A Structurationist View on Knowledge and Strategic Management

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Structurationist View on Knowledge and Strategic Management Going Beyond the Resources Given: A Structurationist View on Knowledge and Strategic Management ALBRECHT BECKER STEPHAN DUSCHEK Department of Business Administration Free University, Berlin Garystr. 21 D- 14195 Berlin, Germany Tel.: +49 30 838 54069 Fax: +49 30 838 53307 [email protected] ELISABETH BRAUNER Institute for Psychology Humboldt-University in Berlin Oranienburger Str. 18 D-10178 Berlin, Germany Tel.: +49 30 285 165 349 Fax: +49 30 285 165-329 [email protected] Paper prepared for The Third European Conference on Organizational Knowledge, Learning, and Capabilities - OKLC - Athens, Greece April 5-6, 2002 Please do not cite without permission 2 Abstract Current knowledge-based theories explain firms' competitive advantages through the use of dynamic resources. They cannot, however, explicate how knowledge-based resources are created and why they are reproducible and inimitable at the same time. We present a model of resource usage and creation, which is based on structuration theory, phenomenology and the concept of transactive knowledge systems. The recursive process of the simultaneous creation and use of knowledge-based resources is conceptualized as a process of structuration. We argue that the concept of transactive knowledge systems may account for firm-specific usages of unshared expertise as the basis for competitive advantages as well as for the inimitability of resources. 3 1 Introduction Within the resource-based view of the firm it is widely acknowledged that knowledge is the main source of competitive advantages (Conner & Prahalad, 1996; Krogh & Roos, 1996). Correspondingly, the so-called knowledge-based view of the firm is gaining more and more acceptance within the overall framework of resource-based theorizing (cf. Kogut & Zander, 1992; Spender & Grant, 1996). Spender (1994, 1996a) argues from a knowledge-based perspective that organizational knowledge, understood as shared, or collective, tacit knowledge, is crucial for the generation of competitive advantages. The tacitness of knowledge brings about nonmarketability, nonsubstitutability, and inimitability, which are necessary qualities of resources that can provide sustained competitive advantages (Hoops & Postrel, 1999). Collective and tacit organizational knowledge, thus, is seen as the main source of economic rents in knowledge-based theories (Spender, 1994, 1996a; Collis, 1996). But the knowledge-based view of competitive advantages, first, fails to conceptualize the generation of knowledge (Gulati, Nohira, & Zaheer, 2000). Second, it cannot cope with the resources' paradoxical character as, on the one hand, tacit and unique and, on the other hand, reproducible at the same time. Our paper focuses on a re-conceptualization of the knowledge-based perspective on the sources of competitive advantages. We start from Penrose's (1995) proposition that not resources per se but the services generated by the use of these resources account for competitive advantages. Our line of reasoning is based on the structurationist theory of organizations (Giddens, 1984), a phenomenological conceptualization of the emergence and reproduction of knowledge (Schütz, 1982; cf. Duschek, 2001), and the concept of transactive knowledge systems (Brauner, in prep.; Brauner & Becker, 2001, under review). We argue that the generation of knowledge as resource may be seen, first, as part of the process of using 4 context-free resources in a unique and context-bound way as modalities of structuration. Second, the differentiation between object-level knowledge and metaknowledge, that is knowledge about knowledge, in the concept of transactive knowledge systems provides a more in-depth understanding of the use and generation of knowledge. It is the interplay of unshared expertise and partly shared, or mutual, metaknowledge which can account for the inimitability of knowledge-based resources of competitive advantages. In the following section of the paper we will, first, demonstrate the knowledge-based view's problems in explaining the origin of knowledge and, thus, of competitive advantages. Then, we will show the paradoxical character of resources. In the last two parts of section 2 we develop a concept of knowledge-based resources and their use based on structuration theory and phenomenology. Section 3 presents our application of the concept of transactive knowledge systems to the use and generation of knowledge-based resources. 2 Knowledge and Sustained Competitive Advantages 2.1 The Unclear Origin of Knowledge Knowledge-based competitive advantages has initially been analyzed within the framework of Ricardian rents (Peteraf, 1993; Schulze, 1994). The focus of resource-based approaches is on valuable knowledge that is rare, immobile, and nonsubstitutable. Beyond this, Ricardian knowledge-based resources have to be in fixed or inelastic supply in the long run (cf. Varian, 1999) As a result, the sources of Ricardian rents are conceptualized as exogenous to the firm (Spender, 1996b), the origins of competitive advantages cannot be explained within the boundaries of this approach. Resources may only be treated as given; they are “intrinsically heterogeneous factors” (Collis, 1996: 140). The task of strategic management, then, is limited to the discovery of nonmarketable, nonsubstitutable, and inimitable knowledge among the 5 firm's entire stocks of knowledge (Barney, 1986, 1991). The generation of (new) knowledge as a source of competitive advantages is beyond its scope. The concept of Penrose rents, which is favored by the knowledge-based approaches of strategic management, explains competitive advantages with dynamic factors endogenous to the firm. Already in 1959, Penrose (1995, first published 1959) argued that competitive advantages are generated not by resources per se but by services, that is by firm-specific uses of resources (Dierickx & Cool, 1989; Mahoney & Pandian, 1992; Teece, Pisano, & Shuen, 1997; Kor & Mahoney, 2000). These unique services are termed, for instance „core competencies“ (Prahalad & Hamel, 1990), „core capabilities“ (Leonard-Barton, 1992, 1995), „combinatorial capacities“ (Kogut & Zander, 1992), „strategic assets“ (cf. Amit & Schoemaker, 1993), or „dynamic capabilities“ (Teece et al., 1997) within the (modern) resource-based and knowledge-based literatures. Achieving competitive advantages, in this view, is an evolutionary process of cumulative growth of knowledge in the specific context of a firm (Penrose, 1995). Hence, this dynamic knowledge-based view is going undoubtedly beyond „resources given“. Quite explicitly, it claims to analyze the generation of resources, namely collective knowledge. But taking a closer look at the literature reveals that the knowledge-based view either is basically taxonomic in character (Spender, 1996a, b; Nonaka & Takeuchi, 1995; see for a critical illustration Tsoukas, 1996) or deals with the process of resource generation rather sketchily (Moran & Goshal, 1999; Tsoukas & Valdimirou, 2001). Thus, Gulati, Nohira, and Zaheer (2000: 207) conclude that even the dynamic knowledge-based view of the firm either takes the resources as given or assumes "that firms 'somehow' develop such resources". The origin of knowledge, that is the value generating process of building knowledge-based competitive advantages, remains unclear as we will explain in more detail in the following section. 6 2.2 The Paradoxical Character of Resources The knowledge-based view's difficulties to explain the origin of knowledge as a resource stems from two closely related sources: First, proponents of this view conceptualize the notion of knowledge in a somewhat unclear way (Grant, 1996; Tsoukas & Vladimirou, 2001) and, second, they cannot deal with the resources' paradoxical character (Duschek, 2001; Ortmann & Sydow, 2001). Organizational knowledge and specifically knowledge that may form the basis for competitive advantages is seen as shared, or collective, and tacit knowledge (Penrose, 1959; Spender, 1996a, b; Hoops & Postrel, 1999). The shared and tacit character of knowledge shall account for the causal ambiguity of knowledge as resource (Collis, 1996), that is the unclear causal link between knowledge and competitive advantages (Reed & DeFillippi, 1990). Causal ambiguity is seen as a main barrier to imitation of resources. This argument raises a main issue about sustained competitive advantages as the tacitness and causal ambiguity of resources contain the seed of the self-destruction of competitive advantages (Collis, 1996). On the one hand, the continuance of the existing dynamic patterns of productive activities must be a repeated process (Amit & Shoemaker, 1993). To produce competitive advantages of the firm it has to stretch beyond the boundaries of single strategic business units (Prahald & Hamel, 1990). Furthermore, the unique way of resource usage must be systematically monitored, that is the firm must know that the services can provide a "template for the creation of new patterns or routines" (Krogh & Roos, 1996: 35). The tacitness and causal ambiguity, on the other hand, obstructs the possibility of systematic observation, intended reproduction, and management of resource usage and knowledge because tacitness implies the inability to explicitly reflect on knowledge (Reber, 1993; Polanyi, 1966). Thus, there is a paradox in the knowledge-based view's conceptualization of unique resources as basis for sustained competitive advantages: The uniqueness implies opacity and tacitness of knowledge, the sustained character requires
Recommended publications
  • Belief in Psyontology Cumstances (Ross & Schroeder, 2014; Schwitzgebel, 2015)
    Philosophers’ volume 20, no. 11 ow are full and partial belief related in psychology’s ontology? Imprint april 2020 H Credence-first philosophers think partial belief is more funda- mental. For example, Lockeans say that to believe P is just to have high credence in P. Whereas categorical-first philosophers make full beliefs fundamental instead. Having credence x in P might just amount to having a categorical belief that P’s probability is x, for example. Work in cognitive psychology supports a different view, however. In humans, beliefs come in both coarse and fine kinds, with neither BELIEF IN more fundamental than the other. Epistemologists who focus on one kind to the exclusion of the other, or who treat one as central and the other as an afterthought, risk toiling at a fiction. This conclusion is necessarily tentative. For one thing, the empir- PSYONTOLOGY ical work is nascent and ongoing, its results subject to revision. But more than that, it’s sometimes unclear what the present results tell us about the ontological and epistemological questions of interest to philosophers. Still, a prima facie case can be made. And making it is an essential step in bringing our best science to bear on what is, at least in part, an empirical question. 1. Background Jonathan Weisberg 1.1 Why Monism? Why think one kind of belief is more fundamental than the other? It’s not just that Anglophone philosophers use ‘belief’ for both kinds, so University of Toronto they must really be the same thing deep down.1 It’s rather what causes us to use ‘belief’ for both attitudes.
    [Show full text]
  • 3. Overview of Core Technical Areas of AI Research Roadmap Research
    A 20-YEAR COMMUNITY ROADMAP FOR ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE RESEARCH IN THE US of actions.22 Future approaches to cybersecurity and defense will benefit from the powerful capabilities provided by AI systems. This report envisions how future AI systems can aid in responses to other types of threats as well, including natural disasters. 3. Overview of Core Technical Areas of AI Research Roadmap As discussed in section 1.2 the CCC, with the support of AAAI, held three community workshops in order to catalyze discussion and generate this research Roadmap. The three workshops were: ◗ Integrated Intelligence ◗ Meaningful Interactions ◗ Self-Aware Learning The research priorities from the three areas are summarized in Figure 3 below and expanded upon in the following three sections of the report. Research Priorities Integrated Intelligence Meaningful Interaction Self-Aware Learning • Science of integrated intelligence • Collaboration • Robust and trustworthy learning • Contextualized AI • Trust and responsibility • Deeper learning for challenging tasks • Open knowledge repositories • Diversity of interaction channels • Integrating symbolic and numeric representations • Understanding human intelligence • Improving online interaction • Learning in integrated AI/robotic systems Figure 3. Research Priorities. 3.1 A Research Roadmap for Integrated Intelligence 3.1.1 INTRODUCTION AND OVERVIEW The development of integrated intelligent systems will require major research efforts, which we group into three major areas: 1. Integration: Science of Integrated Intelligence will explore how to create intelligent systems that have much broader capabilities than today’s systems. Approaches include finding small sets of primitives out of which a broad range of capabilities can be constructed (like many of today’s cognitive architectures) and composing independently developed AI capabilities (like 22 ibid 16 many of today’s deployed intelligent systems).
    [Show full text]
  • Naturalistic Cognition: a Research Paradigm for Human-Centered Design
    Published by AU Press, Canada Journal of Research Practice Journal of Research Practice Volume 6, Issue 2, Article M12, 2010 Main Article: Naturalistic Cognition: A Research Paradigm for Human-Centered Design Peter Storkerson Human Factors Program, College of Engineering University of Illinois Urbana Champaign, USA pks@illinois edu Abstract Naturalistic thinking and knowing, the tacit, experiential, and intuitive reasoning of everyday interaction, have long been regarded as inferior to formal reason and labeled primitive, fallible, subjective, superstitious, and in some cases ineffable. But, naturalistic thinking is more rational and definable than it appears. It is also relevant to design. Inquiry into the mechanisms of naturalistic thinking and knowledge can bring its resources into focus and enable designers to create better, human-centered designs for use in real-world settings. This article makes a case for the explicit, formal study of implicit, naturalistic thinking within the fields of design. It develops a framework for defining and studying naturalistic thinking and knowledge, for integrating them into design research and practice, and for developing a more integrated, consistent theory of knowledge in design. It will (a) outline historical definitions of knowledge, attitudes toward formal and naturalistic thinking, and the difficulties presented by the co-presence of formal and naturalistic thinking in design, (b) define and contrast formal and naturalistic thinking as two distinct human cognitive systems, (c) demonstrate the importance of naturalistic cognition in formal thinking and real-world judgment, (d) demonstrate methods for researching naturalistic thinking that can be of use in design, and (e) briefly discuss the impact on design theory of admitting naturalistic thinking as valid, systematic, and knowable.
    [Show full text]
  • Qualified Hope
    Qualified hope 2nd Huehls.indb 1 3/10/2009 10:58:49 PM 2nd Huehls.indb 2 3/10/2009 10:58:49 PM Q u a l i f i e d H o p e a postmodern politics of time mitchum huehls The ohio State university press Columbus 2nd Huehls.indb 3 3/10/2009 10:58:49 PM Copyright © 2009 by The Ohio State University. All rights reserved. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Huehls, Mitchum, 1976– Qualified hope : a postmodern politics of time / Mitchum Huehls. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-8142-0617-1 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. American literature—20th century—History and criticism. 2. American literature—21st century—History and criticism. 3. Politics and literature—United States—History—20th century. 4. Politics and literature—United States—History—21st century. 5. Time in litera- ture. 6. Time—Political aspects. 7. Postmodernism (Literature)—United States. I. Title. PS228.P6H84 2009 810.9'3581—dc22 2008050627 This book is available in the following editions: Cloth (ISBN 978-0-8142-0617-1) CD-ROM (ISBN 978-0-8142-9184-9) Cover design by Mia Risberg Text design by Jennifer Shoffey Forsythe Type set in Adobe Minion Pro Printed by Thomson-Shore, Inc. The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials. ANSI Z39.48–1992. 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 2nd Huehls.indb 4 3/10/2009 10:58:49 PM for marissa 2nd Huehls.indb 5 3/10/2009 10:58:49 PM 2nd Huehls.indb 6 3/10/2009 10:58:49 PM C o n T e n ts acknowledgments
    [Show full text]
  • On the Relationship of Metaphysics to Transdisciplinarity 79
    Eric L. Weislogel On the Relationship of Metaphysics to Transdisciplinarity 79 On the Relationship of Metaphysics to Transdisciplinarity Eric L. Weislogel, Saint Joseph’s University, Philadelphia, PA, USA, Email: [email protected] doi: 10.22545/2013/00040 his essay shows the parallels between meta- to. For who could possibly be \educated in every physics and transdisciplinarity, both in terms area"? It is no longer possible{if indeed it ever really Tof their aims and methods and in terms of were{to be a Renaissance person, engaged in the their place or role in academic institutions. It widest possible array of scientific, philosophical, and attempts to define metaphysics, addresses criticisms cultural pursuits. In our age of analysis and spe- of metaphysics, and indicates the necessary relation- cialization, one who posed as such could be seen as ship of metaphysics to transdisciplinary endeavors. no more than a dabbler. Perhaps only an Aristotle, who wrote on physics, logic, rhetoric, ethics, zoology, Keywords: metaphysics, philosophy, method, meteorology, poetics, politics, and so on, could make transdisciplinarity, hermeneutics, deconstruction. such a claim, but it seems far too late in the scientific and cultural evolution of humanity for us to expect another Aristotle to arrive on the scene. 1 Introduction But just exactly what did Aristotle mean by this insight that Terrence Irwin translates as being \ed- In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle recognizes that ucated in every area"? Did Aristotle mean by this \each person judges rightly what he knows, and is a that one would need to have developed \expertise" good judge about that; hence the good judge in a in every area, that (in today's terms) one would have given area is the person educated in that area." No to major in every subject, earn PhD's in every field, more succinct statement can be given as the basis in order to be the “unqualifiedly good judge"? And for our traditional disciplinary way of thinking, re- what does that latter phrase really signify? The searching, and educating.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology.Pdf
    Epistemology An overview Contents 1 Main article 1 1.1 Epistemology ............................................. 1 1.1.1 Background and meaning ................................... 1 1.1.2 Knowledge .......................................... 1 1.1.3 Acquiring knowledge ..................................... 5 1.1.4 Skepticism .......................................... 7 1.1.5 See also ............................................ 7 1.1.6 References .......................................... 8 1.1.7 Works cited .......................................... 9 1.1.8 External links ......................................... 10 2 Knowledge 11 2.1 Knowledge ............................................... 11 2.1.1 Theories of knowledge .................................... 11 2.1.2 Communicating knowledge ................................. 12 2.1.3 Situated knowledge ...................................... 13 2.1.4 Partial knowledge ...................................... 13 2.1.5 Scientific knowledge ..................................... 13 2.1.6 Religious meaning of knowledge ............................... 14 2.1.7 See also ............................................ 15 2.1.8 References .......................................... 15 2.1.9 External links ......................................... 16 2.2 Belief ................................................. 16 2.2.1 Knowledge and epistemology ................................. 17 2.2.2 As a psychological phenomenon ............................... 17 2.2.3 Epistemological belief compared to religious belief
    [Show full text]
  • Metaknowledge Management in Inquiring Organizations: Towards a Knowledge Ecology Alice Kienholz, Ph.D
    Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) Americas Conference on Information Systems AMCIS 2000 Proceedings (AMCIS) 2000 Metaknowledge Management in Inquiring Organizations: Towards a Knowledge Ecology Alice Kienholz, Ph.D. Alice Kienholz Associates, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2000 Recommended Citation Kienholz, Ph.D., Alice, "Metaknowledge Management in Inquiring Organizations: Towards a Knowledge Ecology" (2000). AMCIS 2000 Proceedings. 312. http://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2000/312 This material is brought to you by the Americas Conference on Information Systems (AMCIS) at AIS Electronic Library (AISeL). It has been accepted for inclusion in AMCIS 2000 Proceedings by an authorized administrator of AIS Electronic Library (AISeL). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Metaknowledge Management in Inquiring Organizations: Towards a Knowledge Ecology Alice Kienholz, Ph.D., Alice Kienholz Associates, [email protected] Abstract those various approaches to a situation, in the most appropriate way, that is important. This is metaknowledge Metaknowledge management is the judicious or management. strategic management or leveraging of the different ways in which we come “to know,” based on Churchman’s Inquiring Organizations (1971) classic work, “The Design of Inquiring Systems” so that we respond to situations in the most appropriate Building on Churchman’s insights, Courtney, way. It differs from knowledge management in that it is Croasdell and Paradice (1998) have recast Churchman’s concerned more with how we know what we know than (1971) models of inquiring systems in the language of a with what we know per se (information and knowledge). learning organization, to form the basis for effective By helping individuals and organizations to understand learning organizations which they refer to as inquiring and be aware of their preferred ways of thinking and organizations.
    [Show full text]
  • Domain Metatheories: Enabling User-Centric Planning
    Domain Metatheories: Enabling User-Centric Planning Karen L. Myers Artificial Intelligence Center SRI International 333 Ravenswood Ave., Menlo Park, CA 94025 [email protected] Abstract planning knowledge base could completely capture the sub- tleties of a particular domain, users often want to participate Substantial improvements must be made in the usabil- in the plan development process to some extent, in order to ity of AI planning technology in order for it to achieve ensure that they understand both the structure of a plan and widespread adoption. In particular, approaches are re- quired that better serve the needs of users, who gen- the process by which planning decisions were made. erally want to play a central role in the plan develop- For these reasons, the future of automated planning lies in ment process. This user-centric perspective introduces the development of user-centric planning tools that can as- new requirements for the design of planning systems. sist human decision-makers rather than replace them. These In this paper, we argue that increased usability requires tools should enable a user to understand the complexity of a new representational layer that captures metatheo- the underlying problem, as well as providing guidance in retic properties of the planning application. A domain the determination of a solution that is well-suited to their metatheory would provide an abstracted characteriza- specific needs. tion of the planning domain that highlights key seman- tic differences among planning elements. This paper The main thesis of this paper is that effective interaction presents a candidate model for a domain metatheory, between users and planning technology requires an augmen- as well as an instantiation of that model for a simple tation of standard planning models to include an explicit travel domain.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Philosophy of Science in Light of the Question of Naturalism
    Metascience as Self-Knowledge: Hegel’s Philosophy of Science in Light of the Question of Naturalism von der Fakultät für Sozialwissenschaften und Philosophie der Universität Leipzig genehmigte D I S S E R T A T I O N zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Doktor der Philosophie Dr. phil. vorgelegt von M.A. Roi Bar geboren am 28.05.1978 in Aschkelon, Israel Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Pirmin Stekeler-Weithofer Prof. Dr. Wolfgang Neuser Tag der Verleihung: 21.07.2017 Contents Acknowledgements .......................................................................................................... 6 INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................................... 7 1. IS THERE A PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE IN HEGEL’S ‘SYSTEM’? .............. 18 1.1 The formal hermeneutical problem ......................................................................... 19 1.1.1 The absence of an explicit ‘philosophy of science’ .......................................... 19 1.1.2 Two meanings of philosophy of science ........................................................... 21 1.2 The conceptual-historical problem .......................................................................... 26 1.2.1 The pseudoproblem of anachronism ................................................................. 26 1.2.2 The anti-Hegelian philosophy of science .......................................................... 29 1.3 The concrete research problem ..............................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Hierarchical Representation of Legal Knowledge with Metaprogramming in Logic
    J. LOGIC PROGRAMMING 1994:18:55-80 5.5 HIERARCHICAL REPRESENTATION OF LEGAL KNOWLEDGE WITH METAPROGRAMMING IN LOGIC JONAS BARKLUND AND ANDREAS HAMFELT D We present an application of metaprogramming in logic that, unlike most metaprogramming applications, is not primarily concerned with controlling the execution of logic programs. Metalevel computation is used to define theories from schemata that were either given explicitly or obtained by abstraction from other theories. Our main application is a representation of legal knowledge in a metalogic programming language. We argue that legal knowledge is multilayered and therefore a single level representation language lacks the needed expressiveness. We show that legal rules can be partitioned into primary, secondary, tertiary, quaternary, and higher level rules. Our classification enables us to define a multilevel model of legal knowledge and a one-to-one correspondence with levels of metaprogram- ming in logic. We show that this framework has a potential for capturing important legal interpretation principles such as analogia legis, lex specialis Zegigeneruli derogut, etc. We have a running example from commercial law that utilizes rules up to the tertiary level, emphasizing unulogiu legis. The example is expressed in a multilevel metalogic programming language that provides a naming convention and employs reflection between levels. a 1. INTRODUCTION Metalogic programming provides an expressive power that facilitates an intelligible representation of complex knowledge. We exploit a framework based on that proposed by Bowen and Kowalski [4, 291 for representing multilayered legal knowledge and, in particular, show how the reflection principles naturally mirror Address correspondence IO Jonas Barklund and Andreas Hamfelt, Computing Science Department, Uppsala University, Box 311, S-751 05 Uppsala, Sweden.
    [Show full text]
  • Metatheory and Reflection in Theorem Proving: a Survey and Critique
    Metatheory and Reflection in Theorem Proving: A Survey and Critique John Harrison University of Cambridge Computer Laboratory New Museums Site Pembroke Street Cambridge CB2 3QG England [email protected] 15th February 1995 Abstract One way to ensure correctness of the inference performed by computer theorem provers is to force all proofs to be done step by step in a simple, more or less traditional, deductive system. Using techniques pioneered in Edinburgh LCF, this can be made palatable. However, some believe such an approach will never be efficient enough for large, complex proofs. One alternative, commonly called reflection, is to analyze proofs using a second layer of logic, a metalogic, and so justify abbreviating or simplifying proofs, making the kinds of shortcuts humans often do or appealing to specialized decision algorithms. In this paper we contrast the fully-expansive LCF approach with the use of reflection. We put forward arguments to suggest that the inadequacy of the LCF approach has not been adequately demonstrated, and neither has the practical utility of reflection (notwithstanding its undoubted intellectual interest). The LCF system with which we are most concerned is the HOL proof assistant. The plan of the paper is as follows. We examine ways of providing user ex- tensibility for theorem provers, which naturally places the LCF and reflective approaches in opposition. A detailed introduction to LCF is provided, em- phasizing ways in which it can be made efficient. Next, we present a short in- troduction to metatheory and its usefulness, and, starting from G¨odel'sproofs and Feferman's transfinite progressions of theories, look at logical ‘reflection principles'.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletters NEWSLETTER on PHILOSOPHY and COMPUTERS
    APA Newsletters NEWSLETTER ON PHILOSOPHY AND COMPUTERS Volume 07, Number 1 Fall 2007 FROM THE EDITOR, PETER BOLTUC FROM THE OUTGOING CHAIR, MARVIN CROY FROM THE INCOMING CHAIR, MICHAEL BYRON ARTICLES LUCIANO FLORIDI “Understanding Information Ethics” RICCARDO MANZOTTI “Towards Artificial Consciousness” COMMENTARIES ON HARMAN YUJIN NAGASAWA “Formulating the Explanatory Gap” MARION LEDWIG “To Understand the Understanding—das Verstehen zu Verstehen: A Discussion of Harman’s ‘Explaining an Explanatory Gap’” DISCUSSION PAPERS GAETANO A. LANZARONE “Computing and Philosophy: In Search for a New Agenda” BERTIL ROLF “Testing Tools of Reasoning: Mechanisms and Procedures” © 2007 by The American Philosophical Association BOOK REVIEW Amy White: Virtually Obscene: The Case for an Uncensored Internet REVIEWED BY MELISSA WINKEL AMY WHITE “Reponse to Melissa Winkel” NOTES CAMERON BUCKNER, MATHIAS NIEPERT, AND COLIN ALLEN “InPhO: The Indiana Philosophy Ontology” GEOFFREY KLEMPNER “The Pathways School of Philosophy” MATT BUTCHER “NA-CAP@Loyola 2007” APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Computers Piotr Bołtuć, Editor Fall 2007 Volume 07, Number 1 Manzotti’s paper also serves as an excellent link to the second FROM THE EDITOR part of the Newsletter. The next two papers comment on the keynote article from the last issue of this Newsletter, Gilbert Harman’s “Explaining an Explanatory Gap.” In his contribution, Yujin Nagasawa Piotr Bołtuć presents a critical analysis of the way Harman formulates the University of Illinois–Springfield explanatory gap. He refers to Nagel’s what it is like to be a bat example to show that the explanatory gap may emerge from The previous issue of this Newsletter, the first one I edited, one of two reasons: either we have to be bat-type creatures to was devoted to making conspicuous the fact that philosophy know what it is like to have sonar, or objective characteristics and computers is no longer a new, controversial, or unproven of a bat do not tell us what it is like to have sonar.
    [Show full text]