Why Neural Correlates of Consciousness Are Fine, but Not Enough
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Theoretical Models of Consciousness: a Scoping Review
brain sciences Review Theoretical Models of Consciousness: A Scoping Review Davide Sattin 1,2,*, Francesca Giulia Magnani 1, Laura Bartesaghi 1, Milena Caputo 1, Andrea Veronica Fittipaldo 3, Martina Cacciatore 1, Mario Picozzi 4 and Matilde Leonardi 1 1 Neurology, Public Health, Disability Unit—Scientific Department, Fondazione IRCCS Istituto Neurologico Carlo Besta, 20133 Milan, Italy; [email protected] (F.G.M.); [email protected] (L.B.); [email protected] (M.C.); [email protected] (M.C.); [email protected] (M.L.) 2 Experimental Medicine and Medical Humanities-PhD Program, Biotechnology and Life Sciences Department and Center for Clinical Ethics, Insubria University, 21100 Varese, Italy 3 Oncology Department, Mario Negri Institute for Pharmacological Research IRCCS, 20156 Milan, Italy; veronicaandrea.fi[email protected] 4 Center for Clinical Ethics, Biotechnology and Life Sciences Department, Insubria University, 21100 Varese, Italy; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +39-02-2394-2709 Abstract: The amount of knowledge on human consciousness has created a multitude of viewpoints and it is difficult to compare and synthesize all the recent scientific perspectives. Indeed, there are many definitions of consciousness and multiple approaches to study the neural correlates of consciousness (NCC). Therefore, the main aim of this article is to collect data on the various theories of consciousness published between 2007–2017 and to synthesize them to provide a general overview of this topic. To describe each theory, we developed a thematic grid called the dimensional model, which qualitatively and quantitatively analyzes how each article, related to one specific theory, debates/analyzes a specific issue. -
What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells Us About Descartes
What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells us about Descartes Gideon Manning The College of William and Mary Ever since the first generation Cartesian Gerauld de Cordemoy wrote a self- standing book dedicated to the problem of other minds philosophers have proceeded as though Descartes’ work entails some version of the problem.1 In this paper I evaluate Descartes’ own contribution to creating and answering skepticism about other minds. It is my contention, first, that for most of his working life Descartes did not see the problem as distinct from the problem of the external world. Second, that when he was finally presented with the problem in a late letter from Henry More, Descartes looked not to behavior, but to a body’s origins as a guide to who does and does not have a mind. Specifically, the response Descartes offers to More appeals to a shared “nature,” something which has struck many readers as an ineffectual response, even as a response which begs the question. On the contrary, and this is my third contention, Descartes’ response is a fairly plausible one when read as utilizing the meaning of “nature” as complexio found in Meditation Six.2 Though it may be translated as “complex,” complexio is really a technical Latin term coming from the medical tradition, likely introduced into the lexicon at Salerno in the tenth- or eleventh-century. It means, roughly, a unique composition of elements or qualities distinguishing species (and individual members of a species) from one another. By emphasizing our shared complexio Descartes is telling More that having resolved the problem of the external world we can rely on God’s uniform action in the world to entail joining a mind to members of our species. -
Does Binding of Synesthetic Color to the Evoking Grapheme Require Attention?
In press, Cortex DOES BINDING OF SYNESTHETIC COLOR TO THE EVOKING GRAPHEME REQUIRE ATTENTION? Noam Sagiv1,2, Jeffrey Heer3, Lynn Robertson1,4 1Department of Psychology, University of California, Berkeley 2Department of Psychology, University College London 3Computer Science Department, University of California, Berkeley 4Neurology Research Services, Veterans Administration, Martinez, CA Running page heading: The Role of Attention in Synesthesia Address correspondence to: Noam Sagiv Department of Psychology e-mail University College London 26 Bedford Way London WC1H 0AP Tel: +44-20-7679-5365 United Kingdom Fax: +44-20-7436-4276 ABSTRACT The neural mechanisms involved in binding features such as shape and color are a matter of some debate. Does accurate binding rely on spatial attention functions of the parietal lobe or can it occur without attentional input? One extraordinary phenomenon that may shed light on this question is that of chromatic-graphemic synesthesia, a rare condition in which letter shapes evoke color perceptions. A popular suggestion is that synesthesia results from cross-activation between different functional regions (e.g., between shape and color areas of the ventral pathway). Under such conditions binding may not require parietal involvement and could occur preattentively. We tested this hypothesis in two synesthetes who perceived grayscale letters and digits in color. We found no evidence for preattentive binding using a visual search paradigm in which the target was a synesthetic inducer. In another experiment involving color judgments, we show that the congruency of target color and the synesthetic color of irrelevant digits modulates performance more when the digits are included within the attended region of space. -
CHAPTER4: Private Language Argument and the Problem of Other Minds
84 CHAPTER4: Private Language Argument and the Problem of Other Minds The problem of other minds is an age old predicament in the history of philosophy. It existed during the time of Plato and still remains a quandary in philosophical discussions at length. We find in Plato's Theaetetus the question: "Are you quite certain that the several colours .appear to a dog or to any animal whatever as they appear to you? ... Or that anything appears the same to you as to another man?"lls This problem is a kind of other minds dilemma. The problem of other minds is found in Wittgenstein' s philosophy too. As far as Wittgenstein is concerned, the problem arises due to the self- centred perception of knowledge. When one thinks that he can have knowledge of his own psychological states and on that basis he constructs the world from his own private experiences or sense data, problem of other minds take place. This is a major issue which Wittgenstein strikes to resolve. This issue originally came up from the Cartesian Meditations where Descartes takes his own self as the being to doubt, by his method arrives at the conclusion that one has the best possible access to his own private self. Wittgenstein. believes that it is a ns Benjamin Jowett (tr.), Plato's Theaetetus: With Introduction and Analysis (Rockville, Maryland: Serenity Publishers, 2009), p. 102. 85 false idea to construct the world view in this way. His private language argument is related to the problem of other minds in a quite integrated way. -
The Problem of Other Minds: a Yoruba Hermeneutic Deconstruction of the Logical Behaviourist Approach
The Problem of Other Minds: A Yoruba Hermeneutic Deconstruction of the Logical Behaviourist Approach by Babalola Joseph Balogun [email protected] Department of Philosophy Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile-Ife, Nigeria : Abstract Using the hermeneutics of the Yoruba linguistic framework, the paper reconsiders the scepticism about other minds, especially from the logical behaviourist perspectives. As a theory, logical behaviourism equates other minds with the overt movements of other bodies. The paper advances arguments against logical behaviourism, particularly on the ground that it blurred our traditional concept of mind as something different from the body. The paper concludes by proposing a search for an appropriate methodological approach through which the logical behaviourist account could be improved to properly incorporate the role of the mind in the production of physical behaviour of the body. Keywords: Other Minds, Logical Behaviourism, Yoruba, hermeneutics Introduction Our intention in this paper is not to set out a theory of other minds that will explain the theoretical flaws inherent in the existing theories. Rather, it is a demonstration of the inadequacy of one of the earliest theories of other minds, namely, logical behaviourism. Hence, the paper is essentially a critique. This critique is basically aimed at arousing the need for a search for a better theory of other minds that will take into consideration some of the identified shortcomings of the existing theories, especially as they are somewhat reducible to the behaviourist attitude. It should be noted that such exercise is not new, as several contemporary commentators have amply shown. However, the novelty of the present paper derives from the fact that it is the first time an objection to any of the theories of other minds would be attempted using an African language, especially Yoruba language. -
Seeing Souls: Wittgenstein and Cavell on the “Problem of Other Minds”
Seeing Souls: Wittgenstein and Cavell on the “Problem of Other Minds” JÔNADAS TECHIO The human body is the best picture of the human soul. LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, Philosophical Investigations […] not to believe there is such a thing as the human soul is not to know what the human body is […] CAVELL, The Claim of Reason Introduction The so-called “Part I” of Philosophical Investigations (PI) contains many claims con- cerning the grammar of psychological predicates, and particularly about the condi- tions for ascribing them to others. The following are some of the most well-known (and also most representative) among such claims: (i) “only of a living human being and what resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensa- tions; it sees; is blind; hears; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious”;1 (ii) “An ‘inner process’ stands in need of outward criteria.”2 The content of these and other kindred remarks has led a great number of readers to ascribe some kind of “externalistic”3 ac- count to the author of the Investigations. !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 2009), §281. 2. Ibid., §580. 3. I mean this in a very broad sense, so as to cover many different attempts of including in the analysis of the content of (presumably “inner”) mental states some features of the subject’s larger. (“external”) environment, such as her behavior, her community’s standards, the constitution of the objects with which she relates, etc. CONVERSATIONS 1 64! Now, “externalism” comes in many flavors. -
Kicking the Psychophysical Laws Into Gear a New Approach to the Combination Problem
Tam Hunt Kicking the Psychophysical Laws into Gear A New Approach to the Combination Problem Abstract: A new approach to the ‘hard problem’of consciousness, the eons-old mind–body problem, is proposed, inspired by Whitehead, Schopenhauer, Griffin, and others. I define a ‘simple subject’ as the fundamental unit of matter and of consciousness. Simple subjects are inherently experiential, albeit in a highly rudimentary manner com- pared to human consciousness. With this re-framing, the ‘physical’ realm includes the ‘mental’ realm; they are two aspects of the same thing, the outside and inside of each real thing. This view is known as panpsychism or panexperientialism and is in itself a partial solution to the hard problem. The secondary but more interesting question may be framed as: what is a ‘complex subject’? How do simple subjects combine to form complex subjects like bats and human beings? This is more generally known as the ‘combination problem’or the ‘boundary problem’, and is the key problem facing both materialist and pan- psychist approaches to consciousness. I suggest a new approach for resolving this component of the hard problem, a ‘general theory of complex subjects’that includes ‘psychophysical laws’in the form of a simple mathematical framework. I present three steps for characteriz- ing complex subjects, with the physical nature of time key to this new understanding. Viewing time as fundamentally quantized is impor- tant. I also suggest, as a second-order conceptualization, that ‘infor- mation’ and ‘experience’ may be considered identical concepts and that there is no double-aspect to information. Rather, there is a single Correspondence: Tam Hunt, Visiting Scholar, UC Santa Barbara Psychology Department, and Lec- turer, Bren School of Environmental Science & Management, UC Santa Barbara Email: [email protected] Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18, No. -
Can Quantum Physics Help Solve the Hard Problem of Consciousness?
Can quantum physics help solve the hard problem of consciousness? A hypothesis based on entangled spins and photons Christoph Simon, Department of Physics and Astronomy & Institute for Quantum Science and Technology, University of Calgary, Calgary, AB T2N1N4, Canada. Email: [email protected] Introduction There are still many open questions in the sciences of the brain and mind (Adolphs 2015), but the deepest one, and the one where we really haven’t made much progress, is what Chalmers (1995) called the hard problem of consciousness: how does subjective experience arise from brain matter? This question has occupied philosophers and scientists for centuries. Arguably the recent rapid development of artificial intelligence adds a new urgency (Tegmark 2017). We might soon have machines that seem like conscious beings in many respects. It would seem important to understand if they really are, keeping in mind also that arguments by analogy are less convincing in the case of machines than they are for animals. In the following I suggest exploring the possibility that quantum physics may have something to offer in this respect. Building on recent progress in quantum technology and neuroscience, I propose a concrete hypothesis as a basis for further investigations, namely that subjective experience is related to the dynamics of a complex entangled state of spins, which is continuously generated and updated through the exchange of photons. I begin by describing my main arguments in favor of quantum physics playing a role in subjective experience. They address the two most common questions/objections that are raised in response to the ‘quantum consciousness’ thesis, namely (first) why do we need quantum physics, and (second) could it possibly work? Then I outline several additional arguments, before turning to the question of physical and biological plausibility and explaining the motivations for the proposed concrete hypothesis involving spins and photons. -
Of Cortex and Consciousness: “Phenomenal,” “Access,” Or Otherwise
Husband, Scott A (2017) Of cortex and consciousness: “Phenomenal,” “access,” or otherwise. Animal Sentience 13(7) DOI: 10.51291/2377-7478.1241 This article has appeared in the journal Animal Sentience, a peer-reviewed journal on animal cognition and feeling. It has been made open access, free for all, by WellBeing International and deposited in the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Animal Sentience 2017.043: Husband on Woodruff on Fish Feel Of cortex and consciousness: “Phenomenal,” “access,” or otherwise Commentary on Woodruff on Fish Feel Scott A. Husband Department of Psychology The University of Tampa Abstract: From the perspective of a comparative neuroanatomist studying the avian pallium, Woodruff’s (2017) claims about the behavioral and electrophysiological evidence for teleost sentience blur the lines between phenomenal and access consciousness (Block, 1995). I discuss the bias that complex cognition can only arise in the cortical layering typical of the mammalian pallium and conclude that Woodruff makes a good case that the tecto-pallial connections in teleosts are sufficiently complex to support something like sentience. Scott A. Husband, Associate Professor of Psychology, University of Tampa, works on comparative neuroanatomy and cognition: how neural circuits and neurochemistry contribute to complex cognition, within the larger context of brain evolution in non-mammalian species, especially birds. http://www.ut.edu/scotthusband/ Woodruff (2017) presents two main propositions in his article: (1) teleost fish are sentient, and (2) this sentience (what it "feels like" to be a fish) has sufficient neuroanatomical support via tecto-pallial interconnections. The first claim might strike some as audacious. -
The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: a Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism Over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind
Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) Catalogs, etc.) 2019 The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind Tommy Tobias Aahlberg Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Aahlberg, Tommy Tobias, "The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind". The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) (2019). Trinity College Digital Repository, Hartford, CT. https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers/79 The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind Tommy Tobias Aahlberg Introduction Underpinning everything that constitutes our perceived reality is consciousness. The fact that there is something that it is like to be us is at the foundation of everything we consequently come to care about in our lives. Every observation, sensation, thought, and emotion is predicated on the phenomenon that there is something that it is like to observe, sense, think, and feel. The awareness and experience of a world is the essential factor that separates our universe from any conceivable zombie universe where nothing is observed, sensed, thought, or felt. Necessarily, we filter every single moment through our consciousness. If consciousness did not exist there would be no groundwork for meaning as it would hold no basis in any conceivable creature’s awareness, and therefore such a universe would be meaningless. Despite, or perhaps due to, its fundamental nature and important implications – consciousness is poorly understood by contemporary science and philosophy alike, at least in the theoretical sense of understanding. -
Binding Problem Is Frequently Discussed in Consciousness Research
Consciousness and Cognition 8, 173±185 (1999) Article ID ccog.1999.0384, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Binding and the Phenomenal Unity of Consciousness Antti Revonsuo1 Center for Cognitive Neuroscience, Department of Philosophy, University of Turku, Turku, Finland FIN-20014 The binding problem is frequently discussed in consciousness research. However, it is by no means clear what the problem is supposed to be and how exactly it relates to con- sciousness. In the present paper the nature of the binding problem is clari®ed by distinguish- ing between different formulations of the problem. Some of them make no mention of consciousness, whereas others are directly related to aspects of phenomenal experience. Certain formulations of the binding problem are closely connected to the classical philo- sophical problem of the unity of consciousness and the currently fashionable search for the neural correlates of consciousness. Nonetheless, only a part of the current empirical research on binding is directly relevant to the study of consciousness. The main message of the present paper is that the science of consciousness needs to establish a clear theoretical view of the relation between binding and consciousness and to encourage further empirical work that builds on such a theoretical foundation. 1999 Academic Press WHAT IS THE BINDING PROBLEM AND HOW IS IT RELATED TO CONSCIOUSNESS? It seems to be taken for granted that, ®rst, everybody knows exactly what we are talking about when we discuss the binding problem and second, that this problem is bound to be relevant for the study of consciousness. However, if we take a look at the recent literature in which the problem has been discussed, interesting ambiguities and disagreements emerge, revealing that what we are dealing with here is not a single problem at all, but a set of related problems that should be distinguished from each other and analyzed at different levels of description. -
Mcdowell's Disjunctivism and Other Minds
MCDOWELL’S DISJUNCTIVISM AND OTHER MINDS Anil Gomes Birkbeck College, London Forthcoming, Inquiry [accepted 2010] John McDowell’s original motivation of disjunctivism occurs in the context of a problem regarding other minds. Recent commentators have insisted that McDowell’s disjunctivism should be classed as an epistemological disjunctivism about epistemic warrant, and distinguished from the perceptual disjunctivism of Hinton, Snowdon and others. In this paper I investigate the relation between the problem of other minds and disjunctivism, and raise some questions for this interpretation of McDowell. 1. Introduction In his ‘Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge’, John McDowell uses a debate about other minds, as raised in the context of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, to motivate a disjunctive claim about those cases where things appear to a subject to be a certain way.1 In the recent focus on disjunctive theories in the philosophy of perception, a number of writers have moved to distance McDowell’s disjunctivism from the perceptual disjunctivism discussed and advocated by such writers as J.M. Hinton, Paul Snowdon and Mike Martin.2 The standard way of effecting such a distancing is by distinguishing McDowell’s ‘epistemological 1 [McDowell 1982], reprinted as [McDowell 1998a]. All references to this edition. 2 [Hinton 1973], [Snowdon 1980-1], [Martin 2002], [Martin 2004]. disjunctivism’ from the ‘metaphysical’ or ‘perceptual disjunctivism’ of Hinton, Snowdon and Martin, and concluding – as Byrne and Logue do – that ‘[McDowell’s]