One-To-One Relationships Between a Political Party's Programme and Its Broader Ideology Are Extremely Rare, and British Libera

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

One-To-One Relationships Between a Political Party's Programme and Its Broader Ideology Are Extremely Rare, and British Libera The LIberal Party and the New LIberalism One-to-one relationships between a political party’s programme and its broader ideology are extremely rare, and British liberalism at the turn of the nineteenth century was no exception. The cumbersome and frequently conflicted machinery of political parties does not often allow for the quick assimilation of the radical or innovative ideas that are normally initiated at its periphery. Nevertheless, an Leaders of the t is intriguing to explore – as a preliminary to the political unusual amount of New Liberalism: what had happened to propel upheaval. In ideological terms – in David Lloyd liberal thinking and practice the public discourses that com- ideological change George and along a path that would take pete over the control of political Winston it from a focus on entrepre- language and action – a dramatic filtered through into Churchill Ineurship, free trade and a gov- transformation was taking place, the Liberal Party, and ernment largely concerned with one that had begun in the 1880s. law, order and the legal protection That transformation was partly even onto the statute of private spaces, to construct- due to the extension of the fran- ing the rudiments of what was to chise and the gradual introduction books, following become the UK’s greatest domes- of new – and less privileged – sec- the famous Liberal tic achievement, the welfare state. tions of society into the political But one also needs to ask: did the arena, both through the vote and landslide electoral new liberalism fundamentally through unionisation; partly due change the Liberal Party? to the growing awareness among victory of 1906. conscientious intellectuals of the Michael Freeden unacceptable costs of the indus- Setting the scene trial revolution in terms of dis- examines the Before we begin to assess the ease, unemployment, squalor and changes that the Liberal Party the sheer exploitation of the poor relationship between actually underwent in that proc- by the rich; and in part due to the ess, we need to take on board percolation of innovative theo- the New Liberalism the ideational changes that took ries of social structure concern- and the Liberal Party. place – as is so often the case ing human interdependence and 14 Journal of Liberal History 67 Summer 2010 The LIberal Party and the New LIberalism vulnerability through academic sanctity of individual liberty and curious mixture of radical and channels into the public domain. private property over and above conservative imperialist) left The awareness that new social other liberal values such as the the Liberal Party en masse. The classes would now play a perma- development of individuality and remodelled Liberal Party lacked nent role – and a quasi-demo- decency towards others. Indeed, funds (although it still retained cratic one, within the franchise that was one of the central divides: the support of some rich indus- constraints of the period – made between those who had advocated, trialists) but not the potential for it obvious that competition over and were satisfied with, political a sweeping reinvention of itself, their support and consent would reforms such as a fairer and less which it proceeded to carry cause changes in public policies. corrupt electoral system, while through over twenty years. The During the 1880s, various ‘unau- fiercely guarding individual liber- party, unsurprisingly, chose to be thorised’ programmes emerged ties, and those who believed that far more reluctant to speed along from the pens of radicals, socialists social reform had to begin where the path demanded by its radical and liberals which – despite some political reform left off. While left- wing and many of its intellectu- crucial differences – displayed an leaning liberals still retained some als, because it was fearful of losing extraordinary amount of com- standard political reforms on their too much support among its tra- mon ground. From the 1890s, agenda – in particular, they had ditional middle-class base. As the the increasing number of reports, their eye on the unrepresentative Liberal politician and reformer surveys and newspaper articles on nature of the House of Lords – C. F. G. Masterman, expressed it, the abject suffering of the socially they were convinced that the polit- the Liberal dilemma was whether marginalised – in particular those ical authorities had now to address it would ‘retain, for example, its of Charles Booth on London and urgently questions of social justice few men of wealth, without los- Joseph Rowntree on York – had and human need.1 ing those adherents who demand started to make an impact on the In the 1880s, party-political direct taxation of that wealth in public mood. And theories of Liberalism was still display- the interests of social reform’.2 the organic interdependence of ing the features of an older era Of course, there were other society, with its imperatives of – the importance of Noncon- movements afoot towards fun- support for others being as impor- formity, temperance and finan- damental social reform among tant as the cultivation of personal cial retrenchment – and those budding socialist groups – not autonomy, began to replace the features did not go away; indeed, the least the Fabian Society who highly individualistic strictures they continued to have substan- the remod- had mastered the dissemination of English utilitarianism and the tial adherents alongside the radi- of propaganda pamphlets among self-help injunctions of Victorian cal elements of liberalism. But elled Liberal working-class sectors. But ini- moralists. they no longer characterised the tially only the Liberal Party had The debate took place, tellingly party as a whole and they exposed Party lacked the clout, range and organisation enough, in periodicals, newspapers serious problems relating to its that would enable such reform to and popular books long before it middle-class social base. Gener- funds, but reach national platforms. That infiltrated into parliament. The ally speaking, identifying the Lib- first became evident in the New- pages of august monthlies such as eral Party as middle class requires not the castle Programme of 1891, itself the Contemporary Review, the Fort- some caution. Then, as now, it is the successor both to Joseph nightly Review, and the Nineteenth too broad and undiscriminating a potential for Chamberlain’s ‘unauthorised pro- Century, as well as those of pro- term. The middle class included gramme’ of 1884–5 and to the Star gressive and radical weeklies and bankers, lawyers, administrators a sweeping newspaper’s programmes of 1888– monthlies, foremost among which and merchants as well as teachers, 9. That said, the Liberal Party was was the Speaker, later to become journalists and social reformers of reinvention initially very slow to react. Dur- the Nation (and later still to be many stripes, both religious and ing W. E. Gladstone’s final term amalgamated into the New States- secular. The financial, cultural of itself, as prime minister, in 1892–3, the man), became major forums in and ideological differences among which it Grand Old Man rejected the novel which proposals for a national pol- those categories were glaring. political idea of publishing a party icy were deliberated. The liberal The hairline splits in the Liberal proceeded programme, insisting that one daily press, in particular the Man- Party were already a generation issue at a time was the right way chester Guardian, also had a crucial old before they began to widen to carry to proceed, and immediately got role in forging new attitudes. But to create a potential schism, as bogged down in the Irish prob- their readership was limited to the Whigs among the Liberals through lem at the expense of other social small groups of the educated mid- drifted toward the conservative issues. Gladstone’s moral brand dle classes. No less importantly, ranks, a movement exacerbated over twenty of crusading liberalism was pro- they still had to contend with well- in 1886 when the Unionists under found but it was also beginning established liberal views on the Joseph Chamberlain (himself a years. to be stranded on the shores of a Journal of Liberal History 67 Summer 2010 15 the liberal party and the new liberalism creed that in later decades would that stretched way beyond the the Rainbow internal to liberalism itself. We typify enlightened conservatism, budding Labour Party – one has may also observe that some of free trade excepted. Thus, a year to appreciate that London in par- Circle is a the more radical social proposals before his death he praised one ticular was host to a lively scene of the Labour Party, such as the liberal essayist for ‘all the efforts of social reformers, journalists, marvellous right to work, were rejected out of you may make on behalf of indi- religious activists and others in hand by the Liberal Party, and that vidual freedom and independence patterns of discourse and inter- example of it was mostly resistant to plans to as opposed to what is termed Col- action that criss-crossed the city, nationalise industries. lectivism.’3 His successor, Lord with the result that plans and pro- what was The Rainbow Circle is a mar- Rosebery, was no closer to radi- grammes of political and social vellous example of what was hap- cal circles, and the Liberal Party transformation were common happening pening behind and across the seemed destined to widen its among a wide range of progres- behind and party scenes.5 It was a fascinating internal rift between the reform- sives. When Sir William Har- site of ideological formation: a ists and an increasingly ossified court, Liberal Chancellor of the across the discussion group founded in 1894 middle-class conventionalism. Exchequer in the early 1890s and that met monthly and included Ten years in the wilderness from hardly a radical himself, declared party scenes.
Recommended publications
  • Property and Ownership
    Property and Ownership Gerald Gaus 1 PRIVATE PROPERTY: FUNDAMENTAL OR PASSÉ? For the last half century, thinking within political philosophy about private property and ownership has had something of a schizophrenic quality. The classical liberal tradition has always stressed an intimate connection between a free society and the right to private property.1 As Ludwig von Mises put it, “the program of liberalism....if condensed to a single word, would have to read: property, that is, private ownership....”2 Robert Nozick’s Anarchy, State and Utopia, drawing extensively on Locke, gave new life to this idea; subsequently a great deal of political philosophy has focused on the justification (or lack of it) of natural rights to private property.3 Classical liberals such as Eric Mack — also drawing extensively on Locke’s theory of property — have argued that “the signature right of any rights-oriented classical liberalism is the right of self-ownership.”4 In addition, Mack argues that “we have the same good reasons for ascribing to each person a natural right of property” in “extrapersonal objects.”5 Each individual, Mack contends, has “an original, nonacquired right … to engage in the acquisition of extrapersonal objects and in the disposition of those acquired objects as one sees fit in the service of one’s ends.”6 Essentially, one has a natural right to become an owner of external property. Not all contemporary classical liberals hold that property rights are natural, but all insist that strong rights to private property are essential for a free society.7 Jan Narveson has recently defended the necessity in a free society of property understood as “a unitary concept, explicable as a right over a thing owned, against others who are precluded from the free use of it to which ownership entitles the owner.”8 GAUS/2 The “new liberal” project of showing that a free society requires robust protection of civil and political rights, but not extensive rights of private property (beyond personal property) has persistently attacked this older, classical, liberal position.
    [Show full text]
  • Nine Lives of Neoliberalism
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Plehwe, Dieter (Ed.); Slobodian, Quinn (Ed.); Mirowski, Philip (Ed.) Book — Published Version Nine Lives of Neoliberalism Provided in Cooperation with: WZB Berlin Social Science Center Suggested Citation: Plehwe, Dieter (Ed.); Slobodian, Quinn (Ed.); Mirowski, Philip (Ed.) (2020) : Nine Lives of Neoliberalism, ISBN 978-1-78873-255-0, Verso, London, New York, NY, https://www.versobooks.com/books/3075-nine-lives-of-neoliberalism This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/215796 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative
    [Show full text]
  • Liberalisms Ing the Histories of Societies
    Ed#orial Board: Michael University ofüxford Diana Mishkova, Centre for Advanced Study Sofia Fernandez-Sebasthin, Universidad del Pais Vasco, Bilbao Willibald Steinmetz, University ofBielefeld Henrik Stenius, U niversity of Helsinki In Search ofEuropean The transformation of social and political concepts is central to understand­ Liberalisms ing the histories of societies. This series focuses on the notable values and terminology that have developed throughout European history, exploring Concepts, Languages, Ideologies key concepts such as parliamentarianism, democracy, civilization and liber­ alism to illuminate a vocabulary that has helped to shape the modern world. Volume 6 In Search ofEuropean Liberalisms: Concepts, Languages, Ideologies Edited by Michael Freeden,Javier Fernandez-Sebasti<in andJörn Leonhard Edited by Volume 5 Michael Freeden, Javier Fernandez-Sebastian Democracy in Modern Europe: A Conceptual History and Jörn Leonhard Edited by Jussi Kurunmäki, Jeppe Nevers and Henkte Velde Volume 4 Basic and Applied Research: The Language of Science Policy in the Twentieth Century Edited by David Kaldewey and Desin!e Schauz Volume 3 European Regionsand Boundaries: A Conceptual History Edited by Diana Mishkova and Bahizs Trencsenyi Volume 2 Parliament and Parliamentarism: A Comparative Hist01JI ofa European Concept Edited by Pasi Ihalainen, Cornelia Ilie and Kari Palonen Volume 1 Conceptual History in the European Space Edited by Willibald Steinmetz, Michael Freeden, and Javier Fernandez­ Sebastian hn NEW YORK· OXFORD www.berghahnbooks.com First published in 2019 by Berghahn Books www .berghahnbooks.com Contents © 2019 Michael Freeden, Javier Fernandez-Sebastian and Jörn Leonhard All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part ofthis book may be reproduced in any form or by any means, electronic or Introduction.
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptualising Party Political Ideology
    Conceptualising Party Political Ideology: An Exploration of Party Modernisation in Britain Katharine Dommett Department of Politics Faculty of Social Sciences University of Sheffield A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy June 2012 ‘No statesman can stand the strain of modern political life without the inner serenity that comes from fidelity to a number of guiding convictions. Without their steadying influence he is blown about by every passing breeze. Nor is cleverness and political agility a substitute for them. It has always been for me a painful spectacle when some Labour spokesman tries to justify a piece of Socialist legislation on exclusively “practical” grounds. There are at least two considerations to be kept in mind when making policy. Its applicability to the immediate situation certainly; but also its faithfulness to the general body of principles which make up your philosophy. Without the latter, politics is merely a job like any other’ (Aneuran Bevan, 1952). Acknowledgements In presenting this thesis I would like to thank a number of people to whom I owe an intellectual debt. Numerous individuals within the department and beyond have offered the inspiration, support and perspective which allowed me to produce this work. I would specifically like to thank my supervisor, Colin Hay, who offered invaluable advice and encouragement. In addition to his guidance, Matthew Flinders, Maria Grasso, Mike Kenny and Andrew Vincent have also provided a wealth of insights. I would also like to thank the ESRC for the scholarship funding which allowed me to complete this work.
    [Show full text]
  • Manfred B. Steger Political Ideologies and Social Imaginaries in the Global Age1
    MANFRED B. STEGER Political Ideologies and Social Imaginaries in the Global Age1 Abstract: This article argues that proliferation of prefixes like ‘neo’ and ‘post’ that adorn conventional ‘isms’ have cast a long shadow on the contemporary relevance of traditional political ideologies. Suggesting that there is, indeed, something new about today’s political belief systems, the essay draws on the concept of ‘social imaginaries’ to make sense of the changing nature of the contemporary ideological landscape. The core thesis presented here is that today’s ideologies are increasingly translating the rising global imaginary into competing political programs and agendas. But these subjective dynamics of denationalization at the heart of globalization have not yet dispensed with the declining national imaginary. The twenty-first century promises to be an ideational interregnum in which both the global and national stimulate people’s deep-seated understandings of community. Suggesting a new classification scheme dividing contemporary political ideologies into ‘market globalism’, ‘justice globalism’, and ‘jihadist globalism’, the article ends with a brief assessment of the main ideological features of justice globalism. KEY WORDS: globalization, global imaginary, national imaginary, ideology, market globalism, justice globalism, global justice, jihadist globalism, American Empire, modernity, proliferation of prefixes. • Introduction The defeat of Nazi Germany in 1945 and the collapse of the Soviet Empire in 1991 enticed scores of Western commentators to relegate ‘ideology’ to the dustbin of history. Proclaiming a radically new era in human history, they argued that ideology had ended with the final triumph of liberal capitalism. This dream of a universal set of political ideas ruling the world came crashing down with the Twin Towers of the World Trade Center on September 11, 2001.
    [Show full text]
  • POLITICAL IDEOLOGIES András Bozóki Professor, Dept. of Political
    Win POLITICAL IDEOLOGIES András Bozóki Professor, Dept. of Political Science, CEU, Vienna [email protected] MA course, 4 credits, Fall semester, 2020. #D318, Monday at 1.30pm and Wednesday at 3.30pm Description: The purpose of the course is to give a comprehensive overview to the modern political ideologies. The course starts off with the concept of ideology itself, in both historical and post-Cold War context, by paying attention to the linguistic turn in historiography in clarifying different approaches to ideology vs discourse.Then, we examine major ideologies such a way in which we shall discuss the theoretical considerations first, and then the impact of these ideas. The course aim to put these ideologies into the context of social and political practice. Beside some 'classic' ideologies (liberalism, conservatism, socialism, anarchism, fascism, nationalism etc.) which all had significant impact in the history of ideas, we will discuss some 'new' ideologies (feminism, ecologism, new left, new right) and issues in democratic political participation in the era of globalization) will be discussed. We will follow the main debates on ideology too. Learning outcome: Students will be able to understand and analyze different political arguments in their wider, ideological context and they will be more sophisticated in dealing with the cultural, ideological and social embeddedness of political actions, discourses, and rhetorics. The course will enhance the students’ critical thinking in revealing and uncovering one of the major components (i.e. ideology) has been present in the history of politics and political ideas. Grade components: Students are required to follow the readings before each meeting, to attend the seminars, participating actively in the class discussions, and, if asked, introducing the readings of the week (20%).
    [Show full text]
  • Corporate Governance and the Politics of Property Rights in Germany J. Nicholas Ziegler Political Science Department University
    Corporate Governance and the Politics of Property Rights in Germany J. Nicholas Ziegler Political Science Department University of California, Berkeley Barrows Hall 210 Berkeley, CA 94720-1950 Tel. 510-642-4533 Fax. 510-642-9515 Email: <[email protected]> A revised version of this paper will appear in Politics and Society (June 2000) Abstract This paper analyzes debates over corporate governance in Germany. Germany is a critical case for property rights, because the German and Anglo-American concepts of property differ dramatically when applied to industrial assets. In particular, the Anglo-American concept of the firm as an instrument for maximizing shareholder value collides with the German view of the firm as a political construction for balancing the interests of contending social partners. In analyzing this tension, the paper examine three types of political contestation: the enactment of formal-legal changes in the rules of corporate governance; state promotion of a deeper equity market and a more sympathetic culture for shareholding; and the mobilization of labor against Anglo-American practices for hostile takeovers in the market for corporate control. While these instances show evidence for the features of incrementalism and negotiated change that are well-known in German politics, the appearance of increasingly powerful transnational coalitions reveal a potential for change that is much greater than indicated by the modest extent of formal-legal change to date. Corporate Governance and the Politics of Property Rights in Germany J. Nicholas Ziegler Few issues have moved from the dull and dreary to the politically contested as quickly as the rules of corporate governance.
    [Show full text]
  • Municipal Socialism and Anti-Socialism in Contestation, 1889–1939
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Sussex Research Online 'HILQLQJ3URJUHVVLYH3ROLWLFV0XQLFLSDO6RFLDOLVPDQG$QWL6RFLDOLVPLQ&RQWHVWDWLRQ ² (PLO\5RELQVRQ -RXUQDORIWKH+LVWRU\RI,GHDV9ROXPH1XPEHU2FWREHUSS $UWLFOH 3XEOLVKHGE\8QLYHUVLW\RI3HQQV\OYDQLD3UHVV '2, KWWSVGRLRUJMKL )RUDGGLWLRQDOLQIRUPDWLRQDERXWWKLVDUWLFOH KWWSVPXVHMKXHGXDUWLFOH Access provided by University of Sussex (2 Nov 2016 13:46 GMT) Defining Progressive Politics: Municipal Socialism and Anti-Socialism in Contestation, 1889–1939 Emily Robinson INTRODUCTION Reinhart Koselleck halted his inquiry into the history of the term ‘‘prog- ress’’ in the late nineteenth century, on the grounds that at this point it became ubiquitous; merely ‘‘a political catchword’’ used right across the political spectrum.1 However, this is exactly the moment when a very spe- cific form of ‘‘progressive’’ politics has been seen to emerge, based on a reformulation of liberalism and involving a new conception of the role of the state.2 This has been described as an ‘‘ideological turn’’ which ‘‘changed This article has been a long time in development and has incurred too many debts to list here. The principal ones are to the University of Nottingham for funding the research, to Steven Fielding, Philip Cowley and Michael Freeden for their support during that time, to Peter Mandler who read and commented on a draft, and to the anonymous reviewers, all of whom all engaged with the piece and pushed me to improve it. Previous versions of the paper were given at the Institute for Historical Research and at the European Social Science and History Conference; I benefited greatly from the comments and suggestions made by the audiences there.
    [Show full text]
  • Postmodernity and Modernity As Political Terms in Russia's New
    _full_alt_author_running_head (neem stramien B2 voor dit chapter en nul 0 in hierna): 0 _full_articletitle_deel (kopregel rechts, vul hierna in): Postmodernity and Modernity as Political Terms _full_article_language: en indien anders: engelse articletitle: 0 128 Bluhm Chapter 5 Postmodernity and Modernity as Political Terms in Russia’s New Conservatism Katharina Bluhm In his 1995 book on “the invention of Russia,” the philosopher and art theorist Boris Groys ascribes to Russian culture “an extreme sensitivity to the West’s discontent with itself, to the desires and aspirations that the Western political and cultural system cannot satisfy.” At the same time, he posits that Russia has again and again “offered itself as the realization of these Western dreams” and thus sought “simultaneous connection with and opposition to the West.”1 This diagnosis—the interplay of extreme sensitivity, connectivity, and opposi- tion—with which Groys seeks to define the constants of Russian culture, is a good frame of reference for the rise of a new Russian conservatism as a varia- tion of a broader movement that claims to renew conservatism in order to challenge the established European and global order. While Russia’s new con- servatives invest much in the reconstruction of their own intellectual history, its core concepts must be understood in the context of recent Western analy- ses and debates, and in its interactions with the European New Right. Referencing Karl Mannheim, Michael Freeden defines modern conserva- tism as a counter-ideology and counter-movement to the “progressive ideolo- gies” of the 19th and 20th centuries, liberalism and socialism.2 According to Freeden, modern conservatism constructs and varies its ideological core con- cepts through argumentation with these two ideologies, which are themselves constantly evolving.
    [Show full text]
  • 32-1-Norton-Andrew.Pdf
    BOOK REVIEWS Degrees of Freedom: individuality and the institutions of spontaneous Liberal Political order—are liberalism’s political agenda. Other Philosophy and Ideology concepts are assumptions or theories about Edwin van de Haar people and social organisation, such as rationality, Transaction Publishers, sociability, and the feasibility of spontaneous 2015 order. Others still provide high-level normative US$52.89, 155 pages justifications for liberalism: the value of ISBN 978-1-4128-5575-4 individuality, progress, the general interest, and natural rights. Liberalism: Differences in the two authors’ lists are not always A Very Short Introduction or necessarily as significant as they appear. Freeden’s Michael Freeden ideas are more abstract, and some concepts from Oxford University Press, van de Haar’s list could be implied. Tolerance, 2015 which Freeden mentions directly only a few times, $15.95, 143 pages could flow from liberty, individuality, sociability ISBN 978-1-0-19-967043-7 and limited power. Nevertheless, the two men differ substantially on how to characterise contemporary Reviewed by liberalism. Freeden is not convinced that classical Andrew Norton liberalism and libertarianism are clearly within the current liberal family, while van de Haar hese two books both set out to answer the regards this issue as settled in favour of inclusion. question ‘What is liberalism?’ They share Freeden’s doubt comes, at least in part, from his view a methodology for reaching a conclusion. of liberalism’s history. He sees liberalism as having TBut they leave readers with quite different impressions five ‘temporal layers’ or time periods in which certain of contemporary liberal thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Affinities and Disparities
    Introduction European Liberal Discourses Conceptual Affinities and Disparities Michael Freeden and Javier Fernández-Sebastián The term ‘liberal’ occupies a special place in European culture. Its detractors and opponents may rail about its paternalism, its elitism, its oft-deplorable colonial record and, occasionally, its monadic individualism, but liberalism has been associated with emancipation, openness, reform, tolerance, legality, political accountability, the removal of barriers to human interaction and, above all, humanism, values on which most Europeans pride themselves – despite the horrendous events that struck at the heart of European civilization during the twentieth century. If that account may seem too starry-eyed, one has also to recall that many liberals themselves approached their creed from other, extra-humanist angles: the lifting of material economic constraints, a passport to modernization and a constitutional guarantor of a stable, conserv- atively inclined polity. Nor is that all when a conceptual story of Europe is undertaken. It is not only that many non-European societies have embraced and developed these liberal ideas further; contrary to the perspective adopted by many historical studies, as Javier Fernández-Sebastián demonstrates in his chapter, these ideas were preceded or paralleled in parts of Hispanic America, occasioning an early two-way transmission of liberal languages across the Atlantic. For many thinkers, liberalism is neither just an ideology nor a philosophical-political theory like any other, such as socialism, anarchism or conservatism, but rather a set of basic cultural postulates that opens the possibility of debate among all modern ideologies. In that sense, liberalism has often been equated with the mainstream of modern Western civilization and even with modernity as such.
    [Show full text]
  • Deep Cuts: Four Critiques of Legal Ideology
    Deep Cuts: Four Critiques of Legal Ideology Justin Desautels-Stein & Akbar Rasulov This Article begins an effort to rekindle the intellectual tradition of critical legal theory. The context for the project is significant. On the one hand is the grip of a social crisis, the contours of which continue to confound the commentariat. Racism, xenophobia, gendered violence, migration and nation, climate change, health pandemics, political corruption. The parade is as intimidating as it is spectacular. On the other hand, the very tools of criticism we depend upon in identifying these characters in the parade, much less the spectacle of the parade itself, are themselves in crisis. There is, in a word, a crisis for critique itself. The working assumption of this Article is that these crises—crises in society and the crises of critique—are not unrelated. It is in this context that we believe in the need to revitalize the tools of critical legal studies, an intellectual songbook from the 1970s that deserves a 21st century reboot. The argument is as follows. Among the crises of our time is the sense that law is either too marginal or too political to be of any use in the work for social justice—social justice rendered in any one of the crises mentioned above. We all know only too well, according to this sensibility, how to criticize judges, lawyers, and the academic elite. And these criticisms, of which everyone so easily partakes, all seem to bottom out in the same thing: law is either corrupt or ineffective. This Article suggests that this defeatist sensibility, and its affiliation with a popularized notion of legal criticism, is itself a legal ideology.
    [Show full text]