Student Understanding of Time in Special Relativity: Simultaneity and Reference Frames

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Student Understanding of Time in Special Relativity: Simultaneity and Reference Frames Student understanding of time in special relativity: simultaneity and reference frames Rachel E. Scherr, Peter S. Shaffer, and Stamatis Vokos Department of Physics, University of Washington, Seattle, WA This article reports on an investigation of student understanding of the concept of time in special relativity. A series of research tasks are discussed that illustrate, step-by-step, how student reasoning of fundamental concepts of relativity was probed. The results indicate that after standard instruction students at all academic levels have serious difficulties with the relativity of simultaneity and with the role of observers in inertial reference frames. Evidence is presented that suggests many students construct a conceptual framework in which the ideas of absolute simultaneity and the relativity of simultaneity harmoniously co-exist. relativistic kinematics in the laboratory I. INTRODUCTION frame.1 We wanted to expand this research There is growing national interest in base to relativity in order to provide a guide increasing the exposure of students in for the development of instructional 2,3 introductory courses to modern physics materials by ourselves and others. topics, such as relativity. Proponents of This article reports on an investigation enlarging the scope of the curriculum argue of student understanding of time in special that in the beginning of the 21st century the relativity. A major purpose is to identify content of introductory classes should reflect and characterize the conceptual and some of the major intellectual breakthroughs reasoning difficulties that students at all of the 20th century. Others hold that the list levels encounter in their study of special of topics that must be covered is already too relativity. The emphasis is on the relativity daunting. Physics education research can of simultaneity and the role of reference play a pivotal role in this debate. Whether frames. We found that, after instruction, students first encounter modern physics many students are unable to determine the concepts at the introductory level or in time at which an event occurs, recognize the advanced courses, it is important to identify equivalence of observers at rest relative to what students can and cannot do after one another, and apply the definition of instruction and what steps can be taken to simultaneity. We illustrate the process help deepen their understanding of the through which we gradually obtained a material. In addition, analyzing the ways in detailed picture of student thinking by the which students undergo the transition design and successive refinement of a set of between understanding phenomena to which research tasks. they have immedia te access and understanding phenomena that lie outside II. PRIOR RESEARCH their everyday experience can help us There is currently only a small body of identify reasoning skills that are needed for research on student understanding of the study of advanced topics. relativity, mostly in Galilean contexts (in Over the last five years, the Physics particular, relative motion). In many cases, Education Group at the University of the research tasks used (e.g., multiple -choice Washington has been investigating student questions or single questions given to a understanding of key ideas in Galilean, small number of students) do not provide the special, and general relativistic kinematics. kinds of insights that are necessary to Extensive research has already been understand the prevalent modes of student conducted on student understanding of non- reasoning and to develop effective Student understanding of time in special relativity Scherr, et al. 1 instructional strategies. We review salient III. FOCUS OF THE RESEARCH results from relevant investigations. A major goal of the investigation was to Galilean relativity determine the extent to which students, after Investigations of physics undergraduates instruction, are able to apply basic ideas of in India have identified the belief that special relativity to simple physical reference frames have limited physical situations. The context is one spatial extent. Studies by Panse et al. and Ramadas dimension. The concepts probed are et al. suggest that, for many students, frames summarized below. of reference have limited physical extent. The construct of a reference frame is at Students claim that a body can “emerge” the heart of relative motion. Most courses in from the reference frame of an object by special relativity begin with a discussion of leaving the vicinity of the obje ct (e.g., “a a reference frame as a system of observers ball can be thrown to ‘go outside’ a (or devices) by which the positions and 4 reference frame”). times of events are determined. An investigation by Saltiel and Understanding the concept of a reference Malgrange has identified difficulties with frame forms the foundation for relative motion among eleven-year-old- understanding any topic in special relativity. children and first- and fourth-year university It provides the basis for the determination of 5 students in France. The three groups all kinematical (and other physical) showed little difference in error rates to quantities and serves as the framework for written questions. Many students tended to relating measurements made by different identify an object’s motion as intrinsic, not a observers. The concept of a reference frame quantity that is measured relative to a presupposes an understanding of more basic reference frame. Students tended to make a measurement procedures. For clarity in the distinction between “real” motion, which discussion that follows, we review the basic has a dynamical cause, and “apparent” operational definitions associated with motion, which is “an optical illusion, devoid reference frames, i.e., the determination of of any physical reality.” the position and time of an event and the Special relativity conditions under which two events are Villani and Pacca have demonstrated treated as simultaneous.10 that university students’ reasoning in An event in special relativity is relativistic contexts is similar to that associated with a single location in space observed by Saltiel and Malgrange in and a single instant in time. The position of 6 Galilean contexts. A case study by Hewson an event is defined to be the coordinate label with a physics graduate student illustrated on a rigid ruler at the location of the event. the importance of “metaphysical beliefs” The ruler is envisioned to extend indefinitely (e.g., time is absolute) to his understanding from some chosen origin.11 The time of an 7 of special relativity. The student ni the event is most naturally defined as the study classified certain relativistic effects reading on a clock located at the event’s (including length contraction) as distortions position at the instant at which the event of perception. Posner et al. report similar occurs. The rulers and clocks used by any results in interviews with introductory observer are at rest relative to the observer. 8 students and their instructors. All observers in special relativity are O’Brien-Pride has conducted interviews assumed to be “intelligent observers” who and administered early versions of some of use synchronized clocks. To determine the the research tasks described here in which time of a distant event, an observer corrects university students appear to believe that the for the travel time of a signal originating at order of events depends on observer the event.12,13 Inertial observers at rest 9 location. Her preliminary results provided relative to one another determine the same impetus for the investigation detailed in this positions and times for events (and hence paper. the same relative ordering of events). Such Student understanding of time in special relativity Scherr, et al. 2 observers are said to be in the same A. Student populations 14 reference frame. Most of the research was conducted at Events are defined to be simultaneous in the University of Washington in courses that a given frame if their corresponding time include special relativity. The study has readings are identical, according to the involved about 800 students from about 30 definition of the time of an event discussed sections of various courses. The populations above. A judgment of the simultaneity of include: non-physics students (in the widely separated events necessarily includes descriptive course for non-majors students); an appropriate definition of the time of a introductory students (in the introductory 15 distant event. The invariance of the speed calculus-based honors course and in the of light has an inevitable and unsettling sophomore-level course on modern physics); implication. Two events at different students in the junior-level courses on locations that occur at the same time in a electricity and magnetism and relativity and given frame are not simultaneous in any gravitation; and students in our upper- other frame. division course for prospective high school The relativity of simultaneity is among physics teachers.16 We also present results the key results of special relativity and one from physics graduate students at the that is particularly difficult to grasp, as University of Washington who participated evidenced by the numerous “paradoxes” that in interviews and others who were given a arise from it. It is not reasonable to expect written question on a graduate qualifying that students (even those facile with examination. In addition, the investigation mathematical formalism) will master all the includes students in the honors section of the intricacies of the counterintuitive results that calculus-based course at one of the other follow from the operational definition of research universities and advanced simultaneity. In this study, we considered a undergraduate students from the other meaningful understanding of relativistic collaborating university. We found that simultaneity to include the ability to identify student performance from all three relevant events, to determine the time at universities was similar. The results, which an event occurs (by correcting for therefore, have been combined.17 signal travel time), and to recognize that the time interval between two events is not B.
Recommended publications
  • Parts of Persons Identity and Persistence in a Perdurantist World
    UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI MILANO Doctoral School in Philosophy and Human Sciences (XXXI Cycle) Department of Philosophy “Piero Martinetti” Parts of Persons Identity and persistence in a perdurantist world Ph.D. Candidate Valerio BUONOMO Tutors Prof. Giuliano TORRENGO Prof. Paolo VALORE Coordinator of the Doctoral School Prof. Marcello D’AGOSTINO Academic year 2017-2018 1 Content CONTENT ........................................................................................................................... 2 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ........................................................................................................... 4 INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................... 5 CHAPTER 1. PERSONAL IDENTITY AND PERSISTENCE...................................................................... 8 1.1. The persistence of persons and the criteria of identity over time .................................. 8 1.2. The accounts of personal persistence: a standard classification ................................... 14 1.2.1. Mentalist accounts of personal persistence ............................................................................ 15 1.2.2. Somatic accounts of personal persistence .............................................................................. 15 1.2.3. Anti-criterialist accounts of personal persistence ................................................................... 16 1.3. The metaphysics of persistence: the mereological account .........................................
    [Show full text]
  • Presentism/Eternalism and Endurantism/Perdurantism: Why the Unsubstantiality of the First Debate Implies That of the Second1
    1 Presentism/Eternalism and Endurantism/Perdurantism: why the 1 unsubstantiality of the first debate implies that of the second Forthcoming in Philosophia Naturalis Mauro Dorato (Ph.D) Department of Philosophy University of Rome Three [email protected] tel. +393396070133 http://host.uniroma3.it/dipartimenti/filosofia/personale/doratoweb.htm Abstract The main claim that I want to defend in this paper is that the there are logical equivalences between eternalism and perdurantism on the one hand and presentism and endurantism on the other. By “logical equivalence” I mean that one position is entailed and entails the other. As a consequence of this equivalence, it becomes important to inquire into the question whether the dispute between endurantists and perdurantists is authentic, given that Savitt (2006) Dolev (2006) and Dorato (2006) have cast doubts on the fact that the debate between presentism and eternalism is about “what there is”. In this respect, I will conclude that also the debate about persistence in time has no ontological consequences, in the sense that there is no real ontological disagreement between the two allegedly opposite positions: as in the case of the presentism/eternalism debate, one can be both a perdurantist and an endurantist, depending on which linguistic framework is preferred. The main claim that I want to defend in this paper is that the there are logical equivalences between eternalism and perdurantism on the one hand and presentism and endurantism on the other. By “logical equivalence” I mean that one position is entailed and entails the other. As a consequence of this equivalence, it becomes important to inquire into the question whether the dispute between endurantists and perdurantists is authentic, given that Savitt (2006) Dolev (2006) and Dorato (2006) have cast doubts on the fact that the debate between presentism and eternalism is about “what there is”.
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Tense Seriously’ Dean W
    W. Zimmerman dialectica Vol. 59, N° 4 (2005), pp. 401–457 The A-Theory of Time, The B-Theory of Time, and ‘Taking Tense Seriously’ Dean W. Zimmerman† ABSTRACT The paper has two parts: First, I describe a relatively popular thesis in the philosophy of propositional attitudes, worthy of the name ‘taking tense seriously’; and I distinguish it from a family of views in the metaphysics of time, namely, the A-theories (or what are sometimes called ‘tensed theories of time’). Once the distinction is in focus, a skeptical worry arises. Some A- theorists maintain that the difference between past, present, and future, is to be drawn in terms of what exists: growing-block theorists eschew ontological commitment to future entities; pre- sentists, to future and past entities. Others think of themselves as A-theorists but exclude no past or future things from their ontology. The metaphysical skeptic suspects that their attempt to articulate an ‘eternalist’ version of the A-theory collapses into merely ‘taking tense seriously’ – a thesis that does not imply the A-theory. The second half of the paper is the search for a stable eternalist A-theory. It includes discussion of temporary intrinsics, temporal parts, and truth. 1. Introduction Sadly, the great metaphysician J. McT. E. McTaggart is now remembered mainly for what must be his worst argument: the infamous argument for ‘the unreality of time’. But even this ‘philosophical “howler” ’ (as C. D. Broad rightly called it1) includes enough insightful analysis to have made it a natural starting point for most subsequent work on the metaphysics of time.
    [Show full text]
  • Endurantism Or Perdurantism?
    The embodied self: Endurantism or perdurantism? Saskia Heijnen Contents Contents ...................................................................................................................................... 1 Abstract ...................................................................................................................................... 2 Introduction ................................................................................................................................ 2 1. Endurantism versus perdurantism in metaphysics .............................................................. 5 1.1 Particulars ......................................................................................................................... 5 1.2 Persisting particulars ......................................................................................................... 7 1.3 Temporal parts: a closer look ......................................................................................... 10 1.4 Wholly present: a closer look ......................................................................................... 14 1.5 Perdurantism and endurantism in action ........................................................................ 17 1.5.1 Fusion ....................................................................................................................... 17 1.5.2 Fission ...................................................................................................................... 19 2. Endurantism versus
    [Show full text]
  • Temporal Parts and Spatial Location
    Temporal parts and spatial location Damiano Costa Abstract. The literature offers us several characterizations of temporal parts via spatial co-location: by these accounts, temporal parts are roughly parts that are of the same spatial size as their wholes. It has been argued that such definitions would fail with entities outside space. The present paper investigates the extent to which such criticism works. Keywords: temporal parts, spatial location, events, four-dimensionalism, perdurance. § 0. Introduction Temporal parts of an entity – according to current vulgate – incorporate “all of that entity” for as long as they exist (Heller 1984; Sider 2001; Olson 2006). For example, a temporal part of Sam incorporates “all of Sam” for as long as it exists. One immediate consequence of this fact is that some “smaller parts” of Sam, like his brain and hearth, do not count as temporal parts of Sam, because they do not incorporate “all of Sam” at a certain time. A suitable definition for temporal parts must exclude such “smaller parts”. In this regard, two approaches have been put forward, a mereological one (Simons 1987; Sider 1997; Parsons 2007) and a spatial one (Thomson 1983; Heller 1984; McGrath 2007). On the one hand, the mereological approach says that such “smaller parts” of Sam are not temporal parts because they don’t overlap every part of Sam at a certain time. On the other hand, the spatial approach roughly says that such “smaller parts” of Sam are not temporal parts because a temporal part is of the same spatial size as its whole for as long as that part exists.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche's Doctrine of Eternal Return
    University of Rhode Island DigitalCommons@URI Senior Honors Projects Honors Program at the University of Rhode Island 2007 Nietzsche’s Doctrine of Eternal Return David R. Gadon University of Rhode Island, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.uri.edu/srhonorsprog Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Gadon, David R., "Nietzsche’s Doctrine of Eternal Return" (2007). Senior Honors Projects. Paper 47. http://digitalcommons.uri.edu/srhonorsprog/47http://digitalcommons.uri.edu/srhonorsprog/47 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Honors Program at the University of Rhode Island at DigitalCommons@URI. It has been accepted for inclusion in Senior Honors Projects by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@URI. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Nietzsche’s Doctrine of Eternal Return David Ray Gadon Honors Senior Thesis Spring 2007 Sponsor: Dr. Galen A. Johnson Gadon 2 Nietzsche’s Doctrine of Eternal Return “Six thousand feet beyond man and time.” 1 In the Western world, we have a pronounced affinity for understanding time as something ultimately simple. Despite our recognition of the differences in subjective perception of the passing of intervals, we tacitly affirm that time itself must objectively follow a comprehensible structure of unidirectional flow which, like the commonly cited river metaphor, begins at one point and is definitively moving towards another. Thanks especially to the Judeo-Christian model of history plowing inevitably towards a conclusion at the end of days, even in the absence of direct religious influence, our intuitive understanding of time remains linear. We see this model addressed and contested by metaphysicians throughout the ages, but only rarely do we glimpse a philosophy that is able to cogently upturn this intuitively correct ideal.
    [Show full text]
  • Relativity and Three Four Dimensionalism
    Relativity and Three Four-Dimensionalisms Abstract: Relativity theory is often said to support something called ‘the four-dimensional view of reality’. But there are at least three different views that sometimes go by this name. One is the B-theory of time, according to which the past, present, and future are all equally real and there is nothing metaphysically special about the present. A second is ‘spacetime unitism’ (as we call it), according to which there is a spacetime manifold, and if there are such things points of space or instants of time, these are just spacetime regions of different sorts: thus space and time are not separate manifolds. A third is perdurantism, according to which persisting material objects (rocks, trees, human beings) are made up of different temporal parts located at different times. We sketch routes from relativity to the B-theory and to unitism. We then discuss some routes to perdurantism, via the B-theory and via unitism. Introduction Relativity theory1 is often said to support something called ‘the four-dimensional view’ of reality. But there are three independent views that go by this name: (i) spacetime unitism, as we call it, according to which spacetime is more fundamental than space or time, and points of space and instants of time, if they exist at all, are just spacetime regions of different sorts; (ii) the B-theory of time, according to which the past, present and future are all equally real and there is nothing objectively special about the present; and (iii) perdurantism, according to which material objects are four-dimensional wholes made up of different temporal parts.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Readings of the Eternal Return Michael James Maclaggan Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected]
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School 2014 Three Readings of the Eternal Return Michael James MacLaggan Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation MacLaggan, Michael James, "Three Readings of the Eternal Return" (2014). LSU Master's Theses. 861. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/861 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THREE READINGS OF THE ETERNAL RETURN A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies by Michael James MacLaggan B.S., University of Texas at Austin, 2004 August 2014 To the greatest of them all: Sanford L. “Sandy” Bauman, ordinary philosopher. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT ..................................................................................................................................................................................... iv INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • WHO-UMC System for Standardised Case Causality Assessment
    The use of the WHO-UMC system for standardised case causality assessment Why causality assessment? An inherent problem in pharmacovigilance is that most case reports concern suspected adverse drug reactions. Adverse reactions are rarely specific for the drug, diagnostic tests are usually absent and a rechallenge is rarely ethically justified. In practice few adverse reactions are ‘certain’ or ‘unlikely’; most are somewhere in between these extremes, i.e. ‘possible’ or ‘probable’. In an attempt to solve this problem many systems have been developed for a structured and harmonised assessment of causality (1). None of these systems, however, have been shown to produce a precise and reliable quantitative estimation of relationship likelihood. Nevertheless, causality assessment has become a common routine procedure in pharmacovigilance. The advances and limitations of causality assessment are reviewed in Table 1 (2). Table 1. Advances and limitations of standardised case causality assessment What causality assessment can do What causality assessment cannot do Decrease disagreement between assessors Give accurate quantitative measurement of relationship likelihood Classify relationship likelihood Distinguish valid from invalid cases Mark individual case reports Prove the connection between drug and event Improvement of scientific evaluation; Quantify the contribution of a drug to the educational development of an adverse event Change uncertainty into certainty The WHO-UMC causality assessment system The WHO-UMC system has been developed in consultation with the National Centres participating in the Programme for International Drug Monitoring and is meant as a practical tool for the assessment of case reports. It is basically a combined assessment taking into account the clinical-pharmacological aspects of the case history and the quality of the documentation of the observation.
    [Show full text]
  • Temporal Parts and Timeless Parthood
    Temporal Parts and Timeless Parthood Eric T. Olson University of Sheffield abstract: What is a temporal part? Most accounts explain it in terms of timeless parthood: a thing's having a part without temporal qualification. Some find this hard to understand, and thus find the view that persisting things have temporal parts--four- dimensionalism--unintelligible. T. Sider offers to help by defining temporal parthood in terms of a thing's having a part at a time. I argue that no such account can capture the notion of a temporal part that figures in orthodox four-dimensionalism: temporal parts must be timeless parts. This enables us to state four-dimensionalism more clearly. 1. “Four-dimensionalists” say that things persist by having temporal parts spread out across time. A thing exists at a time, they say, by having a temporal part located just at that time. So I exist in 1975 by having a temporal part that exists throughout that year and only then; I exist now by having another temporal part that exists only now. “Three- dimensionalists,” by contrast, say that at least some things persist without having temporal parts. The event that is the history of a person or a dog might have temporal parts, but people and dogs themselves have none. Better, three-dimensionalism says that some persisting things lack proper temporal parts: maybe anything that exists at some time is a temporal part of itself, just as anything whatever a part of itself. Three- and four-dimensionalists disagree about whether persisting things have temporal parts other than themselves.
    [Show full text]
  • Symmetry in Classical Mechanics
    Symmetries and Conservation Laws: 1 J. Hanc, S. Tuleja, M. Hancova Consequences of Noether’s Theorem 1 2 Symmetries and Conservation Laws: 3 Consequences of Noether’s Theorem 4 5 Jozef Hanca) 6 Technical University, Vysokoskolska 4, 042 00 Kosice, Slovakia 7 8 Slavomir Tulejab) 9 Gymnazium arm. gen. L. Svobodu, Komenskeho 4, 066 51 Humenne, Slovakia 10 11 Martina Hancovac) 12 University of Pavol Jozef Safarik, Jesenna 5, 040 11 Kosice, Slovakia 13 14 We derive conservation laws from symmetry operations using the principle of least 15 action. These derivations, which are examples of Noether’s theorem, require only 16 elementary calculus. They help provide physical understanding of the relation be- 17 tween symmetry and fundamental mechanics for introductory university physics stu- 18 dents. We extend these arguments to the transformation of coordinates due to uniform 19 motion to show that a symmetry argument applies more elegantly to the Lorentz 20 transformation than to the Galilean transformation. 21 22 23 I. INTRODUCTION 24 It is increasingly clear that the symmetry group of nature is the deepest thing that we un- 25 derstand about nature today. 26 Steven Weinberg1 27 28 Many of us have heard statements like: For each symmetry operation there is a corre- 29 sponding conservation law. The conservation of momentum is related to the homogeneity of 30 space. Invariance under translation in time means that law of conservation of energy is valid. 31 Such statements come from one of the most amazing and useful theorems in physics, called 32 Noether’s theorem. 33 When the German mathematician Emmy Noether proved her theorem in 19182,3, she un- 34 covered the most fundamental justification for conservation laws.
    [Show full text]
  • Endurantism Endures: Rejoinder to Barker and Dowe
    Endurantism Endures: Rejoinder to Barker and Dowe Brian Garret Australian National University College of Arts and Social Sciences Department of Philosophy Canberra Australian Capital Territory Australia [email protected] ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ Article info CDD: 121 Received: 06.07.2017; Revised: 27.09.2017; Accepted: 04.10.2017 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2017.V40N3.BG ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ Keywords: Enduratism Perdurantism ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ ABSTRACT In Barker and Dowe (2005), Stephen Barker and Phil Dowe present a range of arguments which they take to demonstrate the paradoxical nature of endurantism. I claim that the endurantist has convincing replies to each argument. ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ In Barker and Dowe (2005), Stephen Barker and Phil Dowe offer a range of arguments intended to show that endurance is paradoxical. I argue that all fail. (i) Since some stage-setting is required, I quote the first argument in full (Barker and Dowe cite Beebee and Rush (2003) for this description): Eric is a (short-lived) cat. He persists for 100n, for some small temporal unit n, and thus, assuming Endurantism, is multi-located throughout a 4-D space- time region R of 100n temporal size. Consider the 100 temporal slices r1, r2, ... , r100 of the region R, where each r has temporal length n. At each region r, there is an object, a cat: Eric at r. We refer collectively to these objects as the Ericrs. Take the fusion, or mereological sum, of the Ericrs and call this fusion F(Ericr). Our first paradox of multilocation (version 2) goes as follows: Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 40, n.
    [Show full text]