Toimitateany one is to bringout the element of automatism he has allowed to creep intohis person” (Bergson 1911, 33). The imitative process is cleavedinitself from the beginning (Müller-Schöll 2002,156).  See C. Menke2005,146/118.  See Lehmann 2002,256–257, also 264–266; in addition,see Lehmann, “Die Rücknahme der Maßgabe” (Lehmann 2016,165 – 180).  This is to recall the (rhetorical) figure of the excitation of the absent,ofthe dead, of the faceless, that is, prosopopeia. The “separation of actors and spectators as the dead from the living” (der Spieler vom Publikum wie die Toten von den Lebendigen), which has become inoperable (Benjamin1931b, 519/ 1; 1939,539/307), is indeed to be held by the threshold that Die Maßnahme folds onto the stage in its playing. 136 Bettine Menke

ture-citations – in spacing out these gestures – otherness,absence,defacement,pre- vails. Herewemight recall the (word) episodion in its significancefor ancient theater.It speaksofthe entrance (Zutritt)ofthe protagonists as astepping-into-the-way, open- ing up another time-spaceofthe protagonists’ speech, disruptivelyopening the epi- sodion of each entry between the choruses’ songsand dances.Every stageentry has the character of an interruptingintrusion by astranger.Benjamin cites this access, which as an interruption givesand sets off episodes,⁵⁰ with the entrance of the stranger,who in interruptinga‘situation’ bringsittoastandstill (stillstellen)and in setting it off producesit. The epic theater that is interested in Zustände (“the state of things”)insteadof the development of actions (Handlungen)isgestural,because these Zustände are not available objectswhich would onlyhavetoberepresented or imitated; rather,they first had to be “discovered” by being “distanced from the spectator” (Benjamin 1931b,521–522/4–5; 1939,533/303). This discovery,inthe sense of an alienation of situations, is performed as the “courses” are interrupted and brought to ahalt.⁵¹ The sudden appearance of astranger is the gesture which interrupts the course of things, which inserts the distance of another regard and, in effectingastandstill, bringsforth “astate” (einen Zustand)one runs into:

The most primitive example: afamilyscene. Suddenlyastranger enters. The wife had just been about to clench apillow,inorder to throw it to the daughter;the father had just been about to open the window,tocall apoliceman. In this moment the stranger appears in the door.A‘ta- bleau’–as one called it around 1900.That means:the stranger now runs into asituation: rum- pled bedding, open window,ravaged furnishings. But thereisagaze beforewhich even the fa- miliar scenes of bourgeois life do not look much different.(Benjamin1931b [trans.1998], 5)

Das primitivste Beispiel: eine Familienszene. Plötzlich tritt da ein Fremder ein. Die Frau war ger- ade im Begriff, ein Kopfkissen zu ballen, um es nach der Tochterzuschleudern; der Vaterim Begriff, das Fensterzuöffnen, um einen Schupo zu holen. In diesem Augenblick erscheint in der Tür der Fremde. ‘Tableau’–wie man um 1900 zu sagenpflegte. Das heißt: der Fremde stößt jetzt aufeinen Zustand: zerknülltes Bettzeug, offenes Fenster, verwüstetes Mobiliar.Es gibt aber einen Blick, vordem auch die gewohnteren Szenen des bürgerlichen Lebens sich nicht viel anders ausnehmen. (Benjamin 1931b, 522) ⁵²

Thus, a Zustand in the moment (Augenblick)ofthe interruption by the sudden entry of a ‘spectator’ (of sorts)isbrought forth to apause (Inne-halten)and thereby ex-

 This is referred to by the “episodic character” of gestural theater,organized and presentedby “frameworks” as adisruptive-retarding setting-off of its parts (Benjamin 1931b, 521– 523/4– 6; 1939, 533 – 535/303–305).  In the original, it says: “Diese Entdeckung (Verfremdung)von Zuständen vollzieht sich mittels der Unterbrechungvon Abläufen” (Benjamin 1939,535/304).  In the second text, it says: “verstörte Mienen, offenes Fenster” (Benjamin1939, 535/305). Theater as Critical Praxis: Interruption and Citability 137

posed.⁵³ Such Zustände – in this way ‘dicovered’ through interruption – maybe“cog- nized” (erkannt)bythe spectator “as the real state of things(die wirklichen Zus- tände), not [merely recognizing], as in the theater of , with asmirk, but with amazement” (nicht, wie auf dem Theater des Naturalismus, mit Süffisance son- dern mit Staunen)(Benjamin 1931b, 522/4).⁵⁴ Forthe wirklichen Zustände are cogniz- able where, and insofar as, they are preciselynot available as something to be rep- resented and cannot be imitated (nachgeahmt), but insofaras, to use aphrase from Lehmann (Lehmann 2002,366), they must be pre-mitated (vor-geahmt): “at the end, not at the beginning of this experiment” (Versuch)(Benjamin 1931b,522/4), which is carried out tentatively (probeweise).⁵⁵ This, on the one hand,makes for the “episodic character” of gestural theater,or- ganized and presented by its framing,adisruptive-retarding setting-off of its parts, exposed as such,⁵⁶ that lets us perceive the theatrical presentation – quite contrary to the alleged dramatic coherence of action – as adisjunctive assemblage⁵⁷ of disso- ciated parts or separated “panels.”⁵⁸ On the other hand, the Zustände thatmight be- come cognizable “at the end of this experiment” (Versuch)aswhich, accordingto Benjamin,the theatrical presentation takes place – on trial and revisable (Benjamin 1931b,522/4)⁵⁹ – refertothe otherwise possible: that which is not realized. “Amaze- ment” (Staunen), as Benjamin’stext from 1931 quotesinanextraordinarilylong pas- sageofBrecht,isthe effect of the theatrical observance: that “man [der Mensch]is not to be recognized completely[ganz]ordefinitely[endgültig]but rather is not so easilyexhausted, holding and hiding within him manypossibilities” [viele Möglich- keiten in sich Bergendes und Verbergendes] “is adelighting insight” (lustvolle Erkennt- nis)(531/13). It is made possiblebytheater,which deals with “the elements of the real in the sense of an experimental disposition” (im Sinne einer Versuchsanordnung)

 It is the gaze of the spectator which brings those enteringthe stagefleeingtoastandstill: “Der Augenblick, da sie Zuschauern sichtbar werden, lässt sie einhalten.” (cf. Benjamin 1928b, 72)  See also Benjamin 1931b, 531/13; 1939,535/304).  See also Benjamin 1939,535/305.  Regarding the “episodic character of framing [Umrahmung]” (Benjamin 1931b, 521– 523/4– 6; 1939, 5/303–305), compare the baroque choruses or interludes as “bracketings of the action” that is there- by presented as “part of amereshow” (Bestandstücke einer bloßen Schaustellung)(Benjamin 1928a, 300 –301, 367–369/119,205–207). This corresponds to the observation that the “episodic theater,” “comparable to the imagesofthe film strip,”“advances in jolts” (den Bildern des Filmstreifens ver- gleichbar,inStößen vorrückt); similarly, in the allegorical mourningplay, action advancedintothe allegorical framing,always altered “in jolts”–through “the intermittent rhythm of continual arrest [Einhaltens], sudden reversal [stoßweisen Umschlagens], and new freezing[neuen Erstarrens]” (373/ 213).  This is characteristicfor all the forms of that ‘kin’ of theater,that counters drama, whose “mule track” (Pasch- und Schleichpfad) “today – however unkempt and wild” (wie struppig und verwildert auch immer) – emergesinthe Brechtian theater (Benjamin 1931b, 523/5).  According to Brecht,theater is “aseries of panels” (eine Folgevon Tafeln)(cited in Müller-Scholl 2002,165).  See Benjamin 1939,535/305.The Lehrstück is revisable (see 537/306). 138 Bettine Menke

(522/4), whose “stance” or tenor is that all thatisrepresented, and all those who are presenting, are possibleotherwise or possiblyare not (525/7), which is practicedin theater-playing,inan‘acting on trial’ or ‘in rehearsal.’ In this way, theater refers “productively” to itself as a space of the possible⁶⁰ in which what is presented and the presenters are not givenasidentical with themselvesand are not self-contained – whereevery tentative or experimental arrangement in which the wirkliche Zustände maybe(re)cognizedretrospectively⁶¹ implies(and this applies both to the events on stageand to reality) an uncountable multitude of other “possibilities” (that have not become real)held and hidden in themselves. Therefore: “Der Zustand, den dasepische Theater aufdeckt,ist die Dialektik im Stillstand” (“The state thatepic theater uncovers is the at astandstill”), as Benjamin puts it here for the first time, coining aphrase for theater’sinterrupting Stillstellung,its putting-to-a-halt(Benjamin 1931b, 530/12 – 13),⁶² which he will further develop in his later notations on history and historiography.⁶³ The “amazement” (Staunen)notablyemergesfrom the playofthe signifiers between Staunen and Stauen (“damming-up”), characterized as the “backwards tide” of a “swell in the real flow of life” (Stauung im realen Lebensfluß), in the “instant that its flow comes to astandstill” (im Augenblick, da sein Ablauf zumStehen kommt)(531/13),⁶⁴ there, whereatthe sametime – in the katachrestic breakingofthe metaphors – “the flow of thingsbreaks itself” on the “cliff of amazement” (Fels des Staunens), al- lowing “Being” ()to“spray up high out of the bed of time and, irridescent,in an instant [Nu]tostand in emptiness, in order to bed it anew” (531/13).⁶⁵ The dynamis

 In particular,the Lehrstück discovers the “spaceofthe possible” as a “settingfree of potential, play, fantasy,provisionality,openness” (Lehmann 2002,368); see also C. Menke2005,145/117– 118.  Christoph Menke(followingNietzsche) ties imitation (Nachahmung)toplayingasform-givingout of formlessness, in which the forms,inbecoming, again and againdissolve themselves, “meet[ing] the abyss, the emptiness,and the potential of formlessness”:inthe play, form is the imitated “form of life” (C.Menke 2018, 41)ifwhatisrepresented finds its form giveninreality as that which can be imitated –“the imitation [Nachahmung]ofanother,preceding form” (42).This is, how- ever,justaretroactive effect,asis(according to Benjamin) the cognizability of the “real state of things” (der wirklichen Zustände).  See also Müller-Scholl 2002,160. “Immanent dialecticalbehavior is what in the ‘state of things’ is cleared up in aflash” (Immanent dialektischesVerhalten ist es, was im Zustand […] blitzartig klarge- stellt wird)(Benjamin 1931b, 530/12). Thus,GalyGay in Mann ist Mann is “nothingother than astage of contradictions, which constituteour society” (530/12). Instead of “forcingopen our stateofthings from the outside” (von außen her unsreZustände einzurennen), Brecht is said to let them “mediated, in a “dialecticalway” (vermittelt, dialektisch) “criticize one another,playtheir various elements log- icallyagainst each other” (526/8).  See Benjamin’s Über den Begriff der Geschichte,1935 – 1940,104,102– 105;see also Benjamin’sno- tations (BenjaminGSI,1236, 1250); Benjamin 1934–1940,55, 577–578(N2a,3; N3,1), 1001.  “[D]as Staunen ist diese Rückflut.Die Dialektik im Stillstandist sein eigentlicher Gegenstand” (Benjamin 1931b, 531).  “[…][lässt] das Dasein ausdem Bett der Zeit hoch aufsprühen und schillernd einen Nu im Leeren stehen, um es neu zu betten.” Here there is “no differencebetween ahuman life and aword.” The Theater as CriticalPraxis: Interruption and Citability 139

of rupture in the interruption, in the damming-up (Stauen)asabroken movement, trembles ‘inside’ of the Zustand brought forth by interruptingand in retarding.The dialectic at astandstill manifests itself “alreadyingestural elements that underlie every temporalsequence and that one can onlyimproperlycall elements” (530/ 12).⁶⁶ Indeed, as they are not indivisibleelements but are alreadysplitand doubled in themselves – and thus are citable – they are not themselvesand not identical with themselves.⁶⁷ The forceofthe form-giving interruption putting to ahalt conveys itself to that which it gives, withoutthis attainingany identical givenness. If gestural theater is characterized by Benjamin as “away of acting [spielen]that directs [the actor] to cognition” (die ihn [den Schauspieler] auf Erkenntnis anweist) (Benjamin 1931b,528/11), then the latter, being “produced” in the play-acting or the- ater-playing,isnothing one would have alreadyknown in advance, or which could simplybestated. But here, cognition is amatter of performing,amatter of opening gestures and breaches that holdopen ruptures in the inside, turns and gaps.⁶⁸ The actors act “the one thinking (about his part)”⁶⁹ insofar as, with their distance from both what is represented and “the wayinwhich it is represented,”“in their acting” (in ihrem Spiel), in its difference from itself,they displaythe “intervals,” which give the spectators occasion (Anhalt)totake “critical stances” (kritischeStellungnahmen) (Benjamin 1939,538/306). This takes place in theater-playing,which is doubledand split in itself, and which inserts spectatorship into itself and thereby turns actorsinto spectators, to the effect thatspectatorship sees itself being insertedinto the acting/

broken metaphor continues and transforms the verses cited from Brecht: “Beharrenicht aufder Welle,/Die sich an deinem Fußbricht,solange er/Im Wasser steht, werden sich/Neue Wellen an ihm brechen.” (Benjamin 1931b, 531)  The “mother” of “the dialectic at astandstill”–which is Benjamin’srather irritatingmetaphor – is “not the course of contradictions” but “gesture itself” (Benjamin1931b, 530/12).  Benjamin conceivesthe “dialectic at astandstill” (Dialektik im Stillstand)inthe context of the “di- alectical image” as the “readable image,” for or,moreprecisely, the procedures of his- toriography(Benjamin1934– 1940,570,576 – 578, 591–592).These tie “cognizability” as “readability” to citation, which rips out and makesreadable what has been (das Gewesene), in its broken bits, cited into the textofthe present (595[N11,3]). What has been ‘is’ not what one might be used to conceiving as facts (see Benjamin’s Über den Begriff der Geschichte;see Hamacher 2005). As in aflash, the “read- able image,” that is, the “historical object,” appears in the “now of readability” (Jetzt der Lesbarkeit) (Benjamin 1934–1940,570 [N1,1], 577–578[N3,1], 591–592[N9,7]) that must be grasped as the moment (Augenblick)ofperceptibility of aconstellation, that is, in dangerofbeingmissed “alreadyinthe next moment” (592[N9,7]). The so-called “image”‘is’ the “dialectic at astandstill,”“in its interior,” a “field of tension” that is polarizedinto “pre- and post-history by the effects of “actuality” (Aktualität)(594– 596[N10,3;N10a,2; N10a,3; N11,5], 587–588 [N7a,1; N7,7], 577–578).  The Lehrstück places moreweight on “the reality and the occurrence of the act of representation itself” than on the completion of representation and content(Lehmann 2002,368). This,asanact without completion, contradicts Austin’sconcept of performatives(see Hamacher 2018).  Moreexactly, Benjamin’stext from 1939 claims that the actors should: “[es sich] nicht nehmen lassen, den (über seinen Part) Nachdenkenden vorzumachen” (Benjamin 1939,538/307). 140 Bettine Menke

playing (Schauspielen) – as other.⁷⁰ Distance to oneself (and to one’sown action [Ben- jamin 1931b,521/3]) is taken and given – opened – in and as acting (Verhalten) in play-acting (Schauspielen), which refers ‘critically’ to the “actions on the stage” that it shows, but alsotoitself as this showing (Zeigen). Thus, Theater-playing (Theaterspielen)isa‘critical practice’ not because of some- thing that maybesaid or meant,but duetoits giving of anon-identity – interruption as agift – through which it becomes theoretical, (potentially) everywhere, by refer- ring everything that is shown elsewheretoanother which it is not,tothe fissure or gapthat makes it possibleand thatthe gesture holds open.⁷¹ It is amatter of theater as critical praxis, as the setting-apart of acting in itself, as apraxis thatsplits/dou- bles itself from and in itself,⁷² that, as the act of performing in/as playing,performs an action (allegedlyidentical with itself)onthe stage as split/doubled in itself.What is at stake in theater-playing is not adistinction thatends in judgment (as is the case for criticism or critique).⁷³ Rather,theater-playing is ‘critical’ as performing or as tak- ing place, withoutinstitutingany authority that maystate or judge,consisting (un- decidably) in the event or in what is coming,⁷⁴ whereitdoes not coincide with itself: potentiallyatany moment,inevery place, differing from itself, becomingother. Thus, the behavior or acting in “theater-playing,” the stance (Haltung)towardacting in playing,conflicts with instituting such an authority.Theater can be called critical because, accordingtoChristoph Menke,with its non-identity it counters the repres- sion of the non-identical,⁷⁵ through which alone the supposedlyself-contained iden-

 In particular,inthe Lehrstück “[t]he act of spectating is broughtintothe play. The actors [Spieler] […]are actors[Akteure]and spectators at once and thus,strictlyspeaking, are actingspectators and spectatingactors” (Lehmann 2002,372). Benjamin puts this the other wayaround: “Every spectator will be able to become an actor[Mitspieler]” (Benjamin 1939,536/305).  This is articulated in the theatricalpresentation’srelation to the stage,which allows considering “what theater is about today” (Benjamin 1931b, 519/1;1939, 539/307). While gestural theateristhe at- tempt (Versuch)to‘arrange’ itself on the “podium” (of the stage), this attemptcan onlyeverbeexper- imental, tentative,provisional. The gestureofform-givingremains in reservationbeforeand against every givenness (even that of reality).  If praxis is “reflected and thereby transformed in drama,” this opens up “atension in the inside of praxis”:between completion and possibility (C.Menke2018, 45,41). But Christoph Menke develops the “paradox” of theater-playingasthat of playing(somethingtosomeone)(Vorspielen)and imitating something.  See also C. Menke2018, 37–38, 48.  “‘[E]s gibt’ […]ist im Modus des Entstehens da”; “[es] besteht in einem Ankommen” (Lehmann 2002,368 [with reference to Nancy], 367).  “The critique of theater goes against the defense, the immunizationoflife against the transforma- tion it experiences in the theater.”“Theater criticizes […]the immunization against paradox, and thus against theater; for theater is the implementation of paradox” (C.Menke2018, 45 – 46). “Theater brings forth in its bringing-forth of form, and indeed throughits paradox, an other play and indeed another life. This always alreadyhappens when there is theater.[…]Theater transformslife (or the world).” (44) Theater as Critical Praxis: Interruption and Citability 141

tity and necessity of the world asserts itself as given.⁷⁶ Moreover,itcan be called ‘crit- ical’ as it (that is to say, the “reflection [Nachdenken]about theater” implied in it) demonstrates “that one can criticize in the name of paradox, decide in the name of undecidability” (C.Menke 2018, 48). Its halt is without place, it comes from a (non)place of difference – which attains no unity.The theatrical distancing of the presentation and thosepresenting/acting from themselvescontests (pretensions to) self-identityand self-containment.Itrefers the represented actiononthe stageand the act of performing (suspending it in its becoming) to their margins; refers form to (excluded) other possibilities (not having become reality), to the shadows of the otherwise-possible, which is excluded in every instance of form-giving,but which ac- companies each constituted form. Each ‘form,’ thatis, everythingpresented (accord- ing to Benjamin citing Brecht), thus birgt – implicates and holds – the otherwise pos- sible in its interior,being thereby divided and virtualized. The potential being-other of what is provisionally(probeweise)cited from the space of the possiblepartakes in ‘what is shown’:asits gaps, ambivalences, and ambiguities,⁷⁷ in “the tremblingof the contours” (Zittern der Umrisse),⁷⁸ in the shadows of the otherwise possible.

Bibliography

Agamben, Giorgio. “NotesonGesture.” Infancy and History: The destruction of experience. London et al.: Verso, 1993, 133–140.Reissue: Means Without End: Notes on Politics. Minneapolis: UniversityofMinnesota Press, 2000.49–54. Benjamin, Walter. Gesammelte Schriften [=GS]. Eds.RolfTiedemann and Hermann Schweppenhäuser et al. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1972–1989. [This edition is referred to by Roman numbers forthe volumeand Arabic page numbers.] Benjamin, Walter. “Der Begriff der Kunstkritik in der deutschen Romantik” [1920]. GS. Vol. I, 1974. 7–122. Trans.: “The Concept of Criticism in GermanRomanticism.” Selected Writings. Vol. I. Eds. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversityPress, 2002. 116–200. Benjamin, Walter. “El mayor mónstruo, los celos vonCalderonund Herodes und Mariamne von Hebbel: Bemerkungen zumProblem des historischen Dramas” [1923]. GS. Vol. II, 1977. 246–276. Trans.: “Calderon’s El Mayor Monstruo, LosCelos and Hebbel’s Herodes und

 Identity ‘is’ solelythroughthe exclusion, or repression, of difference from itself, of hidden (other) possibilities (whichsplit actions,figures, and worlds in themselves), through excluding and making forgotten the non-form for the sakeofthe supposedlyself-contained, ‘finished’ form, through the re- pression of the margins of (other)possibilities which arecut off by the figuration for the sake of the supposedly realized figure.  On this point,see Lehmann 2002,376 – 378.  “[T]he trembling of its contours still reveals from which intimateproximity they have torn them- selvesinorder to become visible” [das Zittern ihrer Umrisse verrätimmer noch, aus welcher innigen Nähe sie sich gerissen haben, um sichtbar zu werden](Benjamin 1931b, 525/7). Nägele comments not onlyonthe “spatial difference” and (possible) reversals of foreground and background (Nägele 2005,113–114; see also Müller-Scholl 2002,162– 164) but also notices this “trembling” to have affect- ed Benjamin’stext (Nägele 2005,114– 116). 142 Bettine Menke

Mariamne. Commentsonthe Problem of Historical Drama.” Selected Writings. Vol. I. Eds. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UniversityPress, 2002. 363–386. Benjamin, Walter. “Goethes Wahlverwandtschaften” [1924–1926]. GS. Vol. I, 1974. 123–201. Benjamin, Walter. “Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels” [1928a]. GS. Vol. I, 1974. 203–430. Trans.: The Origin of the German Trauerspiel. Trans. Howard Eiland. Cambridgeand London: HarvardUniversityPress, 2019. Benjamin, Walter. “Einbahnstraße” [1928b]. Werkeund Nachlaß. Kritische Gesamtausgabe. Vol. VIII. Eds. Detlev Schöttker et al. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2009. Benjamin, Walter. “Memorandumzuder Zeitschrift ‘Krisisund Kritik’” [1930]. GS. Vol. VI, 1985. 619–621. Benjamin, Walter. “Karl Kraus” [1931a]. GS. Vol. II, 1977.334–367. Benjamin, Walter. “Wasist das epische Theater? Eine Studie zu Brecht” [1931b]. GS. Vol. II, 1977. 519 – 531. Trans.: “What is the Epic Theater? AStudy on Brecht.” Understanding Brecht. Trans. AnnaBostock. Introd. Stanley Mitchell. London: Verso, 1998. 1–14. Benjamin, Walter. “Der Autorals Produzent. Ansprache im Institut zumStudiumdes Faschismus in Paris am 27.April 1934” [1934]. GS. Vol. II, 1977.683–701. Trans.: “The Author as Producer. Addressatthe Institutefor the Study of ,Paris, April 27,1934.” Selected Writings. Vol. II.2. Eds. HowardEiland and Michael W. Jennings.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2005. 768–782. Benjamin, Walter. Passagenwerk [1934–1940]. GS. Vol. V, 1982. Benjamin, Walter. “Über den Begriff der Geschichte” [1935–1940]. Werke und Nachlaß:Kritische Gesamtausgabe. Vol. XIX. Eds.Christoph Gödde and Henri Lonitz. Berlin: Suhrkamp, 2010. Benjamin, Walter. “Wasist das epische Theater?” [1939]. GS. Vol. II, 1977.531–539. Trans.: “What is the Epic Theater?” Selected Writings. Vol. IV.Eds. HowardEiland and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UniversityPress, 2006. 302–309. Bergson, Henri. Laughter: An Essayonthe Meaning of the Comic. New York et al.: Macmillan, 1911. de Man, Paul. “The Concept of Irony.” Aesthetic Ideology. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996. 163–184. Derrida, Jacques. Given Time: I. Counterfeit Money. Chicago and London: UniversityofChicago Press, 1992. Hamacher,Werner. “‘Now’:Walter Benjamin on Historical Time.” Trans. N. Rosenthal. Walter Benjamin and History. Ed.Andrew Benjamin. London and New York: Continuum, 2005. 38–68. Hamacher,Werner. “Das eine Kriteriumfür das,was geschieht. Aristoteles: Poetik. Brecht: ‘Kleines Organon’.” Theater als Kritik: Theorie, Geschichte und Praktiken der Ent-Unterwerfung. Eds. Olivia Ebert, EvaHolling, Nikolaus Müller-Schöll, Philipp Schulte, BernhardSiebert, and Gerald Siegmund. Bielefeld: transcript, 2018. 19–36. Lehmann, Hans-Thies. Das Politische Schreiben. Essays zu Theatertexten; Sophokles,Shakespeare, Kleist, Büchner,Jahnn, Bataille,Brecht, Benjamin, Müller,Schleef. Berlin: Theater der Zeit, 2002. Lehmann, Hans-Thies. BrechtLesen. Berlin: Theaterder Zeit, 2016. Menke,Bettine. “Reflexion des Trauer-Spiels. Pedro Calderón de la BarcasElmayor mónstruo, los celosnachWalter Benjamin.” Literatur als Philosophie: Philosophie also Literatur. Eds. Eva Horn, Bettine Menke and Christoph Menke. Munich: Fink, 2005. 253–280. Menke,Christoph. Die Gegenwart der Tragödie: Versuch über Urteil und Spiel. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2005. Trans. Tragic play: irony and theater from Sophocles to Beckett. New York: Columbia UniversityPress, 2009. Theater as CriticalPraxis: Interruption and Citability 143

Menke,Christoph. “DasSpiel des Theatersund die Veränderung der Welt.” Theater als Kritik: Theorie, Geschichte und Praktiken der Ent-Unterwerfung. Eds. Olivia Ebert, EvaHolling, Nikolaus Müller-Schöll, Philipp Schulte, BernhardSiebert, and Gerald Siegmund. Bielefeld: transcript, 2018. 37–48. Meyer,Petra Maria. “Die Gesteals intermediale Vergleichskategorie. ZurUmwertung von Sprachgesten undGestensprachen zwischen dem 18. und20. Jahrhundert.” Crossing Media – Theater – Film – Fotographie – Neue Medien. Eds. Christopher Balme and Markus Moninger.Munich: ePODIUM, 2004. 55–73. Müller-Schöll, Nikolaus. Das Theater des “konstruktiven Defaitismus”:Lektüren zur Theorie eines Theaters der A-Identität bei Walter Benjamin, Bertolt Brechtund Heiner Müller. Frankfurt/M. and Basel: Stroemfeld/Nexus, 2002. Nägele, Rainer. “Trembling Contours: Kierkegaard-Benjamin-Brecht.” Walter Benjamin and History. Ed.Andrew Benjamin. London and New York: Continuum, 2005. 102–117. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Vomästhetischen Werthe der Griechischen Komödie” [1794]. Kritische Friedrich-Schlegel-Ausgabe [=KFSA]. Vol. I. Ed.Ernst Behler.Paderborn et al.: Schöningh, 1979. 19–33. Schlegel, Friedrich. “ZurPhilosophie” [1797]. KFSA. Vol. XVIII. Ed. Ernst Behler.Paderborn et al.: Schöningh,1963. 79–117. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Über Goethes Meister” [1798]. KFSA. Vol. II. Ed.Hans Eichner.Paderborn et al.: Schöningh,1967.126–146. Trans.: “On Goethe’s Meister.” Classic and Romantic German Aesthetics. Ed.J.M. Bernstein. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversityPress, 2003. 269–286. Schlegel, Friedrich. “Über die Unverständlichkeit” [1800]. KFSA. Vol. II. Ed.Hans Eichner. Paderborn et al.: Schöningh,1967.363–372. Steiner,Uwe. “Kritik.” Benjamins Begriffe. Eds. Michael Opitz and Erdmut Wizisla. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2000.479–523. Szondi, Peter. “Friedrich Schlegel unddie romantische Ironie. Mit einer Beilageüber Tiecks Komödien.” Schriften II. Eds. Jean Bollack et al. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1978. 11–31. Trans.: “Friedrich Schlegel and Romantic Irony, with Some Remarks on Tieck’sComedies.” On Textual Understanding and Other Essays. Trans. Harvey Mendelsohn. Manchester: Manchester UniversityPress, 1986. 57–73. Wizisla, Erdmut (Ed.). Brechtund Benjamin:Denken in Extremen. Exhibitioncatalogue. Berlin: Suhrkamp, 2017.

Walter Benn Michaels Historicism’sForms: The Aestheticsof Critique

In 1989,inanessaycalled “The History of the Anecdote: Fiction and Fiction,” Joel Fineman undertook an analysis of what he called “The formal operation of the an- ecdote, understood as aspecific literary genre” (Fineman1989,50) and thus also of what he called “the characteristic writing practice of the ‒ those essays thatbegin with an anecdote” (64). Fineman’sinterest was in the way that the foregrounding of the anecdote (his example was Stephen Greenblatt) took up aproblem that had been central to historiographysince its beginning,inThucy- dides, wherethe problem of how to locate the anecdote –“the narration of asingle event” that “uniquelyrefers to the real” (56) ‒ in some “logic of sequential and tran- sitional necessity” (53) was, he argued, first posed. Andthe central point of his essay was to assert the aporetic relation between the anecdote’sclaim on the real and the logic of transition, the wayinwhich the anecdote’sopening to “contingency” is, he says,closed off by its opposite, the “transitional necessity” that givesit“historical significance” (53). Twoyears later,inthe “Theory” chapter of Postmodernism,Fredric Jameson also undertook an analysis of what he called not the “writing practice” but the “writing convention” or “aesthetic” (Jameson 1991, 188) of the new historicism and he too fo- cused on the question of transition while saying nothing,however,about the anec- dote. ForJameson, the problem in new historicism was not exactlyhow to getfrom the anecdotetothe largerhistorical narrative, it was how to construct arelation be- tween literarytexts and what he called the analyses of “adazzling heterogeneity of rawmaterial” (“medicine, gambling, land tenure, masochism, slavery,photography, contracts” etc.) (193) without producing such anarrative – without astory about how one thing caused the other or was about the other.And the new historicist aesthetic, in which “Elegance[…]consists in constructingbridgepassages between the various concrete analyses,transitions […]inventive enough to preclude the posing of theoret- ical or interpretive questions” (188) was its solution to this problem, its wayofrefus- ing or avoiding the “theoretical” question of how these analyses were connected. Forthe purposes of avolume on poetic critique,myinitial interest here is in the idea ‒ taken usefullyfor granted in boththese texts – that amodeofcriticism might be said to have an aesthetic. So we do not have to worry about making it poetic, it already(for betterorfor worse)is. But my more basic interest is in the idea thattran- sition is the formal problem the new historicismisseen to confront or the solution it is seen to deploy.And that interest,Ishould confess,isinpart personal – since it was mainlythe question of transitions in my book TheGold Standard and the Logic of Naturalism that Jameson was interested in and since it seems to me that re-raising that question might help me understand something afew people have

OpenAccess. ©2021 Walter BennMichaels, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the CreativeCommons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-011 146 Walter Benn Michaels

asked me about and that Ihaveasked myself – the relation between the Gold Stand- ard’s1987account of the work of art as entirelyembeddedinits culture and having thereforenocritical distance from it and TheBeauty of aSocial Problem’saccount (in 2015) of art as providing just the kind of opportunity for critical understanding that TheGold Standard deniedart could or did do (cf. Michaels 1987and Michaels 2015). And if, with respect just to thosetwo books, this question is at most of limited inter- est,ithas, Ithink, amoregeneral application. Forif, as we have alreadyseen, the new historicism was understood right from the start to have an aesthetic, that aes- thetic should also be understood to have ahistory.And we can very quicklyidentify what will provetobeone salient aspect of that history by noting that the moment of the new historicism’semergence was the moment also of the emergenceofneoliber- alism and the take-off point in the U.S. for the new economic inequality.1968 was the most equal year on record; the Gini coefficient (0 is perfect equality; 1, one household has everything)was .38; by 1983, whenthe first issue of Representations (at the time a kind of foundingorgan of the new historicism) appeared, it had risen to alittle over .41; in 2018, it was .49, the highest ever recorded (so far). Of course, to characterize the rise in economic inequality as belonging to the his- tory of an aesthetic might in itself seem problematic – just another exercise in the of suspicion which (no doubt because it never existed) has been essen- tial to the rise of postcritique. But thereare also more interesting objections. Think of Adorno criticizingBenjamin for his “tendencytorelate”–“immediatelyand perhaps even causally”–some of the “features” of Baudelaire’swork “to adjacent features in the social history of his time, preferablyeconomic features” (Adorno 1980,128–129). What would it mean to “relate” formal features of the new historicistaesthetic (the anecdote, the transition) “immediately” to an adjacent feature of our social history like the redistribution of income upwards thatbegan in the late 70s? The possibility of answering this question – in “perhaps even causally,” Ican feel my own as well as Adorno’sfear of base and superstructure! – is further complicated by the fact that probablynone of the Berkeley new historicists was the slightest bit aware of the supposedlydeterminative economic event that was taking place. So any account of its relevancetothem would have to contend with theirignorance of it.But the interest in trying to raise it again is intensified by the fact that at least one of the formal features,the transition, can be understood, as Jameson had alreadybegun to suggest,asawayoftrying not to raise it.Onhis account,nothing is more character- istic of the new historicist aesthetic thanjuxtapositions of literary features like Frank Norris’sMcTeague being both aminer and adentist (two professions intertwined by the fact that the miner takes gold out of the earth to put it into circulation, whereas the dentist takes gold out of circulation to put it into people’smouths) with economic ones like the political battlesoverwhether the U.S. should stick to the gold standard or monetize silver(with its default consensus on the necessity of money with “intrin- sic” value as opposed to dollarbills with none). And then with the effort to put both the dentist and the gold-buginto relation with the popularity of trompe l’oeil paint- ing (which seeks to describe representational paintingsas, like dollar bills, aform of Historicism’sForms: The AestheticsofCritique 147

deception) and with the fact thatTrina McTeague is amiser about whom it is impos- sible to tell whether her love of money depends upon denying its status as arepre- sentation or fetishizingits status as arepresentation. How can we theorize the con- nection between trompe l’oeil paintersand hard money Democrats, much less the connection of anyofthemtothe novel? The crucial thing for Jameson is what is not said: it is not said (in fact,itisex- plicitlydenied) thatthe novel is about the gold standard and no theory of mediation that might explain how one could connect up the practice of dentistry with the vogue for acertain kind of painting,orpamphlets on freesilvertonovels that never even mention it is ever proffered. Indeed, as Jameson says, “elegance” consists in not pro- viding these things. Moregenerally, there’snoaccount of what makes one historical context morerelevant than another to the literarytext – which is the problem that Fineman understands the anecdotetodeconstruct.Rather the very idea of the rela- tion between text and context seems to be refused and replacedbythe effort to pro- duceacriticism in which history figures but preciselynot as context,not as akind of explanatory background. In this criticism there is no background and not much in the wayofexplanation either – everything is foreground, and is made relevant by the mode of presentation rather than by some theoretical justification. So, why? What was the attraction of that aesthetic?One answer would be that it works to provewhat was widelytaken (not least by the new historicists themselves) to be the new historicist point – thatall these phenomena are so equallyapart of capital’s dispositif thatitmakes no sense to selectone of them – literature – and con- fer on it adistinctively oppositional potential. Jameson generouslysaysthat when the transitions work, the reader is left with “asense of breathlessness, of admiration for the brilliance of the performance, but yetbewilderment,atthe conclusion of the essay, from which one seems to emerge with empty hands ‒ without ideas and inter- pretations to carry away with us” (Jameson 1991, 188), apoint that in arecent issue of American LiteraryHistory is put with less charity but equal accuracy by Francesca Sawaya when she refers to TheGold Standard in particularas“exasperatingly tauto- logical and deterministic” (Sawaya2019,305). Thetautology – the dentist is the miser is the trompe l’oeil painter ‒ is what youget instead of the interpretation. On this account,whether youare left breathless or exasperated, what youare being told is that art cannotproduce areflection on capitalism, it can onlyparticipate in it (that would be also the ). ForJameson, however,itisthe tautological transitions that matter rather than the thesis they are supposed to serve. In fact,hefocuses on the aesthetic precisely because he regardsthe thesis as of secondary interest – it is apretext for producing the transitions, for motivating “the device” (Jameson 1991, 189). Hence, the question we just asked – what is the attractionofthe transitions? – cannot be answered by invoking the argument they are supposed to prove. How,then, can it be answered?Fineman reads the transition as aproblem, not a solution. The appeal of the anecdoteisinits ability to “produce the effect of the real” (Fineman 1989,61) (whichiswhat history demands) but,insofarasthe real is iden- 148 Walter Benn Michaels

tified with what he calls “the occurrenceofcontingency” (61), the anecdotedisrupts what history also demands – a “logic of sequential and transitional necessity” (53). Hence, he thinks, there is afundamental discrepancy between the “experience of his- tory” (53) as offered by the anecdoteand the “estranged distance from the anecdotal real” (63) required by the logic of historicism, and the power of the anecdoteispre- ciselythe problem it produces: it resists transition – it marks the moment in the con- stitution of what he calls the “subjectofhistory” (62) that is transcended but not fullysubsumable by the “logic” (53) of historicism. But Jameson’sproof text (TheGold Standard)invokes the “logic,” not the “sub- ject” of its history,and the juxtaposition with Fineman helps us to seethat what it was resisting(what made the tautology ‒ this is this,asopposed to this explains this or this leads to this ‒ attractive)was preciselywhat Fineman valued. Fineman valued the disruption of the relation between text and context because it was in that disruption that the subject’sexperience of the real emerged – the moment before contingency is subsumed by historicalnecessity,the moment when youcannot say whythis is the right context in which to understand that,why this event is the back- ground thathelps us understand this text in the foreground. By contrast, TheGold Standard sought not to disrupt the relation between text and context but to iron out the differencebetween them, so that therewould be no foreground or back- ground, which is to say, no position from which some thingslookedcloser and others fartheraway, which is to saynopoint of view,which is to say, no subject.IfFineman thoughtthathistory’slogic condemned youtoan“estranged distance from the anec- dotal real,” what TheGold Standard wanted from naturalism’slogic was neither dis- tance nor proximity (which after all are both positions of the subject). It wanted not the non-existencebut the irrelevanceofthe subject. Thus we have two versions of new historicist aesthetics, and although neither is in anyway current today, it is not hard to see that Fineman’scommitment to the sub- ject – albeit in adomesticated and completelymoralized form – has flourished.In- deed, at the heart of what we now call postcritique is aversion of that commitment so completeitrequires us to treat everything as at least what Latour calls a “quasi- subject” (Latour 2014,5–6) and hence, in Rita Felski’swords, to put “people, ani- mals, texts and thingsonasimilar ontological footing” (Felski 2015,184) in order to “emphasiz[e] their interdependence” (164) and thus “the agencyofboth texts and readers” (165). And if, at the root of this ontological egalitarianism is Latour’s studied obliviousness to the difference between natural and non-natural signs (to use aGricean example, the difference between the waythe spots on your face mean measles and the waythe phonemes “measles” mean measles¹), its real rele-

 Perhapsstudied obliviousness is not quiteright,sincethe main point of Latour’sidea of agencyis that it is supposed to call into question distinctions likethe one between natural and non-natural signs. Sometimes he does this by insistingthat meaningis“aproperty of all agents” (Latour 2014, 13) and thus central to both (which is uncontroversiallytrue: “measles” means measles;spots mean measles); sometimes he does it by suggestingthat the “word”“meaning”“be dropped altogeth- Historicism’sForms: The Aesthetics of Critique 149

vancefor my purpose is not this conceptual confusion in itself but the waythe actor- network theory it enables underwrites,for Felski, amodel of the social thatbegins with the “sociologyofthe individual” and “ways of thinkingabout individuals” that do not “flattenand reduce them” (Felski 2015,171‒172). There is akind of aesthetic at work here too, not so much in the writing perhaps as in the expression of taste – what Felski wantsisaworld made up of the novel’s round characters,those who, in ahumanisticversion of Fineman’sinsistenceon “contingency,” embodywhat E.M. Forster called “the incalculability of life” (Forster 1956,78) and what Felski calls “the ever-present possibilityofbeing surprised” (Fel- ski 2019).² Thus, for example, as against a “melancholic Marxism” that sees “eco- nomic interests” everywhere, she praises what she thinks of as sociology’smoreLa- tourian concept of “society” as “highlyvariegated and differentiated, made up of manykinds of institutions, communities,norms and behaviors.” And against what she takes to be tooeasy acommitment to “the languageofstructure,” she complains that Leavisites did not and Marxist literarycritics (all nine of them) do not think about “how structure is to be defined” or “what kind of analytical work it does” (Fel- ski 2019). But here the very crudest possibleanalytical work Marxism does – understand society in terms of capital and labor ‒ is of some use. Postcritique’spicture of the social is the intersubjective (or,touse one of Felski’spreferred terms, the “relation- al”), which is also the neoliberal picture and is, in fact,its therapy for anymembers of the workingclass who might have been made alittle melancholic by the rising inequality Imentioned above. The treatment is just to understand that in political economythere reallyisnosuch thing as the workingclass. Indeed, from Foucault’s analysis of how the concept of human capital turnsthe worker into acapitalist (and thus turns his salary into areturn on thatcapital) to the Uber contractthat operation- alizes Foucault’sanalysis by turning employees into “independent contractors,” a crucial feature of neoliberalism has been its commitment to making the structural – structural instead of relational, instead of intersubjective ‒ antagonism between capital and labor disappear.Itthus replacesthe problem of structural injustice – ex- ploitation – with an array of individual injustices (as variegated and differentiated as intersectional analysis can make them), but all marchingunder the banner of dis- crimination. Theoretical sophistication here consists preciselyininfinitelymultiply-

er” and that we talk instead about “path-building,ororder-making, or creation of directions” instead, which relieves us fromhaving “to specify if it is languageorobjects” we areanalyzing and endows “things” with the “dignity of texts” while “elevating” texts “to the ontological status of things” (La- tour 1996,10). But,whichever words we use and whoever gets to be the most dignified, the difference between the spots (which areasymptom) and the word (which is aname) remains. As the fact that usingthe word does not require us to be sick whilehavingthe spots does reminds us.  Forthe complete quote, see Forster 1956,78: “The test of around character is whether it is capable of surprisinginaconvincingway […]. It has the incalculability of life about it ‒ life within the pages of abook.” 150 Walter Benn Michaels

ing the number of subjectpositions anyofusmight occupy,while at the sametime guaranteeingthat they are just that – positions of the subject.And the success of this program is demonstrated every time someone insists, for example, that the tension between aclass politics and an identity politics is specious because class is an iden- tity too.³ Felski herself was an earlyadopter of class as identity(albeit a “negative” one) in her important (and fun to read) article “Nothing to Declare: Identity,Shame, and the Lower Middle Class” (Felski 2000). Here, her focus “on the psychicaswell as the so- cial, as much as ” (34) is presented as amethodological rather than an ontological commitment.But actor-network theory would do for literary criticism what intersectionality has done for politics – takethe idea of an essentially impersonal structure right out of it.Inthis respect,itisstriking that all the different versions of postcritique especiallyhaveitinfor Jameson, who keeps seeing not class identity,but class struggle in texts whereitdoes not belong.And it is striking also that what Felski calls “everyday” reading and especiallythe kind of readingthat goes on in the classroom provide her with an alternative model for interpretation as “the coproduction between actors” (12). Youdonot have to be avery suspicious reader to notice that for universityprofessors teaching our studentsthe relationalvir- tues of what Latour calls “the care for phenomena”–sympathy, empathy, recogni- tion – is redescribable (or reallyjustdescribable) as teachingthe sons and daughters of the upper class the responsibilities appropriate to the beneficiaries of the class system: how to appreciate their agencyand use it humanely, how to exercise the priv- ilegeofchecking their privilege.⁴ Obviously, using our privilegehumanelyisavirtue (the alternative is Trump), but,also obviously, it is away of living with inequality,not combattingit, of keepingthe essential antagonism of class out of the classroom as well as out of the textsweread in that classroom. The point here is not that postcri- tique is apolitical; it is rather that it is liberal, the professoriat’scontribution to mak- ing sure that our wealthystudentsdonot understand the system that has made them

 Acharacteristicinstancewould be Peter Frase (2014) acknowledgingthat class is “astructural re- lation,” but onlytoremind us that it is “also an identity.” Which is to say, it also “exists in its socio- logical sense,” which means – and here his relief at having made it to neoliberal highground is al- most palpable ‒ that “Classism is areal phenomenon” and that we should combat “classist attitudes.”  The most recentfigures show that 80%ofstudents from the topquintile of wealth enroll in 4-year institutions, while students from the lowest quintile mainlyenroll in two-year community colleges or in for profits;only28% find their wayto4-year colleges (see https://www.insidehighered.com/news/ 2019/05/23/feds-release-broader-data-socioeconomic-status-and-college-enrollment-and-completion). When Felski teaches undergraduate classes at Virginia, twothirds of her students arefromthe top 20%(https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/projects/college-mobility/university-of-virginia) (13 March 2020). Historicism’sForms: The AestheticsofCritique 151

wealthy, and that their conception of social justiceremains fixed on technologies of individualization: equalityofopportunity,meritocracy,social mobility.⁵ Which is not to saythat if we return to our original textsand our founding mo- ment,the situation was much different.Actually, from this point of view,the new his- toricism was alreadyakind of crucial first stepinthe wrong direction. Catherine Gal- lagher (the othernew historicistnamed by Jameson and writing in the sameyear as Fineman) explicitlyand acutelydisarticulates new historicism from what Marxism thoughtofas“the one conflictthat counted: class conflict” (Gallagher 1989,40) and connects it instead to the New Left,which she characterizes as “invoking the principle of individual and group [rather than class] liberation,” and which she iden- tifies as emerging out of “the problem of the constitution of the subject” (41) as re- formulated in what wasincreasinglycalled post-Marxism. And TheGold Standard is no exception to this rule: although the wordclass appears with some frequency in it, the concept of class (much less class struggle) is pretty much absent.Infact,we could saythat the thematics of the text – the impossibilityorirrelevance of acertain resistance, as embodied in apassagelike the following – preciselyexemplify its pre- occupation with what Gallagher calls “the constitution of modern subjectivity” (46).

Dreiser didn’tsomuch approveordisapproveofcapitalism; he desired pretty women in little tan jackets with mother-of-pearl buttons, and he fearedbecomingabum on the streets of New York. These fears and desireswerethemselvesmade available by consumer capitalism, partlybecause acapitalist economymade it possible for lower class women to wearniceclothes and for mid- dle-class men to lose their jobs,but moreimportantlybecause the logic of capitalism linked the loss of jobs to afailure of self-representation and linked the desirability of those women to the possibilityofmimesis.Carrie is desirable, in this reading, because she herself desires –“to re- produce life,” to makeherself intoarepresentation.And this insatiable appetitefor representa- tion Dreiser identifies with sexual promiscuity,corporategreed, and his own artistic practice. (Michaels 1987, 19)

This is preciselythe kind of claim about the inescapability of the marketthat every- one – includingme–thought of as the main new historicist point.And it is not ex- actlyfalse. As long as youwerelooking for resistance to capitalism in the subject of capitalism, youwerenever going to find it.But if we understand the new histori- cism’saesthetics (the aesthetics of the bridge passagebetween concrete instances that turns explanation into tautology)asarefusal of text and context,ofpoint of view,and thus of the subject,then we can see that refusal as aplaceholder precisely

 One reader of this texthelpfullyobjected that it is unfair to single out postcritique in this waysince the same criticism could be made of virtuallyeverythingdone in the humanities at American univer- sities,oratleast everythingexcept Marxist criticism. Iagree! (Except that he forgottoinclude the so- cial sciences.)But Ithink it is still worth grantingacertain pride of placetopostcritique, which in its allegiance to the idea that thereis“no society” and that social analysis consists aboveall in “marvel- ing at” and “attend[ing] to” the “ongoing connections,disconnections, and reconnections between countless actors” (and their families?) (Felski 2011,578)does amuch morethoroughjob of making class structureinvisible even than intersectionality. 152 Walter Benn Michaels

for the non-intersubjective,non-relational structure of acapitalist society – for the conflict between capital and labor.Inotherwords, class is excluded from the new historicism as aconcept but gets into it as a ‘writingconvention,’ and opposition gets into it not as apolitical position but as an entailment of its conception of ‘ele- gance.’ In this respect,wecan not onlysay with Jameson thatthe polemical claim of the new historicism – the work of art’ssubsumption by the society it might be thoughttocritique – is reallythere justtomotivatethe device, we can sayalso that the device (the transitions) negates the motive.The new historicism had demon- strated, Gallagher wrote, that “the thingsintexts” which oppositional critics had hopefullyidentified as “subversive” and “destabilizing” wereinfact “inscriptions of the formative moments, not the disruptions, of the liberal subject” (Gallagher 1989,45); the aesthetic of the transition negated this demonstration not exactlyby showing that it was mistaken(there was indeed nothing oppositional about the de- stabilized subject) but by making it irrelevant. Which is not to saythatany of the Berkeley new historicists werepolitically in- teresting except insofar as we wereearlyadopters of what todaywould be called left neoliberalism,and our interest in the history of the liberal subjectwas itself acom- ponent in the making of the neoliberal subject.AsInoted above, we had no idea that we wereparticipatinginaprofound transfer of wealth from the bottom90% of the population to the top10%;our politics found expression in diversifying the western canon not in organizingafaculty union. And if youthink of politics as mainlyan expression of class interest, rightlyso. We werenot the faculty members who would need aunion; we would be more the beneficiaries of that transfer of wealth than its victims. So bothinits politics and in its intellectual commitment to the his- tory of the subject,the new historicismbelonged to that 90 %ofthe world that,as the joke goes, is perfectlyexplained by vulgarMarxism.⁶ But in its aesthetics, in its ‘writing practice,’ not so much.Inits literary critical form, vulgarMarxism – the debatesoverthe gold standard made McTeague adentist – was basicallywhat Adorno condemned as the insufficientlymediated “materialis- tic determination of culturaltraits,” and the ambition of the new historicistaesthetic was to avoid the kind of separation between the two that would make the explana- tion of the one by the other look attractive.But Adorno also thought we could bridge this gapbyrunning the whole thing through the “total social process” (Adorno 1980, 129) ‒ italics his, presumably in the spirit of “we absolutelyneed to do this although we don’tquite know how to do it and aren’tcompletelysure what it is.” One way, then,tosee the new historicism is as arecognition of the problem Adorno identified, arejection of his suggestion thatitcould onlybesolvedby“theo- ry,” and the creation insteadofanaesthetic designed not exactlytosolve it,but to make it go away.That such an effort wasbound to fail is obvious, just as the ongoing attraction to the idea that something is indeed explained by juxtaposing(but not de-

 The jokeisthat sociology is interested onlyinthe remaining10%.Hence Felski’s “sociology envy.” Historicism’sForms: The AestheticsofCritique 153

riving)our literarycritical ambitions with (not from) our economic ones is also ob- vious. Jameson said that TheGold Standard differed from “standard New Historicist practice” in its commitment to a “total” (albeit “absent”) “system,”“the market” (Jameson 1991, 212).Perhaps the relevant point here is just – Jameson’spoint – that the commitment to totality is the thing that is needed (even when youcannot totallyfigure out how it works) and that TheGold Standard’s periodic imagination of this totality as necessarily “asphyxiating” (212)was akind of sentimentalism. If that is right,then the new historicistthematic was justthe sad version of “thereisnoalternative” (postcritique would be not exactlythe happy but the mind- ful version), and it is the contradictory relation this thematic had with its aesthetic that makes new historicism interesting.Why?Because by linking the history of the subjecttothe problem of the transition, new historicism also made it possible to see the replacement of the structural by the intersubjective,the formal by the rela- tional,asaproblem, and in this, it wasitself, despite its mockery of the subversive and the oppositional, akind of critique. Even, although none of its practitionerswas aMarxist,akind of Marxist critique, and especiallybycontrast to the ways in which most of what passes for critique has in fact been as embarrassingly uncritical as post- critique is proudlyuncritical. The title of the conference for which this paper was written and of the book for which it is being revised is Poetic Critique. My ownway of understanding the “poetic” in that title has not been in terms of generic alternatives(not poetry or fiction or memoir as critique), but in terms of an aesthetic that might be made possiblein the genre of literary criticism itself. By aesthetic – following Fineman and Jameson – Ihaveobviouslymeant something other than amethodand also something more than astyle, includingaprose style. Obviously, Ihavenot meant an aesthetic instead of apolitics. But Ialsodonot mean an aesthetic as apolitics. Herewecan see the very strict limits of poetic critique – aMarxism withoutMarxists had no political fu- ture, and the lasthalf century has made it very clear that aclass aesthetic cannot do the work of aclasspolitics.

Bibliography

Adorno, Theodor. “Letters to WalterBenjamin.” Aesthetics and Politics. WithanAfterwordby Fredric Jameson. London: Verso, 1980.110‒133. Felski, Rita. “Nothing to Declare: Identity,Shame, and the Lower Middle Class.” PMLA 115.1 (2000): 33‒45. Felski, Rita. “‘ContextStinks!’” New LiteraryHistory 42.4 (2011): 573‒591. Felski, Rita. The LimitsofCritique. Chicago: University of ChicagoPress,2015. Felski, Rita. “My Sociology Envy.” Theory,Culture&Society (25 July 2019). https://www.theoryculturesociety.org/rita-felski-my-sociology-envy/ (11 December 2019). Fineman, Joel. “The History of the Anecdote: Fiction and Fiction.” The New Historicism. Ed.Harold Avram Veeser.London and New York: Routledge, 1989. 49‒76. Forster,E.M. Aspectsofthe Novel. Orlando: Mariner Books, 1956. 154 Walter Benn Michaels

Frase,Peter. “StayClassy.” Jacobin (26 June 2014). https://jacobinmag.com/2014/06/stay-classy (5 May 2019). Gallagher,Catherine. “Marxism and the New Historicism.” The New Historicism. Ed.Harold Avram Veeser.London and New York: Routledge, 1989. 37‒49. Jameson, Fredric. Postmodernism or,The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. Durham,North Carolina: Duke,1991. Latour,Bruno. “On actor-network theory. Afew clarifications plus morethan afew complications.” Soziale Welt 47.4 (1996). http:// transnationalhistory.net/interconnected/wp-content/uploads/2015/05/Latour-Actor-Net- work-Clarifications.pdf(13 March 2020). Latour,Bruno. “Agency at the Time of the Anthropocene.” New LiteraryHistory 35 (2014): 1‒18. Michaels, Walter Benn. The Gold Standard and the Logic of Naturalism. Berkeley: University of California Press,1987. Michaels, Walter Benn. The Beauty of aSocial Problem: Photography, Autonomy, Economy. London and Chicago: University of ChicagoPress, 2015. Sawaya,Francesca. “Safeguarding the Past: ‘Presentist’ Historicism.” American LiteraryHistory 31.2 (2019): 301‒311. Yi-Ping Ong Poetic Criticismand the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce,and Coetzee

It is ahot June dayinDublin, mid-afternoon. Ayoung,would-be, but as yetunknown poet lockshorns with his elders in the age-old fight for dominance. More of askir- mish than aflat bid to wrest command from the heads of the pack: this is how they see it.They keep his foraysincheck with nudgesand nips, but otherwise they tolerate him. We begin in the middle of things. Adust-cloaked office of the National Library. The Director is holding court: “And we have,havewenot,those priceless pages of Wilhelm Meister. Agreat poet on agreat brother poet” (Joyce 1986,151). On he drones, dull notes creakinginthe dim air,before he is called away by his work. As soon as he leaves, the youngpoet takes his shot: “Monsieur de la Palice […]was alive fifteen mi- nutes before his death” (151). Ajeer like this from amere underling,nomatter how light,will not be let to stand.Instantly asharp voice cracks backwith “elder’sgall”: “Have youfound those six bravemedicals […]towrite Paradise Lost at your dicta- tion? TheSorrows of Satan he calls it” (151). This last aside is directed not to the young man, but to afellow elder.Taking up his cue, the other joins in: “All these questions are purelyacademic […]. Imean,whether Hamlet is Shakespeareor JamesIor Essex. […]Art has to reveal to us ideas, formless spiritual essences.[…] All the rest is the speculation of schoolboys for schoolboys” (151). The challenge of youth to the authority of the elders is dispatched. This openingframes the episode of Joyce’s Ulysses (1918) that is best known for Stephen Dedalus’spyrotechnic and at times bizarrelyfar-fetched account of how to read Shakespeare’s Hamlet. Manycritics take his readingasaveiled guide to how Joycehimself intends Ulysses to be read. Falling exactlyatthe midpoint of the novel, there is no question that the episodeiscrucial. But if Joycehad wanted to highlight Stephen’stheory of art as akey to his own creation, whydid he stageit like this – as part of an academic pissing contest? If we lookback, to Goethe’sexecution of asimilar scene in Wilhelm Meister’sAp- prenticeship (1795–1796), and forward, to another scene in Coetzee’s Elizabeth Cost- ello (2003), we might discover further clues.All three texts exemplifywhat Schlegel calls, in his essay “On Goethe’s Meister” (1798), “poetic criticism”:awork of art that “come[s] into being when apoet in full possession of his powers contemplatesa work of art and represents it in his own” (Schlegel 2003,281). Schlegel is here de- scribing the sections of WilhelmMeister’sApprenticeship between Book 4, chapter 13 and Book 5, chapter 12 that contain Wilhelm’selaboration upon and re-staging of Shakespeare’s Hamlet. These are the samepages of Goethe’snovel that Joyce’sep- isode alludes to at its opening – an earlyhint that Joycewill set his occasion for po- etic criticism beside Goethe’s. Both texts contain areadingofHamlet. Both feature

OpenAccess. ©2021Yi-Ping Ong, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-012 156 Yi-Ping Ong

Hamlet-like protagonists who represent themselvestoothers in and through the act of readingShakespeare’splay. Finally, in Coetzee’snovel, although the performance of Elizabeth Costello focuses on Kafka’sape and not on the Prince of Denmark, Cost- ello herself is anovelist whose claim to fame lies in her re-writing of Joyce’s Ulysses from the point of view of MollyBloom. How should we read these looselyconcatenated texts of poetic criticism?This question is complicated by the fact that, in all three cases, the crucial act thatestab- lishes the work as an instance of poetic criticism is carried out by afictional charac- ter.Wilhelm’sproduction of Hamlet,Stephen Dedalus’sdazzlingperformance in the library,and Elizabeth Costello’sspeech on Kafka: all embodySchlegel’sclaim that “[p]oeticcriticism does not act as amere inscription, and merelysay what the thing is” but rather “want[s] to represent the representation anew,and form once more what has alreadybeenformed” (Schlegel 2003,281). These exemplary instan- ces of poetic criticism interpret the texts they represent by re-enacting the dynamics found in these texts.Yet these acts of poetic criticism are not stand-alone works.Each is represented within the compass of alargernarrative,one thatstages the making of the character-qua-critic as well as the conditions surroundingand inflecting their key performance. Time and time again, the art of poetic criticism accomplishes itself by wayofanovelistic form that embeds an act of critical response to another work of art within the narrative of acentral figure’slife. Whatdothese fictionsofthe livesof critics tell us about the formand meaning of poetic criticism? From its origin in “On Goethe’s Meister,” the concept of poetic criticism is inter- twined with the attempt to reorient the purpose and meaningofliterary criticism. Schlegel’sessaymarks aseminal turn in Romantic literary history,when the critic breaks freefrom his traditionalrole as “ajudge who applied neoclassical aesthetic standards,derivedmostnotablyfrom Aristotle and Horace, to the understanding and assessment of awork of art” (Norman 2018, 196). Schlegel – and, after him, No- valis,Schleiermacher,and Tieck – reenvisions the act of criticism as intimately bound up with the self-understanding of the literarywork. Criticism amplifies, re- flects, and intensifies the self-reflexive understanding that is internal to the individ- ual work of art,and as such it must itself assume a “mode of literary self-knowledge” (204). It must become, in Schlegel’sterm, poetic.Inmyinterpretation of these texts of poetic criticism, what emergesisaform of criticism as critique:criticism qua in- vestigation of the nature and limits of self-reflection. This self-understanding is por- trayed in and through the protagonists who engageinacts of literary criticism within the workoffiction. In Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee, the fictional critic encounters a profound form of self-knowledge thatisnot solelygenerative, but also potentiallyde- structive.The act of criticism does not,asSchlegel would have it,merelyamplify,re- flect,and raise self-understanding to ahigher power.Italsodeflects, avoids, and dis- avows, defending the critic from the danger and pain thatisinherent in knowing him or herself. This ambivalent tension is revelatory not onlyofthe nature of criticism, but also of the structure of fictions thatwould seek to portrayit. PoeticCriticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 157

In this essay, Iseek to renew our understandingofSchlegel’saccount of poetic criticism by re-embedding the characterological act of criticism within the more pro- saic frame in which it is originallyrepresented. The narratives of Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee all draw attention to the conditions and motivations that underlie these var- ious performances. Keyaspects of the act fall away if we attempt to theorize poetic criticism in isolation from its fictional context.The frame of fictionopensupnew questions about whyfigures such as Wilhelm Meister,Stephen Dedalus,and Eliza- beth Costello might seek to interpret and re-enlivenliterary works.These questions in turn connect the form of poetic criticism with deeper currents and tensions at playinthe fictionsthemselves. They reveal the inner conflicts that animate charac- terological acts of criticism, and illuminatethe power and significanceofthese acts anew.

1Goethe

The question of how to describe the instance of poetic criticism within its original fictional context straightawayraises an important problem, namely, how to circum- scribe the boundaries of the critical act.Isitlimited to the character’sown act of in- terpretation and re-presentation of another work of art?Orisitthe text’srepresenta- tion of this act,and if so, does the significanceofthe act ripple outward to other seemingly unrelated episodes, so thatafull consideration of its meaningwould re- quire us to trace its implications throughout the novel as awhole? Finally, does the inherentlymetafictional structure of the act attempt to breach the implicit bounded- ness of the work, and implicate the reader of the text in adeliberate way? These over- archingquestions frame the problem at hand. Setting them aside for the time being, however,let us turn to the chief paradigmofpoetic criticism in Schlegel’sseminal text.Atthe heart of his discussion lies the extended subplot of Wilhelm Meister’sAp- prenticeship,comprisingoveraquarter of the novel, in which the protagonist not onlypresents extended interpretations of Shakespeare’s Hamlet,but also produces and acts in his own version of the play. Wilhelm is franklyobsessed with Shake- speare’sgenius, pouring his heart and soul into scrutinizing the intentions of the playwright,the structure of the play, and the inner life of Hamlet.Helives and breathes the playtothe point that the reality of everything else in his life falls away.Indeed, it is at this juncturethatWilhelm makes adecisive commitment to de- vote his life to the theater. The narrative buildinguptothis climax, however,sheds asomewhat different light on the state of mind in which Wilhelm first encounters Hamlet. Shakespeare does not appearinWilhelm’slife by chance. He is planted there by Jarno, an older man upon whom Wilhelm has projected his craving for mentorship and guid- ance. The novel portrays this yearning for approval and direction as naïveand indis- criminate.Wilhelm desires recognition from justabout anyone who presents himself to be better thanthosearound him. When aprince arrivesatthe baron’scastle where 158 Yi-Ping Ong

Wilhelm’stroupe is performing,Wilhelm immediatelyseizes the opportunitytoingra- tiate himself with apotential patron. Thescene of their encounter stages an earlyact of literary criticism that is purelyinstrumental, deployed solelyfor the purposes of self-advancement:

Wilhelm had been advised to praise Racine, the prince’sfavoritedramatist,when an appropriate opportunity presenteditself, and thereby put himself in the prince’sgood graces.Hefound such an occasion one afternoon, when he had been summoned to appear with the others,and the princeasked him whether he toohad studied the great French dramatists.Wilhelm said that he had. He did not noticethat the princehad alreadyturned to speak to someone else, without waitingfor an answer.Almost interposinghimself, he claimed the prince’sattention by declar- ing that he had indeed avery high opinion of Frenchdrama and had read its masterpieceswith great appreciation; and he had been delightedtohear that the princepaid great respect to the talents of aman like Racine. “Ican well imagine,” he went on to say, “that persons of noble station will appreciateanauthor who portrays so excellentlyand correctlythe circumstances of high social rank.” (Goethe 2016,475)

Herefollows alengthyand fawningmonologue on Racine’sportrayal of “‘the gods of this earth,’” “‘kingsadored by whole nations, courtiers envied by multitudes’” (476). Wilhelm concludes his paean by noting, “‘The reportthatRacinedied of grief be- cause Louis XIV showed his dissatisfaction by no longer looking at him – that to me is the keytoall his works.Itwas impossiblefor such atalented writer,whose whole life, and his death, depended on the eyes of aking,not to write plays worthy of the admiration of aking – and of aprince’” (476). By this point,needless to say, the prince is no longer looking at Wilhelm. But Wilhelm persists. Interpreting Racine through the lens of his own desperate bid for royal attention, Wilhelm performs his critical admiration of the poet as an act of obsequious flattery to the greatness of his audience, who is in turn castasthe “‘prince’” to Wilhelm’s “‘talented writer.’” The readingofRacine becomes ameans of rendering his own self legible to another. It is at this moment that Jarno, who just so happens to have overheard the entire speech, pulls Wilhelm aside and demands, “‘Have younever seen aplaybyShake- speare?’” (476)Wilhelm admits that he has not.The playwright’sdubious reputation is, he goes on to confess,areason to keep avoiding him: “‘what Ihaveheard about his plays has not made me eager to know more about such strangemonstrosities’” (476). Cautioning him not to “‘takeoffense’” at what he reads,but rather to rely on his “‘owntrue judgment,’” Jarno sends him the plays (476). When Jarno and Wilhelm meet again, Wilhelm hastens to thankhim for his role in “providinghim with such an experience” (484). Jarnoexpresses pleasure with himself for his pedagogical insight and with Wilhelm for having the sensibility to ap- preciateShakespeare, while Wilhelm expresses his admiration of Shakespearein ever more effusive and ardent terms, assuring Jarnothat he has been as deeply moved by the poet as the older man had hoped.

“Icannot remember abook, aperson,oranevent that has affected me as deeplyasthese won- derful plays that yousokindlybrought to my attention. They seem to be the work of some spirit Poetic Criticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 159

from heaventhat comesdown to men and gentlymakes them moreacquainted with themselves. They arenot fictions! One seems to be standingbeforethe huge open folios of Fate in which the storm winds of life in all their turbulenceare raging, blowingthe pages back and forth. Iamso astonished by the forcefulness and tenderness, the violenceand the control of it all, that Iam completelybeside myself and long for the time when Iwill be able to continue reading.” (484)

“‘Bravo!’” declares Jarnoatthe end of Wilhelm’sspeech: “‘that’sjust what Iwanted; and the results thatIhoped for will not be long in coming’” (484). Both playtheir roles to perfection: caring yetsuperior guide, impassioned yetsolicitous pupil. Their exchangesets into sharp relief the livedcontext of Wilhelm’sfirst response to Shakespeare. Having longed for the favorand esteem of Jarnofrom the moment he laid eyes on him, he is finally in aposition to getthe attentionheseeks. His success in doing so is confirmed without delay. Jarno, reassured and perhaps flattered by Wilhelm’sreaction to his favorite playwright,affirmshis mentorship of the young man by making him apromise of future advancement: “‘if youare prepared to put your talents and abilities at our service […]then Iwould have an opportunity to put youinaposition which youwill not regret having occupied for atime’” (485). Wilhelm is elated. His dreams of bringing his innermost yearningstofruition in the world seem at lasttobewithin reach. Schlegeldoes not remark upon these details of the narrativeframe surrounding Wilhelm’sreadingofShakespeare. Insofar as the scene provides one of the most di- rect articulations of Shakespeare’svalue and significance within the novel as a whole, however,itbears further scrutiny. By framing Wilhelm’sencounter with Shakespeareinlight of his relation to Jarno, and furthermore ironizingthis encoun- ter by closelyjuxtaposing it with his praise of Racine to the prince, mundane and banal motivesfor readingawork of art in aparticularway at aparticular time are allowed to surface. The human situation of the critic is foregrounded.Wilhelm’sread- ing of Shakespeareappears to emerge as much out of his desperate need for guid- ance and admiration as it does from anysort of spontaneous, deep, or disinterested lovefor the work itself. Shakespeareisameans for uniting Jarno and Wilhelm. As soon as Jarno has declared his mentorship of Wilhelm, Shakespearedrops away and the real subject of their discussion emerges: “Wilhelm, extremelygrateful for this, now felt in the mood to tell his friend and benefactorhis whole life story” (485). Thus Wilhelm’sreadingofShakespeareopens inevitably into the life story of Wilhelm, which of course the novel tells better than Wilhelm could ever tell him- self. Whydoes Goethe’sluminous act of poetic criticism congeal around the dull ker- nel of Wilhelm’spersonal ambition?Without casting anysuspicion on Goethe’suse of Shakespeare, which relies on acomplex metafictional stagingofthe relation be- tween mimesisand existence, it is fair to saythat Wilhelm’suse of Shakespearein 160 Yi-Ping Ong

this initial encounter is somewhat less subtle.¹ Wilhelm appears entirelytobelieve, or to have convinced himself, in the transformative powers of Shakespearean plays. But if Jarnohad asked him to read anynumber of playwrights, his response would no doubt have been as adulatory.Just as in his previous encounter,inwhich he “would gladly have gone on talking and proved to the prince that he had read the prince’sfavorite poet with profit and emotional involvement” (476), so too would he have generated aresponse to anypoet marked as Jarno’sfavorite in the terms that he thinks Jarnowould wish to hear.What might appearasanardent,spontane- ous critical response when taken in isolationishence revealed by the narrativeframe to be highlyconditioned by the structural position of the critic. The trope of self-advancement continues to figureprominentlyinthe scenes that stageWilhelm’sextended commentary on and performance of Hamlet. His early identification with the role of Hamletappears to arise from the samedesire to affili- ate himself with nobility.Inhis reconstruction of Hamlet’sformative years prior to the death of his father,Wilhelm lays inordinate stress on the marks of Hamlet’saris- tocracy:

“This sensitive,noble scion, this flower of kingship, grewupunder the immediateinfluences of majesty;concepts of right and of princelydignity,the sense of what is good and whatisseemly, developed in him simultaneouslywith an awareness of beingborn into high station. He was a prince, he was born aprince, and he was desirous of rulingsothat good men should be unim- peded in the exercise of goodness. Winsome in appearance, courteous by nature, pleasingby temperament,hewas fashioned to be amodel of youth and adelight for everybody.” (500)

The fact that Wilhelm himself desires to achieveand to be regarded in terms of this noble ideal is made clear by the letter that Wilhelm writestoWerner, in the chapter immediatelypreceding the episodesinwhich he embarksonthe production of Ham- let in earnest.Inhis letter,Wilhelm lays out his view of the differencesbetween the nobleman and the burgher.For the nobleman, the full development and expression of personality is in harmonywith the public nature of his role, whereas for the burgh- er,personal developmentisdeformed by the necessity of developing his talents and knowledge for material profit.Explaining his choice to become an actor,Wilhelm writes to Werner: “‘Ihaveanirresistible desire to attainthe harmonious development of my personality such as was deniedmebymybirth […]. On the stageacultured human being can appear in the full splendor of his person, justasin theupper classes of society.There, mind and bodykeep stepinall one does, and there Iwill be able simultaneouslytobe and to appear better than anywhereelse’” (547– 548).² The letter elides acrucial fact.The newlyinherited fortune that makesWil-

 Foranaccount of the metafictional significanceofGoethe’srepresentation of actinginthe produc- tion of Hamlet,see Pirholt2012, 46–50.  Christian Garve’s Über die notwendigen Grenzen beim Gebrauch schöner Formen (1792),cited in a footnoteofSchiller’s1795essay On the NecessaryLimits of the Beautiful, especially in the Presentation of Philosophical Truths,isconsidered by scholars to have been aprobable source for “Goethe’streat- Poetic Criticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 161

helm’snew career possible derivesentirely from the bourgeois labor of his dead fa- ther. This, then,isthe context in which Wilhelm pursues his readings and re-staging of Hamlet. Believing thatinner refinement of spirit and taste will enable him to tran- scend the bondsofclassidentity,hecannot admit that he is tied to aprofession de- pendent upon noble patronage,let alone funded by the wealth of asocial class that he despises. Wilhelm is in abind.Hecannot be who he wants to be. But he cannot stop himself from wanting to be it.His inner conflict,revolving around issues of self- realization and external determination, in turn inflects his readingofShakespeare’s play. Wilhelm’sHamlet is too pure for actuality,beset by adestinyhecannot control. Like the prince of his imaginative reconstruction, Wilhelm is avulnerable young man who doesn’tquite know how to carveapath for himself in the world. His dependence on others does not square with his aspiration to be an artist,free, transcendent of petty need. What he needstowork out is how to bypassthis paradoxofhis situation – namely, the requirement that,onthe one hand, he perform himself as totallyfree and disengaged from the world (recall Jarno’sdirections to Wilhelm on how to read Shakespeare: “‘youcould not employ your time better thanbydisassociating your- self from everythingelse and,inthe solitude of your ownroom,peering into the ka- leidoscope of this unknown world’” [476]), and that, on the other hand,hesimulta- neously come to terms with the reality of being conditioned by his fundamental dependency.This paradox, which eventuallycomes to embodythe central conflict of the Bildungsroman between striving for autonomyand acceptance of heteronomy, is not here resolvedbywhat Franco Moretti calls the “interiorization of contradic- tion” (Moretti 1987, 10) but rather by its exteriorization in drama. Wilhelm’sreading of Hamlet’spersonality discloses afurther aspect of his psy- chologythat has not been widelyemphasized by previous critics. Wilhelm is often taken to be describing himself when he sets out “‘the key to Hamlet’swhole behav- ior’” (Goethe 2016,518). But what,exactly, is this key?When Wilhelm elucidates the “‘fine,pure, noble and highlymoral person,’” who “‘devoid of that emotional strength that characterizes ahero, goes to pieces beneath aburden thatitcan neither support nor cast off,’” it is not immediatelyclear what his own burden might be. In- deed, the burden that he contends with throughout the novel is not presented in the form of anyweighty external responsibility towards others, but rather in the knowl- edge of who he is: aknowledge that he cannot avow without imploding the fragile structure of his very self. As in Shakespeare’s Hamlet,the “‘oak tree planted in apre- cious pot which should onlyhaveheld delicate flowers’” must be controlled, mas- tered, and overcome by the greater vessel of the work of art that surrounds and con- tains it,while at the sametime exposing via the character life it portrays its own vulnerability to the power and forceofwhat has taken root in it.

ment of the rolethat art and the aesthetic might playinthe attempt of the Bürger to rise in the socio- culturalscale” (Wilkinson and Willoughby 1968, 103). 162 Yi-Ping Ong

The nature of poetic criticism is hence inextricablylinked to the nature and lim- its of the self-understanding that the work of artcan tolerate within itself. “‘Hisfeel- ing of insignificance,’” says Wilhelm of Hamlet, “‘never leaveshim’” (517). The sol- ution thatWilhelm arrivesatisembodied in every line of his interpretation and reenactment of Hamlet. In the act of re-writing and acting,thus dying, within the play, he solvesthe dilemma of whether to be HamletorShakespearebybeing both. He realizes his childhood dream of being in the playand outside of it at once, splitting his desires for total control and total immersive transport,shielding himself from the compromises and banality of life that the narrative in which he is embedded shows all too readily. Is his attempt at self-deliverance successful? Per- haps that is the wrong question. At the close of Book V, after the all-consumingpro- duction of Hamlet is staged, afire breaks out in the house whereheisliving,anac- tress dies of abroken heart,and Wilhelm sets off on new adventures.

2Joyce

Seen in light of the largernarrative frame that surrounds it,itisdifficult to under- stand how Wilhelm’sreadingofShakespearemight be attributed to the novel’sau- thor in anystraightforwardway.Yet this was the dominantview throughout the nine- teenth century,and it is announcedassuch in the opening of the libraryscene of Joyce’s Ulysses. The episode begins with an unnamed voice uttering the lines we have alreadyquoted: “And we have,havewenot,those priceless pages of Wilhelm Meister. Agreat poet on agreat brother poet” (Joyce 1986,151). The speaker who in- vites us to see Wilhelm as articulatingGoethe’sown stance on Hamlet is significantly not Stephen Dedalus,but rather Thomas Lyster,director of the National Library of Ireland in Dublin between 1895 and 1920.Along with John Eglinton, bornWilliam Kirkpatrick Magee and anointed by Yeats as “our one Irish critic,” and George Wil- liam Russell, a “prophet,poet,philosopher,artist, journalist,economic theorist” (Gif- ford and Seidman 2008, 35) known as AE, his is avoice of established authority throughout the episode.These titans,gatekeepers of Ireland’sliterary scene, mark their turf with ease. The young poet must be subdued – always with laughter and wit,for alight touch shows mastery – but nonetheless, made to know his place in the hierarchy. The scene in the library thus reveals that Stephen must deliverhis famous inter- pretation of Shakespearebetween the gaps of another conversation, one from which he is left out.His audience is more preoccupied with displaying their ownintelli- gence and bolstering one another’segosthan they are with paying heed to a young upstart.Stephen is time and again made conscious of his exclusion. As they natterawayabout their gatherings – this evening at George Moore’shouse to celebrate the work of new poets, the Hermetic Society on Thursday – they hardly even notice thatheisthere, much less wanting to be recognized. They single out oth- ers of his generation for praise and advancement,all the while overlookinghim: PoeticCriticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 163

YoungColum and Starkey.George Roberts is doingthe commercial part.Longworth will give it a good puff in the Express. O, will he? Iliked Colum’s Drover. Yes, Ithink he has that queer thing genius.Doyou think he has genius really? Yeats admired his line: As in wild earth aGrecian vase. Did he? Ihope you’ll be abletocometonight.Malachi Mulligan is coming too. Moore askedhim to bring Haines.(Joyce1986,158)

Stephen thinks to himself as he listens to them: “Cordelia. Cordoglio. Lir’sloneliest daughter” (158). Cordelia, KingLear’sdispossessed youngest daughter; Cordoglio, Italian for “deep sorrow”;and Fionnuala, daughter of the Irish sea god, Lir,whose place was usurped by his son: this net of allusions places Stephen in aconstellation of loss,tragic rivalry,and exclusion (Gifford and Seidman 2008, 215). Stephen feels that his genius, such as it maybe, is unrecognized by his audience. But the scene drawsour attention to something else. What is at stake for him in the library is not apurelyintellectual need for esteem, but something much more viscer- al: the need of apup to be chosen and mentored by the alphas,soastoensure his survival and the continuance of his progeny.Inhis case, the offspring are intellectu- al: “Coffined thoughts around me, in mummycases, embalmedinspice of words. […] And Iheard the voice of that Egyptian highpriest” (Joyce 1986,159).The walls of the National Library that surround him are astark reminder of what it means to exist in this world, aliterary world into which he wishes to gain entrée. Here each thought that survivesisentombed, granted immortality,because real people with egos and institutional power elect to valorize, preserve, and sustain it. But Stephen is not in favorwith the highpriests. He is reduced to an attendant,a suppliant,intheir temple. He must bow and scrape to beg GeorgeRussell to deliver Deasy’sletter to the editor of the IrishHomestead. He must sayhis own views “super- politely” (152). He must watch silentlyasrivals are promotedabovehim (“They make him welcome” [162],hethinks when his companion and antagonistBuck Mulligan enters). And always,hemust offer his submission and deference –“Flatter.Rarely. But flatter,” he thinks, as he works agratifying allusion to Eglinton’swork into his speech and watches the older man’sface “quick with pleasure, look[] up shybright- ly” (171). The playwithin the play, then, is more than apretext for Stephen to delivera readingofShakespearethat sheds light on the novel in which it is implanted. Let us return for amoment to Lyster’scharacterization of Goethe on Shakespeareat the opening of the chapter: “Agreat poet on agreat brother poet.” Stephenargues that for Shakespeare, brothers are rivals and usurpers. Poets are opportunistic sello- uts, willingtocurry favorwith those in power if it might lead to aconsolidation of their worldlyposition. What, then, are great poets? Stephen’sShakespeareisaman whose late tragedies are fueled by crisisand misery:grief at the loss of his son, bitterness at the unfaithfulness of his wife with his ownbrother.But he is also acontriver, achancer,aman without scruples in near single-minded pursuit of social and financial gain. As Stephenputs it, “his 164 Yi-Ping Ong

name is dear to him, as dear as the coat and crest he toadied for” (172).The bard, he alleges, is “lead[] astray” by “the sense of property” (168):

He drew Shylockout of his own long pocket.The son of amaltjobber and moneylender he was himself acornjobber and moneylender,with ten tods of corn hoarded in the famine riots. […]He sued afellowplayerfor the price of afew bagsofmaltand exactedhis pound of flesh in interest for every money lent.How else could Aubrey’sostler and callboy getrich quick?All events broughtgrist to his mill. Shylock chimes with the jewbaitingthat followed the hangingand quar- teringofthe queen’sleech Lopez […] Hamlet and Macbeth with the coming to the throneofa Scotch philosophaster with aturn for witchroasting.The lost armada is his jeer in Love’sLabour Lost. His pageants,the histories, sail fullbellied on atide of Mafekingenthusiasm.(168)

The keen instinct that turns his art like asail in response to the winds of his royal patrons’ whims, and every transaction to his ownadvantage – from whenceisthis born?Stephen givesnoaccount.The elision is all the morecurious,since Shake- speare’sbiographer George Brandes, who is cited by Stephen throughout the epi- sode, statesexplicitlythat “it was [Shakespeare’s] constant ambition to restorethe fallen fortunesofhis family” (Brandes 1898, 166),after seeing his father imprisoned for debt and stripped of his position as Alderman in his youth (12). Accordingto Brandes, Shakespeare “never for amoment lost sight of Stratford, and […]had no soonermade afootingfor himself in London than he set to work with the definite aim of acquiringland and property in the town from which he had gone forth penni- less and humiliated. His father should hold up his headagain, and the familyhon- our be re-established” (15). The missing explanation in Stephen’sfiction of Shakespeareisnot omitted from Joyce’sfiction of Stephen. The young poet’shardships duetohis father’sfinancial troubles are detailed in APortrait of the Artist as aYoung Man.³ His debts to friends and acquaintances are enumerated meticulously throughout Ulysses. In this episode alone, he notes the pound lent to him by Russell (Joyce 1986,155), the two shillings by Fred Ryan (176), and the boots by Mulligan, to whom he owes an additional nine pounds: “His boots are spoiling the shape of my feet” (173), he thinks, looking down midwaythrough this performance. “Buy apair.Holes in my socks. Handkerchief too” (173). Financial need permeates the performance in the library,which ends not with a discussion of the intellectual or aesthetic merits of the theory but with the elders’ ruling thatStephen shall extract neither profit nor fame from it.⁴ “Idon’tsee why youshould expect payment for it,” chides Eglinton, ending their exchangeona note of personal insult: “Youare the onlycontributor to Dana who asks for pieces of silver. Then Idon’tknow about the next number.Fred Ryan wants space for an article on economics” (176). If Stephen’sperformance had been pitched at selling

 Foradiscussion of the significanceofthese hardships,see Hepburn Fall 2004–Summer 2006,197– 218.  Foranextended analysis of the relation between Stephen’sdebts and his reading of Shakespeare’s usury,see Osteen 1995,214 – 227. Poetic Criticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 165

himself or his theories to this audience, it has clearlyflopped – not because of the value of the ideas themselves, but because his reputation as adebtor has removed him from social recognition, just as it removed his own father and Shakespeare’sfa- ther before him. Critics rarelydrawattention to these aspects of the situation in which Stephen deploys his portrait of Shakespeare. The episode is read primarilyasaguide to inter- preting Ulysses as awork of art in which Joyceplaces himself as bothfather and son. The keyispresumably giveninthe climax of Stephen’sperformance, which brings together his claim that Shakespeareimprints the incidents of his life’sdrama upon his plays with aquasi-Sabellian view of Trinitarian being.This highlyabstract theory of creation holds that the poet,likethe divine “Father [who] was Himself His Own Son” (171), sublimateshimself aboveand beyond needingothers and ultimately becomes one with himself through this creation: “We walk through ourselves, meet- ing robbers, ghosts,giants, old men, youngmen, wives, widows, brothers-in-love, but always meeting ourselves” (175). The fictional frame in which this mystical is embedded, however,reinscribes Stephen within the earthlytragedy of an alien- ated, dispossessed figure, even as he asserts his aspirations to rise abovehis situa- tion through the performance that articulates it.Stephenfindsexiled heroes every- wherebecause he is excluded from the inner circle he dreams of entering. He is not in tune with the intellectual fads of his time. He likes Aristotle and not Plato. He has holes in his socks. Lonely,stricken by poverty-consciousness, he seeks an ab- stract ghostlyfather within himself because he cannot connect to his own. Hisread- ing of Shakespeareisconfirmation of his own orphanhood and alienation, even as it attempts to transcend it. Stephen’sarticulation of his theory of creation is immediatelypreceded by the strangest tangent in his entire performance. Fatherhood,heabruptlydeclares after noting thatShakespearewrote Hamlet in the months afterhis father’sdeath, is “founded […][u]pon uncertitude, upon unlikelihood” (170). Paternity is but “a legal fiction” (171). There is no paternal correlate to the undeniable physical bond of mother and child – afather onlyknows himself to be afather by his marriagecer- tificate. Fathers and sons are forever “sundered by abodilyshame” (171), the shame of their disconnection. All sons, in the end, are rivals to and usurpers of theirfathers. Stephen’sdisjointedand obsessive rant culminates in his claim that the fundamental leitmotif of Shakespeare’swork is the unfaithful wife who renders her husband’spa- ternity unsure. What connects this sudden digression on paternity,which erupts seemingly out of nothing,and the aforementioned context for his lecture in the li- brary?Protection and survival, once again. No father willprotect the child born out of wedlock. But even the rightful heir is separated from the alienation and dis- placement of the bastard by the avowal of the father.Denying the defenselessness of the child in the face of the father’swhim, Stephenseeks to find the meansofse- curity and self-creation in his ownsolipsisticimagination. Publicly, he announces that “[f]atherhood, in the sense of unconscious begetting,isunknown to man” 166 Yi-Ping Ong

(170). But inwardly, what he finds unknowable in himself is the fact of his own vul- nerability and dependence upon afather who is merelyhuman. Something that the character does not want to know,toown about themselves: this is the dark seed that unfurls into the flower of poetic criticism in bothofthese novels. In Joyceand in Goethe, we find acharacter thinking about acharacter think- ing about acharacter:acharacter (Stephen Dedalus) who creates acharacter (Shake- speare) who creates acharacter (Hamlet) who stages aplaythat mirrors his own sit- uation. In each case, as Stephen himself intimates,the creation of character is a strategytoovercome ablock. The character within the frame of fictionisunder an unacknowledgedthreat or pressureofexistence. He seeks to protect himself and to advance his aims in and through this act of critical reinvention and artistic imag- ination. Yetwithin the act thereremains atrace of the fatal block: the impossibility – or as we might call it,the necessary fictionality – of overcoming it.The peculiar power and magnetism of these scenes of poetic criticism derives in part from the inner conflict of the character thatgalvanizes the act of criticism, spurring the char- acter on to generate an ever more elaboratelyramified re-presentation of the conflict, and prolonging the energy of grapplingwith its equivocal consequences. As we shall see in Coetzee’s Elizabeth Costello,the final instance of poetic criticism we shall an- alyze, this structure of intensification givesrise to akind of metafictional echo. The character returns ultimatelytothemselvesinthe form of the other-self of their invent- ed fiction.

3Coetzee

In the lecture hall of asmall American college, anovelistfrom Australia mounts the podium and unfolds her notes.Her argument meanders, confusingher listeners. Each gesture is obliquely self-canceling. She declaresherself obsessedwith the im- mortality of her books, yetnotes that the great libraries of the world that hold them will one day “‘crumble and decay’” (Coetzee 2003,17). She evokes Kafka’sape, whose performance she views as akind of “‘test,’” “‘an examination, avivavoce,’” but she deniesthatshe too is aspeakingape before an academy(18). Repeatedlyshe tests her authority to saywhat the text of Kafka’s “AReport to an Academy” means, and then justasabruptlywithdraws it: “‘That is not the point of the story,say I, who am, however in no position to dictate what the point of the story is’” (19). By wayofconclusion, she expresses her gratitude for the literary award they have be- stowed upon her work, and remindsher audience in the very same breath of the fact that she “‘will cease to be read and eventuallycease to be remembered’” (20). The applause begins, tentative at first,then rising.She smiles, savoring the moment. Just as the dean of the collegerises to announce the end of the event,avoice inter- rupts him: “‘Excuse me! […]Excuse me! Ihaveaquestion for the speaker.May Iad- dress the speaker?’” (20 –21)The novelistdoes not respond. “Frostilyshe gazes into Poetic Criticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 167

the distance” (21). The hosts are embarrassed; the would-be questioner,irked. The ceremonyends on anote of awkwardness and discord. Embedded within the openingepisodeofJ.M. Coetzee’s Elizabeth Costello,this scene stages an act of literary criticism that subverts the intended purpose of the oc- casion. Indeed, the novel’sown chapters are provocatively identifiedas“Lessons,” and several of these “Lessons” (includingthis one) wereread aloud by Coetzee in lieu of conventional lectures at academic institutions. Theperformance of fictions which themselvesstageperformed acts of criticism, often via lectures by Elizabeth Costello that explicate literaryand philosophical texts,raises several questions: the question of what it means to read atext,ofwhat it means to be instructed by one, and, moreover,ofwhat happens when our desire for instruction is supplanted by awork of fiction. Although Elizabeth Costello is often taken by critics to be amouthpiece for her author’sviews and her lecturesread as thinlyfictionalizedaccounts of his own eth- ical stance, the text itself complicates this interpretationbyframing her lectures within anarrative that bringsinto playother conflicts and energies. Costello’sperfor- mance of the lecture described aboveisembedded within anarrative of her visit to Altona College. As is also the case with Lessons 3and 4ofthe novel (delivered by Coetzee on the occasion of the TannerLectures at Princeton University,and later publishedseparatelyasTheLives of Animals), the frame narrative surroundingthe occasion for her talk is largely focalized through the eyes of her son, John. John is ayoung professor at acollegeinMassachusetts.His onlyreason for accompanying his mother on this trip to collect her prize is, he thinks, “simply to protect her” (30). But is that all?

He is herewith her,out of love. He cannot imagine her gettingthroughthis trial without him at her side. He stands by her because he is her son, her lovingson. But he is also on the point of becoming – distasteful word – her trainer.

He thinks of her as aseal, an old, tiredcircus seal. One moretime she must heave herself up on to the tub, one moretime show that she can balancethe ball on her nose. Up to him to coaxher, put heart in her,get her through the performance. (3)

It is, in John’smind, aplayinseveral acts: dinner with the jury,aninterview,aradio show,anawards ceremony, and an acceptance speech. He is present for all of them as aminor character,albeit as her loving and supportive son. Yetthe allusion in this passagetohis role as a “trainer” recalls the trainerofRed Peter in Kafka’sstory.The role is not without its occupational hazards.AsRed Peter recalls,his first trainer, driveninsane by the spectacle of the ape’sself-flagellation, “soon gave up teaching, and had to be carted off to amental hospital” (Kafka 1993, 292). Elizabeth Costello begins her speech about Kafka’s “Report” by remindingher audience of its poetic form: “‘If youknow the story,you will remember that it is cast in the form of amonologue, amonologue by an ape. Within this form thereis no means for either speaker or audience to be inspected by an outsider’seye’” (Coet- 168 Yi-Ping Ong

zee 2003,18). Herrefusal of the would-be interlocuter’squestion at the end of her speech reminds us that her appearance, too, is staged as amonologue. Kafka, in fact,composes several incomplete draft versions of “AReport to an Academy,” in which he experiments with focalizingthe narrative from various points of view: the point of view of an anonymous visitor to Red Peter,ofanaudience member who has just witnessed one of his performances,and of Red Peter’strainer, “an hon- orary doctor of great universities” (Kafka 2005,259). All of these spectatorial perspec- tivesonRed Peter – the audience member, the trainer,the visitor – fall away in the final version of “AReport.” Red Peter speaks in the first person throughout Kafka’s text,inwhich no other voices are heard.⁵ In contrast,Elizabeth Costello’sutterances are staged within anarrative that is focalized largely from the “‘outsider’seye’” (Coetzee 2003,18), furnished in this epi- sode by her son’spoint of view.His perspective on his mother is notablyambivalent. There is, of course, blind loyalty and gratitude for having been givenlife, for having been kept alive by his parent when he was at his most vulnerable and dependent. But there are alsomemoriesofabandonment,neglect,and rejection:

Forasfar back as he can remember,his mother has secludedherself in the mornings to do her writing. No intrusionsunder anycircumstances. He used to think of himself as amisfortunate child, lonelyand unloved. When they felt particularlysorry for themselves, he and his sister used to slump outside the locked door and maketinywhiningsounds.Intime the whining would change to hummingorsinging, and they would feel better, forgettingtheir forsaken- ness. (4)

Like Red Peter’schoice to seek away out of his captivity,Elizabeth Costello’schoice to seek transcendencethrough art,todevote her life to courtingthe acceptance and applause of the academy, is achoice that involves strategy,performance, and – at least from her own child’spoint of view – abetrayal of natural bonds. His memories of his mother’sworking life are colored by pain. Yetherecalls thatasheand his sis- ter’slamentations proceed from animal whiningtohuman singing, their anguish abates. What takes the place of pain is voice: voice that proceeds from akind of lone- liness, just as in Kafka’sstory.⁶ This voice even develops until the point that John joins the author within her innermost sanctum. The passageabovecontinues:

Now the scenehas changed. He has grown up. He is no longer outside the door but inside, ob- servingher as she sits, back to the window,confronting, dayafter day, year after year,while her hair slowly goes from black to grey, the blank page. What doggedness,hethinks! She deserves

 Foranextended discussion of the significanceofthe monologic voiceof“AReport,” see Ong 2016, 220 –230.  Red Peter describes the utterance of his first words in human languageasthe moment at which he enters into human society: “And then what avictory it was both for him and for me when one evening in front of alarge group of spectators […]Icurtlyexclaimed ‘Hey!’ breakingout in human sounds, plunging into human society with that cry,and feelingits echo, ‘Listen, he’stalking!’ likeakiss over my entiresweat-soaked body.” (Kafka1993, 291) Poetic Criticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 169

the medal, no doubt about that,this medal and manymore. Forvalour beyond the call of duty.(4–5)

In this changeofscene, John places himself beside the writer, his mother,but alsoin asense aboveher,inthe position of ajudge who can saywhat she deserves. He has become, in other words, acritic: one who endowsher labor with value and signifi- cance. The motif repeats throughout the narrative. At her radioshow,hewatches from “the control booth” (11); he defends her to the critic Susan Moebius, offering his own interpretation of her work; in the airport,hequestions his mother,in what is the final interview of the visit,about the meaning of her lecture. His effortstounderstand her are also, as the locus of his perspective in the con- trol boothsuggests, attemptstorewriteher from his ownpoint of view:tosee her in a wayinwhich she cannot seeherself, to know her.But why? In his own mind, he has come with her on this visit in order to protect her from the academics,the journalists, and the critics who seek to grasp the secret at the heart of her work. They dissect her utterances, invade her privacy, and continuallybait her to reveal her personal opin- ions and private experiences.Costello herself is adept at evading them: “Her strategy with interviewers is to take control of the exchange, presentingthem with blocks of dialogue thathavebeen rehearsed” (9). She controls the highlyscripted version of her authorial persona that is available for public consumption. “She can come home with her true self safe,” John thinksasthey preparetoleave the college, “leav- ing behind an image, false, like all images” (30). When the critic Susan Moebius goes so far as to question John in bed about his mother after she seduces him –“Research: will thatbeher name for it afterwards? Using asecondarysource?” he thinksasthey kiss in the hotel elevator (24) – he al- lows himself to entertain the thoughtthat perhaps his mother’sauthorial control over her imageisanillusion to protect her from the knowledge of what she is “really like”:

What is the truth of his mother?Hedoes not know,and at the deepest level does not want to know.Hehas opinions of his own, but he will not speak them. This woman, he would sayif he weretospeak, whose words you hang on as if shewerethe sibyl, is the same woman who, forty years ago, hid day after day in her bedsitter in Hampstead, crying to herself,crawling out in the evenings into the foggy streets to buythe fishand chips on which shelived, falling asleep in her clothes.She is the same woman who later stormed around the house in Melbourne, hair fly- ing in all directions,screaming at her children, ‘Youare killing me! Youare tearing the fleshfrom my body!’ (Helay in the dark with his sister afterwards, comforting her while she sobbed; he was seven; it was his first taste of fathering.) This is the secret worldofthe oracle. How can you hope to understand her beforeyou know what sheisreally like? (30 –31)

Throughout the episode, John has described himself as his mother’screation (“‘Out of her very bodyIcame, caterwauling,’” he declarestoSusan, “‘[f]lesh of her flesh, blood of her blood’” [28]) and his mother’scharacter (for “[h]e is in her books, or some of them” [5]). In this moment,however,heshows that he too has acertain au- 170 Yi-Ping Ong

thorial power: acapacity to produce this other,rival imageofhis mother.Subverting his mother’simagewith his own perspective on her,hestrips her of “her ladynovel- ist’suniform” (4), her scripted ease, her sphinx-like mystery and invulnerability.The divineauthor has amortal bodythat is exhausted, in need; abodyfrom which flesh can be torn, and in which fear of dyingand rage at being consumed by the needsof other bodies resides.Yet this power over his mother,the power to reenvision her, comes at acost.The sacred myth of mother love(what StephenDedalus calls “the onlytrue thing in life” [Joyce 1986,170]) is destroyed by John’srecollections. What emergesinits place is araging, self-centered, wounded, limited,and neglectful mother.What can she tell John of his own value and importance? Is he waiting faith- fullyfor his mother to finally receive the recognition she craves, so that she can at last turn to him and lovehim? The ambivalence of her son’sdesire – on the one hand, to recognize his mother’s vulnerability and need,and, on the other hand, to maskitbypresentingher to the world (and even to himself)asarenownednovelist whose sole ambition is immortal fame – suggests thatthe dynamics underlying the reception of these interpretive per- formances are equallyatstake in their fictional representations. At the end of her visit,John accompanies his mother on the flight home:

She lies slumped deep in her seat.Her head is sideways,her mouth open. She is snoringfaintly. Light flashes from the windows as they bank, the sun settingbrilliantlyoversouthern California. He can see up her nostrils,into her mouth, down the back of her throat.And whathecannot see he can imagine: the gullet,pink and ugly,contractingasitswallows, like apython, drawing things down to the pear-shaped belly-sac. He draws away,tightens his own belt,sits up, facing forward. No, he tells himself, that is not where Icomefrom, that is not it.(Coetzee 2003,33–34)

As theirbodies descend, spiraling,tothe ground, John’sbodyismomentarily orient- ed between the western sun to his left and his mother’sbodytoeast.The scene re- calls Kant’sessay “What does it mean to orient oneself in thinking?” (1786), in which the very possibility of cardinal orientation (and hence of the intelligibility of the world to us) is grounded in afelt bodilyintuition of the differencebetween the right and left sides of one’sbody.

In the proper meaningofthe word, to orient oneself means to use agiven direction […]inorder to find the others – literally, to find the sunrise. Now if Isee the sun in the sky and know it is midday, then Iknow how to find south, west, north, and east.For this,however,Ialso need the feelingofadifference in my own subject,namelythe difference between my right and left hands.Icall this a feeling because these twosides outwardlydisplaynodesignatable difference in intuition. If Idid not have this faculty of distinguishing, without the need of anydifferencein the objects,between movingfromleft to right and right to left and movinginthe oppositedi- rection and thereby determining apriori adifferenceinthe position of the objects,then in de- scribingacircle Iwould not know whether west was right or left of the southernmost point of the horizon, or whether Ishould complete the circle by movingnorth and east and thus back to the south.Thus even with all the objective data of the sky,Iorient myself geographically only through a subjective ground of differentiation; and if all the constellations,though keeping the same shape and position relative to one another,wereone daybyamiracle to be reversed Poetic Criticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 171

in their direction, so that what was east now became west, no human eyewould noticethe slightest alteration on the next bright starlit night,and even the astronomer – if he pays atten- tion onlytowhathesees and not at the same time to what he feels – would inevitablybecome disoriented. (Kant 1998, 4–5)

Kant’smention of the “astronomer” who “become[s] disoriented” from having lost the feeling of his own bodysheds light on the figure of John, an “assistant professor of physics and astronomy,” who earlier on in this Lesson loseshis sense of orienta- tion when navigatingthe corridors of the hotel (Coetzee 2003,60). Now,asheglimp- ses the bodyofhis own mother beside him, he is disgusted by avision of the snake- like innards of his origin. He denies what the poet Allen Grossman calls in his read- ing of Kant’stext “the perishing basis of our common life, our corporeal singularity, our physical subjectnature, our bodyasitisthe bearerofrecognition and intelligi- bility” (Grossman 2009,8): the basic form of pre-cognition that is his birthright,and with it the (re)cognition of the embodied condition of his mind. At the same time, it is not bodilyintuition thatgives him this vision of his moth- er,but imagination. To imagine what she is like inside mirrors what an author would do to acharacter,and indeed what critics have tried to do to Elizabeth Costello throughout her visit in an attempt to understand her works.The scene thus empha- sizes athemethatwehaveseen alreadytovaryingdegrees in Goethe and Joyce. A character who seeks to interpret afictional character,tomaster the work of artin which the fictional character is embedded, is eventuallydriventodecipher the mys- tery of the author.⁷ Coetzee’stext amplifies the mutual entanglement of these differ- ent positions, insofar as it takes the form of anovel bearing the sametitle as the name of its main character,who is anovelist,and whose son bears the samefirst name as the author of the novel in which he appears as acharacter.The son becomes acritic of his mother,inwhose bodyheliterallycame to life, and of her novels, in which he figures as acharacter;heis, as he thinksinanother episode, “written into her books in ways that he sometimes finds painful” (Coetzee 2003,60). But as the scene on the flight suggests, John’simaginative reconstruction of his moth- er-and-author’slife ends in sudden, involuntary recoil. He is torn between the desire to know his mother and an almostinstinctive urge to denythis knowledge.Hedoes not seem to want to acknowledge thatknowing Elizabeth Costello amounts, in the last analysis, to knowing himself. In different ways,each of these texts inviteustounderstand acts of poetic criti- cism as boundupwith the search for an indirect dialogue, aform of existential self- examination, in which the encounter with another work of art becomes an occasion for readingthe self. Every attempt at self-knowledge,however,also belies an attempt to hide or refashion the self. Whereas Schlegel’sidea of poetic criticism emphasizes

 Describing the process by which he interpreted Hamlet,Wilhelm Meister declares: “‘An actor,on the other hand, must be able to account for his praise or disapproval of aplay. And how is he to do that if he does not penetrate to the author’smind and intentions?’” (Goethe 2016,499) 172 Yi-Ping Ong

the creative power of the author to reshape and represent awork of artwithin their own creation, these fictions of poetic criticism cut against acertain ideal of mastery. The disowningordisplacement of what belongstothese characters surfaces again and again in each of these scenes.Wilhelm approaches his condition of passivity and ineffectuality through Hamlet,but at the same time lays emphasis on Hamlet’s inherent aristocratic identity,burying his owndilemmaoverhow to takeonthe im- possibletask of becomingnoble.Similarly,Stephen Dedalus reimagines aShake- speare whose opportunism and ambition matches his own. At the same time, he re- presses the shameofthe son at his father’sfailure, and the impossibilityofknowing himself in the absenceofhis father.Elizabeth Costello attempts to own her impossi- ble relation to reality by enacting the performance of Kafka’sape, but she leavesout the fundamental motive at the heart of Red Peter’snarrative – namely, the adoption of apurelyperformative identity thatdriveshim nearlyinsane in order to avoid end- ing up dead or imprisoned. Theinner conflict at playfor each character cannot be resolvedinthe imaginative attempt to revivify another work of art.Itmust be livedout,not thought out,ineach of these character’slives, as otherevents beyond their control and beyond the domain of their intellectual and artistic efforts become nodes for its refraction, resolution, and reawakening.Atthe sametime, the paradox at the heart of each character’sconflict has adynamic energy that carries throughout the plot,permeatingthe character system and inflecting events that lie outside any one person’slocusofagency.The novel represents what appears to be aconflictthat is internal to one character as formative of awhole world: arival world, in which the conflict and reconciliation of mutuallyexclusive aims thatwould otherwise not be legiblewithin the reality surrounding it can be staged. Manyotherresonances between these episodes emerge from their juxtaposition. Each of these figures are,indistinct ways,spurred by asense of loneliness, aliena- tion, and alack of attunement to the values of the world in which they live.They share apowerful sense of wanting to be known, recognized, valued, and even loved in spite of this alienation. Neither Goethe, Joyce, nor Coetzee attempt to ironize this impulse – on the contrary,itisthe forceofthis longing that brings these char- acters face to face with the possibility of non-being or meaninglessness when con- frontingthe other,and that givesrise to the concurrent desire for control over how they are to be understood by others. The interplaybetween the authoritative,disem- bodied voice of criticism and the emergence of the character’sbodyinto apublic realm that is conditioned by socioeconomic forces is hence foregrounded in the stag- ing of each of these performances of poetic criticism. What is at stake in these scenes appears to be avery difficult and painful form of self-knowledge that has to be highly protected by the mediation of art – almostasifthe more woundingthe knowledge, the more layers of protection must be marshaled to bringitinto the world. The expo- sure of vulnerability and lack of control within these narrativesisbound up with the dialectical relation between authorial and characterological modes of being,be- tween the one who controls all and suffers nothing and the one who controls nothing and suffers all. This relation in turn highlights the intractable problem of finding a PoeticCriticism and the Work of Fiction: Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee 173

waytolivewith powerlessness, contingency,commonness,suffering, and meaning- lessness. Ultimately, however,Iam less interested in developing ageneral theory or ac- count of the significance of poetic criticism than in taking seriously the idea that a conceptual definitionmight miss the mannerofits embodiment within the fictional text.Why do we read these fictions? What,inthe end, do we want from them?In stagingacts of poetic criticism, Goethe, Joyce, and Coetzee pose the question of what it means to encounter aworkofart,ofwhat it means to be areader.Tofully respond to this question, it becomes necessary to create another workofart.This other fiction – a ‘poetic’ fictioninSchlegel’ssense – highlights the tension between three interwoven fieldsofrepresentation: the work of art that is encountered, the fic- tional interpretationgeneratedbythe character encountering it,and the fictional life of the character in which this encounter is embedded. In the interplayofthese rep- resentations,the reader is caught.For,asthese works of poetic criticism reveal, the egoofthe fictional reader/critic both spurs the work of criticism and is the block to understanding the work of art to which the criticisexposed.The narrativesinwhich these acts of criticism are embeddedunderscorethe energies of the critic’sego in en- ablingand limiting the act of criticism, in part by narrating the conditions under which the fictional criticsubmits to suffering alongside the character whom they read while simultaneouslydeveloping various forms of self-protection to cope with their difficulties in reality.Toexpose oneself to awork of poetic criticism, then,is to be radicallydisarmed, undefended against the needs of afictional character in confronting awork of art.Isthis what we desire of art? Of criticism?AsToril Moi puts it,works of art demand acts of acknowledgment that “reveal us: who we take ourselvestobe, how we picture our relationship to the other” (Moi 2017,207) – and, crucially, how we mayfail in our attempts to respond to the other. “Iwrite criti- cism to find out about myself,” claims Michel Chaouli, “includingabout the limits of my cognitive and affectiveresources” (Chaouli 2013,333). Intimacy with awork of art involves openness to exposing one’slimits in the encounter.The fictionofpoetic criticism yields aform in which these attempts and limits meet.Insodoing,they give rise to yetanother work of art.⁸

Bibliography

Brandes, George. : ACritical Study. Vol. 1. New York: The Macmillan Company,1898. Chaouli, Michel. “Criticism and Style.” New LiteraryHistory 44.3 (2013): 323–344. Coetzee, J.M. The Lives of Animals. Princeton: PrincetonUniversityPress, 1999.

 Ithank PhilipFisher,Michel Chaouli, JanLietz, and the participants in the ConferenceonPoetic Critique – especiallyJeff Dolven, Eli Friedlander,Amanda Goldstein, and Dennis Tenen – for their generous comments on earlier versions of this essay. 174 Yi-Ping Ong

Coetzee, J.M. Elizabeth Costello. New York: Penguin Group,2003. Gifford, Don, and Robert J. Seidman. Ulysses Annotated: Notes for James Joyce’s Ulysses. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008. Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von. Wilhelm Meister’sApprenticeship. The Essential Goethe. Ed. Matthew Bell. Princeton: PrincetonUniversityPress, 2016. 371–749. Grossman, Allen. “Poetry and Enlightenment (Kant on Orientation, Whitman on the Brooklyn Ferry, Celan on the Meridian).” True-Love:Essays on Poetry and Valuing. Chicago: University of ChicagoPress,2009. 1–14. Hepburn, Allan. “APortrait of the ArtistasaYoung Man and Poverty.” James JoyceQuarterly 42/43 (No. 1/4: Fall 2004–Summer 2006): 197–218. Joyce, James. Ulysses. Ed.Hans Walter Gabler.New York: Random House, 1986. Kafka,Franz. “AReportfor an Academy.” The Metamorphosis, In the Penal Colony, and Other Stories. Trans. Joachim Neugroschel. New York: Simon &Schuster, 1993. 284–285. Kafka,Franz. “AReporttoanAcademy: TwoFragments.” The Complete Short Stories. Ed.Nahum N. Glatzer.London: VintageBooks, 2005. 259–262. Kant, Immanuel. “What Does It Mean to Orient Oneself in Thinking?” Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason and Other Writings. Trans. and Eds.Allen Wood and Giorgio di Giovanni. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversityPress, 1998. 1–14. Moi, Toril. Revolution of the Ordinary: LiteraryStudies after Wittgenstein, Austin, and Cavell. Chicago: UniversityofChicagoPress, 2017. Moretti, Franco. The Wayofthe World: The BildungsromaninEuropean Culture. Trans. Albert Sbagria. London: Verso, 1987. Norman, Judith. “Literary Criticism in the Age of CriticalPhilosophy.” Brill’sCompanion to German Romantic Philosophy. Eds. Elizabeth Millán Brusslan and Judith Norman. Leiden: Brill, 2018. 195‒216. Ong, Yi-Ping. “Lectures on Ethics:Kafkaand Wittgenstein.” Wittgenstein and LiteraryModernism. Eds. Karen Zumhagen-Yekplé and Michael LeMahieu.Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2016. 206–230. Osteen, Mark. The EconomyofUlysses: Making Both Ends Meet. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1995. Pirholt, Mattias. Metamimesis: Imitation in Goethe’s Wilhelm MeistersLehrjahre and EarlyGerman Romanticism. Rochester,NY: Camden House, 2012. Schlegel, Friedrich. “On Goethe’s Meister.” Classic and Romantic German Aesthetics. Ed.J.M. Bernstein. Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniversityPress, 2003. 269–286. Wilkinson, Elizabeth M., and L.A. Willoughby. “Having and Being, or Bourgeois versus Nobility: Notesfor aChapter on Socialand or foraCommentaryonWilhelm Meister.” German Life and Letters 22.1 (October 1968): 101–105. Simon Schleusener Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside

Introduction

In this article, Iwill refer to the concept of poetic critique rather loosely, and certainly not with anyintention to adequatelycapturewhat Friedrich Schlegel originallyhad in mind (cf. Schlegel 2003). While the notion is closelyconnected with the literary program of earlyGerman Romanticism, it is my sense that there is aspecial allure to it thatprompts its reactivation in the context of present-day theory.Inparticular, the idea of poetic critique appears to me as opening up asort of ‘third space,’ or functioningasa‘line of flight,’ that counteracts the false alternative that has brought much of the current methodological discussions in culturaland literary studies to an effective dead-end. Indeed, if one follows much of the contemporary debate about ‘critique and postcritique’ (Anker and Felski 2017), one might getthe impression that the choice for practitionersinliterarystudies is as follows: between, on the one hand, akind of reading that is steeped in the ‘hermeneutics of suspicion’ (Ric- œur), that is paranoid, symptomatic, judgmental, and overlymoralizing,while more or less uninterested in questions of aesthetics, attachment,and form; and, on the other hand, an essentiallyaffirmative or aestheticist reading, devoid of social or po- litical context,that is exclusively interested in the surface of texts,intheirformal properties,affective capacities,and enchanting qualities. With regard to this unsatis- factory alternative,the concept of poetic critique represents both arejection and a displacement along the lines of the famous formula of Melville’sBartleby: “I would prefer not to.”¹ Forwhat it suggests, in my understanding,isavery different encounter with artand literature – one that does not see the desire to do justiceto the work of art and the goal of exploring historico-political contexts and ideological contents as an irreconcilable either/or choice.² In other words, my use of the concept of poetic critique is meant to resist both postcritique’squasiaestheticist refusal to take into account the text’soutside and the ‘anti-poetic’ implications of some forms of contemporary political critique. What this text seeks to do, then, is engagewith the current discourse on critique and postcritique and present an alternative.Inanutshell,the essay’sgoal is to use

 According to Gilles Deleuze, the formula represents neither an affirmation nor anegation, but the “devastating” repudiation of afalse choice(cf. Deleuze 1997, 71).  What this further entails is the insight that in order to do to aliterary text,itisequallynec- essary to do justice to its outside (the famous Derridean hors-texte)too. Forthe idea that the text’s outside must be understood as an essential dimension of the textitself, cf. Schleusener2018a.

OpenAccess. ©2021Simon Schleusener,published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110688719-013 176 Simon Schleusener

the postcritical intervention as an opportunity to think anew about the proper means of engaging, simultaneously, with literature and politics, art and society.The premise here is thatareturn to some reductively formalist or aestheticist principle would be an unfortunate regression, but that thereare better and worse ways of readingliter- ature critically and politically. In the first chapter,Iwillexplore the theoretical land- scape of postcritique, discussingtwo of the major elements of the sort of ‘critique of critique’ most boldlyrepresented by RitaFelski (2015): First,the claim that what makes contemporary critique so tiresome and problematic – in other words: what represents its limits – is its reliance on the logic and hermeneutics of suspicion. And second, the implicit assertion that what is wrongwith critique methodologically is its taking for granted ‘abstract totalities’ such as society,capitalism, or modes of production – apremise postcritics typicallycounter by appropriatingmodels that are more descriptive or empiricist,such as Bruno Latour’sactor-network theory. In the second chapter,Iwill concentrate on the distinction between symptomatic and surface reading (as drawnbyStephen Best and Sharon Marcus), discussingthe theoretical premises of the latter in view of one of postcritique’sprime targets, name- ly Fredric Jameson. As an alternativetoboththe short-sighted advice to merelyfocus on the surface of the text itself (and thereby abandonany discussion of its outside) and astrictlyallegorical reading(or “rewriting”)assuggested by Jameson (cf. James- on 2002,x), Iwill draw attention to the work of Siegfried Kracauer and,inparticular, his analysis of the ‘massornament.’ While Kracauer thoroughly investigates his sub- ject matter’s “surface-level” (Kracauer 1995,75), he simultaneouslypaysattention to its socioeconomic context or constellation. Such areadingneeds to operate both from up close and from adistance, like acamerarepeatedlyswitching between close-up and long shot.Rather than focusing on the opposition between ‘close’ and ‘deep’ analysis (Love2010) or ‘latent’ and ‘manifest’ meaning, this sort of en- gagementwith culture, art, and literature simultaneouslyaims at precision (hence its closeness to the surface of its object)and distance – adistance that should neither be confused with Franco Moretti’sapproach of digital quantification (cf. Moretti 2013) nor with ‘critical distance,’ in the sense of the critic maintaining her distance in order to keep her handsclean. Instead, to look at atext from adistance here sim- plymeans thatone chooses aperspective from which it is possibletoalso perceive its particularoutside. In my third and final chapter,Iwill demonstrate the effectiveness of the sort of readingoutlined with respect to Kracauer in view of aconcrete literary example, namelyHerman Melville’s Moby-Dick. Here, in distinction to the dominant (allegori- cal) readingsofthe book, Ipay close attention to what is on the surface of the novel: whales and whaling. What Iseek to demonstrate,however,isthatthis non-allegori- cal focus on the book’smanifestsubjectmatter does preciselynot implyanabandon- ment of the text’soutside – its socioeconomic and political context.Instead, Iwill draw attention to the fact that Melville’streatment of whalingisnot just inextricably linked to the book’speculiar,proto-modernistaesthetic form, but alsoseamlessly in- volves the reader with questions of political economyand socioeconomic history. Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 177

Postcritique’sPolitical Unconscious

There is astructural obstacle thatcomplicates anyeffort at responding to postcri- tique critically.For if one rejects postcritical claims regarding the alleged negativity, suspiciousness, self-righteousness,and parasitic nature of critical practice, how can one make sure not to getcaughtinaperformative contradiction and confirm the ac- cusation?AsBenjamin Noys puts it:

This is the difficultspiral in which the critics of anti-critique find themselves. To engageinthe critique of anti-critique is to feed and reinforcethe claims of anti-critique, which suggests that critique can never escape attachmenttowhat it criticises and ascend to anew joyous,creative, and productive alternative.Tocontinue to engageincritique,especiallythe critique of anti-cri- tique, is to feel outdated and, sometimes,miserable, twoclichés that surround the critic. By def- inition, the critic is secondary to what they criticise, hence alreadydated, and dissatisfiedwith what they criticise, hence miserable. (Noys2019,31)

Obviously, this article will not be able to escape this trap. Although its aim is ulti- matelytopresent aversion of critique that manifests itself as a “productive alterna- tive,” therewillalsobealotof“miserable” negativity and criticizing.But if, as Eve Sedgwick claims, suspicion and paranoia are contagious (Sedgwick2003,127), then this malady neither spares the criticnor the post-oranti-critic. The perfect example here is Felski’s TheLimits of Critique,abook that seems to perform the ultimatecon- tradiction: asweeping attack on the hermeneutics of suspicionthat – how could it be otherwise? – is motivated by suspicion; an anti-dialecticalpolemic thatperforms “a negation of anegation” (Felski 2008, 1); alament about critique’s “secondariness” that is itself utterlydependent on “words that come from elsewhere” and “the think- ing of others” (Felski 2015,121‒122);³ amanifesto against the notion of totalization that subsumes Marxism, psychoanalysis,, deconstruction, New His- toricism, and much of feminism, Gender Studies, and Queer Theory under asingle category;arepudiation of the striving for “apanoramic vision of the social order” (157) that offers apanoramic vision of the theoretical landscape; an approach that rejects the desire to reveal atext’shiddenmeaningsand hiddenagendas, yetpraises actor-network theory’sability to highlight what lies “hidden among thick blades of grass” (158).Inshort: a “critique of critique.”⁴ To be sure, Felski is well aware of the difficulties of expressingher “dissatisfac- tion with critique” (192) in the appropriate (postcritical) manner. Claiming that she

 By definition, this obviouslyapplies to postcritique on the whole, just as it applies to countless other currents in contemporary theory that all use the prefix ‘neo-’ or ‘post-’ (‘post-postmodernism’ beingaparticularlystrikingexample).  Felski of course rejects that label but confirms the difficulty of avoidingitinpractice: “As acritic schooled in suspiciousreading,Iam hardly immune to its charms,yet Ihavetried, as much as pos- sible, to avoid beingdrawn into a ‘critique of critique.’” (Felski 2015,192) 178 Simon Schleusener

has “tried to avoid critiquiness by opting for different shadingsofstyle and tone,” she also acknowledgesthat such an attempt “can have onlyapartial success,” for “in the act of disagreeing with certain ways of thinking,wecannot help being drawninto the negative or oppositional attitude we are trying to avoid” (192).Her book’s “questioning of critique” (8) thus appears likeasomewhat curious exercise: while at times it reads likeanoutright rebuttal bluntlydenouncing “crrritique’s” de- structiveness (117‒150) or proclaiming that “context stinks!” (151‒185), there are other passages in which the whole methodological discussion becomes oddlydefensive, suggesting that thereisnothing wrongwith critical suspicion per se, as long as it is understood to be just one of many ‘usesofliterature’ (Felski 2008). “It is one wayofreadingand thinkingamong others: finite, limited, and fallible” (Felski 2015,192). At atime, then, when others have lamentedan“affirmationist consensus” (Noys 2010,ix) in continental theory,and after her own book discusses an enormous array of diverse postcritical currents – from actor-network theory and the new formal- ism to readingpractices likesurface reading, just reading,orreparative reading – Felski’smanifesto, in its somewhat belatedeffort to dethrone critique, paradoxically calls for apluralism that alreadyexists. This confusingmélangeoffervent anti-critical polemic, wide generalization, and rhetorical maneuvering is also expressedinFelski’stake on the political. Throughout her book,she argues thatpostcritical is not uncritical, vehementlydenying that “any questioning of critique can onlybeareactionary gesture or aconservative conspira- cy” (Felski 2015,8). At the same time, however, TheLimits of Critique offers practi- callynohints as to how apostcritical engagement with politics would actually look like.⁵ Moreover,what is curiously lacking in the book is anymeaningful discus- sion of the fact that manyofthe issues Felski raises – like the question of autonomy and form or the role of aesthetic experience – are hardlyforeign to the critical tradi- tion per se. This certainlydoes not mean that she has no point in drawing attention to aroutinization of critical maneuvers, claims to moral superiority,orexcessive sus- picion in some currents of contemporary criticism and theory.But instead of analyz- ing the concrete conditions of these phenomena, she blames them on ‘critique’ as a whole, on the tradition’scollective affiliation with ageneralized version of the her- meneutics of suspicion.⁶ While she laments that in contemporary literarystudies all value is assigned “to the act of reading and none to the objectsread” (Felski 2008, 3), she herself puts all the emphasis on the act of critiquing and none on

 In fact,when the political is mentioned at all, it is typicallyinthe form of passive-aggressive jibes against the banality of political critique. Cf. Felski 2015,17‒18: “Anyone whoattends academic talks has learned to expect the inevitable question: ‘But what about power?’ Perhapsitistime to start ask- ing different questions: ‘But whatabout love?’ Or: ‘Whereisyour theory of attachment?’”  What should be kept in mind here is that next to Marx and Freud, Ricœur also counts Nietzsche amonghis “masters of suspicion” (Ricœur 1970,33), somethingwhich complicates Felski’sassocia- tion of critique and the hermeneutics of suspicion with negativity.Onthe Nietzschean notion of af- firmation – his ‘affirmation of affirmation’–cf. Deleuze 1983. Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 179

the objects of critique. But take, for instance,the recent utilizationofsome aspects of postmodern and critical theory in the context of rightwing populist (‘post-truth’)dis- course (cf. Schleusener 2018b).Isthe key problem of such appropriations reallythe hermeneutics of suspicion? Or is it the flawedpolitical analysis underlying this meth- odological choice? Here, Felski’slack of differentiatingbetween various versions of critique – which she transforms into mere cases of auniformlysuspicious hermeneu- tics, irrespective of whether or not their particular suspiciousness is appropriate – seems to underline the limits of her own approach. In this respect,Felski’sperspective differs significantlyfrom thatofEve Kosofsky Sedgwick, who is often described as apioneer of postcritique. But Sedgwick’smid- 90s ‘critique of critique’ was not simply directed against routinization and predicta- bility per se. It was also premised on the idea that the problem with acertain kind of critique was its political uselessness in achanged ideological context.For instance, she argues that aFoucauldian genealogyand critique of the welfarestate – in the 1980s and 1990s advocated by New Historicists like D.A. Miller – onlyplayedinto the handsofthe neoliberal dismantling of healthcare coverageand other public services:

Sincethe beginningofthe tax revolt, the governmentofthe United States […]has been positively rushingtodivest itself of answerability for care to its charges, with no other institutions propos- ing to fill the gap. This development,however,isthe last thinganyone could have expected from reading New Historicist prose, which constitutes afull genealogy of the secular welfarestatethat peaked in the 1960s and 1970s, along with awatertight proof of whythings must become more and morelikethat forever.(Sedgwick2003,141‒142)

Sedgwick, then, lamentsthatacritique of ‘disciplinary society’ comes to nothing (or worse) under neoliberal circumstances,when public welfare as such is increasingly at stake.⁷ Along these lines, she also reflects on the relationship between the neoli- beralization of Americansociety and the practice of critique, highlighting

the dreary and routine forms of good dog/bad dogcriticism, by which, like good late-capitalist consumers,wepersuade ourselvesthat decidingwhatwelikeordon’tlike about what’shappen- ing is the same thingasactuallyintervening in its production. (Sedgwick 2006,619)

Or similarly:

The “subversive or hegemonic?” structureofinquiry requires awholesale reification of the sta- tus quo. One’srelation to it becomes reactive,likethat of aconsumer:acceptingorrefusing this or that manifestation of it,dramatizingextremes of compulsion and voluntarity.(Sedgwick and Frank 1995, 501)

 On this argument,cf. also Zamoraand Behrent 2016. 180 Simon Schleusener

Despite Felski’sclaim thatpostcritical is not uncritical,these sorts of contextualiza- tion are entirelyabsent from TheLimits of Critique. Indeed, if Sedgwick notes that,in retrospect, certain theories and theoretical attitudes of the late 1980s and 1990s, de- spite their pronounced radicalism,manifest themselvesnot as resistant to,but,tothe contrary,asreflectiveofthe realities of the new neoliberal order,one could justifia- blyargue that this is even more the case with the postcritical turn of the late 2000s. Again, this does not bear upon the (re‐)emphasisofaesthetics,form, attachment, and affectsper se, but rather involves what,inloose analogytoJameson, can be called postcritique’s ‘political unconscious’:its seeming indifferenceto(or non-con- sideration of)the political implications of its discursive positioning.⁸ This concerns not onlypostcritique’smethodological choices and its tendencyto sideline history,politics, and economics, but also its narrativeofwhat is problematic about contemporary critique.For one thing,what that narrative misses is the ‘great transformation’ that occurred in the history of critical thought since around the time of the neoliberal revolution to which Sedgwick drawsattentioninher essays from the 1990s. While Felski treats Jameson as the dominant representative of contemporary critique and symptomatic analysis,what she fails to mention is the significant de- cline of preciselythe kind of Marxism Jameson represents in the early1980s, which sawthe rise of poststructuralism and American-style , includ- ing disciplines like gender studies, ethnicstudies, and queer theory.Asmanyauthors have noted, what went along with this development was not onlyagrowingavoid- ance of economic issues in cultural and critical theory,but also ashift from ‘struc- ture’ to ‘identity’ (cf. Michaels 2006) and from ‘redistribution’ to ‘recognition’ (cf. Fraser 1995). In the context of the postcritical turn,this development is givenawhole new twist.Now,recognition, functioning as the dominant (cultural)currencyinatheoret- ical environment thathas largely abandoned structuralanalysis and the concept of social totality,tends to be extended to applytothe non-human realm as well. This is most obvious in the context of and the new materialism, for example in the writingsofJane Bennett. While Charles Taylor and others had advocated re- specting the identitiesofthosewho are marginalized due to their cultural difference (cf. Taylor 1992),Bennett extends this logic, calling on us to also “respect” (Bennett 2010,ix) non-human actors marginalized due to their ontological difference. Felski, having at numerous occasions voiced her sympathyfor Bennett’sideas,⁹ goes in a similar direction. FollowingLatour and ANT (Felski 2015,162‒172), she places “peo- ple, animals, texts,and thingsonasimilar ontological footing,” conceptualizing art works and texts as “non-human actors” that “help to modify states of affairs,”“are

 On arelated note, cf. also what Foucaulthas addressed in terms of the ‘unthought’ (Foucault1994, 322‒328).  Forinstance, Felski is quoted on the back cover of Bennett’s Vibrant Matter,praisingthe book as “an invigoratingbreath of fresh air” (Bennett 2010). Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 181

participants in chains of events,” and “help shape outcomes and influenceactions” (164). What she deems necessary is

arecognition – longoverdue – of the text’sstatus as acoactor: as somethingthat makes adiffer- ence, as somethingthat makes things happen. […]And oncewetake on boardthe distinctive agencyofart works – rather than their imagined roles as minionsofopaque social forcesorhe- roesofthe resistance – we cannot help orientingourselvesdifferentlytothe task of criticism. Such ashift is desperatelyneeded if we aretodobetter justice to what literaturedoes and whysuch doing matters. (12‒13)

Like Bennett,Felski thus attempts to restore to nonhuman actors – texts,inthis case – aform of recognition thatislacking in readings in which they are subject “to interrogation” (Felski 2015,173). The goal is “to do better justice” to texts, which implies that they weretreated unjustlyinthe critical readingsofthe past. To be sure, justiceisalways betterthan injustice – and if Felski means that the reader should payclose attention to what atext says,and what it does by saying it,hardly anyone would disagree. Yet, one mayagain wonder about the broad generalization here: Should all textssimplybeapplauded for being “coactors”?Ordosome,per- haps,deservetobeinterrogated?And what about the specific use or function of one’sreading: are diagnostic readings by definition unjust,because they link the text to “opaque social forces”?Once again, Felski does not reallyoffer much in terms of aconstructive combination of political analysis and ‘close’ or ‘just’ reading here. Yet, in describingtexts as coactors that participate “in chains of events,” Felski indeedlinks the text to its outside, suggesting that readingand writing are not just philological activities, but thatthey are situated in the realm of the social – connect- ed to,and affecting,other actors and actions, events and states of affairs. In terms of its specific concept of the social, however,Felski’snetwork or assemblagemodel leavesalotofquestions open. One mayask, for instance, how,precisely, texts do what they do, and what their specific agency and role is in “what literaturedoes.” Another question mayconcern the role of said “opaque social forces”:wouldn’t they need to be included in the assemblagetoo – even if, as Felski suggests, they might be merely “imagined”?Ormore generally, is there away to specificallydeter- mine what needs to be included and what doesn’t, and how all the assembled actors and coactors (such as authors, readers,critics, writing programs, schools, universi- ties, bookshops, online markets,etc.) relate to each other?Are they all equallyinflu- ential, or do they differ in impact and strength?And finally,what are the specific cri- teria for determiningwhether what literature does “matters” and for whether what we sayabout literature “does justice” to it? The promise of anetwork model such as the one used here, for Felski and others, is thatitallows the critic “to forgo theoretical shortcuts” (Felski 2015,158), thatis, abstract generalizationsorthe presupposition of the existence of “opaque social forces” (13). The problem, however,isthat the task of completelyavoiding such shortcuts is by definition impossible: since it is hardlyfeasible to include all the ac- 182 Simon Schleusener

tors and coactors involved in agiven assemblage, anyauthor – critic as well as post- critic – will necessarilymake aselection. In principle, there is no givenlimit as to what anetwork mayinclude, since, as Felski explains, nonhuman actors can basi- callybeanything: “Speed bumps, microbes,mugs, baboons,newspapers,unreliable narrators,soap, silk dresses,strawberries, floor plans, telescopes, lists, paintings, can openers” (163). Consequently, anetwork model thatdesperatelyseeks to avoid all shortcuts and selections would simplyend up with endless arbitrary enumera- tions, lists, or catalogues of ontologicallydiverse, random content.How,then,are the selections being made here? It seems that the more the author refrains from ‘the- oretical’ shortcuts – whose principles could be discussed and refuted – the more he or she will relyon‘phenomenological’ ones, that is, individual acts of apperception. Along these lines, Jane Bennett presents an assemblageinher Vibrant Matter that includes the following items:

one large men’sblack plastic workglove one dense mat of oak pollen one unblemished dead rat one white plastic bottle cap one smooth stick of wood (Bennett 2010,4)

From the perspective of apostcritical theory,the advantage of this image(or poetic collage)iscertainlyits concreteness,its ‘close’ or ‘thick’ description of what is con- cretelygiven, what is perceivedbythe subject at aspecific point in time and space – in Bennett’scase, on “asunnyTuesdaymorning on 4June in the grate over the storm drain to the ChesapeakeBay in front of Sam’sBagels on ColdSpring Lane in Balti- more” (4). From the perspective of apolitical ecology – which Bennett’sapproach imagines itself to be – there is, however,something deeplyfrustratingabout the com- mitment to remain on this empirical surface-level of things, without connectingcon- creteobjects, items,and devices to the ‘abstract machines’ that are involved in their production, distribution, and consumption. This is preciselywhat characterizes the ecological politics of Bennett’sbook as aposthumanist version of the ‘politics of rec- ognition’:trash, Bennett writes,isnot simply “dead stuff” (5) but should be concep- tualized as animate or active ‘vital matter’;she thereforerecommends thatweshould be more mindfulofhow we engage with things, matter,objects, junk. What the book does not include, however,isany serious analysis of the causes, conditions,course, and scale of the current ecological crisis – and of an effective politics that would po- tentiallybeabletoresolve it. This drawsattention to what,inreference to Felski, we maycall the limits of post- critique. It appears that these limitations are ageneral issue in theoretical currents that relyonLatour and ANT – and it is here wherethe charge of political (cf. Robbins 2017)and compliancewith the neoliberal status quo (cf. Michaels in this Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 183

volume) can indeedclaim some validity.¹⁰ This is not to saythat actor-network theory is without merit, especiallynot since Latour can be credited for reintroducingaver- sion of the (now ubiquitous) concept of materiality into the humanities, at atime when the focus was almost exclusively on discourse, signs,and signification. Never- theless, it is his deliberately ‘flat’ topography of the social – which seems to conflate the commitment to an egalitarian ontology with an accurate description of social re- ality – thatoften contributes to an oversimplified understanding of systemic asym- metries, political conflict,and the constitution of social regularities.¹¹ Still, Latour’s dismissal of the concept of social totality is akey point of reference in the postcritical discourse: “ForLatour […]there is no historicalbox and no society,ifwemean by this termabounded totality governedbyapredeterminedset of structures and func- tions” (Felski 2015,157). Theidea of totality,however,against which Felski and other postcritics polemicize, had alreadybeen defeated with the rise of poststructuralism in the early1980s. Hence, when Martin Jaywrote Marxism and Totality (1984),awide- rangingaccount of the diverse history of the concept,hedid so “in atragic or satiric mode” (20), discussing its decline in an epilogue entitled “The ChallengeofPost- Structuralism” (510‒537). Yet, while some authors related to poststructuralism were careful not to dismiss the notion toutcourt,¹² Latour and his followers made sure to eradicate the last remnants of it,directingtheir focus exclusively towards concrete (human and nonhuman) actorsand assemblages. Now,inastrangeechoing of Mar- garet Thatcher’sneoliberal dictum that there’snosuch thing as society (cf. Latour 2005,5), to even use fairlyfamiliar ‘shortcuts’ like capitalism, society,ormode of production comes under suspicion (pun intended). “LikeGod,” writesLatour, “cap- italism does not exist” (Latour 1993, 173). And: “It is no longer clear whether there exists [sic] relations that are specific enough to be called ‘social’ and that could be grouped togetherinmaking up aspecial domainthatcould function as ‘asoci- ety’” (Latour 2005,2). To be sure,postcritique’sall-too-readyadoption of ANT’spolemicagainst the concept of totality may, in the late 2000s, seem abit like flogging adead horse. The point in time, however,issignificant.For the late 2000s not onlysaw the rise of postcritique in academic discourse, they werealso in manywaysinformed by the experience of the globalfinancial and economic crisis of 2008. This event – which started with aseemingly isolated depreciation in the American subprimemort- gage market that led to the then deepestglobaleconomic downturn since the Great

 Thereare,however,various attempts at adoptingaspects of actor-network theory for aleft poli- tics. As one example, cf. Mitchell 2013.  Cf. Robbins 2017,374: “Latour’ssignature example for actor-network theory,and one that Felski repeats, is the modest speed bump. […]Itisthe allegory of asocial world whereall the infractions are minor – where some people maywant to drive toofast,but thereare no malevolent intentions,there is no collective coercion,thereisnosystemic injustice.”  Deleuze,for example,preferredtospeak of “nodes of totalization” (Deleuze 1995, 86). 184 Simon Schleusener

Depression¹³ – has evidentlycontributed to acertain resurgence not onlyofthe con- cept of totality in critical discourse, but also of the general engagement with econom- ic issues and Marxist theory in some sections of the humanities, including cultural and literarystudies.¹⁴ Against this backdrop, it maynot requiretoo suspicious a reader to assess the interventions of postcritique – includingits adoption of ANT’s concept of the social – not just in view of their philological methodology, but also in terms of their political implications.

Close-Up and Long Shot

As another instance of the postcritical turn, Iwillnow focus on Marcus and Best’s concept of surface reading – articulated in their introduction to a2009 special issue of Representations – which ties in well with the previouslydiscussed new ma- terialist version of apolitics of recognition: the tendencytofocus on, and champion, the concretelygiven (actual actors,objects, and relations) over abstract totalizations or adversarial decryptions. Along these lines, Marcus and Best arguethat readers should concentrate on the ‘surface’ of texts,rather thanreading them ‘symptomati- cally’ by attemptingtouncover their hiddendepths and latent meanings:

[W]e take surfacetomean what is evident,perceptible, apprehensible in texts; what is neither hidden nor hiding; what,inthe geometrical sense, has length and breadth but no thickness,and therefore covers no depth. Asurfaceiswhatinsists on beinglooked at rather than what we must trainourselvestosee through. (Best and Marcus 2009,9)

While Felski has statedthat she shares Marcus and Best’sreservations about routi- nized attempts at “deciphering hidden meaning,” she claims that the problem of a suspicioushermeneutics is not restricted to symptomatic approaches: “an interest in surfacesdoes not automaticallyfree us from the straitjacket of suspicion” (Felski 2015,55‒56). Nevertheless, there are obvious overlaps between the two approaches. One of them is the status of Fredric Jameson, who functions, for Marcus and Best as well as for Felski, as the perhapscentral antagonist.InMarcus and Best’scase, the twenty-fifth anniversary of the publication of ThePolitical Unconscious (1981) was in fact constitutive of theiridea to devote an entirespecial issue to the concept of sur-

 It is possible that the current Covid-19pandemic will have even moresevere effects on the world economy. What the twoevents have in common is that they both reveal how todayany incident,how- ever local and seeminglyinsignificant,isultimatelyembedded in the totality of social and economic relations that constitutewhat Immanuel Wallerstein has conceptualized as the ‘world-system’ (cf. Wallerstein 2004).  On the resurgenceofthe concept of totality,cf., for example, the perspective of Toscano and Kin- kle (2015), whose point of departureisnot Hegel’sAbsolute Spirit or the idea of an unbrokengod’s- eye-view,but Jameson’snotion of ‘cognitive mapping’ (cf. Jameson 1988). Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 185

face reading, thereby seeking to renderobsolete the approach attributed to Jameson, symptomatic reading. Despite the loss in significanceofMarxist criticism since at least the 1990s, this choice of Jameson as counterexample is understandable. “Interpretation,” writes Jameson, “is here construed as essentiallyanallegorical act,which consists in rewrit- ing agiven text in terms of aparticular interpretative master code” (Jameson 2002: x). Thisprogrammatic definition – highlightingthe necessityof“rewriting” the text’ssurface in order to reveal its deeper structure or ‘political unconscious’–cer- tainlymakes Jameson into akey representative of what Marcus and Best conceptu- alize as symptomatic reading. But their engagementwith Jameson appears reductive in thatthey leave out akey dimension of his idea of interpretation. While they take statements as the one justquoted as normative prescriptions of how the critic should engagewith literarytexts,what they payless attention to are the more general her- meneutic and philosophical principles on which Jameson’sperspective is based. Here, statements as the one referred to are not simplynormative,for Jameson’sargu- ment is that any readingisnecessarilybased on certain premises – or theoretical pre- conceptions, codes, filters, selections, values, etc. – which is whythe idea of apure surface reading,from Jameson’sperspective,would be flawedfrom the start. “It should not,” he writes,

be necessary laboriouslytoarguethe position that every form of practice,including the literary- critical kind, implies and presupposes aform of theory;that , the mirageofanutterly nontheoretical practice, is acontradiction in terms;that even the most formalizing kinds of lit- erary or textual analysis carry atheoretical charge […]. (Jameson 2002,43)

One does not have to agree with the details of Jameson’sperspective to see that this argument touches asore spot when it comestocontemporarypostcritique. From Bennett’snew materialism and Felski’sappropriation of Latour’snetwork model to Marcus and Best’ssurface reading,there is apronounced reluctance to reveal the theoretical premises that guide one’s ‘selections.’ Asimilar point is made by Winfried Fluck, who criticizes symptomatic approaches in the style of Jameson – and in par- ticular Jameson’sreliance on the Althusserian idea of structural totality – but holds that Marcus and Best’ssurface approach in no waypresents aproper alternativeasit is marked by “astunning hermeneutical naiveté.”¹⁵ “The problem of interpretation,” Fluck writes,

is that of selection (which even a ‘mere’ description has to make)and the principles […]onwhich these selections aremade. is not the oppositetodescription; it is the attempt to

 According to Fluck, this is most evident in Marcus and Best’streatment of the New Criticism: “In spiteofsixty years of scholarship on the New Criticism, the authors seem to be entirelyunawareof the fact that the close reading practiced by the New Criticism stood in the serviceofaparticular aes- thetic theory which made New Critics register and value certain formal properties and dismiss or ig- nore others.” (Fluck 2014,57) 186 Simon Schleusener

clarify what the principles of selection are, no matter whether the interpretivefocus lies on the surfaceoronother levels.(Fluck 2014,57)

In this respect,Jameson’swork has the obvious advantage of displaying aform of self-reflection and transparencythat is absent from most postcritical approaches. Forinstance, when Jameson famouslyclaims, in the first sentence of ThePolitical Un- conscious,thatliterary criticism shall ‘always historicize’ (Jameson 2002,ix), he does so based on aspecific concept of history,whose outlinesand dimensions he puts up for discussion. This is strikingly different from Marcus and Best,whose own engage- ment with history seems largely anecdotal. When they argue, for instance, that the idea of surface readingistodayanattractive mode of reading “because, at the end of the first decade of the twenty-first century, so much seems to be on the sur- face” (Best and Marcus 2009,2), it appears as if the mere gesture of is retained, but without anyactual interest in seriouslyexploring historical processes. Indeed, well after postmodernism and ageneration of scholars focusingoncultural or textual simulacra,and decades after the emergence of literary or artistic move- ments and techniques such as concrete poetry,the cut-up and fold-in technique, the nouveaux roman,pop art,photorealism, and hyperrealism, to hearliterary schol- ars highlight the timeliness of surface reading by claiming – in 2009 – thatsomuch these days “seems to be on the surface” mayappear not onlybelated, but alsolike a fitting demonstration of the postcritical notion that ‘context stinks.’¹⁶ In anycase, what amore serious engagement with the history of the turn to the surface would undoubtedlyhaverevealedisthat the phenomenon is in manyways entangled with questions that postcritics typicallyomit,namelythose pertainingto the nexus of culture and economy. In this context,the work of earlytwentieth-cen- tury German authors and culturalcritics like GeorgSimmel, WernerSombart,Walter Benjamin,and SiegfriedKracauer is particularlyilluminating.For these authors linked their own analytical interestinwhat JanetWard has emblematicallytermed ‘Weimar Surfaces’ (Ward 2001) to aparticulardevelopment of capitalism, one that was marked by the shop window’s ‘flat’ aestheticization of commodities.Inthis earlyphase of consumer capitalism, manyauthors felt inclined to combine aphe- nomenological impulse to ‘go back to the thingsthemselves’ (Husserl) and examine concrete, everydaysurface phenomena with akeen interest in Marxism and historical

 To underpin their argument for surfacereading,Marcus and Best mention anumber of political examples – likethe photos of torture at AbuGhraib that “immediatelycirculatedonthe internet” or “the real-time coverageofHurricaneKatrina”–meant to confirm that demystification as acritical strategyisnowadays “superfluous” (Best and Marcus 2009,2). While the impact of contemporary media technologyiscertainlyrelevant here, to insinuatethat because these incidents werevisible, everything is, or that their sheer visibility suggests aparticular hermeneutics – namely, surfaceread- ing – is an obvious generalization. (In other words, what is seen on the surfacemay still be un- thought.) Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 187

materialism – atendencythat is strikingly absent in the work of most contemporary postcritics.¹⁷ Turning to atext in which the tendencytocombine phenomenologyand histor- ical materialism – or surface readingand economic analysis – is especiallyevident,I will now brieflydiscuss SiegfriedKracauer’s1927article on the ‘mass ornament.’¹⁸ In this mere 14-pageessay, which reads todaylike an anticipation of Horkheimer and Adorno’s Dialectic of Enlightenment (1947), Kracauer outlinesaphilosophyofhistory entailing the by now well-known idea that capitalist rationalization facilitates apos- sible regression from enlightenment to mythology. Whatisnoteworthy, however,is the role Kracauer assigns to surface-level phenomenathat risk gettinglostinthe grand narrativesofhistoriographybut are immenselyvaluable for historicalknowl- edge and understanding. “The position that an epoch occupies in the historicalpro- cess,” Kracauer writes, “can be determinedmore strikingly from an analysis of its in- conspicuous surface-level expressions than from thatepoch’sjudgmentsabout itself” (Kracauer 1995,75). Along these lines, and somewhat similar to Walter Benja- min’sdescription of modernity from the perspective of the flâneur,Kracauer aimed at engagingwith his epoch by diagnostically ‘reading’ its surfaces and, in particular, everydaydetails,architectural features,and mass cultural phenomena (film, photog- raphy, dance, travel, advertising,department stores, hotel lobbies, etc.) that seeming- ly encapsulatethe wider socioeconomic trends and transformations.¹⁹ In “The Mass Ornament,” Kracauer’sfocus lies on the precision dance routines of showgirl troupes like the Tiller Girls, whose popular revues constituted acentral aspect of 1920sentertainment culture. What Kracauer findssignificant about the Till- er Girls’ chorus lines is how their synchronized movements and collective formation of abstract ornamental patterns resonatewith the Taylorist system of industrial pro- duction: “The hands in the factory correspond to the legs of the Tiller Girls” (79).²⁰ AccordingtoKracauer,this analogybetween popularmass cultureand scientific management is plausible in that the Tiller Girls, too, embodythe (Taylorist) princi- ples and logic of instrumental , real abstraction, de-individualization, and astrict division of labor: “These products of Americandistraction factories are no longer individual girls, but indissoluble girl clusters whose movements are demonstrations of mathematics” (75‒76). Hence, comparable to the industrial worker who, under capitalist circumstances,isunable to oversee (and recognize his own role

 Which is not to saythat thereare no exceptions.Cf., for example, Christopher Nealon’scontribu- tion in Marcus and Best’s Representations issue (Nealon 2009).  Iwould like to thank Tanja Prokić for her helpful comments on Kracauer and 1920svisual culture.  Epistemologicallyspeaking, this hermeneutical interest in details and surfaces manifests itself against the backdropofareinvigoration – and diversification – of physiognomic thoughtinthe 1920s. With respect to authors likeKracauer and Benjamin, cf. Christians2000.  BeforeKracauer,this link had alreadybeen highlighted by Fritz Giese, whose work was locatedat the intersection of industrial psychology and motion study. Cf. especiallyhis book on ‘Girl Culture’ (Giese 1925). 188 Simon Schleusener

in) the totality of the production process, the single Tiller girl is unable to behold the mass ornament as awhole and thus recognize her own role in its constitution:

Although the masses give rise to the ornament,they arenot involved in thinkingitthrough.As linear as it maybe, thereisnoline that extends from the small sections of the mass to the entire figure. […]The morethe coherence of the figure is relinquished in favorofmerelinearity,the moredistant it becomes from the immanent consciousness of those constitutingit. (Kracauer 1995, 77)

What,then, is the significance of this analysis from the perspective of the contempo- rary debate about symptomatic reading and surface reading? On the one hand,Kra- cauer’sposition must appeartothe postcritic as atypical form of symptomatic read- ing,with the mass ornament representing merely “the aestheticreflex of the rationality to which the prevailing economic system aspires” (79). On the other hand, however,Kracauer substantiallycomplicates the distinction between the two kinds of hermeneutics. First off,bystatingthat “the aesthetic pleasure gained from ornamentalmass movements is legitimate” (79),his engagement with the Tiller Girls’ dance performances can hardlybeswept aside as overlynegative or suspi- cious. More important,and different from how Marcus and Best characterize symp- tomatic reading, Kracauer does not conceptualize the surface as hiding anything.To the contrary,what he finds valuable about the mass ornament is preciselyits imme- diate visualization of the socioeconomic constellation. Kracauer thus argues that the mass ornament’s “degree of reality is still higher thanthatofartistic productions which cultivateoutdated noble sentimentsinobsolete forms” (79):

The intellectuallyprivileged who,while unwillingtorecognize it,are an appendage of the pre- vailing economic systemhavenot even perceivedthe mass ornamentasasignofthis system. They disavowthe phenomenon in order to continue seekingedification at art events that have remained untouched by the reality present in the stadium patterns.The masses whoso spontaneouslyadopted these patterns aresuperior to their detractors among the educated class to the extent that they at least roughly acknowledge the undisguised facts.The same ra- tionality that controls the bearers of the patterns in real life also governs their submersion in the corporeal. (Kracauer 1995, 85)

This passageunderlines the differencesbetween Kracauer’sapproach and what is typicallyunderstood as symptomatic reading. Forthe mass ornament is not ameta- phor or allegory of the economic system; rather,itis this system – aminiature ver- sion of it.More accurately, it constitutes asection or detail of aconstellation in which culturaland economic production are effectively intertwined. To highlight this con- stellation, Kracauer undoubtedlyapproaches the surfaces he studies not ‘spontane- ously,’ but basedonanumber of theoretical premises,among them both Marxist and phenomenological ideas and concepts.²¹ Yet, while Kracauer’sreliance on context analysis and historical materialism seems to be incompatible with contemporary

 ForanintroductiontoKracauer’sworkand its intellectual influences, cf. Koch 2012. Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 189

postcritique, his approach also differs from Jameson’sinsofar as he neither conceives of the massornament as an allegory – if we understand by it aliterary device that implies some kind of substitution – nor does he engageinanactual ‘rewriting.’ Rather,touse Kracauer’sown film-theoretical vocabulary,what he does is repeatedly switch between long shot and close-up, seeking to understand the massornament not as asingular,isolated phenomenon but to also grasp its particular outside: the assemblageorconstellation in which it is embedded.²²

The Living Leviathan

Without wishing to replicateKracauer’scritical method, but along the lines of his im- pulse to combine (rather thantear apart) surface and context,distance and proxim- ity,Iwill now engage with an example from literary history,namely HermanMel- ville’s Moby-Dick (1851).²³ That Melville’snovel lends itself to areadinginterms of the notionofpoetic critique is not surprising,given that it seems to represent precise- ly the text Schlegel had in mind when he reflected on the concept in his review of Goethe’s Wilhelm Meister. After all, with its fusion of literature and philosophy, its exuberant mix of various narrative formulas, metaphysical ideas, theological insin- uations, and literary references, Moby-Dick embodies just the kind of intertextual ‘critique’ performed as part of aliterary (i.e. ‘poetic’)creation Schlegelcalled for. And just as Wilhelm Meister comments on Shakespeare’s Hamlet – thereby forming “once more what has alreadybeen formed” (Schlegel 2003,281) – Melville’sown en- gagementwith Shakespeare’sliterature (especiallyinMoby-Dick)isawell-establish- ed fact.²⁴ Giventhe novel’shypercanonization – especiallyinthe Americancontext,where it has long functioned as asort of sacredtext for the national imaginary – Moby-Dick has of course been read and analyzedinall kinds of fashions. Andyet,the most in- fluential readings seem to proceed in asymbolic or allegoricalmanner – with the whale, Ahab, the Pequod,etc. serving as symbols, conceptual personae, or meta- phors that function as placeholders for something else, while the book’smanifest

 Cf. Kracauer 1969, 122: “The macrohistorian will falsify his subject unless he inserts the close-ups gained by the microstudies – inserts them as integrant elementsofhis over-all pictures. In conse- quence, the historian must be in aposition freelytomovebetween the macroand microdimensions.” While his books From CaligaritoHitler (1947) and TheoryofFilm (1960) give the most detailed ac- count of his engagement with cinema, it is noteworthythat Kracauer frequentlyuses film-theoretical vocabulary – as demonstrated in the abovequote – in his social and historical analyses too.  Some of the ideas laid out in this chapter arealso discussed in two earlier publications of mine (cf. Schleusener2011 and Schleusener2015,181‒233).  Cf., for example, Matthiessen’sremarks on Shakespeare’sinfluenceinhis American Renaissance (Matthiessen 1968, 369‒514). 190 Simon Schleusener

subjectmatter (the whale hunt) plays aminor role at best.²⁵ Against this backdrop, my own readingattempts to take seriously what the novel says on its surface, but without neglectingtoexamine the text’soutside. The aim here is not to pit text against context,nor is it to value content over form, but to demonstrate the impos- sibility of separating one from the other.²⁶ To be sure, academic criticism has taken great pains to establish Moby-Dick as an allegorical text so as to divorceitfrom anysense of the merelyentertaining, trivial, exotic, or adventurous – an imagethat Melville himself soughttoget rid of afterthe publication of his first twonovels, the much morefinanciallysuccessful Typee and Omoo. The notion that the whitewhale needstoberead as asymbol has been estab- lished ever since the 1920s, the period thatsaw the reappraisal of Melville’soeuvre. Forinstance, Melville’snovel is addressed by D.H. Lawrenceinhis highlyinfluential StudiesinClassic American Literature. “Of course,” Lawrence writes, “[Moby-Dick]is asymbol. Of what?IdoubtifevenMelville knew exactly” (Lawrence1923, 214). Along similar lines, Moby-Dick was later approachedinMatthiessen’s American Renais- sance and in the context of the myth-and-symbol school, where, against the back- drop of the Cold War, the conflict between Ishmael and Ahab was habituallyread as an allegory of the conflict between Americanfreedom and totalitarianism.²⁷ But even after the revisionist turn and the methodological reorientation of the field (cf. Pease 1994), allegoricaland symbolic readings of Moby-Dick persisted. Forexample, Toni Morrison analyzed the novel in the context of American race relations,arguing that the whiteness of the whale needs to be read against the backdrop of the ideology of whitesupremacyand the racist idealization of whiteness. Consequently, she de- clares Ahab to be not a “maniacal egocentric” but “the onlywhitemale American heroic enough to try to slaythe monster that was devouring the world as he knew it” (Morrison 1989,17). Morrison’sreading of Moby-Dick thus differs from older American Studies ap- proaches in that she underlines the importance of race in Melville’swriting and in-

 While morecould be said about the specific differencesbetween allegory,symbol, and metaphor here – especiallyintheir morecomplex formulation (Benjamin, Blumenberg, etc.) – such adiscus- sion goes beyond the scope of this essay. My general point is that insofar as Moby-Dick can be said to makeuse of anyofthese literary devices, it is not based on alogic of substitution but for the sake of intensification.  This obviously is not anew idea, datingback at least to Hegel’sreflections on “the absolute re- lation of content and of form” in §133ofhis Encyclopedia (Hegel 2010,200). In practice, however, critics and postcritics rarely drawthe conclusions that follow from the frequentlyinvoked insepara- bility of content and form: while old or new formalisms privilegeform over content,much of dis- course analysisand social or political criticism typicallyfavor content over form.  With regardtothe exceptionalist context of these readings, Donald Pease has underlined the role of Ishmael as the sole survivorofthe novel’scatastrophe: “That final cataclysmic image of total de- struction motivated Matthiessen and forty years of Cold Warcritics to turn to Ishmael, who in surviv- ing must,the logic would have it,havesurvivedasthe principle of America’sfreedom.” (Pease 1989, 144) Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 191

verts the relationship between Ishmael and Ahab (now it is Ahab who, due to his readiness to combat the plague of whitesupremacy, is elevated to the status of Amer- ican hero). Whatremains in place, however,isthe allegoricalframework as such, even though it too undergoes anoticeable revision. As Winfried Fluck has argued, revisionist approacheslike Morrison’soperate ‘metonymically,’ while the myth- and-symbol critics of an earlier generation focused on what they understood to be central ‘organic’ metaphors(the machine in the garden, the errand into the wilder- ness, etc.) reflective of keyfacts about American culture. In Morrison’scase, however, there “is no ‘organic,’ metaphoric relation between the whiteness of the whale and the race problem; their ‘relation’ simplyconsists of the fact that they are both man- ifestations of aproblem that pervades all of Americansociety.” In otherwords, “rac- ism is everywhereand thus every aspect of the text can, in principle, stand for the whole” (Fluck 2014,48). What Fluck’sanalysis points to is thatdue to the allegorical(or metonymic) ori- entation of Morrison’sreading, relatively little attention is giventothe specificities of Moby-Dick’smanifest subject matter.Hence, the equation ‘whiteness of the whale’ = ‘the monsterofracism’ not onlyreduces the countless associations offered by Mel- ville on the meaning of whiteness to asingle signifier (‘race’); it alsoneglects the ‘whaleness’ of Moby Dick and the significanceofthe whale’sfunction as anonhu- man actor (torefer to Latour here for once) for Melville’sdismantlingofthe tradition- al (Cartesian) subject-object relation, which is reflective of the book’scentral philo- sophical concern: that of the elusiveness of human knowledge,the withdrawal of any definitive truth, the impossibility of establishing ultimatefacts about life basedon mechanist systems of scientific classification. This – quite commonlyheld in the context of dark or gothic romanticism – is in Moby-Dick inextricablyimplicated with the world of whaling: with the narrator’scetological reflections, with his delib- erations about the (more or less) ‘erroneous’ depictions of the whale, and with the human-animal relation in general. With regard to the whiteness of the whale – as discussed in chapter42ofthe book (Melville 2003,204‒212) – this link between the novel’sepistemologicalskep- ticism and its situatedness in the world of whalingmight at first appear likeanall too artificial construct.What distinguishesMoby-Dick from other whales,the readers are told, is his conspicuous whitecolor:awhiteness that inspires Ishmael to forge a burst of associations rangingfrom reflections on the idea of whiteinnocenceto doubts about the adequacy of human cognition,and culminating in ageneral lament about “the heartless voids and immensities of the universe.” Is it,heasks, that

in essencewhiteness is not so much acolor as the visible absenceofcolor,and at the same time the concreteofall colors; is it for these reasons that thereissuch adumbblankness, full of meaning, in awide landscape of snows – acolorless, all-color of from which we shrink? And when we […]proceed further,and consider that the mystical cosmetic which produces every one of her hues,the great principle of light,for ever remains whiteorcolorless in itself, and if operatingwithout medium upon matter,would touch all objects,eventulips and roses,with its own blank tinge – ponderingall this, the palsied universe lies before us aleper;and likewilful 192 Simon Schleusener

travellers in Lapland, whorefuse to wear colored and coloring glasses upon their eyes, so the wretched infidel gazes himself blind at the monumentalwhite shroud that wraps all the pros- pect around him. And of all these things the Albino whale was the symbol. (Melville 2003,212)

Here, then, Melville himself articulates thatMoby-Dick shallberead as asymbol, one that relates to the great ‘inversion of light’ performedinthe abovecited passage. From antiquity to the enlightenment, light – as the condition for renderingthings visibleand drawing them “out of their native darkness” (Deleuze 2008, 63) – was typicallyassociated with knowledge,reason, consciousness, and truth. The white light on which Ishmael reflects, however,isnot the light of the enlightenment. Rather,itisanessentiallyblinding light that obstructsany effort to obtain definitive insights, drawingattention to both the elusiveness of truth and the illusions on which human knowledge and perception are based. All this,Ishmael claims, is sym- bolizedbythe whiteness of Moby-Dick. Thisstatement undoubtedlycomplicates the postcritical commitment to evade allegorical or symbolic readings and stayfocused on what is present on the text’ssurface.For what if atext like Moby-Dick,explicitly and on its surface, tells us thatthe entity that givesitits title shall be takenasasym- bol? Melville’sactual employment of symbolic imagery,however,isaspecific and of- tentimes ambiguous one.²⁸ Obviously, Moby-Dick entails anumber of elements that might at first sight lend themselvestoanallegoricalorsymbolic reading. The whale, for instance,ispersistentlyaddressed as ‘Leviathan,’ ahighlyloaded political sym- bol thatseems to refer to the heroic emblematics of the ‘charismatic animal’ (cf. Vogl 2007)rather thantothe actual living creature. But while Melville is eager to include all such symbolicand allegorical dimensions as part of the polyphonic and multi- layered conception of his novel, it would be amistake to assign their use to amethod of substitution. In other words, the whale in Moby-Dick is not the substitute for some- thing else; instead, the actual animal is here related to its allegorical meaningsina weirdkind of parallelism in which the meticulous, naturalistic description of the whale’smassive body, “his mighty swells and undulations” (Melville 2003,288), is consistentlyamplified by the mythological meaning of Leviathan as the most power- ful creature of the sea. This fusion of naturalistic depiction and symbolic connotation is best highlighted when Ishmael – paradoxically – refers to the whale as “the living Leviathan” (288). If we thus see the use of allegory and symbolism in Moby-Dick not as aform of substitution but as one of intensification, we might also getadifferent sense of the relationship between Ishmael and Ahab. Although the roles assigned to them differ

 With regard to this ambiguity,cf. another passagethat plainlyrejects the idea of takingthe white whale as an allegory: “So ignorant aremost landsmen of some of the plainest and most palpable wonders of the world, that without some hints touching the plain facts,historical and otherwise, of the fishery,they might scout at Moby Dick as amonstrous fable, or still worse and moredetestable, ahideous and intolerable allegory.” (Melville 2003,223) Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 193

from one interpretationtothe next,theirrelationship is typicallycharacterized as one of strict antagonism. In analogytothe parallelism between the text’smanifest content and its use of symbolic imagery,however,one could also speakofaparal- lelism between Ishmael and Ahab.While Ahab most clearlypersonifies the trajectory of the actual plot – the ‘manifest’ hunt for the whitewhale – Ishmael can be said to articulate the book’s ‘latent’ meaning in his metaphysical reflections about the elu- siveness of absoluteknowledge and truth. His endeavor,then, can be characterized as a hunt too. Yet, while Ahab’shunt is for the actual whale, Ishmael’sisa‘hunt for knowledge,’ one that is directed towardthe whale as an object of science (cetology) and representation(the “monstrous” and “less erroneous” pictures of whales;cf. Melville 2003,285‒293). Different from how the book is typicallyinterpreted, this ‘parallel’ readingofMoby-Dick would thus not differentiatebetween Ahab’ssublime failureand Ishmael’sfortunate survival, for both hunts – the epistemologicalhunt for certainty and knowledge and the physical hunt for the actual whale – are even- tuallyunsuccessful. Aboveall, what the parallel readingproposed here would underline is that the whale is certainlynot adisposable vehicle merelyusedtotransport ageneral mes- sageormeaning. Indeed, the latent content that Moby-Dick is assumedtoentail is inextricablyconnected with the whale, to the effect that anymeaning must necessa- rily ‘pass through’ the whale, and anyeffort to reveal the book’s ‘deeper’ significance must follow the whale’sown “hidden ways […]beneath the surface” (Melville 2003, 197‒198) and through “the utmost depths” (398) of the sea. Forexample, the critique of representation articulated in Moby-Dick is based on an understanding of the whale as aliving creature with certain specific attributes and qualities that render impos- sible the desire for an adequate depiction. As Ishmael explains:

Most of the scientific drawingshavebeen takenfromthe stranded fish; and these areabout as correct as adrawing of awreckedship, with broken back, would correctlyrepresent the noble animal itself in all its undashed pride of hull and spars.Though elephants have stood for their full-lengths, the livingLeviathan has never yetfairlyfloated himself for his portrait.The livingwhale, in his full majesty and significance, is onlytobeseen at sea in unfathomable wa- ters. (288)

This passageunderlines thatthe centrality of the whale in Melville’snovel is by no means arbitrary or coincidental, which is whyitwould be impossible to subtract Moby-Dick’struth or meaning from the subject matter of whales and whaling. The novel’scritique of representation, in other words – in the same wayasits critique of mechanistic concepts of science – is based on aquestioning of the traditionalno- tion of the subject-object relation. AccordingtoMelville’snovel, to represent or to categorize means, aboveall, to objectify,toturn the living whale into a “stranded fish” or “wrecked ship.” It is thereforepreciselyMelville’sdiscovery of the whale as alivingactor – aquasi-subject possessingaparticular form of knowledge and be- 194 Simon Schleusener

havior²⁹ – thatcomplicates the traditional understanding of the subject-object rela- tion, which, in Descartes, explicitlyrelies on an understanding of animalsas(equiv- alent to) machines.³⁰ Hence, Melville’srevision of the subject-object relation, in which the whale is cruciallyimplicated, is constitutive of both Moby-Dick’scritique of representation and the book’sskepticism towards acertain imageofscientific thought. While this analysis seems to be fairlyinline with postcritical principles – in the sense that the attention giventoMoby-Dick’ssituatedness in the world of whaling implies an appreciation of the novel’smanifest content or surface level – Iwill now arguethat the focus on whalingwill also engage the reader with precisely those aspects postcritics typicallyseek to omit or relativize, namelyhistory,social context,and political economy. Of course,Ido not claim that the novel’snarrative is an “allegory of capitalism” (Morrison 1989,15).What Idoclaim, however,isthat insofar as nineteenth-century whalingisacrucial part of capitalism, this context is necessarilyafundamental aspect of Moby Dick’s ‘constellation.’ Similar to the case of Kracauer’sanalysis of the mass ornament,one could thus arguethat capital- ism is simultaneouslypart of the novel’soutside and inside. It constitutes the text’s outside but is folded inward, so that Melville’sreflections about whalingare simul- taneously reflections about capitalism. Again, to grasp this constellation adequately, it is necessary to switch repeatedlyfrom long shot to close-up and vice versa. Hence, what needs to be kept in mind is that whalingwas one of the most ad- vanced capitalist industries of the nineteenth century,especiallygiven the high de- mand for the valuable whale oil (used for lamps, among other things) before the large-scale use of petroleum initiated the gradual decline of the whalingindustry. Despite the romantic notions typicallyassociated with life on the highseas, nine- teenth-century whalinginthe US was thus “eerilymodern […]inthe wayitaccumu- lated capital and spread risk. At atime when most of the nation’scapital was dis- persed in homes and on farms,” whalingwas “centralized,”“technologically innovative,” and “organizationallysophisticated” (Saunders2004). While literature often renders the spaceofthe sea asite of romanceand adventure, this other side of the maritime experience – the seaas“aplace of business” and “labor” (Jameson 2002,201) – is an issue in manysea novels too. To be sure, the tension between ‘romance and reification’ discussed by Jameson in terms of the seafiction of Joseph Conrad (194‒270) is also akey aspect of Moby- Dick. After all, the original reason for the Pequod’svoyage is the commerciallymo- tivated purpose of delivering whale oil to the “Nantucket market” (Melville 2003,

 In fact,Melville repeatedly describes the knowledge of the whale as surpassingthe knowledgeof humans.For example, Ishmael suggests “that the Nor’ West Passage,solong aproblem to man, was never aproblem to the whale” (Melville 2003,198). In this context,cf. also Bühler and Rieger 2006.  Cf. Descartes 1998, 31: “[I]f therewere such machines havingthe organsand the shape of amon- keyorofsome other animal that lacked reason,wewould have no wayofrecognizingthat they were not entirelyofthe same nature as these animals.” Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 195

177), an endeavor with which Ahab’sdesire to take revengeonMoby-Dick naturally conflicts.AsDeleuze notes,Ahab breaks “the Whalers’ law, which says that any healthywhale encountered must be hunted, without choosing one over another” (Deleuze 1997, 79). Aboveall, what Ahab’ssingularization of one specific whale – Moby-Dick – thereby contradicts, is the capitalistlogic of treatingwhales like a mere naturalresource,whose individual parts – blubber,whale bone, sperm oil, or meat – all end up as commodities on the Nantucket market.InMoby-Dick,this economic logic of commodification evidentlycoincides with the sort of objectifica- tion highlighted above: the turning of the whale into an object of scientific categori- zation and representational depiction. Melville’scritique of science is thus simulta- neously acritique of capitalistreification. As Samuel Otter writes:

Melville represents the process of cuttingintothe skin and head of the whale as extraordinarily violent and liquid, violatingthe integrity of the object and threatening to inundatethe observer. He associates knowledge with appropriation, representingthe ways in which anatomyenables commodity and the parts of the bodybecome vendible. (Otter 1999,132)

But the economic context of whalingisnot just reflected in Moby-Dick’snarrative;it also plays arole in the novel’speculiarform. How so?Being acapitalist industry, whalingofcourse involves astrict divisionoflabor,aprecise timing of the workpro- cesses,acomplex knowledge and understanding of these processes, and ahighde- gree of self-discipline on the part of captain and crew.Yet,manyelements of the novel contradict this tendency,especiallyregarding the question of temporality. What this alludes to is the untimeliness of the whale hunt – its curious situatedness at both the (dominant) center and on the (residual) fringes of nineteenth-century capitalism. Forifthereisanunexpected calm at sea, there is hardlyanything to do on board of the ship but to exchangestories of past adventures (the famous ‘sea- man’syarn’). In other words, the time on board of the ship is not onlythe time of labor and capitalist production; it is also the time of ‘the storyteller,’ as one might assert with reference to Walter Benjamin’sessayonthe works of Nikolai Leskov. Here, Benjamin makes asharp distinction between the novel and the “art of storytell- ing,” the latter of which he sees “comingtoanend” in the eraofmodern capitalism (Benjamin 2007,83). What makes Benjamin’sanalysis all the more relevant with re- gardtoMoby-Dick is that he posits the “trading seaman” (85) as one of the major sources of storytelling. Moby-Dick,however,complicates Benjamin’sdistinction. Moreinline with Bakh- tin’sconception of the novel, what is characteristic about the book is its baroque het- erogeneity and polyphony: the wayinwhich it manifests itself as aproto-modernist novel but also integratesaspects of storytelling,something which becomes especial- ly evident in those episodes wherethe Pequod encounters other ships, such as the Town-Ho (cf. Melville 2003,265‒284) and the Jerobeam (341‒347). Here, the stories of past journeys and adventures essentiallyinterrupt the central plot and thereby contributetothe novel’sheterogenous, heterochronic, and polyphonic character. 196 Simon Schleusener

It can be argued, then, thatpart of the transgressive charmofMoby Dick – the book’smultiplicity of voices,genres,narratives, and modes of communication that are onlylooselykept togetherbythe central storyline – is related to the untimely el- ement of the whale hunt: the fact that nineteenth-century whalingwas both acrucial part of the capitalist economywhile simultaneouslycontradicting some of its central forms of organization and temporality.The whalingvesselisthus not just “the het- erotopia per excellence”–as Foucault notes about the ship (Foucault 1986,27) – but is also marked by apeculiar ‘heterochronicity’:the coexistence of atime of capitalist acceleration (which is also the time of the novel) with atime of boredom and relax- ation (which is alsothe time of storytelling).³¹ In this sense,nineteenth-century whalingcan be said to manifestanuntimelytendency within capitalism, represent- ing not so much aromantic flight away from the worldasa‘line of flight’ within the world, within, that is, the confines of the market.

Conclusion

In the previous chapter,Ihave sought to present areading that resonates with the notion of poetic critique in (1) the attempt to bridgethe alleged gapbetween art and criticism (demonstratedhere by not so much ‘judging’ Moby-Dick than aiding the book in performing its own version of poetic critique); and (2)the impulseofre- fusing to separate the poetic and aesthetic from the critical and political. What this implies is the idea thattogenuinely do justicetoaliterary text,itisnecessary to do justicetoits outside too. Here, Iproposed areadingthatisattentive to the text’ssur- face and its manifest subject matter while simultaneouslyseeking to determine its particularconstellation. As Ihavetried to demonstrate, this does not mean caging the text in its historicalcontext – as if history were a “box” (Felski 2015,154). Rather, what is significant about Moby-Dick is the book’suntimeliness:the untimelyway in which its form is related to mid-nineteenth-century Americanliterature and the world of whalingitdepicts was to the era’seconomic system. Arguably, its untimeli- ness is alsorelated to whythe novel continues to resonate and is time and again re- actualizedbythe readers of acominggeneration.³²

 On “boredom” and “mental relaxation” as conditions of storytelling,cf. Benjamin2007, 91.  This is not to denythe roleofthe novel’shypercanonizationinits ongoing(academic and non- academic)popularity and relevance.Itisnoteworthy, however,that in American Studies Moby-Dick is amongthe few ‘renaissance’ texts that have survivedthe revisionist turn and areread as assiduously among ‘old’ as among ‘new’ Americanists (cf. Chase 1962and Jehlen 1994). More recently, Moby-Dick has receivedmuch attention in the contextoftransnational and globalization studies (cf. Tally Jr.2009 and Cohen 2012). Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 197

The untimely, however,isnot timelessness.³³ It does not implyamovement ‘out of history’ (cf. Brown 2001) for it is itself aproduct of it.Or, as Casarino writes: “The untimelyisthe temporalregister of that which is nonsynchronous with its own his- tory,ofthat which at once is in history and yetcan never completelybelong to it” (Casarino 2002,xxxix‒xl). Obviously, that Moby-Dick continues to be read is not un- related to the fact that the world the novel depicts, imagines, and anticipateshas something in common with ‘the world we live in,’ as C.L.R. James subtitled his own studyabout Melville in 1953. But this commonality is not to be perceivedin terms of amere resemblanceoranalogy. Rather,itisaquestion of ‘resonance’ (Rosa 2019), of affinities that,however timeless or universal they mayappear,are still relatable to historical circumstances. In other words, if Melville’snovel contin- ues to resonateinthe twenty-firstcentury, this is not least assignable to our ownhis- torical moment’sversion of globalization and rootlessness, transnationalcommerce and mobility, waning state sovereignty and lawfulness, the commodification of ‘na- ture’ and social relations,and precarious labor conditions for anew cohort of ‘mari- ners, renegades, and castaways’ (cf. James 1953). In this respect,a“theory of attach- ment” (Felski 2015,18), as called for by postcritics like Felski, will remain insufficient if it separates the affective and cognitive aspects of the readingprocess from their historical conditions (hence Kracauer’sinsistence on the combination of phenomen- ologyand historical materialism). The reading Iproposed, then, suggests an approach aimedatworking out and reactivatingthe political and historicalimplications of the text in question, yetwith- out switching to another linguistic or semantic register,and without separatingbe- tween content and form. Hence, this sort of readingismeanttoconstituteanalter- native to both the ahistoric and descriptivistic tendencies of postcritical readings and Jameson’sconcept of interpretation as an allegorical rewriting(in the strict sense of the term). But what,exactly, means ‘alternative’ here? This is an important point,for it un- derlines the wayinwhich contemporary critical and postcritical approachesare not so different after all. Under the increasinglyeconomized conditions of higher educa- tion and the academy, the production of theory is in some sense bound to the same market logic as is the production of other commodities. More specifically, the prod- ucts of theory (concepts, turns, readings,approaches) are marked by the samelogic of competition, branding,self-fashioning,distinction, acceleration, and plannedob- solescencethat is characteristic of today’scapitalism on the whole. Whatever their particularintellectual merits, the various ‘turns’ (linguistic, performative,material, postcritical, speculative,descriptive,etc.) that have occurred in recent years are in- extricablybound up with this context.³⁴ Here, what is suggested is thatanew meth-

 According to CesareCasarino, the Nietzschean notion of the untimelyrepresents an alternative to the binary relation between “the myth of the timeless genius” and “the timelywriter” whoiscom- pletelydetermined by his historical context(Casarino 2002,xxxviii).  Cf. Mark Seltzer’spointeddiscussion of whatherefers to as the “turn turn” (Seltzer 2016,166). 198 Simon Schleusener

odologywill make up for alack that characterized the previous one. The new theo- retical product is then typicallypresented in such away as to offer a ‘general alter- native’:anacross-the-board method of readingorinterpretation that ostensibly works in anycase,irrespective of the nature of the specific text at hand. Along these lines, and despite the postcritical imperative to be mindful, attentive and ‘do justice’ to art and literature, what is hardlyeverdiscussed is whether some texts maynot deservetoberead criticallyand suspiciously, while others do not; or that in some cases it maybesufficienttoreadand ‘thicklydescribe’ the surface of a text,while other texts are designed in such away as to necessitate being read alle- gorically. Of course, the fact that Iengaged with Moby-Dick to exemplify my version of a readingthat circumvents the deadlocked binarism between critique and postcritique was based on the assumption that (this sortof) readingand (this sortof) text go well together.Implied in my readingisthe general idea that the text should be examined in conjunction with its outside. But apart from this general commitment it is difficult to assume thatthe reading Iproposed works with anytext whatever.Tobesure,this is not meant as ageneral call for pluralism and variation, but simply to acknowledge that different kinds of textsrequiredifferent kinds of readings.Perhaps,then, what a reconsideration of Schlegel’sconcept of poetic critique – includinghis understand- ing of the literary text as demanding to be read “on its own terms” (Schlegel 2003, 275) – might encourageustodoisreflect more thoroughlyonhow our approach to literature(be it critical or poetic, postcritical or uncritical)isrelated to our choice of the specific texts and objects we study.

Bibliography

Anker,Elizabeth S., and Rita Felski (Eds.). Critique and Postcritique. Durham and London: Duke UP,2017. Benjamin, Walter. “The Storyteller.Reflections on the Works of Nikolai Leskov.” Illuminations. New York: Schocken Books, 2007.83‒109. Bennett, Jane. VibrantMatter: APolitical Ecology of Things. Durham and London: DukeUP, 2010. Best, Stephen, and Sharon Marcus. “Surface Reading: An Introduction.” Representations 108.1 (2009): 1‒21. Brown, Wendy. Politics Out of History. Princeton, NJ: PrincetonUP, 2001. Bühler,Benjamin, and Stefan Rieger. VomÜbertier: Ein Bestiarium des Wissens. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2006. Casarino,Cesare. Modernity at Sea: Melville, Marx, Conrad in Crisis. Minneapolisand London: UniversityofMinnesota Press, 2002. Chase,Richard (Ed.). Melville: ACollection of Critical Essays. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall,1962. Christians, Heiko. “Gesicht, Gestalt, Ornament. Überlegungen zumepistemologischen Ort der Physiognomik zwischen Hermeneutik und Mediengeschichte.” Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte 74 (2000): 84–110. Cohen, Margaret. The Novel and the Sea. Princeton, NJ: PrincetonUP, 2012. Deleuze, Gilles. Nietzsche and Philosophy. New York: Columbia UP,1983. Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 199

Deleuze, Gilles. Negotiations (1972‒1990). New York: Columbia UP,1995. Deleuze, Gilles. Essays Critical and Clinical. Minneapolis:UniversityofMinnesotaPress, 1997. Deleuze, Gilles. Cinema 1: The MovementImage. London and New York: Continuum, 2008. Descartes, René. Discourse on Method and Meditations on FirstPhilosophy. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company,1998. Felski, Rita. Uses of Literature. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2008. Felski, Rita. The LimitsofCritique. Chicago and London: The UniversityofChicago Press, 2015. Fluck, Winfried. “SurfaceReadings and Symptomatic Readings: American Studies and the Realities of America.” REAL. Yearbook of Research in English and American Literature 30: Towards a Post-ExceptionalistAmerican Studies. Eds. Winfried Fluck and Donald E. Pease.Tübingen: Narr Verlag, 2014. 41‒65. Foucault, Michel. “Of Other Spaces.” Diacritics 16.1 (1986): 22‒27. Foucault, Michel. The OrderofThings. An Archaeologyofthe Human Sciences. New York: Vintage Books, 1994. Fraser, Nancy. “From Redistribution to Recognition? Dilemmas of Justiceina‘Post-Socialist’ Age.” New Left Review 212 (1995): 68‒93. Giese, Fritz. Girlkultur. Vergleiche zwischen amerikanischem und europäischem Rhythmus und Lebensgefühl. Munich: Delphin Verlag, 1925. Hegel, GeorgWilhelm Friedrich. Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline. Part I: ScienceofLogic. New York: HarvardUP, 2010. James, C.L.R. Mariners, Renegadesand Castaways:The Story of Herman Melville and the World We Live In. New York (privately printed), 1953. Jameson, Fredric. “Cognitive Mapping.” Marxismand the Interpretation of Culture. Eds.Cary Nelson and LawrenceGrossberg. Urbanaand Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 1988. 347‒ 357. Jameson, Fredric. The Political Unconscious. Narrative as aSocially Symbolic Act. London and New York: Routledge, 2002. Jay,Martin. Marxismand Totality.The Adventures of aConcept fromLukács to Habermas. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press,1984. Jehlen, Myra (Ed.). Herman Melville: ACollection of Critical Essays. Englewood Cliffs: PrenticeHall, 1994. Koch, Gertrud. Siegfried Kracauer zur Einführung. Hamburg: Junius, 2012. Kracauer,Siegfried. History.The Last Things Beforethe Last. New York: Oxford UP,1969. Kracauer,Siegfried. “The MassOrnament.” The Mass Ornament: Weimar Essays. Cambridgeand London: HarvardUP, 1995. 75‒86. Latour,Bruno. The Pasteurization of France. Cambridgeand London: Harvard UP,1993. Latour,Bruno. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxfordand New York: Oxford UP,2005. Lawrence, D.H. Studies in Classic American Literature. New York: Thomas Seltzer, 1923. Love,Heather. “Close but not Deep: Literary Ethicsand the DescriptiveTurn.” New Literary History 41 (2010): 371–391. Matthiessen, F.O. American Renaissance: Art and Expression in the Age of Emerson and Whitman. Oxford and New York: OxfordUP, 1968. Melville, Herman. Moby-Dick; or,The Whale. London: Penguin, 2003. Michaels, Walter Benn. The Trouble with Diversity.How We Learned to Love Identity and Ignore Inequality. New York: HenryHolt, 2006. Mitchell, Timothy. Carbon Democracy.Political Power in the Age of Oil. London and New York: Verso, 2013. Moretti, Franco. Distant Reading. London and New York: Verso, 2013. 200 Simon Schleusener

Morrison, Toni. “Unspeakable Things Unspoken: The Afro-American PresenceinAmerican Literature.” Michigan Quarterly Review 28.1 (Winter 1989): 1‒34. Nealon, Christopher. “Reading on the Left.” Representations 108.1 (2009): 22‒50. Noys, Benjamin. The Persistenceofthe Negative. ACritique of ContemporaryContinental Theory. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP,2010. Noys, Benjamin. “The Hammer of the Gods: Critique, After All.” The Value of Critique: Exploring the Interrelations of Value, Critique, and Artistic Labour. Eds.Isabelle Grawand Christoph Menke.Frankfurt/M. and New York: Campus Verlag, 2019. 31‒43. Otter, Samuel. Melville’sAnatomies. Berkeley,Los Angeles, and London: University of California Press, 1999. Pease, Donald. “Moby Dick and the Cold War.” The American Renaissance Reconsidered. Eds. WalterBenn Michaels and Donald Pease. Baltimoreand London: Johns Hopkins UP,1989. 113‒155. Pease, Donald. “New Americanists: Revisionist Interventions into the Canon.” Revisionary Interventions into the AmericanistCanon. Ed.Donald E. Pease. Durham and London: DukeUP, 1994. 1‒37. Ricœur,Paul. Freudand Philosophy: An EssayonInterpretation. New Haven and London: Yale UP, 1970. Robbins, Bruce. “Not So Well Attached.” PMLA 132.2 (2017): 371–376. Rosa, Hartmut. Resonance:ASociologyofOur Relationship to the World. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2019. Saunders,Laura. “Blubber Capitalism.” Forbes (11 October 2004). http:// www.forbes.com/forbes/ 2004/1011/096.html(14 June 2020). Schlegel, Friedrich. “On Goethe’s Meister.” Classic and Romantic German Aesthetics. Ed.J.M. Bernstein. Cambridge: CambridgeUP, 2003. 269–286. Schleusener,Simon. “Sovereignty at Sea: MobyDick and the Politics of Desire.” REAL: Yearbook of Research in Englishand AmericanLiterature 27: StatesofEmergency – States of Crisis. Eds. Winfried Fluck, Katharina Motyl, Donald E. Pease, and Christoph Raetzsch. Tübingen: Narr Verlag, 2011. 121‒142. Schleusener,Simon. Kulturelle Komplexität: Gilles Deleuzeund die Kulturtheorie der American Studies. Bielefeld: transcript, 2015. Schleusener,Simon. “Das Außerhalb des Textes: LiteraturtheorienachDerrida und Deleuze.” (Paper given at the conference Philologie und Kritik,Freie Universität Berlin, 22 June 2018 [2018a]). https://www.academia.edu/36915844/Das_Außerhalb_des_Textes_Literaturtheorie_ nach_Derrida_und_Deleuze(14 June 2020). Schleusener,Simon. “Post-Truth Politics: The New Right and the Postmodern Legacy.” Modernities and Modernization in North America. Eds.IlkaBrasch and Ruth Mayer.Heidelberg: Universitätsverlag Winter,2018b.353‒370. Sedgwick, EveKosofsky. “Paranoid Reading and ReparativeReading, or,You’re so Paranoid, You probably Think ThisEssay Is About You.” Touching Feeling. Affect, Pedagogy, Performativity. Durham and London: Duke UP,2003. 123‒151. Sedgwick, EveKosofsky. “Queer Performativity: HenryJames’sThe Art of the Novel.” The Novel: An AnthologyofCriticismand Theory,1900‒2000. Ed.Dorothy J. Hale. Malden: Blackwell Publishing, 2006. 605‒620. Sedgwick, EveKosofsky, and Adam Frank. “Shame in the Cybernetic Fold: Reading Silvan Tomkins.” Critical Inquiry 21.2 (1995): 496‒522. Seltzer,Mark. The Official World. Durham and London: Duke UP,2016. Tally Jr., Robert T. Melville, Mapping and Globalization: LiteraryCartographyinthe American Baroque Writer. London and New York: Continuum, 2009. Surface, Distance, Depth: The Text and its Outside 201

Taylor,Charles. Multiculturalismand the Politics of Recognition: An Essay. Princeton: PrincetonUP, 1992. Toscano, Alberto,and Jeff Kinkle. Cartographies of the Absolute. Winchester and Washington: Zero Books, 2015. Vogl, Joseph. “Das charismatische Tier.” Politische Zoologie. Eds. Anne vonder Heiden and Joseph Vogl. Zurich and Berlin: Diaphanes, 2007.119‒130. Wallerstein, Immanuel. World-Systems Analysis: An Introduction. Durham: DukeUP, 2004. Ward, Janet. Weimar Surfaces: Urban Visual Culturein1920s . Berkeley and Los Angeles: UniversityofCalifornia Press, 2001. Zamora,Daniel, and Michael C. Behrent (Eds.). Foucault and Neoliberalism. Cambridgeand Malden: PolityPress2016.

Contributors

Jennifer Ashton is Associate Professor of English at the University of Illinois at Chicago. She is the author of FromModernismtoPostmodernism: American Poetry and Theory in the Twentieth Centu- ry (CambridgeUP2005) and the editor of The Cambridge Companion to American Poetry Since 1945 (2013). Her articles haveappeared in numerous edited volumes and in journals such as ELH, ALH, Modernism/Modernity, Chicago Review, Interval(le)s,and Nonsite (of which she is also a foundingmember of the editorial board).

Michel Chaouli teaches German and comparative literature at IndianaUniversity,Bloomington, and, as Einstein Visiting Fellow,directs the “Philological Laboratory” at Freie Universität Berlin. Mostly,hewritesabout the waysconceptual thought and poetic work come into contact withone another,forming and deforming each other.Hehas written about Friedrich Schlegel’s experimental writing (The LaboratoryofPoetry,2002) and about aesthetic experience(Thinking with Kant’sCritique of Judgment,2017). He is at work on abook about poetic criticism.

Amit Chaudhuri is the author of sevennovels, the latest of which is Friend of My Youth. He is also an essayist, poet, musician, and composer.HeisaFellow of the Royal Society of Literature. Awards forhis fiction include the Commonwealth WritersPrize, the Los Angeles Times Book Prize forFiction, and the Indian government’sSahityaAkademi Award. In 2013, he wasawarded the first Infosys Prizeinthe Humanities. In 2017,the government of West Bengal awarded him the Sangeet Samman forhis contribution to Indian classicalmusic. He is Professor of Contemporary Literature at the University of EastAnglia in the UK.

Jeff Dolven teaches poetry and poeticsatPrincetonUniversity.Hehas written three booksof criticism, Scenes of Instruction (Chicago 2007), Senses of Style (Chicago2018),and the admittedly hasty Take Care (Cabinet 2017), as well as essays on avariety of subjects, including Renaissance metrics,Edmund Spenser,Shakespeare’sreading, Fairfield Porter,and player pianos. His poems haveappeared in magazines and journals in the US and the UK and in avolume, Speculative Music (Sarabande 2013). He wasthe founding director of Princeton’sInterdisciplinary Doctoral Program in the Humanities and is an editor at largeatCabinet magazine.

Alexander GarcíaDüttmann teaches philosophy at Universität der KünsteinBerlin. Hismost recent book publications include What is ContemporaryArt? On Political Ideology (Konstanz UniversityPress2017), Love Machine. The Origin of the Work of Art (Konstanz UniversityPress 2018), and In Praise of Youth (Diaphanes 2021).

JonathanElmer is Professor of English at IndianaUniversity, whereheisalso Director of the CollegeArtsand Humanities Institute. He haspublished two monographs: On Lingering and Being Last: Raceand Sovereignty in the New World (2008) and Reading at the Social Limit: Affect, Mass Culture, and (1995). He hasalso published essaysonawide rangeoftopics, from the rhetoric of pornography to the origins of the cocktail. In 2020,hewas the Pforzheimer Fellow in American Literature at the American Council of Leaned Societies.

Anne Eusterschulte is Professor of History of Philosophy at Freie Universität Berlin. Her research areasinclude intellectual history, aesthetics, and the intersections of philosophy,literature, and the arts. She also worksonsocial philosophy,including medieval and early modern studies, as well as contemporary approaches in the field of criticaltheory. Among her publications arethe volumes Gratia. Mediale und diskursive Konzeptualisierungen ästhetischer ErfahrunginMittelalter und FrüherNeuzeit (co-ed., Harrassowitz 2018) and Theodor W. Adorno: Ästhetische Theorie. 204 Contributors

Klassiker Auslegen (co-ed., De Gruyter,forthcoming). Her current research project focuses on philological practices from atranscultural, comparative perspective.

Joshua Kates is currently Professor of English and an AdjunctProfessor of Germanic Studies and of ComparativeLiteratureatIndianaUniversity,Bloomington. He haspublished widely in the fields of philosophy,literary theory, literary criticism, and historiography.His latest book is ANew PhilosophyofDiscourse: Language Unbound (BloomsburyAcademic, 2020).

Jan Lietz is aPhD candidateatthe Friedrich Schlegel Graduate School forLiteraryStudies at Freie Universität Berlin. HisPhD project interrogates the notion of ‘Haltung’ in regard to theories of literary realism,namely in GeorgLukács, ,Walter Benjamin, Theodor W. Adorno, and Alexander Kluge. He is aresearch associate in the project “Das Philologische Laboratorium” and haspreviously taught at Universität Greifswald.

Bettine Menke is Professor of ComparativeLiteratureatUniversität Erfurt.Her research interests include literarytheoryand theater,deconstruction, scripturality of texts, conceptsofmedia, mediality,and cultural techniques. Recent publications: Flucht und Szene. Perspektiven und Formen einesTheaters der Fliehenden (co-ed. with Juliane Vogel, Theater der Zeit 2018); “Writing Out – Gathered Up at aVenturefromAll FourCornersofthe Earth: JeanPaul’sTechniques and Operations (on Excerpts),” in: Cultural Techniques: AssemblingSpaces, Texts&Collectives,de Gruyter 2020. Her current research projects focusonwit and jokes, theater and translation.

Walter Benn Michaels teaches English at UIC. Hismost recent book is The Beauty of aSocial Problem: Photography, Autonomy, Economy. His most recent essayshave been focused on the relations between theoryofaction, artand architecture. He is amember of the editorial board of nonsite.org.

JuttaMüller-Tamm is Professor of (19th centurytothe present) at Freie Universität Berlin, Director of the Friedrich Schlegel Graduate School of Literary Studies, and host of the “Philological Laboratory.” Her research interests include the history of the humanities,the relationship between literature and the sciences,and contemporary literature. Recent publications: Schreiben als Ereignis. Künsteund Kulturen der Schrift (co-ed., Fink2018) and Alexander von Humboldt.Sämtliche Schriften. Bd. 6: 1840–1849 (co-ed., dtv 2019). Her current research project focuses on Berlin as international literary metropolis sincethe 1960s.

Yi-Ping Ong teaches at Johns Hopkins University whereshe is AssociateProfessor of Comparative Thought and Literature. Her book The Art of Being: Poetics of the Novel and Existentialist Philosophy (Harvard UniversityPress, 2018) examines issues of authority,freedom, and self- knowledgeinrealism, bringing together the history and theoryofthe novel with . Her current research explores the power of literary form to illuminatestructuresofmoral community and dehumanization in the everyday.Ong is executive co-editor of the Comparative LiteratureIssue of ModernLanguage Notes.

Simon Schleusener is apostdoctoralresearcher at the Freie Universität Berlin’sFriedrich Schlegel Graduate School of LiteraryStudies, whereheisengaged in the project “Das Philologische Laboratorium.” Previously,hehas taught at the UniversityofWürzburgand at the John F. Kennedy Institutefor North American Studies in Berlin. He is the author of Kulturelle Komplexität: Gilles Deleuzeund die Kulturtheorie der American Studies (2015) and hasworked on topicssuch as the neoliberal imagination, ecologyand the new materialism, affect politics, and rightwing populism. Currently,heispursuing apostdoctoralproject on literature and in the contextof the new capitalism.