6.5. the Recursion Theorem the Recursion

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

6.5. the Recursion Theorem the Recursion 6.5. The Recursion Theorem The Recursion . The recursion Theorem, due to Kleene, is a fundamental result in recursion Extended Rice . theory. Creative and . Theorem 6.5.1 (Recursion Theorem, Version 1) Let ϕ0, ϕ1,... be any acceptable indexing of the partial recursive functions. For every total re- cursive function f, there is some n such that ϕn = ϕf(n). Home Page Title Page The recursion Theorem can be strengthened as follows: JJ II Theorem 6.5.2 (Recursion Theorem, Version 2) Let ϕ0, ϕ1,... be any J I acceptable indexing of the partial recursive functions. There is a total Page 388 of 405 recursive function h such that for all x ∈ N, if ϕx is total, then Go Back ϕϕx(h(x)) = ϕh(x). Full Screen Close Quit A third version of the recursion Theorem is given below. The Recursion . Theorem 6.5.3 (Recursion Theorem, Version 3) For all n ≥ 1, there is Extended Rice . a total recursive function h of n + 1 arguments, such that for all x ∈ , if N Creative and . ϕx is a total recursive function of n + 1 arguments, then ϕϕx(h(x,x1,...,xn),x1,...,xn) = ϕh(x,x1,...,xn), for all x1, . , xn ∈ N. Home Page As a first application of the recursion theorem, we can show that there is Title Page an index n such that ϕn is the constant function with output n. JJ II J I Loosely speaking, ϕn prints its own name. Let f be the recursive function such that Page 389 of 405 f(x, y) = x Go Back for all x, y ∈ N. Full Screen Close Quit By the s-m-n Theorem, there is a recursive function g such that The Recursion . ϕg(x)(y) = f(x, y) = x Extended Rice . Creative and . for all x, y ∈ N. By the recursion Theorem 6.5.1, there is some n such that ϕg(n) = ϕn, Home Page the constant function with value n. Title Page As a second application, we get a very short proof of Rice’s Theorem. JJ II J I Let C be such that PC 6= ∅ and PC 6= N, and let j ∈ PC and k ∈ N − PC . Page 390 of 405 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit Define the function f as follows: The Recursion . j if x∈ / P , f(x) = C Extended Rice . k if x ∈ PC , Creative and . If PC is recursive, then f is recursive. By the recursion Theorem 6.5.1, there is some n such that ϕf(n) = ϕn. Home Page Title Page But then, we have n ∈ PC iff f(n) ∈/ PC JJ II by definition of f, and thus, J I ϕf(n) 6= ϕn, Page 391 of 405 a contradiction. Go Back Full Screen Hence, PC is not recursive. Close As a third application, we have the following Lemma: Quit The Recursion . Lemma 6.5.4 Let C be a set of partial recursive functions and let Extended Rice . Creative and . A = {x ∈ N | ϕx ∈ C}. The set A is not reducible to its complement A. The recursion Theorem can also be used to show that functions defined by recursive definitions other than primitive recursion are partial recursive. Home Page This is the case for the function known as Ackermann’s function, defined Title Page recursively as follows: JJ II f(0, y) = y + 1, J I f(x + 1, 0) = f(x, 1), Page 392 of 405 f(x + 1, y + 1) = f(x, f(x + 1, y)). Go Back It can be shown that this function is not primitive recursive. Intuitively, Full Screen it outgrows all primitive recursive functions. Close Quit However, f is recursive, but this is not so obvious. The Recursion . We can use the recursion Theorem to prove that f is recursive. Consider Extended Rice . the following definition by cases: Creative and . g(n, 0, y) = y + 1, g(n, x + 1, 0) = ϕuniv(n, x, 1), g(n, x + 1, y + 1) = ϕuniv(n, x, ϕuniv(n, x + 1, y)). Home Page Clearly, g is partial recursive. By the s-m-n Theorem, there is a recursive Title Page function h such that ϕh(n)(x, y) = g(n, x, y). JJ II J I By the recursion Theorem, there is an m such that Page 393 of 405 ϕ = ϕ . h(m) m Go Back Full Screen Therefore, the partial recursive function ϕm(x, y) satisfies the definition of Close Ackermann’s function. Quit We showed in a previous Section that ϕm(x, y) is a total function, and thus, Ackermann’s function is a total recursive function. The Recursion . Extended Rice . Hence, the recursion Theorem justifies the use of certain recursive defini- Creative and . tions. However, note that there are some recursive definition that are only satisfied by the completely undefined function. In the next Section, we prove the extended Rice Theorem. Home Page Title Page JJ II J I Page 394 of 405 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit 6.6. Extended Rice Theorem The Recursion . The extended Rice Theorem characterizes the sets of partial recursive func- Extended Rice . tions C such that PC is r.e. Creative and . First, we need to discuss a way of indexing the partial recursive functions that have a finite domain. Using the uniform projection function Π, we define the primitive recursive Home Page function F such that Title Page F (x, y) = Π(y + 1, Π (x) + 1, Π (x)). 1 2 JJ II J I We also define the sequence of partial functions P ,P ,... as follows: 0 1 Page 395 of 405 n F (x, y) − 1 if 0 < F (x, y) and y < Π (x) + 1, P (y) = 1 Go Back x undefined otherwise. Full Screen Close Quit The Recursion . Lemma 6.6.1 Every Px is a partial recursive function with finite domain, Extended Rice . and every partial recursive function with finite domain is equal to some P . x Creative and . The easy part of the extended Rice Theorem is the following lemma: Recall that given any two partial functions f: A → B and g: A → B, we Home Page say that g extends f iff f ⊆ g, which means that g(x) is defined whenever f(x) is defined, and if so, g(x) = f(x). Title Page JJ II J I Lemma 6.6.2 Let C be a set of partial recursive functions. If there is an Page 396 of 405 r.e. set A such that, ϕx ∈ C iff there is some y ∈ A such that ϕx extends P , then P = {x | ϕ ∈ C} is r.e. y C x Go Back Full Screen Close Quit Proof . Lemma 6.6.2 can be restated as The Recursion . PC = {x | ∃y ∈ A, Py ⊆ ϕx}. Extended Rice . Creative and . If A is empty, so is PC , and PC is r.e. Otherwise, let f be a recursive function such that A = range(f). Home Page Title Page Let ψ be the following partial recursive function: JJ II n Π (z) if P ⊆ ϕ , ψ(z) = 1 f(Π2(z)) Π1(z) undefined otherwise. J I Page 397 of 405 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit It is clear that PC = range(ψ). The Recursion . Extended Rice . Creative and . To see that ψ is partial recursive, write ψ(z) as follows: Π1(z) if ∀w ≤ Π1(f(Π2(z))) ψ(z) = [F (f(Π2(z)), w) > 0 ⊃ ϕ (w) = F (f(Π (z)), w) − 1], Π1(z) 2 undefined otherwise. Home Page Title Page JJ II J I Page 398 of 405 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit To establish the converse of Lemma 6.6.2, we need two Lemmas. The Recursion . Extended Rice . Creative and . Lemma 6.6.3 If PC is r.e. and ϕ ∈ C, then there is some Py ⊆ ϕ such that Py ∈ C. As a corollary of Lemma 6.6.3, we note that TOTAL is not r.e. Home Page Lemma 6.6.4 If PC is r.e., ϕ ∈ C, and ϕ ⊆ ψ, where ψ is a partial Title Page recursive function, then ψ ∈ C. JJ II J I Observe that Lemma 6.6.4 yields a new proof that TOTAL is not r.e. Finally, we can prove the extended Rice Theorem. Page 399 of 405 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit The Recursion . Theorem 6.6.5 (Extended Rice Theorem) The set PC is r.e. iff there is Extended Rice . an r.e. set A such that Creative and . ϕx ∈ C iff ∃y ∈ A (Py ⊆ ϕx). Proof . Let PC = dom(ϕi). Using the s-m-n Theorem, there is a recursive function k such that Home Page ϕk(y) = Py Title Page for all y ∈ N. JJ II Define the r.e. set A such that J I Page 400 of 405 A = dom(ϕi ◦ k). Go Back Full Screen Close Quit Then, y ∈ A iff ϕi(k(y)) ↓ iff Py ∈ C. The Recursion . Extended Rice . Creative and . Next, using Lemma 6.6.3 and Lemma 6.6.4, it is easy to see that ϕx ∈ C iff ∃y ∈ A (Py ⊆ ϕx). Home Page Title Page JJ II J I Page 401 of 405 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit 6.7. Creative and Productive Sets The Recursion . In this section, we discuss some special sets that have important applica- Extended Rice . tions in logic: creative and productive sets. Creative and . The concepts to be described are illustrated by the following situation: Assume that Wx ⊆ K Home Page for some x ∈ N.
Recommended publications
  • 6.5 the Recursion Theorem
    6.5. THE RECURSION THEOREM 417 6.5 The Recursion Theorem The recursion Theorem, due to Kleene, is a fundamental result in recursion theory. Theorem 6.5.1 (Recursion Theorem, Version 1 )Letϕ0,ϕ1,... be any ac- ceptable indexing of the partial recursive functions. For every total recursive function f, there is some n such that ϕn = ϕf(n). The recursion Theorem can be strengthened as follows. Theorem 6.5.2 (Recursion Theorem, Version 2 )Letϕ0,ϕ1,... be any ac- ceptable indexing of the partial recursive functions. There is a total recursive function h such that for all x ∈ N,ifϕx is total, then ϕϕx(h(x)) = ϕh(x). 418 CHAPTER 6. ELEMENTARY RECURSIVE FUNCTION THEORY A third version of the recursion Theorem is given below. Theorem 6.5.3 (Recursion Theorem, Version 3 ) For all n ≥ 1, there is a total recursive function h of n +1 arguments, such that for all x ∈ N,ifϕx is a total recursive function of n +1arguments, then ϕϕx(h(x,x1,...,xn),x1,...,xn) = ϕh(x,x1,...,xn), for all x1,...,xn ∈ N. As a first application of the recursion theorem, we can show that there is an index n such that ϕn is the constant function with output n. Loosely speaking, ϕn prints its own name. Let f be the recursive function such that f(x, y)=x for all x, y ∈ N. 6.5. THE RECURSION THEOREM 419 By the s-m-n Theorem, there is a recursive function g such that ϕg(x)(y)=f(x, y)=x for all x, y ∈ N.
    [Show full text]
  • April 22 7.1 Recursion Theorem
    CSE 431 Theory of Computation Spring 2014 Lecture 7: April 22 Lecturer: James R. Lee Scribe: Eric Lei Disclaimer: These notes have not been subjected to the usual scrutiny reserved for formal publications. They may be distributed outside this class only with the permission of the Instructor. An interesting question about Turing machines is whether they can reproduce themselves. A Turing machine cannot be be defined in terms of itself, but can it still somehow print its own source code? The answer to this question is yes, as we will see in the recursion theorem. Afterward we will see some applications of this result. 7.1 Recursion Theorem Our end goal is to have a Turing machine that prints its own source code and operates on it. Last lecture we proved the existence of a Turing machine called SELF that ignores its input and prints its source code. We construct a similar proof for the recursion theorem. We will also need the following lemma proved last lecture. ∗ ∗ Lemma 7.1 There exists a computable function q :Σ ! Σ such that q(w) = hPwi, where Pw is a Turing machine that prints w and hats. Theorem 7.2 (Recursion theorem) Let T be a Turing machine that computes a function t :Σ∗ × Σ∗ ! Σ∗. There exists a Turing machine R that computes a function r :Σ∗ ! Σ∗, where for every w, r(w) = t(hRi; w): The theorem says that for an arbitrary computable function t, there is a Turing machine R that computes t on hRi and some input. Proof: We construct a Turing Machine R in three parts, A, B, and T , where T is given by the statement of the theorem.
    [Show full text]
  • Intuitionism on Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem
    The Yale Undergraduate Research Journal Volume 2 Issue 1 Spring 2021 Article 31 2021 Incomplete? Or Indefinite? Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem Quinn Crawford Yale University Follow this and additional works at: https://elischolar.library.yale.edu/yurj Part of the Mathematics Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Crawford, Quinn (2021) "Incomplete? Or Indefinite? Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem," The Yale Undergraduate Research Journal: Vol. 2 : Iss. 1 , Article 31. Available at: https://elischolar.library.yale.edu/yurj/vol2/iss1/31 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by EliScholar – A Digital Platform for Scholarly Publishing at Yale. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Yale Undergraduate Research Journal by an authorized editor of EliScholar – A Digital Platform for Scholarly Publishing at Yale. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Incomplete? Or Indefinite? Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem Cover Page Footnote Written for Professor Sun-Joo Shin’s course PHIL 437: Philosophy of Mathematics. This article is available in The Yale Undergraduate Research Journal: https://elischolar.library.yale.edu/yurj/vol2/iss1/ 31 Crawford: Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem Crawford | Philosophy Incomplete? Or Indefinite? Intuitionism on Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem By Quinn Crawford1 1Department of Philosophy, Yale University ABSTRACT This paper analyzes two natural-looking arguments that seek to leverage Gödel’s first incompleteness theo- rem for and against intuitionism, concluding in both cases that the argument is unsound because it equivo- cates on the meaning of “proof,” which differs between formalism and intuitionism.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory
    Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory To criticize mathematics for its abstraction is to miss the point entirely. Abstraction is what makes mathematics work. If you concentrate too closely on too limited an application of a mathematical idea, you rob the mathematician of his most important tools: analogy, generality, and simplicity. – Ian Stewart Does God play dice? The mathematics of chaos In mathematics, a proof is a demonstration that, assuming certain axioms, some statement is necessarily true. That is, a proof is a logical argument, not an empir- ical one. One must demonstrate that a proposition is true in all cases before it is considered a theorem of mathematics. An unproven proposition for which there is some sort of empirical evidence is known as a conjecture. Mathematical logic is the framework upon which rigorous proofs are built. It is the study of the principles and criteria of valid inference and demonstrations. Logicians have analyzed set theory in great details, formulating a collection of axioms that affords a broad enough and strong enough foundation to mathematical reasoning. The standard form of axiomatic set theory is denoted ZFC and it consists of the Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) axioms combined with the axiom of choice (C). Each of the axioms included in this theory expresses a property of sets that is widely accepted by mathematicians. It is unfortunately true that careless use of set theory can lead to contradictions. Avoiding such contradictions was one of the original motivations for the axiomatization of set theory. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. LOGIC AND SET THEORY A rigorous analysis of set theory belongs to the foundations of mathematics and mathematical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Theorem Proving in Classical Logic
    MEng Individual Project Imperial College London Department of Computing Theorem Proving in Classical Logic Supervisor: Dr. Steffen van Bakel Author: David Davies Second Marker: Dr. Nicolas Wu June 16, 2021 Abstract It is well known that functional programming and logic are deeply intertwined. This has led to many systems capable of expressing both propositional and first order logic, that also operate as well-typed programs. What currently ties popular theorem provers together is their basis in intuitionistic logic, where one cannot prove the law of the excluded middle, ‘A A’ – that any proposition is either true or false. In classical logic this notion is provable, and the_: corresponding programs turn out to be those with control operators. In this report, we explore and expand upon the research about calculi that correspond with classical logic; and the problems that occur for those relating to first order logic. To see how these calculi behave in practice, we develop and implement functional languages for propositional and first order logic, expressing classical calculi in the setting of a theorem prover, much like Agda and Coq. In the first order language, users are able to define inductive data and record types; importantly, they are able to write computable programs that have a correspondence with classical propositions. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Steffen van Bakel, my supervisor, for his support throughout this project and helping find a topic of study based on my interests, for which I am incredibly grateful. His insight and advice have been invaluable. I would also like to thank my second marker, Nicolas Wu, for introducing me to the world of dependent types, and suggesting useful resources that have aided me greatly during this report.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Mathematical Foundations of Learning
    BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 39, Number 1, Pages 1{49 S 0273-0979(01)00923-5 Article electronically published on October 5, 2001 ON THE MATHEMATICAL FOUNDATIONS OF LEARNING FELIPE CUCKER AND STEVE SMALE The problem of learning is arguably at the very core of the problem of intelligence, both biological and artificial. T. Poggio and C.R. Shelton Introduction (1) A main theme of this report is the relationship of approximation to learning and the primary role of sampling (inductive inference). We try to emphasize relations of the theory of learning to the mainstream of mathematics. In particular, there are large roles for probability theory, for algorithms such as least squares,andfor tools and ideas from linear algebra and linear analysis. An advantage of doing this is that communication is facilitated and the power of core mathematics is more easily brought to bear. We illustrate what we mean by learning theory by giving some instances. (a) The understanding of language acquisition by children or the emergence of languages in early human cultures. (b) In Manufacturing Engineering, the design of a new wave of machines is an- ticipated which uses sensors to sample properties of objects before, during, and after treatment. The information gathered from these samples is to be analyzed by the machine to decide how to better deal with new input objects (see [43]). (c) Pattern recognition of objects ranging from handwritten letters of the alpha- bet to pictures of animals, to the human voice. Understanding the laws of learning plays a large role in disciplines such as (Cog- nitive) Psychology, Animal Behavior, Economic Decision Making, all branches of Engineering, Computer Science, and especially the study of human thought pro- cesses (how the brain works).
    [Show full text]
  • Plato on the Foundations of Modern Theorem Provers
    The Mathematics Enthusiast Volume 13 Number 3 Number 3 Article 8 8-2016 Plato on the foundations of Modern Theorem Provers Ines Hipolito Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme Part of the Mathematics Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Hipolito, Ines (2016) "Plato on the foundations of Modern Theorem Provers," The Mathematics Enthusiast: Vol. 13 : No. 3 , Article 8. Available at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme/vol13/iss3/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Mathematics Enthusiast by an authorized editor of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TME, vol. 13, no.3, p.303 Plato on the foundations of Modern Theorem Provers Inês Hipolito1 Nova University of Lisbon Abstract: Is it possible to achieve such a proof that is independent of both acts and dispositions of the human mind? Plato is one of the great contributors to the foundations of mathematics. He discussed, 2400 years ago, the importance of clear and precise definitions as fundamental entities in mathematics, independent of the human mind. In the seventh book of his masterpiece, The Republic, Plato states “arithmetic has a very great and elevating effect, compelling the soul to reason about abstract number, and rebelling against the introduction of visible or tangible objects into the argument” (525c). In the light of this thought, I will discuss the status of mathematical entities in the twentieth first century, an era when it is already possible to demonstrate theorems and construct formal axiomatic derivations of remarkable complexity with artificial intelligent agents the modern theorem provers.
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms and Theorems for Plane Geometry (Short Version)
    Axioms and theorems for plane geometry (Short Version) Basic axioms and theorems Axiom 1. If A; B are distinct points, then there is exactly one line containing both A and B. Axiom 2. AB = BA. Axiom 3. AB = 0 iff A = B. Axiom 4. If point C is between points A and B, then AC + BC = AB. Axiom 5. (The triangle inequality) If C is not between A and B, then AC + BC > AB. ◦ Axiom 6. Part (a): m(\BAC) = 0 iff B; A; C are collinear and A is not between B and C. Part (b): ◦ m(\BAC) = 180 iff B; A; C are collinear and A is between B and C. Axiom 7. Whenever two lines meet to make four angles, the measures of those four angles add up to 360◦. Axiom 8. Suppose that A; B; C are collinear points, with B between A and C, and that X is not collinear with A, B and C. Then m(\AXB) + m(\BXC) = m(\AXC). Moreover, m(\ABX) + m(\XBC) = m(\ABC). Axiom 9. Equals can be substituted for equals. Axiom 10. Given a point P and a line `, there is exactly one line through P parallel to `. Axiom 11. If ` and `0 are parallel lines and m is a line that meets them both, then alternate interior angles have equal measure, as do corresponding angles. Axiom 12. For any positive whole number n, and distinct points A; B, there is some C between A; B such that n · AC = AB. Axiom 13. For any positive whole number n and angle \ABC, there is a point D between A and C such that n · m(\ABD) = m(\ABC).
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected]
    Boise State University ScholarWorks Mathematics Undergraduate Theses Department of Mathematics 5-2014 Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.boisestate.edu/ math_undergraduate_theses Part of the Set Theory Commons Recommended Citation Rahim, Farighon Abdul, "Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice" (2014). Mathematics Undergraduate Theses. Paper 1. Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Advisor: Samuel Coskey Boise State University May 2014 1 Introduction Sets are all around us. A bag of potato chips, for instance, is a set containing certain number of individual chip’s that are its elements. University is another example of a set with students as its elements. By elements, we mean members. But sets should not be confused as to what they really are. A daughter of a blacksmith is an element of a set that contains her mother, father, and her siblings. Then this set is an element of a set that contains all the other families that live in the nearby town. So a set itself can be an element of a bigger set. In mathematics, axiom is defined to be a rule or a statement that is accepted to be true regardless of having to prove it. In a sense, axioms are self evident. In set theory, we deal with sets. Each time we state an axiom, we will do so by considering sets. Example of the set containing the blacksmith family might make it seem as if sets are finite.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Proof Release 3.18.4
    Logic and Proof Release 3.18.4 Jeremy Avigad, Robert Y. Lewis, and Floris van Doorn Sep 10, 2021 CONTENTS 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Mathematical Proof ............................................ 1 1.2 Symbolic Logic .............................................. 2 1.3 Interactive Theorem Proving ....................................... 4 1.4 The Semantic Point of View ....................................... 5 1.5 Goals Summarized ............................................ 6 1.6 About this Textbook ........................................... 6 2 Propositional Logic 7 2.1 A Puzzle ................................................. 7 2.2 A Solution ................................................ 7 2.3 Rules of Inference ............................................ 8 2.4 The Language of Propositional Logic ................................... 15 2.5 Exercises ................................................. 16 3 Natural Deduction for Propositional Logic 17 3.1 Derivations in Natural Deduction ..................................... 17 3.2 Examples ................................................. 19 3.3 Forward and Backward Reasoning .................................... 20 3.4 Reasoning by Cases ............................................ 22 3.5 Some Logical Identities .......................................... 23 3.6 Exercises ................................................. 24 4 Propositional Logic in Lean 25 4.1 Expressions for Propositions and Proofs ................................. 25 4.2 More commands ............................................
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 8 Hilbert Proof Systems, Formal Proofs, Deduction Theorem
    CHAPTER 8 Hilbert Proof Systems, Formal Proofs, Deduction Theorem The Hilbert proof systems are systems based on a language with implication and contain a Modus Ponens rule as a rule of inference. They are usually called Hilbert style formalizations. We will call them here Hilbert style proof systems, or Hilbert systems, for short. Modus Ponens is probably the oldest of all known rules of inference as it was already known to the Stoics (3rd century B.C.). It is also considered as the most "natural" to our intuitive thinking and the proof systems containing it as the inference rule play a special role in logic. The Hilbert proof systems put major emphasis on logical axioms, keeping the rules of inference to minimum, often in propositional case, admitting only Modus Ponens, as the sole inference rule. 1 Hilbert System H1 Hilbert proof system H1 is a simple proof system based on a language with implication as the only connective, with two axioms (axiom schemas) which characterize the implication, and with Modus Ponens as a sole rule of inference. We de¯ne H1 as follows. H1 = ( Lf)g; F fA1;A2g MP ) (1) where A1;A2 are axioms of the system, MP is its rule of inference, called Modus Ponens, de¯ned as follows: A1 (A ) (B ) A)); A2 ((A ) (B ) C)) ) ((A ) B) ) (A ) C))); MP A ;(A ) B) (MP ) ; B 1 and A; B; C are any formulas of the propositional language Lf)g. Finding formal proofs in this system requires some ingenuity. Let's construct, as an example, the formal proof of such a simple formula as A ) A.
    [Show full text]
  • Symbolic Logic: Grammar, Semantics, Syntax
    Symbolic Logic: Grammar, Semantics, Syntax Logic aims to give a precise method or recipe for determining what follows from a given set of sentences. So we need precise definitions of `sentence' and `follows from.' 1. Grammar: What's a sentence? What are the rules that determine whether a string of symbols is a sentence, and when it is not? These rules are known as the grammar of a particular language. We have actually been operating with two different but very closely related grammars this term: a grammar for propositional logic and a grammar for first-order logic. The grammar for propositional logic (thus far) is simple: 1. There are an indefinite number of propositional variables, which we have been symbolizing as A; B; ::: and P; Q; :::; each of these is a sen- tence. ? is also a sentence. 2. If A; B are sentences, then: •:A is a sentence, • A ^ B is a sentence, and • A _ B is a sentence. 3. Nothing else is a sentence: anything that is neither a member of 1, nor constructable via successive applications of 2 to the members of 1, is not a sentence. The grammar for first-order logic (thus far) is more complex. 2 and 3 remain exactly the same as above, but 1 must be replaced by some- thing more complex. First, a list of all predicates (e.g. Tet or SameShape) and proper names (e.g. max; b) of a particular language L must be specified. Then we can define: 1F OL. A series of symbols s is an atomic sentence = s is an n-place predicate followed by an ordered sequence of n proper names.
    [Show full text]