The Rule of Law Ideal in Early American Constitutional Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Rule of Law Ideal in Early American Constitutional Theory Sigma: Journal of Political and International Studies Volume 9 Article 6 12-1-1991 Founding a Republic of Laws: The Rule of Law Ideal in Early American Constitutional Theory Robert Moye Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/sigma Recommended Citation Moye, Robert (1991) "Founding a Republic of Laws: The Rule of Law Ideal in Early American Constitutional Theory," Sigma: Journal of Political and International Studies: Vol. 9 , Article 6. Available at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/sigma/vol9/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Sigma: Journal of Political and International Studies by an authorized editor of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. , Founding a Republic of Laws: The Rule of Law Ideal in Early American Constitutional Theory by Robert Moye Introduction contemporary implications. Their constitu­ tional experiment attempted, among other Although there is a wealth of scholarship things, to minimize the tendency toward available on the political and constitutional arbitrary government by incorporating the theories of the American Founders, many rule of law ideal in their governing institu­ commentaries overlook or misunderstand tions and procedures. While most scholars one of the most important elements in the recognize the great care with which the Framers' thought: their desire to implement Founders refashioned the nation's authorita­ the rule of law ideal into the new national tive institutions, they often ignore important government. Much of this confusion may procedural aspects of constitutional theory; be attributed to contemporary disagreement some even exacerbate this mistake by dis­ about what the rule of law actually implies, missing certain of the Constitutions' proce­ and the remainder to a mistaken belief of dural innovations as unsophisticated. what the term meant for the Founders. In Fortunately, some scholars avoid such current parlance, the term suggests only a errors. Noting the enormous difference minimal equality--that no person should be between rule by established legal procedures "above the law"--but the concept meant a and rule by an unpredictable human will, great deal more to the Founders. George and Scarlett Graham observe that: During the nation's formative years, American statesmen had a clear conception Underlying each principle, institution, and practice of what the term "the rule of law" meant to explored by the Founders was one basic presuppo­ classical thinkers, as well as the ideal's sition that was unchallenged by any theory of RULE OF LAW IDEAL 51 experience brought to their deliberations: the informed political judgement on the value of government to be founded must be a government of procedure. In fact, the rule of law has been law rather than of men. (1977, xiii) described as a political ideal which defines ~e nature of law itself and imposes limita­ In this paper, I will attempt to show that the tions on government (Hayek 1960, 206). American Founders' constitutional theories Sor:ne modern commentators dispute this were influenced by their perceptions of the claIm; but, for the Founders, the notion of rule of law ideal and its procedural implica­ the rule of law was a legal ideal which tions. I do not argue that the Founders were informed the time-honored procedures order­ uninspired by other sources (i.e. classical ing a free society. economics, protestant religion, civic virtue, or their faith in "enlightened" reason), but rather that this type of explanation offers, at The Ori&ins and Development of an Ideal best, only an incomplete picture of the Founder's intentions. A truer picture of the The philosophers of ancient Greece and Framers' motivations must also include their Rome were among the first to formulate the commitment to the rule of law ideal and its concrete implications of what later came to traditional emphasis on legal procedures. be called "the rule of law." In his 1960 To liberal statesmen living before and work ~ Constitution of Liberty, Austrian during the Founding era, there seemed to be economIst F. A. Hayek challenged the a fairly obvious, necessary connection be­ pr~vailing ass~mption that ancient political tween the rule of law and the legitimacy of phIlosophy rejected an individualistic con­ a government. Although they rarely em­ ception of personal liberty . He insisted that, ployed the phrase "rule of law," they made for many Greeks, government by legal frequent references to the ideal and its implications in a myriad of documented p~~u~es (which he calls isonomia) , as dIStingUIshed from human will or caprice discussions on the subject. The Founders entailed certain conditions. Those stan: and their intellectual predecessors envisioned dards, as described by the lawgiver Solon, the legal processes of any legitimate political were that 1) all citizens, regardless of class, system as limited by certain procedural would share the same laws, and 2) that the norms implied by the rule of law ideal: government would abide by known and these included nulla poena sin lege (Usually certain rules (Hayek 1960, 165). Hayek translated as "no punishment in the absence further argued that many Greeks even pre­ of a crime"), due process, just compensa­ ferred government by isonomia over demo­ ~on, trial by jury, the general and prospec­ kratia, or equal participation, because estab­ ~ve na~re of legal statutes, and the prohibi­ lished legal procedures protected their free­ tion agamst ex post facto laws and bills of dom (165). For the Greeks then, a free attainder. government was a government of law, since Given the Founders' commitment to legal procedures, by definition, placed individual liberty, the line separating their limitations on the exercise of power in any legal conventions from liberal political government that claimed legal sanction. theory often becomes tenuous or even Spurred by the ancient Greeks most indiscernible. From the persp~tive of the liberal thinkers recognized that a as Framers, the legal process itself reflected an l~w, opposed to a command or some other direc- 52 PSA REVIEW tive, implied a certain generality of purpose (Hayek 1960, 164). In fact, legal equality and prospectivity of scope (Wormuth 1949, implied more in the traditional, British 10). The equal, general, public, and pro­ context than an individual's formal standing spective nature of human law suggested that before a court. Hayek notes that the strug­ legal procedures, by definition, could serve gle between Parliament and the monarchy as an effective curb on sovereign caprice. further defmed the rule of law to include a Equally important, while ill-suited to ad­ prohibition on the exercise of arbitrary vance certain policy goals, the municipal power: not simply power exercised by an law could function as a facilitator for the unauthorized source, but rather a usage in actions of an individual. In governments violation of general, fundamental rules which claimed to serve the people, the rule (169). The rule of law principle of generali­ of law ideal encouraged the rulers to restrain ty implied equality under the law, and pro­ their actions and protect the liberty of their spectivity required that legal judgments be subjects. Even Plato, whom many commen­ based on the results of individual choices, tators paint as a totalitarian, intimated that not on human caprice (Wormuth 1949,212). "a primary function of government was to Francis D. Wormuth has observed that protect and maintain the law of [and for] the in classic constitutional theory, the doctrine people" (Reynolds 1987, 83). of separation of powers is a vehicle for The influence of the classical rule of law safeguarding the generality of rules: keep­ ideal was not wholly a Greek phenomena. ing the legislature from enforcing its own In ancient Rome, Cicero noted that freedom laws, and the executive from judging its should never be confused with lawlessness; own case (1949, 8). During the English liberty actually hinged on the certainty Civil Wars, John Lilburne, a leader of the supplied by general rules. Such rules, or radical Leveler party, advocated separating leges legwn, served as both a guide for the power among the distinct arms of the British citizen and a restraint on the state (Hayek government organization as a way of confin­ 1960, 167). Such a notion of liberty im­ ing the legislature to enacting only" general plied a relationship, analogous to a contract, and prospective rules" (Hickman 1983, between the people and their rulers 369). Although Parliament could not be (Reynolds 1987, 84). Indeed, the law func­ persuaded, nearly every American thinker of tioned as an equally accessible protector of the Founding era eventually accepted Mon­ the people's prerogatives (Hayek 1960, tesquieu's separation of powers as an essen­ 166). Although this ideal did not reflect tial part of constitutional theory (369). later Imperial practices, the "recognized During the English Civil Wars this ultimate basis" for all laws in ancient Rome "Enlightenment" conception of political was professedly the will or consent of the institutions managed to win the near-univer­ people themselves (Reynolds 1987, 84). sal acceptance of ideas like common con­ The ancient rule of law ideal received a sent, the separation of powers, an indepen­ warm reception in sixteenth-century Eng­ dent judiciary, and written constitutions. land. The terminology gradually changed Significantly, each of these ideas is based on from the anglicized "isonomy" to "equality the notion of the rule of law. Although in before the law," or "a government of laws, " Great Britain, especially just prior to the and finally to "the rule of law," but the Colonial rebellion, the classical concepts concept of isonomia remained the same were often subordinated to policy goals, RULE OF LAW IDEAL 53 they have remained an integral part of mod­ Blackstone further remarks that the legal ern conceptions about legitimate govern­ relationship between individual property ment.
Recommended publications
  • Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (In a Constitutional Democracy)
    Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 2013 Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy) Imer Flores Georgetown Law Center, [email protected] Georgetown Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 12-161 This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/1115 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2156455 Imer Flores, Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy), in LAW, LIBERTY, AND THE RULE OF LAW 77-101 (Imer B. Flores & Kenneth E. Himma eds., Springer Netherlands 2013) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Legislation Commons, and the Rule of Law Commons Chapter6 Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy) lmer B. Flores Tse-Kung asked, saying "Is there one word which may serve as a rule of practice for all one's life?" K'ung1u-tzu said: "Is not reciprocity (i.e. 'shu') such a word? What you do not want done to yourself, do not ckJ to others." Confucius (2002, XV, 23, 225-226). 6.1 Introduction Taking the "rule of law" seriously implies readdressing and reassessing the claims that relate it to law and liberty, in general, and to a constitutional democracy, in particular. My argument is five-fold and has an addendum which intends to bridge the gap between Eastern and Western civilizations,
    [Show full text]
  • Direct and Economic Democracy in Ancient Athens and Its Significance Today
    SOCIETY & NATURE, Vol. 1, No. 1 (1992) Direct and Economic Democracy in Ancient Athens and its Significance Today TAKIS FOTOPOULOS Abstract This article examines the intrinsic relationship between direct and economic democracy as it was exemplified in the case of classical Athens. The aim is to show that the final failure of the Athenian democracy was not due, as is usually asserted, to the innate weaknesses of direct democracy but, firstly, due to the fact that it always remained partial, embracing only part of its population, and, second, that it was never completed by a corresponding economic democracy. This fact implies that any attempt today at establishing direct democracy, which is not complemented by economic democracy, is condemned to failure. During the Athenian celebrations for the 2,500th anniversary of Cleisthenes' reforms (where there appeared a ridiculous show of the elite who celebrated, by themselves, the most anti- elitist form of democracy that has ever existed!), as well as in the wider `discussion' that followed on the significance of direct democracy, no reference was made to the relationship between direct and economic democracy. As I will try to show, however, the development of the Athenian democracy amongst its citizens (that is with the slaves and women excluded) kept pace with a determined effort to diminish the socio-economic differences between the citizens. Also, the decline itself of the Athenian democracy was, in my view, directly connected with its failure to become universal, and with the contradiction created by the fact that the political equality which the Athenian democracy had established for its citizens was, in the last instance, founded on economic inequality.
    [Show full text]
  • Download (4MB)
    ARISTOTLE AND DEMOCRACY A PhD Thesis submitted by Charalambos Ioannou Papageorgiou k k k k University College University of London LONDON 1991 ** ProQuest Number: 10609803 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a com plete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest ProQuest 10609803 Published by ProQuest LLC(2017). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States C ode Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC. 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106- 1346 2 ABSTRACT The thesis undertakes a reconstruction and critical assessment of Aristotle's theory of democracy. The process of reconstruction requires at first the collection and organisation of the relevant material, since Aristotle's references to democracy, although numerous, are scattered throughout his political and ethical writings. A chapter is devoted to this task. This chapter also seeks to describe the historical and intellectual context in which Aristotle developed his ideas on democracy. The thesis then attempts to identify the fundamental principles which underlie Aristotle's conception of democracy. These are examined both in their relation to one another and also in their relation to the fundamental principles of Aristotle's political philosophy in general. Aristotle's teleological conception of the state and his theory of distributive justice based on proportionate equality are singled out as the salient principles which shape his conception, classification and criticism of democracy.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Athenian Democracy.Pdf
    Rethinking Athenian Democracy A dissertation presented by Daniela Louise Cammack to The Department of Government in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Political Science Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts January 2013 © 2013 Daniela Cammack All rights reserved. Professor Richard Tuck Daniela Cammack Abstract Conventional accounts of classical Athenian democracy represent the assembly as the primary democratic institution in the Athenian political system. This looks reasonable in the light of modern democracy, which has typically developed through the democratization of legislative assemblies. Yet it conflicts with the evidence at our disposal. Our ancient sources suggest that the most significant and distinctively democratic institution in Athens was the courts, where decisions were made by large panels of randomly selected ordinary citizens with no possibility of appeal. This dissertation reinterprets Athenian democracy as “dikastic democracy” (from the Greek dikastēs, “judge”), defined as a mode of government in which ordinary citizens rule principally through their control of the administration of justice. It begins by casting doubt on two major planks in the modern interpretation of Athenian democracy: first, that it rested on a conception of the “wisdom of the multitude” akin to that advanced by epistemic democrats today, and second that it was “deliberative,” meaning that mass discussion of political matters played a defining role. The first plank rests largely on an argument made by Aristotle in support of mass political participation, which I show has been comprehensively misunderstood. The second rests on the interpretation of the verb “bouleuomai” as indicating speech, but I suggest that it meant internal reflection in both the courts and the assembly.
    [Show full text]
  • Weak Rule of Law As the Primary Cause of Lower-Quality Latin American Democracies
    ABSTRACT Weak Rule of Law as the Primary Cause of Lower-Quality Latin American Democracies Dacie A. Bradley Director: Victor Hinojosa, Ph.D. Drawing on a deep tradition of rule of law literature, spanning from Aristotle to O’Donnell, this thesis argues that the main problem in modern Latin America is a weak rule of law evidenced by ineffective judicial systems unable to sustain vertical and horizontal accountability. A broad analysis of the necessary characteristics and conditions for democratic rule of law leads to mid-range theory on the application of these characteristics in combination with the unique challenges facing modern day Latin America. A case study of Peru examining crime rates and court systems supports gives evidence to the paramount importance of rule of law and its lack thereof within the state and the region as a whole. This lack of strong rule of law gives rise to a host of other current issues and undermines democratic institutions lowering the quality of democracy. APPROVED BY DIRECTOR OF HONORS THESIS: ______________________________________________________ Dr. Victor Hinojosa, Thesis Director, Department of Political Science APPROVED BY THE HONORS PROGRAM: __________________________________________________________________ Dr. Elizabeth Corey, Director DATE: _____________ WEAK RULE OF LAW AS THE PRIMARY CAUSE OF LOWER-QUALITY, LATIN AMERICAN DEMOCRACIES A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of Baylor University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Honors Program By Dacie A. Bradley Waco, Texas August 2020 TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter One: Rule of Law Tradition……………………………………………………...1 Chapter Two: Democratic Rule of Law in Modern Latin America……………………...23 Chapter Three: Crime and the Court Systems of Peru: A Case Study…………………..46 Chapter Four: Concluding Remarks on the Strength of Peruvian Rule of Law…………68 Bibliography……………………………………………………………………………..76 ii CHAPTER ONE: Rule of Law Tradition Latin America has been undergoing a process of democratization for the past thirty years resulting in a plethora of very different outcomes.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy & Social Criticism
    Philosophy & Social Criticism http://psc.sagepub.com/ Apathy: the democratic disease Jeffrey E. Green Philosophy Social Criticism 2004 30: 745 DOI: 10.1177/0191453704045763 The online version of this article can be found at: http://psc.sagepub.com/content/30/5-6/745 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com Additional services and information for Philosophy & Social Criticism can be found at: Email Alerts: http://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://psc.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav >> Version of Record - Dec 6, 2004 What is This? Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at UNIV OF PENNSYLVANIA on May 6, 2013 12 045763 (to/d) 2/9/04 11:38 am Page 745 Jeffrey E. Green Apathy: the democratic disease Abstract This essay turns to ancient sources in order to rethink the relation- ship between political apathy and democracy. If modern democratic theorists place political apathy entirely outside of democracy – either as a destructive limit upon the full realization of a democratic polity, or, more sanguinely, as a pragmatic necessity which tempers democracy so that it may function in a workable yet watered-down form – the ancients conceived of political apathy as a peculiarly democratic phenomenon that was likely to flourish in tandem with the expansion of egalitarian institutional structures and moral ideas. Evidence for the ancient recognition of political apathy as a uniquely demo- cratic kind of affliction centers on, but is not limited to, three main sources. In literature, the Homeric epic, and specifically the story of Achilles, present apathy for politics and commitment to human equality as synonymous forces.
    [Show full text]
  • How Ancient Greece and Rome Provide Insight for Citizenship and Immigration in the 21St Century
    Xavier University Exhibit Honors Bachelor of Arts Undergraduate 2019-4 Comparing Ancient to Modern: How Ancient Greece and Rome Provide Insight for Citizenship and Immigration in the 21st Century Viktoria Schumacher Follow this and additional works at: https://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, Classical Archaeology and Art History Commons, Classical Literature and Philology Commons, and the Other Classics Commons Comparing Ancient to Modern: How Ancient Greece and Rome Provide Insight for Citizenship and Immigration in the 21st Century Viktoria Schumacher CPHAB Senior Thesis Xavier University 2019 Director: Thomas Strunk Readers: Jay Arns and Tim Severyn 1 Introduction Migration plays an extremely vital role in the advancement of human societies. Despite our world’s staggering history with immigration, the conversation about how to manage current issues has fallen flat. Patterns of immigration have demonstrated that the number of migrants, especially refugees, has peaked in the 21st century, and numbers are still raising steadily.1 The increase is caused by an abundance of factors, including major events such as the Syrian refugee crisis, harmful or unfavorable political climates, and ongoing gang violence in Mexico and Central America. These issues have gone largely unsolved, causing immense suffering resulting in millions of people to migrate out of their home countries. Movement away from home due to tumultuous times is not a new concept. In fact, migration history demonstrates that major movement of people is a characteristic of our world. I posit that looking at migration in our past as well as examining its effects on different societies will offer a perspective that has otherwise been ignored.
    [Show full text]
  • Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy the Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of Its Impending End
    Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy The Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of its Impending End A doctoral thesis by O. H. Linderborg Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Engelska Parken, 7-0042, Thunbergsvägen 3H, Uppsala, Monday, 3 September 2018 at 14:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Docent Elton Barker (Open University). Abstract Linderborg, O. H. 2018. Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy. The Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of its Impending End. 224 pp. Uppsala: Department of Linguistics and Philology, Uppsala University. ISBN 978-91-506-2703-9. This investigation proposes a historical theory of the origins of political philosophy. It is assumed that political philosophy was made possible by a new form of political thinking commencing with the inauguration of the first direct democracies in Ancient Greece. The pristine turn from elite rule to rule of the people – or to δημοκρατία, a term coined after the event – brought with it the first ever political theory, wherein fundamentally different societal orders, or different principles of societal rule, could be argumentatively compared. The inauguration of this alternative-envisioning “secular” political theory is equaled with the beginnings of classical political theory and explained as the outcome of the conjoining of a new form of constitutionalized political thought (cratistic thinking) and a new emphasis brought to the inner consistency of normative reasoning (‘internal critique’). The original form of political philosophy, Classical Political Philosophy, originated when a political thought launched, wherein non-divinely sanctioned visions of transcendence of the prevailing rule, as well as of the full range of alternatives disclosed by Classical Political Theory, first began to be envisioned.
    [Show full text]
  • Herodotus' Constitutional Debate and the Spread of Isonomia
    Herodotus’ Constitutional Debate and the Spread of Isonomia Herodotus’ depiction of the Constitutional Debate in Persia prior to the ascension of Darius in Book 3 (3.80-83) has been questioned by scholars both for its location of apparent fifth-century Greek political language in sixth-century Persia and for its seeming lack of connection to the surrounding narrative, as radical political concepts such as isonomia are strikingly introduced only to be immediately obscured by the resumption of the Persian monarchy (e.g. Connor 1971; Pelling 2002). By examining subsequent passages in which Herodotus discusses isonomia, my paper shows that the introduction of this concept in the Constitutional Debate forms an integral part of Herodotus’ narrative, as isonomia spreads from the Persian court to Greek Ionia. The term isonomia occurs four times in the text of Herodotus. While the first two (3.80.2 and 3.83.1) occur during the Constitutional Debate, Herodotus next uses the term during the insurrection on Samos when Maeandrius proposes to relinquish his power, absolve the tyranny, and establish isonomia (3.142.2-3). As previous scholars have noted (Immerwahr 1957; Raaflaub 2004), the language attributed to Maeandrius during this episode recalls the speech of Otanes in the Constitutional Debate. But the significance of this apparent allusion to Otanes’ speech and the role of isonomia here has not been fully explored. Herodotus’ inclusion of Darius’ decision to send the same Otanes to Samos to deal with the insurrection further emphasizes the connection between the two passages. The surprising appearance of Otanes creates the impression that isonomia has spread from Persia to Samos along with him.
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of Rule of Law in Hayek's Thought, 1935–1955
    No. 10-38 July 2010 WORKING PAPER THE EVOLUTION OF RULE OF LAW IN HAYEK’S THOUGHT, 1935–1955 By Steven D. Ealy The ideas presented in this research are the author’s and do not represent official positions of the Mercatus Center at George Mason University. THE EVOLUTION OF RULE OF LAW IN HAYEK‘S THOUGHT, 1935-1955: FROM COLLECTIVIST ECONOMIC PLANNING TO THE POLITICAL IDEAL OF THE RULE OF LAW Steven D. Ealy Senior Fellow, Liberty Fund, Inc. Abstract: Friedrich Hayek‘s interest in the ideal of rule of law as the centerpiece of a free society grew out of his analysis of the nature of centralized economic planning. This paper traces the development of rule of law in Hayek‘s thought from his early studies on economic planning through his political analysis of economics and political life as contained in The Road to Serfdom to his lectures on ―The Political Ideal of the Rule of Law‖ delivered in Cairo in 1955. These lectures became the core of The Constitution of Liberty, in which Hayek integrates his concern with rule of law with basic philosophical principles, on the one hand, and an analysis of approaches to public policy on the other. Dr. Steven D. Ealy (M.A., Government, Claremont Graduate University and Ph.D., Political Science, University of Georgia) is a senior fellow at Liberty Fund. Before joining Liberty Fund in 1993, he was professor of government at Armstrong State College (now Armstrong Atlantic State University) in Savannah, Georgia (1981–1993), and assistant professor of political science at Western Carolina University (1979–1981).
    [Show full text]
  • "Herodotus and the Question Why," Written by Christopher Pelling
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship Political Science 2021 Review of "Herodotus and the Question Why," written by Christopher Pelling Joel A. Schlosser Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs Part of the Political Science Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. https://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/57 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Christopher Pelling, (2019) Herodotus and the Question Why. Austin: University of Texas Press. xv + 360 pp. $55.00. ISBN 9781477318324 (hbk). ‘Does Herodotus think democracy a good thing?’ Christopher Pelling asks toward the end of his erudite and wide-ranging Herodotus and the Question Why. ‘The answer surely will be “yes and no”’ (p. 234). Freedom and democracy often lead to disturbing consequences as well as inspiring ones; Herodotus praises nothing without also revealing, sometimes subtly, its potential downsides. Strengths and weaknesses go closely together, both building and then imperiling greatness. Herodotus’ ability to hold these opposing interpretations together is not, Pelling asserts, an incoherence of thought. It is just a paradox. Summoning many decades of inquiries into Herodotus (and citing 35 of his own articles, chapters, and books on the subject), Pelling centers the work of explanation in his study of Herodotus. Explanation appears as one of the motivations for the Histories themselves, which Herodotus describes (in Pelling’s translation) as ‘why they [sc. the Greeks and the barbarians] came to war with one another’ (p.
    [Show full text]
  • From Athens to Atlantis: Democratic Mythmaking in Classical Greece
    FROM ATHENS TO ATLANTIS: DEMOCRATIC MYTHMAKING IN CLASSICAL GREECE Casey Edward Stegman A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Department of Political Science. Chapel Hill 2013 Approved by: Michael Lienesch Susan Bickford Jeff Spinner-Halev ©2013 Casey Edward Stegman ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii ABSTRACT CASEY EDWARD STEGMAN: From Athens to Atlantis: Democratic Mythmaking in Classical Greece (Under the direction of Michael Lienesch) This paper is concerned with political myth and the process of political mythmaking in Classical Athens (5th-4th centuries B.C.E.), and by extension, in other democracies as well. While there has been a number of political science works that have looked at how monopolistic political myths are formed in authoritarian or otherwise restricted nationalist regimes, few have considered how political myths are created and transmitted in democracies. This paper addresses this dearth in the literature by investigating the understudied phenomenon that it labels democratic mythmaking. In looking at Classical Athens, this paper illustrates that democratic mythmaking has been a part of democracy since its inception. Discussing Herodotus, The Old Oligarch, Thucydides, Isocrates, and Plato, this paper illustrates that their works: 1) refer to and describe other democratic myths; 2) contribute myths of their own; and 3) demonstrate that the process of political mythmaking in a democracy is pluralistic, contested, and above all democratic. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This thesis reflects the high level of encouragement and intellectual support I have received from faculty and friends since arriving at UNC-Chapel Hill as a graduate student in the department of political science.
    [Show full text]