Environmental Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Environmental Philosophy INTRODUCTION Environmental Philosophy Anthropocentrism, Intrinsic Value, and Worldview Clash ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY HAS CHALLENGED THE DOMINANT WESTERN CULTURE’S CONCEPTION OF human nature through critiques of anthropocentrism (human chauvinism). It has annoyed the mainstream with critiques of instrumental rationality and its plea on behalf of the intrinsic value of nature. It has irritated nonenviron- mentalists and even some environmentalists with its criticism of mechanism or the reductionist scientific worldview and has argued in favor of some form of ecological worldview. The critique of anthropocentrism, the intrinsic value of nature, and the ecological worldview are central topics for environmental phi- losophers, appearing across a wide range of environmentalist writing, from environmental ethics and policy to political ecology, ecocriticism, and meta- physics. As I understand them, these topics have characterized environmental philosophy since its inception in the 1970s. In the widespread environmental imaginary of a few decades ago, perhaps the central term of engagement for environmental philosophers and ethicists was the concept of anthropocentrism. Anthropocentrism—whose core mean- ing is human-centric evaluation—was also considered by many to be one of the central causes of the environmental crisis. Identifying its historical and conceptual sources and pulling them out by the roots formed a large part of 1 © 2020 State University of New York Press, Albany the environmentalist response.1 By the early 1990s, the Australian environ- mental philosopher Warwick Fox could write that “virtually every paper and book that ecophilosophers have written either implicitly or explicitly develops some kind of answer to [the] question ‘what’s wrong with being anthropocen- tric?’ ”2 It effectively encapsulates a number of issues that have attracted critical attention: the Modern western dualistic opposition between humans and non- human nature; the notion of human chauvinism or human-centric evaluation; and the concept of nature as mere resource passively awaiting instrumentalist exploitation. Current debates around the concept of the Anthropocene sug- gest that renewed attention to this topic is warranted. In addition to the critique of anthropocentrism, a “new ethics” was called for by many environmental philosophers. Are traditional ethical categories and theories so fundamentally anthropocentric that a completely new ethics is required? Adopting a nonanthropocentric perspective would mean accepting the propositions that nonhumans have moral worth, and that they must be taken seriously in human decisions about environmental issues. In a nonan- thropocentric ethics, this also means that in cases of conflict their interests may often carry greater weight than those of humans. Environmental ethics might have to be “new” if traditional theories cannot accommodate these points.3 After briefly entertaining the possibility of using the existing concepts of “rights” or “standing” for nonhumans in the 1970s, environmental ethics came more and more to be identified with arguments for the intrinsic value of nature. A trickle of references to the intrinsic value of nature in the 1970s grad- ually became a steady stream in the late 1980s, and the high-water mark was reached in the debate in the 1990s.4 Finding the appropriate epistemological, ontological, and normative arguments to secure the concept became a major preoccupation. J. Baird Callicott explicitly declared that the distinctive fea- ture of environmental ethics would be its claim that nature possesses intrinsic value.5 He claimed that “the most important philosophical task for environ- mental ethics is the development of a non-anthropocentric value theory,” and he defined the difference between anthropocentric and nonanthropocentric ethics in terms of intrinsic value. An anthropocentric value theory (or axiology), by common consensus, confers intrinsic value on human beings and regards all other things, in- cluding other forms of life, as being only instrumentally valuable, i.e., valuable only to the extent that they are means or instruments which may 2 Introduction © 2020 State University of New York Press, Albany serve human beings. A non-anthropocentric value theory (or axiology), on the other hand, would confer intrinsic value on some non-human beings.6 Reflecting on the concept itself, some writers noted that this very specific quest for the establishment of the intrinsic value of nonhuman nature was motivat- ed by the need to identify some transcultural anchor of environmental value against the backdrop of value relativism. It is only if some value “independent of and overrid[ing] individual human judgment and . relative and evolv- ing cultural ideals” could be found that environmental value would be safe from provincial nature-exploitative interests.7 Although it was and remains a fundamental part of the discourse of environmental ethics, I will provide some reasons to doubt the efficacy of this approach to value theory in part two of the book. Finally, by the 1980s it became conventional among environmental phi- losophers to contrast an “ecological worldview” with “the Modern scientific worldview”—where the latter is taken to be an expression of Cartesian dual- ism, atomism, mechanism, and reductionist materialism—and to indict it as one of the central causes of the ecological crisis. The theoretical and techno- logical transformations characterizing the Scientific Revolution, along with its supporting Judeo-Christian tradition, were seen as chief contributors to the highly anthropocentric, exploitative relationship of humankind to nature in western culture. From Arne Naess’s contrast between thing- and field-ontology (1972), to Carolyn Merchant’s case against Modern science and her plea for a return to a holistic, organismic conception of nature (1980), to Charles Birch and John Cobb Jr.’s mechanistic and ecological models of the living (1981), to J. Baird Callicott’s “metaphysical implications of ecology” (1986), and, ultimate- ly, to the elaboration of these alternative conceptions by other writers during the 1990s, including Warwick Fox (1990, 1995), Bryan Norton (1991), Murray Bookchin (1996), and Arran Gare (1996), this contrast became a defining fea- ture of environmental philosophy. Since “worldview” talk is also central to the post-Kantian tradition, the Continentalists among environmentalists seam- lessly extended the general antipathy to the sciences in the dominant strains of Continental philosophy into environmentalism, and works like Neil Evernden’s (1985) and David Abram’s (1995) also traded on a series of oppositions cen- tral to the grand contrast between mechanist and ecological worldviews. Even today, there are calls for “worldview remediation” and proposals to explicit- ly use the worldview concept as a tool in sustainable development debates.8 Introduction 3 © 2020 State University of New York Press, Albany Although the figures and approaches listed are often conceived as antagonistic to one another (e.g., deep ecology is often not compatible with pragmatism, nor is ecophenomenology compatible with social ecology), they share the preoccu- pation with distinguishing a minority environmentalist “ecological worldview” from a hegemonic “mechanistic worldview.” I will call this the “worldview clash” model for thinking about science-environmentalism relations. This book is organized around these three major topics. Used in the sense of “central issues” or “places” (topoi) of contention and thought, topics are “clear enough and serious enough to engage a mind to whom they are new, and also abrasive enough to strike sparks off those who have been thinking about these things for years.”9 This book directly engages with the fundamental assumptions, categories, concepts, and value priorities that characterize large parts of environmentalist thinking, and considers the conditions under which environmentalists and others generally think about the nature of humankind (philosophical anthropology), how they think about the value of nonhuman nature (metaethics and value theory), and how they understand more-than- human nature generally (ontology and epistemology).10 The three parts of the book deal with these three broad topics. I have organized the book in terms of them not because I think they embody timeless philosophical questions, but because initially I found it helpful to organize the wide array of literature that falls under the heading of environmental philosophy in this way, and hopefully it will be for others. For introducing environmental philosophy to those unfamiliar with it, they also serve a heuristic function, like a ladder to be pulled up and carefully dismantled once one reaches the desired height. I consider environmental philosophy to be an informed examination of the concepts, categories, assumptions, and priorities in historically and cultural- ly diverse human interaction with the human and nonhuman natural world, along with the implications of their mostly tacit operation. Philosophers have long recognized that much human activity is caused and conditioned in large part—but never exclusively—by linguistic and conceptual categories, value pri- orities, and unspoken assumptions that remain mostly invisible to those who think and act with them. Philosophers are particularly good at thinking about such conditions, and if they have shown that these conditions motivate anti-en- vironmental activity in significant ways, finding the flaws
Recommended publications
  • A Metaphysical Approach to Environmental Sustainability- Alfred
    A METAPHYSICAL APPROACH TO ENVIRONMENTAL SUSTAINABILITY: ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD’S PROCESS PHILOSOPHY By DYNESIUS NYANGAU C50/79646/2015 A Research Project Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Award of the Degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy, University of Nairobi 2016 DECLARATION I declare that this research project is my original work and has not been presented for examination in any other university. __________________________ _______________________________ Sign Date Dynesius Nyangau C50/79646/2015 This research project has been submitted for examination with my approval as the university supervisor. ____________________________ _______________________________ Sign Date Dr. Patrick O. Nyabul Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies University of Nairobi ii DEDICATION To the late Professor Joseph Nyasani, in whose sense of duty I will ever remain, for his acerbic academic discernment, resolute inspiration and unflagging demonstration of the most philosophical audacity, charity and bounteousness in the face of great hardship. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENT I hold with esteem the input of Prof. Stephen Ifedha Akaranga, the Head of Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies for his specific contribution on methodology while working on this document. I remain indebted to my supervisor Dr. Patrick O. Nyabul for his dedication, continuous review and guidance throughout the study. I acknowledge with gratitude the input of Prof. Karori Mbugua and Prof. Solomon Monyenye who listened, critiqued, and helped me organize my thoughts before beginning to put down the proposal for this project. I thank my educators Dr. Francis Owakah and Dr. Oriare Nyarwath, whose constructive criticism and input helped shape up this work. I express gratitude to Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Mainstream Religion in Australia
    Is 'green' religion the solution to the ecological crisis? A case study of mainstream religion in Australia by Steven Murray Douglas Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the Australian National University March 2008 ii Candidate's Declaration This thesis contains no material that has been accepted for the award of any other degree or diploma in any university. To the best of the author’s knowledge, it contains no material previously published or written by another person, except where due reference is made in the text. Steven Murray Douglas Date: iii Acknowledgements “All actions take place in time by the interweaving of the forces of nature; but the man lost in selfish delusion thinks he himself is the actor.” (Bhagavad Gita 3:27). ‘Religion’ remains a somewhat taboo subject in Australia. When combined with environmentalism, notions of spirituality, the practice of criticality, and the concept of self- actualisation, it becomes even harder to ‘pigeonhole’ as a topic, and does not fit comfortably into the realms of academia. In addition to the numerous personal challenges faced during the preparation of this thesis, its very nature challenged the academic environment in which it took place. I consider that I was fortunate to be able to undertake this research with the aid of a scholarship provided by the Fenner School of Environment & Society and the College of Science. I acknowledge David Dumaresq for supporting my scholarship application and candidature, and for being my supervisor for my first year at ANU. Emeritus Professor Valerie Brown took on the role of my supervisor in David’s absence during my second year.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Or Metaphors for the Anthropocene? Scientific Naturalism and the Agency of Things
    Open Philosophy 2018; 1: 191–212 Patrick Gamez* Metaphysics or Metaphors for the Anthropocene? Scientific Naturalism and the Agency of Things https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2018-0014 Received June 17, 2018; accepted July 31, 2018 Abstract: In this paper, I provide the outlines of an alternative metaphilosophical orientation for Continental philosophy, namely, a form of scientific naturalism that has proximate roots in the work of Bachelard and Althusser. I describe this orientation as an “alternative” insofar as it provides a framework for doing justice to some of the motivations behind the recent revival of metaphysics in Continental philosophy, in particular its ecological-ethical motivations. In the second section of the paper, I demonstrate how ecological-ethical issues motivate new metaphysicians like Bruno Latour, Jane Bennett, Timothy Morton, Ian Bogost, and Graham Harman to impute to objects real features of agency. I also try to show how their commitments lead to deep ambiguities in their metaphysical projects. In the final section, I outline a type of scientific naturalism in Continental philosophy that parallels the sort of naturalism championed by Quine, both conceptually and historically, and suggest that it might serve our ecological-ethical purposes better. Keywords: speculative realism, vital materialism, environmental ethics, non-anthropocentrism, Bachelard, Althusser, Continental philosophy 1 Introduction 1.1 Overview The landscape of Continental philosophy has changed radically in the early 21st century. The last 15 years have seen a resurgence of speculative philosophy, rationalisms, and realisms of all stripes. We see this in the “new materialism” of Diana Coole and others, the Deleuzian realism of Manuel Delanda, the “object-oriented philosophy” of Graham Harman, and many others.
    [Show full text]
  • Ontology and Ethics at the Intersection of Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy*
    Inquiry, 47, 380–412 Ontology and Ethics at the Intersection of Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy* Iain Thomson University of New Mexico The idea inspiring the eco-phenomenological movement is that phenomenology can help remedy our environmental crisis by uprooting and replacing environmentally- destructive ethical and metaphysical presuppositions inherited from modern philosophy. Eco-phenomenology’s critiques of subject/object dualism and the fact/value divide are sketched and its positive alternatives examined. Two competing approaches are discerned within the eco-phenomenological movement: Nietzscheans and Husserlians propose a naturalistic ethical realism in which good and bad are ultimately matters of fact, and values should be grounded in these proto- ethical facts; Heideggerians and Levinasians articulate a transcendental ethical realism according to which we discover what really matters when we are appropriately open to the environment, but what we thereby discover is a transcendental source of meaning that cannot be reduced to facts, values, or entities of any kind. These two species of ethical realism generate different kinds of ethical perfectionism: naturalistic ethical realism yields an eco-centric perfectionism which stresses the flourishing of life in general; transcendental ethical realism leads to a more ‘humanistic’ perfectionism which emphasizes the cultivation of distinctive traits of Dasein. Both approaches are examined, and the Heideggerian strand of the humanistic approach defended, since it approaches the best elements of the eco-centric view while avoiding its problematic ontological assumptions and anti-humanistic implications. I. Introduction: Uncovering the Conceptual Roots of Environmental Devastation What happens when you cross phenomenology with environmental philoso- phy? According to the editors of Eco-Phenomenology: Back to the Earth Itself, you get an important interdisciplinary movement.
    [Show full text]
  • Environmental Philosophy: Beyond Environmental Ethics
    Environmental Philosophy: Beyond Environmental Ethics Mark Colyvan* Abstract: There are many interesting philosophical issues associated with the science and policy of conserving our natural environment. Despite much of the philosophical work being passed off as environmental ethics, it is clear that the issues in question go well beyond anything that can reasonably be thought of as belonging to environmental ethics. A great deal of the philosophical work required involves epistemology and decision theory. Moreover, this is no mere terminological issue. Misconstruing the nature of the issues in question, and the tools available to deal with them, can result in sub- optimal environmental outcomes. Once we disentangle the various philosophical issues in question, the proper role of environmental ethics, and environmental philosophy more generally, becomes clearer. The central focus of environmental ethics ought to be that of how to implement ethical environmental strategies in the face of uncertainty—uncertainty both about how the world is and about the relevant values. But the proper representation of the uncertainties in question is the business of epistemology, and the proper framework for making the decisions in question is the business of decision theory. Thinking that either of these latter issues falls within the purview of environmental ethics is a dangerous mistake. Environmental ethics concerns itself with ethical issues arising from the relationship between humans and the natural environment. Of particular interest are ethical considerations in relation to human efforts to conserve the natural environment. Some of the key environmental ethics issues are whether environmental value is intrinsic or instrumental, whether biodiversity is valuable in itself or whether it is an indicator of some other value(s), and what the appropriate time scale is for conservation planning.
    [Show full text]
  • "Environmental Justice"
    IIENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE"JUSTICE" Holmes Rolston, IIIIII Colorado State UniversityUniversity nvironmentalJustice is a welcome addition to the rapidly growing literature in envi­ A review of Peter S. Wenz's Environmental ronmental ethics. Two dozen titles are Justice, (Albany: State University of New York E currently in print or in press, and this Press, 1988).368 pages. $52.50 hardbound, book will hold its own in that vigorous discussion. Peter S. Wenz is Associate Professor of Philosophy $19.95 paper. and Legal Studies at Sangaman State University, Springfield, Illinois. His background in law as well as philosophy shapes his approach, which is from the perspective of justice. "Environmental Justice is primarily about theories of distributive justice, the­ ories concerning the manner in which benefits and burdens should be allocated when there is a scarcity of benefits (relative to people's wants or needs) and a surfeit of burdens" (pp. xi-xii). "The present book is largely devoted to examining com­ peting principles of distributive justice as they are, or may be used to make environmentally focused decisions" (p. 24). Wenz finds environmental justice of critical importance, both practically and theoretically. "I have argued that we live in an extremely unjust world" (p. 338). "From the environmentalenvironmental justice perspective, the world is a mess" (p. 339). In his .~~., '~~''q ~ q'# REVIEW q'# Ii 1.L.)~ I!l~ Summer 1989 147 Between the Species '-"~.>j',,~ ..'?!l'{;-""'i,,)<,'i:*,'~"'., :c.."-." Environmenta1Jusnee search for justice, Wenz surveys available theories animal rights. Humans have a right to be rescued and tests them against cases real and imagined.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking Duck the Newsletter for the Department of Philosophy at the University of Oregon Spring 2008
    The THINKING DUCK THE NEWSLETTER FOR THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY AT THE UNIVERSITY OF OREGON SPRING 2008 The Society for Interdisciplinary Feminist Phenomenology A new initiative promises to change the face of feminist philosophy by Lori Brown, graduate student he Society for Interdisciplin- ary Feminist Phenomenology T (SIFP) will host its inaugural institute and public forum over Me- morial Day weekend, May 28–31. SIFP is the brainchild of philoso- phy faculty members Bonnie Mann and Beata Stawarska. Bringing it to fruition, however, has involved the efforts of people and programs from across—and beyond—the uni- versity. Bonnie and Beata founded the institute in 2006 with advisory assistance from Sara Heinämaa, senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of Helsinki, and Eva Maria Simms, professor of psychology at Duquesne University. The society’s inception was further aided by gen- erous funding from the University Seated (left to right): cofounders of SIFP Dr. Beata Stawarska and Dr. Bonnie Mann. Back row of Oregon’s Center for the Study of (left to right): current administrative graduate teaching fellows and graduate students Caroline Lundquist, Elena Cuffari, Emma Jones, Amrita Banerjee and Sarah LaChance Adams Women in Society, the College of Arts and Sciences, the Wired Humanities Project, the Oregon complished through a small-group focus, an opportunity for deep Humanities Center, and the Department of Philosophy. engagement with one another’s work beforehand, and a commit- Graduate students in the philosophy department also have ment to holding the sessions in a beautiful place. been integral to the society’s success. Sarah LaChance Adams Now, that last point may catch you off guard.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Reflection on Environmental Pragmatism
    A CRITICAL REFLECTION ON ENVIRONMENTAL PRAGMATISM A Thesis Submitted in to Indian Institute of Technology Guwahati in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Award of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy By DEVARTHA MORANG ROLL NO-09614105 DEPARTMENT OF HUMANITIES AND SOCIAL SCIENCES INDIAN INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY GUWAHATI Guwahati 781039 India October 2016 1 DEDICATION To my parents & my mother-in- law Smti. Tileswari Loing 2 TH-1633_09614105 Indian Institute of Technology Guwahati Department of Humanities & Social Sciences Guwahati 781039 Assam, India DECLARATION I hereby declare that the thesis entitle “ A Critical Reflection on Environmental Pragmatism ” is a research work carried out by me in the Department of Humanities and Social Sciences, Indian Institute of Technology Guwahati, under the supervision of Prof. Prabhu Venkataraman for the award of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. This work has not been submitted elsewhere for award of any degree or diploma in any university or institute. Devartha Morang 21 st October 2016 IIT Guwahati i TH-1633_09614105 Indian Institute of Technology Guwahati Department of Humanities & Social Sciences Guwahati 781039 Assam, India CERTIFICATE It is certified that the matter embodied in the thesis entitled A Critical Reflection on Environmental Pragmatism, submitted for the award of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Devartha Morang, a student of the Department of Humanities and Social Sciences, Indian Institute of Technology Guwahati, India, has been carried out under my supervision. It is also certified that this work has not been submitted anywhere else for the award of a research degree. IIT Guwahati Dr. V. Prabhu October 2016 Associate Professor Department of Humanities and Social Sciences IIT Guwahati, Assam, India ii TH-1633_09614105 ACKNOWLEDGEMENT I thank my parent organization the Biswanath College for giving me opportunity to pursue my research work at the Indian Institute of Technology Guwahati, India in the department of Humanities and social sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Environmental and Ecological Justice
    Environmental and ecological justice Book or Report Section Accepted Version Okereke, C. and Charlesworth, M. (2014) Environmental and ecological justice. In: Betsill, M. M., Hochstetler, K. and Stevis, D. (eds.) Advances in International Environmental Politics. 2nd Edition. Palgrave Advances. Palgrave Macmilian, New York, pp. 123-147. ISBN 9781137338969 Available at http://centaur.reading.ac.uk/38520/ It is advisable to refer to the publisher’s version if you intend to cite from the work. See Guidance on citing . Published version at: http://www.palgrave.com/page/detail/advances-in-international-environmental-politics-michele- m-betsill/?K=9781137338969 Publisher: Palgrave Macmilian All outputs in CentAUR are protected by Intellectual Property Rights law, including copyright law. Copyright and IPR is retained by the creators or other copyright holders. Terms and conditions for use of this material are defined in the End User Agreement . www.reading.ac.uk/centaur CentAUR Central Archive at the University of Reading Reading’s research outputs online 13 Environmental and Ecological Justice Chukwumerije Okereke and Mark Charlesworth Introduction Justice is a central theme in international environmental politics (IEP). In fact, one of the most distinctive contributions of IEP to the broader International Relations (IR) scholarship and discourse is arguably the firm insertion and elevation of questions of distributive justice. It is broadly accepted that justice occupies a central position in Western moral political philosophy. Hume (1975) described justice as the most important virtue of social relations and political institutions. St Augustine (1467/2003: 139) considered that the very legitimacy of a state lays on its claim to do justice.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defence of Plant Personhood
    religions Article In Defence of Plant Personhood Matthew Hall Victoria University of Wellington, Kelburn Parade, Wellington 6023, New Zealand; [email protected] Received: 21 March 2019; Accepted: 3 May 2019; Published: 10 May 2019 Abstract: The philosopher Michael Marder has asserted that animist engagement with plants involves a projection of human purposes and goals leading to veneration. He has also argued that an extension of a categorical concept of personhood underpins my previous work on plant personhood. This paper draws on the growing scholarship of animist traditions following the work of Hallowell to reject Marder’s characterization of a naïve animist approach to plants. It draws on these insights from animist traditions to outline a relational plant personhood, which is fully realized only in grounded, situated relationships of care that seek to enable the flourishing of plants. Keywords: plants; personhood; animism; kinship; relational autonomy; ethics; care; subjectivity 1. Introduction The geographer Puleo(2019) has recently charted the ever-increasing body of research into plant subjectivities. Starting his journey with Michael Pollan’s The Botany of Desire, Puleo navigates through the work of Stefano Mancuso, a pioneer of plant neurobiology, name checks this author’s work on plant personhood and explores Michael Marder’s vegetal ontology alongside Jeffrey Nealon’s work on plant theory. Of particular interest to this author, and to this Special Issue on religions and plants, is Marder’s criticism of the concept of plant personhood. In a discussion of plants as subjects, Puleo cites Marder’s assertion in his work Plant-Thinking (Marder 2013, p.
    [Show full text]
  • G20 Interfaith Summit Istanbul, November 16-18, 2015 Religion, Harmony and Sustainable Development
    G20 Interfaith Summit Istanbul, November 16-18, 2015 Religion, Harmony and Sustainable Development Panel Religion, Environment and Sustainable Development THE MAKING AND MESSAGE OF ISLAMIC DECLARATION ON GLOBAL CLIMATE CHANGE Professor İbrahim Özdemir The Founding President, Gazikent University, Turkey [email protected] 1. Common Problems Facing Humanity It seems that environmental problems is the root cause of world’s greatest problems, climate change, deforestation, erosion, floods, drought, hunger, racism, migration international and domestic terror, human rights violations, human trafficking, economic inequality, and even nihilism. When trying to understand the current conflicts in the Middle East and the respective domestic and international terror, we should also think the negative and devastating effects of climate change on the region on the one hand and the rush of powerful states to control the region for the enormous resources of fossil fuels on the other. As much as our dependency on these resources continue, it seems these conflicts will prevail, too. After the fall of Berlin Wall, symbol of cold war era, eco-philosopher Henryk Skolomowski warned the West with these remarkable words: … the West has won the battle against communism. But winning this battle - is it a victory? Or perhaps a pyrrhic victory? Entranced and mesmerized by this battle, we have perhaps neglected to see that we have been losing another, a more important battle - the battle to save the earth and to save the meaning of our lives. (Skolomowski, 1991, italics mine) Today, we understand and appreciate what Skolomowski’s words really meant and how to fight to win “the battle to save the earth and to save the meaning of our lives” with a new spirit of optimism, understanding, and cooperation.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Nature As Text: Towards an Environmental Hermeneutics and Space Identity Awareness in Portuguese Eco-Culture Key-Words
    Reading nature as text: towards an environmental hermeneutics and space identity awareness in Portuguese eco-culture Key-words: Landscape, Interpretation, Biodiversity, Selfhood, Sustainability 1. Background Concerns about the environment and the acknowledgment of human emplacement have led in the last few years to the emergence of a new philosophical discipline. The ‘emerging field of environmental hermeneutics’ (Clingerman, Treanor, Drenthen & Utsler 2014) intends to interpret and understand the complex interactions between human beings and the natural environment. In its most robust sense, environmental hermeneutics seeks to understand how our 'hermeneutical consciousness' (Gadamer’s concept) enlightens our relationship with environments. There is no doubt that, «as beings with physical bodies, our embodiment implies our emplacement» (Clingerman and Dixon 2011: ix). Or, as Heidegger said, ‘to be is to dwell’, but to dwell implies changing the environment and landscape in which we dwell for better and for worse. In turn, the places we inhabit influence our identity – who we are, what we do, and how we conceive ourselves in relation to other human beings, non-human animals and the wider natural environment. Understanding these complex influences and interactions is essential to determine how we interpret who and what we are and how we emplace ourselves in the world. Given this stance, environmental hermeneuticists have proceeded from an understanding of hermeneutics which draws mainly on the works of Gadamer and, in particular, Ricœur (see Utsler 2009; Drenthen 2011, 2014; Clingerman 2014). If landscapes and places can be read like texts (see the concept of 'legible landscape' in Drenthen 2011 and 2014 and the meditations of Clingerman 2009 about the 'Book of Nature'), then the act of reading landscape texts could be formative for personal and collective identities.
    [Show full text]