Language and Reality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Language and Reality BOOK REVIEWS LANGUAGE AND REALITY: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE inevitably, from such lack of neutrality (even antholo- PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE gies do, in the editor's choice of what to include and what to exclude), although the less neutral such a book Michael Devitt and Kim Sterelny is, the less it can be considered an introductory text. (Department of Traditional and Modern Philosophy, Before examining the substance of this book's per- University of Sydney, Australia; and Department spective, I should make some observations on its style: of Philosophy, Australian National University, Each chapter ends with a detailed and helpful biblio- Canberra) graphical/historical essay called "Suggested Reading". Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987, xii + 274 pp. There is also a brief glossary and an index. The writing ISBN 0-262-04089-1, $27.50 (hb); ISBN 0-262-54046-0, style is conversational and somewhat colorful, even $12.50 (sb) sarcastic at times. For example: Much of this work [on modal logic] is complex, difficult and technical. All of it depends to some extent on modern THE MEANING OF LANGUAGE logic. We shall, therefore, spare you an exposition of Robert M. Martin these results. (p. 23.) (Department of Philosophy, Dalhousie University, We are as enthusiastic for conquest as any causal theorist Halifax, Canada) could be, but the wise imperialist knows his limitations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books, 1987, ix We think that Putnam goes way too far. (p. 75.) The text is aimed at a wide variety of students from + 230 pp. ISBN 0-262-13224-9, $19.95 (hb); ISBN 0-262-63108-3, various disciplines, with harder passages--from as short as a part of a sentence to as long as an entire $9.95 (sb) chapter---delimited by the mark **. The placement of Reviewed by **s is often odd: sometimes the middle of a sentence is William J. Rapaport **ed, and there is at least one un**ed sentence whose State University of New York at Buffalo pronouns refer back to a **ed sentence! Curiously, the passage in the Preface that describes the authors' the- I INTRODUCTION oretical perspective is within **s! What, then, is their perspective? It consists of four MIT Press has given us two new introductory philoso- aspects: phy-of-language books, both of which fall within the 1. Naturalism: "The theory of language.., is an category of "single-author" texts (despite the multiple empirical and conjectural theory like any authorship of one of them); that is, they are not anthol- other .... [P]eople [are] . nothing but com- ogies, but presentations of the material from the per- plex parts of the physical world" (p. x). Thus the spective of the author(s). Why would a publisher issue authors are opposed to certain views of Whorf, two such texts in the same year, running the risk of Kuhn, Feyerabend, Putnam, Dummett, structur- having each undercut the other? One answer might be alists, and Wittgenstein, but they are not opposed that these books address very different audiences. Mi- to Quine (although he is only mentioned, not chael Devitt and Kim Sterelny's Language and Reality discussed). is a scholarly, high-level introduction, while Robert M. 2. Functionalism: The authors view philosophy of Martin's The Meaning of Language is an elementary, language as part of cognitive science; they are in somewhat simplified introduction. In what follows, I sympathy with certain views of Fodor, Dennett, shall describe and briefly summarize the two books, and Lycan, and Stich. conclude with some observations and recommenda- 3. The authors accept some of "the insights of tions. transformational generative grammar, whilst re- maining sceptical of its claims about psychological 2 LANGUAGE AND REALITY reality" (p. x). According to Devitt and Sterelny, Language and Real- 4. The authors are in favor of causal theories of ity "is an introduction to the philosophy of lan- reference, as presented by Kripke, Donnellan, guage.., intended primarily, but not solely, as a Putnam, and Field. textbook .... We make no pretence at neutrality. A Whether these can all be juggled successfully is beyond definite theoretical perspective pervades this book" (p. the scope of this brief review. Readers of this journal ix). Of course, all "single"-author texts suffer, albeit should be aware that there is no mention of Situation 108 Computational Linguistics, Volume 14, Number 3, September 1988 Book Reviews The Meaning of Language Semantics and only brief mention of Montague's con- (rejected) theories while avoiding some of the bad ones. tributions. They then develop the theory to handle empty names, Part I ("Introduction") discusses ways in which existence statements, etc. Chapter 5 ("Theories of philosophy is concerned with language. It discusses the Reference: Other Terms") extends (and rejects) de- nature of language for communication and for private scription theories and extends (without rejecting) causal use; it characterizes language as being stimulus-inde- theories to natural-kind terms and artifactual-kind pendent, abstract, arbitrary, medium-independent, pro- terms. There is also a section on Donnellan's distinction ductive, and powerful (in the sense of being able to talk (although it is **ed, which I find odd, given its impor- about anything); and it spells out the authors' natural- tance). ism. In Chapter 6, ("Syntactic Structure"), the authors Part II ("Meaning") begins with a chapter on "Truth state that they "are setting aside the findings of the and Reference", which cites the importance of truth logicians [about syntactic structure] as too difficult for conditions as "central to explaining meaning" (p. 17). this book .... In the present chapter, we shall discuss The authors discuss reference, syntactic structure, and the findings of the grammarians, in particular, the "decompositionality" as aspects of explaining truth revolutionary findings of Noam Chomsky" (p. 89). This conditions. There is a **ed section covering speech-act is, then, another major omission, one that--given the theory, theories of questions, and Gricean implicature reliance of most philosophers of language on logical (all in three pages). Next, they turn to theories of proper analyses of sentences--is difficult to comprehend in an names, as a challenge to the doctrine that word meaning allegedly introductory text. Nevertheless, an introduc- = reference. They state that they "are attempting to tion to syntactic theory as done by (at least some) give a scientific theory of language. There is no place in linguists is valuable and important, and that they give. science for talk of the non-existent" (p. 27). This stands They discuss phrase-structure trees, the notions of in stark contrast with their claim in Part I concerning the surface and deep structures, transformations, and such "power" of language. For surely there is a place in contemporary transformational theories as generative science for talk of nonexistents, perhaps especially in semantics, extended standard theory, and trace theory cognitive science and computational natural-language (but they do not discuss government and binding theory understanding, where it is essential to recognize that or, for that matter, such newer grammatical theories as people use language to talk about everything and any- generalized phrase-structure grammar or the several thing, existing or otherwise (including such once scien- functional-unification grammar formalisms). tifically respectable things as phlogiston and such cur- Part III ("Language and Mind") begins with a chap- rently respectable but, for all we now know, nonexisting ter on "Thought and Meaning", in which thoughts are things as quarks: cf. Castafieda 1972; Rapaport 1978, identified with propositional attitudes. The authors take 1981, 1985; Routley 1979; Parsons 1980; Maida and the view that "Thoughts... are inner states: beliefs, Shapiro 1982; Zalta 1983; Shapiro and Rapaport 1987.) desires, hopes, fears, etc .... They are inner represen- Although Devitt and Sterelny introduce the notion of tations (and misrepresentations) of the external world; opacity, they decide, unfortunately, that opaque con- they have content" (p. 115). Further, thoughts are texts "are too hard for more than a passing mention in "language-like .... [They] seem to have the same this book" (p. 29). Finally, they offer two strategies to semantic properties as sentences of human lan- cope with nonreferential roles: the Fregean strategy guages .... [They] have the syntax of sentences" (p. introduces senses as new roles for meaning, besides the 116), and they are productive and abstract. The authors referential role; and the strategy of Alexius Meinong consider and reject Chomsky's and Grice's objections and David Lewis is to extend ontology to include to this view, but "seem caught in the following circle: possible worlds (though the authors are technically (a) speaker meaning is explained by thought content; (b) wrong here: Meinong did extend ontology, but to inten- that content is explained by the meaning of the thought sional individuals, not to possible worlds: cf. Casta- sentence; (c) that meaning is explained by conventional fieda, Rapaport, Routley, Parsons, and Zalta, op. cit.). meaning; and (d) conventional meaning is explained by Chapter 3 ("Description Theories of Reference: speaker meaning" (p. 124). They extricate themselves Names") presents the theory of Frege and Russell, from the circle by patching up Grice's theory. shows how it handles various problems, and raises Chapter 8 ("Linguistic Competence") explains that several objections to it. The authors then do the same syntax is a formal theory of symbols and that compe- for the cluster theory of Wittgenstein, Strawson, and tence is a theory about human minds. This poses a Searle. Next comes Kripke's argument against descrip- problem for Chomskian linguistics, which claims that tion theories, followed by the authors' claim that "We linguistics is supposed to be the study of both. The think that description theories of names are wrong not authors, however, "think that linguistic theories are not merely in details but in fundamentals" (p.
Recommended publications
  • The Polarization of Reality †
    AEA Papers and Proceedings 2020, 110: 324–328 https://doi.org/10.1257/pandp.20201072 The Polarization of Reality † By Alberto Alesina, Armando Miano, and Stefanie Stantcheva* Evidence is growing that Americans are voters have been illustrated in the political sci- polarized not only in their views on policy issues ence literature. Bartels 2002 shows that party and attitudes toward government and society identification shapes (perception) of economic but also in their perceptions of the same factual indicators that can be seen as the government’s reality. In this paper, we conceptualize how to “performance indicators” e.g., unemployment think about the polarization of reality and review or inflation , with Republicans( being more opti- recent papers that show that Republicans and mistic than) Democrats on economic variables Democrats as well as Trump and non-Trump during the Reagan presidency.1 Similar results voters since (2016 view the same reality through about the importance of partisan assessment a different lens. Perhaps) as a result, they hold of the government’s performance in shaping different views about policies and what should perceptions of economic indicators is found in be done to address different economic and social Conover, Feldman, and Knight 1987 . More issues. recently, Jerit and Barabas 2012( shows) that The direction of causality is unclear. On the people perceive the same reality( in a) way consis- one hand, individuals could select into political tent with their political views and that learning affiliations on the basis of their perceptions of is selective: partisans have higher knowledge reality. On the other hand, political affiliation for facts that corroborate their world views and affects the information one receives, the groups lower knowledge of facts that challenge them.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Pragmatism and Scientific Realism Author(S): Cleo H
    Notes on Pragmatism and Scientific Realism Author(s): Cleo H. Cherryholmes Source: Educational Researcher, Vol. 21, No. 6, (Aug. - Sep., 1992), pp. 13-17 Published by: American Educational Research Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1176502 Accessed: 02/05/2008 14:02 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aera. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Notes on Pragmatismand Scientific Realism CLEOH. CHERRYHOLMES Ernest R. House's article "Realism in plicit declarationof pragmatism. Here is his 1905 statement ProfessorResearch" (1991) is informative for the overview it of it: of scientificrealism.
    [Show full text]
  • Folk Intuitions About Reference Change and the Causal Theory of Reference
    Folk intuitions about reference change and the causal theory of reference Steffen Koch & Alex Wiegmann Institute for Philosophy II Ruhr University Bochum Final Version for Ergo November 4, 2020 Abstract In this paper, we present and discuss the findings of two experiments about reference change. Cases of reference change have sometimes been invoked to challenge traditional versions of semantic externalism, but the relevant cases have never been tested empirically. The experiments we have conducted use variants of the famous Twin Earth scenario to test folk intuitions about whether natural kind terms such as ‘water’ or ‘salt’ switch reference after being constantly (mis)applied to different kinds. Our results indicate that this is indeed so. We argue that this finding is evidence against Saul Kripke’s causal-historical view of reference, and at least provisional evidence in favor of the causal source view of reference as suggested by Gareth Evans and Michael Devitt. Keywords: semantic intuitions; natural kind terms; reference change; Kripke; causal-historical view; causal source view 1 1 Introduction Descriptivism holds that the links between proper names and their referents are established by the definite descriptions which speakers associate with them (e.g. Frege 1948; Russell 1905; Searle 1958). Kripke (1980) challenged descriptivism and proposed what became known as the causal-historical view of reference. On this view, the reference of a proper name is fixed by ostension or a reference-fixing description. Once reference is fixed in this way, it is preserved through communicative chains. Importantly, this does not require the speaker to know how the term was used before; the mere intention to use it as it has previously been used suffices for successful reference.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory and Reality : an Introduction to the Philosophy of Science / Peter Godfrey-Smith
    2 •••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••• Logic Plus Empiricism 2.1 The Empiricist Tradition The first approach to science that we will examine is a revolutionary form of empiricism that appeared in the early part of the twentieth century, flourished for a time, was transformed and moderated under the pressure of objections, and then slowly became extinct. The earlier version of the view is called “logical positivism,” and the later, moderate form is more usually called “logical empiricism.” There is variation in terminology here; “logical empiricism” is sometimes used for the whole movement, early and late. Although we will be looking at fossils in this chapter, these remnants of the past are of great importance in understanding where we are now. Before discussing logical positivism, it will be helpful to go even further back and say something about the empiricist tradition in general. In the first chapter I said that empiricism is often summarized with the claim that the only source of knowledge is experience. This idea goes back a long way, but the most famous stage of empiricist thought was in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, with the work of John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume. These “classical” forms of empiricism were based upon the- ories about the mind and how it works. Their view of the mind is often called “sensationalist.” Sensations, like patches of color and sounds, ap- pear in the mind and are all the mind has access to. The role of thought is to track and respond to patterns in these sensations. This view of the mind is not implied by the more basic empiricist idea that experience is the source of knowledge, but for many years such a view was common within empiricism.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatic Realism†
    Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso Año 4 / 2016 / 2do semestre / N° 8 Págs. 107 - 122 ISSN 0719-4234 / eISSN 0719-4242 Pragmatic Realism† Hasok Chang* Abstract In this paper I seek to articulate and develop Roberto Torretti’s advocacy of pragmatic realism. At the core of Torrietti’s view is a rejection of the notion that the truth of scientific theories consists in their correspondence to the world. I propose to understand correspondence in that sense as a metaphorical notion. I articulate a notion of pragmatist coherence, on the basis of which I make new coherence theories of truth and reality. Then it becomes possible to say that pragmatic realism consists in the pursuit of true knowledge of reality, in a way that is also consonant with Torretti’s pluralism. Keywords: pragmatism, realism, pluralism, coherence, truth, reality Realismo Pragmático Resumen En este trabajo intento articular y desarrollar la defensa que Roberto Torretti hace del realismo pragmático. En el núcleo de la visión de Torretti existe un rechazo a la idea de que la verdad de las teorías científicas consista en su correspondencia con el mundo. Propongo entonces entender la correspondencia como una noción metafórica. Articularé una noción de coherencia pragmática sobre la cual establezco una nueva teoría de la coherencia entre verdad y realidad. __________________En consecuencia, resultará posible afirmar que el realismo pragmático † Recibido: octubre 2016. This paper is partly based on a presentation entitled “Pragmatist Coherence as the Source of Truth and Reality,” given at the sixth biennial conference of the Society for Philosophy of Science in Practice (SPSP) on 17 June 2016 at Rowan University.
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Devitt, a Naturalistic Defense of Realism
    Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring 2008 [Handout 6] Michael Devitt: A Naturalistic Defense of Realism Professor JeeLoo Liu § Summary of Main Theses • His defense is of commonsense realism and scientific realism. • His main claim is that realism does not entail, and does not involve the correspondence theory of truth. • His main position is that of “naturalism” – experience is our only teacher. Devitt: “Anti-realism about the physical world is an occupational hazard of philosophy.” § Realism Realism usually has two elements: 1. semantic claim about truth and reference 2. metaphysical claim about (i) existence; (ii) mind-independence. ( the existence dimension and the independence dimension) Realism as a metaphysical thesis (the semantic element should be disassociated from Realism): ___ Tokens of most commonsense, and scientific, physical types objectively exist independently of the mental. § Idealism ___ Mostly deny only the independence dimension, not the existence dimension, of the metaphysical claim of realists. [A] According to some traditional idealists, the entities identified by the first dimension are made up of mental items, “ideas” or “sense data,” and so are not external to the mind. Devitt 2 [B] According to recent idealists, the entities are not, in a certain respect, “objective”: they depend for their existence and nature on the cognitive activities and capacities of our minds. § Realist’s claim about the objectivity of the world: ____ The world is not constituted by our knowledge, by our epistemic values, by our capacity to refer to it, by the synthesizing power of the mind, nor by our imposition of concepts, theories, or languages; it is not limited by what we can believe or discover.
    [Show full text]
  • Musings on the Theory of Everything and Reality (PDF)
    Lecture Notes 7: Musings on the Theory of Everything and Reality 1 Is a \Theory of Everything" Even Possible? In Lecture Notes 6, I described the ongoing quest of theoretical physicists to­ day in uncovering the “theory of everything” that describes Nature. Nobody knows yet what that theory is — it would have to somehow reconcile the conflict between quantum theory and general relativity, i.e., it would have to be a theory of “quantum gravity” — but people are certainly trying, and many optimistic people even feel that we’re “almost there.” I personally have no idea if we’re close at all, because I am definitely not an expert on any candidate theory of quantum gravity. However, I do feel that we’ve come a long way in the past 100 years. And, when I marvel at the progress we’ve made, it makes me feel that, some day, we will finally have the correct theory of quantum gravity. Whether that day is 50 years from now or 500 years I won’t try to guess. But it seems like we can understand the Universe. In­ deed, as Einstein once mused: “The most incomprehensible thing about the Universe is that it is comprehensible.” But is the Universe really comprehensible? We can certainly understand aspects of the Universe today, but could we someday understand everything about it? The prospect of understanding everything — not only the laws of physics, but also the state of every single object in the (possibly infinite) Universe — probably seems rather bleak. After all, we humans are only only small, finite systems in an incredibly vast (possibly infinite) Universe, so maybe complete knowledge of every system in the Universe is impossible to attain.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant's Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation Between
    Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation between Sensibility and Understanding Wendell Allan Marinay Kant’s critique of reason does not provide an ultimate justification of knowledge, is not the last word in philosophy but is an initial thesis aimed at successfully solving the challenge posed by two warring schools of thought during Kant’s time: empiricism and rationalism.1 Following the ancient-Greek’s nothing-in-the-mind-without-passing-through-the- senses (Aristotle), Immanuel Kant’s inquiry of knowledge starts with the things “seen” or “experienced.”2 Such inquiry entails the materials and a process by which there can (probably) be known. It probes into or upon the constitution of human reason – an epistemic investigation from within yet necessarily involving from without. This is so because “in the mind we have the pure forms of sensible intuition and the pure concepts of an object in general. Extraneous to the mind we have the unknown and unknowable source of the matter for these forms, the source of that out of which our contentful experience is made.”3 Kant mentions two faculties of the mind that are involved in the knowing process, namely, sensibility and understanding. “He distinguishes between the receptive faculty of sensibility, through which we have intuitions, and the active faculty of understanding, which is the source of concepts.”4 Through the former, the objects are “given” while 1 Otfried Höffe. Immanuel Kant trans. Marshall Farrier (New York: State University of New York Press, 1994), 55. 2 We should not be misled that by starting with things seen or experienced, knowledge would mean like a result of or is consequent to such experience.
    [Show full text]
  • The Language of Fundamentalism: a Language of the Past Or a Reality of the Future?
    THE LANGUAGE OF FUNDAMENTALISM: A LANGUAGE OF THE PAST OR A REALITY OF THE FUTURE? The rise and growth of Fundamentalism is obvious to all. What is not obvious is how one should classify Fundamentalism. (When we use the term Fundamen- talism without any explanation we have in mind American Biblical Fundamen- talism. The reason for this designation becomes obvious in the course of the workshop.) In other words, whether one should see it as an anti-intellectual ab- erration or as a conservative religious movement with its own identity and per- spective of life? The works of Sandeen and Marsden make clear that Fundamentalism is not an aberration, but rather a conservative tradition that has deep roots in American soil. Through an examination of the language of Funda- mentalism we hope to disclose not only the broad foundation in which it is built, but also come to some understanding with regard to its future. Making use of Hal Lindsey's work we shall illustrate our point as well. In broad terms one may describe the language of Fundamentalism as a lan- guage of militant defense and separation. Falwell describes Fundamentalists as "militant defenders of the faith."1 Its militant defense is in favor of the five fun- damentals at the heart of the Fundamentalist-Modernist controversy. They are: (1) the inspiration and infallibility of Scripture; (2) the deity of Christ (including the Virgin birth); (3) the substitutionary atonement of Christ's death; (4) the literal resurrection of Christ from the dead; (5) the literal return of Christ in the Second Advent.
    [Show full text]
  • Reality, Information, and Information Observer †
    Proceedings Reality, Information, and Information Observer † Vladimir S. Lerner Independent researcher, 13603 marina pointe drive, Marina Del Rey, CA 90292, USA; [email protected]; Tel.: +1-310-8226279 † Conference Theoretical Information Studies (TIS), Berkeley, CA, USA, 2–6 June 2019. Published: 20 May 2020 Abstract: Up to now both information and its connection to reality do not have scientifically conclusive definitions, nor implicit origin. They emerge in observing multiple impulses’ interactive yes‒no actions modeling information bits. Each memorized bit of information binds a reversible microprocess with an irreversible information macroprocess along a multi-dimensional observing process. Interactive information dynamics assemble geometrical and information structures of observer cognition and intelligence in double spiral rotating code. Information Path Functional integrates multiple interactive dynamics in finite bits which observe and measure reality. The time and space of reality exists only as discrete units of information. The observed information process, creating its Observer, connects reality, information, and the Observer. Keywords: reality; interaction; impulse; interactive observation; logic; certainty; information process; micro‒macroprocess; Information Path Functional; triple structural unit; triplet code 1. Introduction Observers are everywhere, from communicating people, animals, and different species up to any interacting subjects, accepting, transforming, and exchanging information. What do the observers actually observe? Do they observe reality? What is the information they observe? And how is the observed information connected with the reality of observation? What is the scientific path to uncovering the fact of reality through its observed information? All these questions are still unanswered in known publications. In [1] the eminent scientists discussed various aspects of information and reality, from quantum information to biological and digital information, in order to understand how nature works.
    [Show full text]
  • INFORMATION– CONSCIOUSNESS– REALITY How a New Understanding of the Universe Can Help Answer Age-Old Questions of Existence the FRONTIERS COLLECTION
    THE FRONTIERS COLLECTION James B. Glattfelder INFORMATION– CONSCIOUSNESS– REALITY How a New Understanding of the Universe Can Help Answer Age-Old Questions of Existence THE FRONTIERS COLLECTION Series editors Avshalom C. Elitzur, Iyar, Israel Institute of Advanced Research, Rehovot, Israel Zeeya Merali, Foundational Questions Institute, Decatur, GA, USA Thanu Padmanabhan, Inter-University Centre for Astronomy and Astrophysics (IUCAA), Pune, India Maximilian Schlosshauer, Department of Physics, University of Portland, Portland, OR, USA Mark P. Silverman, Department of Physics, Trinity College, Hartford, CT, USA Jack A. Tuszynski, Department of Physics, University of Alberta, Edmonton, AB, Canada Rüdiger Vaas, Redaktion Astronomie, Physik, bild der wissenschaft, Leinfelden-Echterdingen, Germany THE FRONTIERS COLLECTION The books in this collection are devoted to challenging and open problems at the forefront of modern science and scholarship, including related philosophical debates. In contrast to typical research monographs, however, they strive to present their topics in a manner accessible also to scientifically literate non-specialists wishing to gain insight into the deeper implications and fascinating questions involved. Taken as a whole, the series reflects the need for a fundamental and interdisciplinary approach to modern science and research. Furthermore, it is intended to encourage active academics in all fields to ponder over important and perhaps controversial issues beyond their own speciality. Extending from quantum physics and relativity to entropy, conscious- ness, language and complex systems—the Frontiers Collection will inspire readers to push back the frontiers of their own knowledge. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/5342 For a full list of published titles, please see back of book or springer.com/series/5342 James B.
    [Show full text]
  • The New Age Movement (1994)
    THE NEW AGE MOVEMENT (1994) CONTENTS Introduction Part 1 Characteristics and Origins of the New Age Movement I Characteristics II Origins Part 2 New Age Perceptions of Creation: A Christian Response Part 3 Humankind, Salvation and the Person of Christ: A Christian Response I Humankind and Salvation II The Person and Work of Christ Part 4 Missiological and Pastoral Questions Raised by the New Age Movement Part 5 Concluding Reflections Resolution Recommended Reading INTRODUCTION 1 The Conference of 1990 referred to the Faith and Order Committee the following Memorial (M.8) for consideration and report not later than the Conference of 1992: The Pickering (29/22) Circuit Meeting (Present 32. Vote: unanimous) request that Conference examine the New Age Movement with respect to its theological content and socio-political ambitions, in order that the Methodist people may receive guidelines as to its compatibility with the Christian faith and Methodist doctrines. 2 In 1992 the Faith and Order Committee expressed its regret that, for a number of reasons, it was not in a position to present a recommended reply to the Memorial, and requested that it be allowed a further two years in which to prepare its report. The Conference directed the Faith and Order Committee to bring a reply to Memorial M.8 to the Conference of 1994. 592 PART 1: CHARACTERISTICS AND ORIGINS OF THE NEW AGE MOVEMENT I Characteristics 3 New Age ideas are all around us on television and radio, in newspapers and magazines. We meet them in the shopping place, possibly – depending on the work we do – during training.
    [Show full text]