Darwinism, Disvalues and Design Taylor & Francis. Not for Distribution

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Darwinism, Disvalues and Design Taylor & Francis. Not for Distribution Chapter Six Darwinism, Disvalues and Design Section 1: Darwinism It is time to say more about Darwinism, partly to explain its coherence and cogency, partly to introduce its implications for the Teleological Argument, and partly to illustrate and appraise the problem of natural evil which, as we have seen, contributed to Darwin’s own loss of belief in God. Darwinism will be discussed in the current section, together with some of its grounds and some of its varieties, to which we revert in later chapters. Its possible implications in the area of sociobiology will also be considered. In later sections of this chapter its bearing will be considered on the Design Argument, as will subsequently its compatibility with belief in God’s goodness. The theory of evolution by natural selection provides the backdrop for contemporary environmental concern, and several of the themes of this chapter will thus prove relevant to the scope and limits of environmental stewardship, discussed in the final two chapters of this book. Darwin’s theory asserts, in part, that life on Earth has evolved from a common ancestry1 and from relatively simple to relatively complex forms of life.2 Michael Ruse summarizes Darwin’s evidence as including grounds from palaeontology (the fossil record), bio-geography (for evolution best explains the distribution of bird and reptile species in places such as the Galapagos Islands), anatomical similarities across diverse species (for evolution from common ancestors best explains such ‘homologies’), and from systematics, for common ancestry best explains the way species can be ordered in a hierarchy of groups, which seem to call for an explanation of such a nature.3 In view of this and additional evidence (like that from embryology), the evolution of species was soon recognized as a fact.4 Darwin further argued that a major cause of the adaptedness of organisms that facilitates their evolution was natural selection. Because more individual organisms are produced than can survive, there is competition for survival, and only the fittest survive and reproduce. Darwin was hereby generalizing the findings of Thomas Robert Malthus to all biological populations, and deducing relevant Taylor & Francis. Not for Distribution implications. His central grounds, however, were an argument by analogy with 1 Michael Ruse (2001), Can a Darwinian Be a Christian?, pp. 12–18. 2 Alvin Plantinga (1991), ‘When Faith and Reason Clash: Evolution and the Bible’, p. 684. 3 Ruse, op. cit., pp. 13–18. 4 Ruse, ibid., pp. 20 and 25. 110 Creation and Evolution the artificial selection among animal and plant varieties conducted by human breeders who select and breed from the best available variants;5 thus Darwin’s analogical argument was to supersede the previously influential analogical argument of William Paley who had explained adaptations by a cosmic watch- maker or designer. More recently, Richard Dawkins has developed this analogical argument as supporting apparent design by a ‘blind watch-maker’, or in other words natural selection, adding to this conclusion a rejection of any other designer;6 the suggestion (detected by some in the text of Darwin7) that natural selection may be regarded as personal and intentional is firmly excluded. The source of the variations on which natural selection operates was unknown to Darwin, who also adhered to mistaken beliefs about heredity; but when the work of his contemporary, Gregor Mendel, on genetics and on random mutations, was rediscovered at the turn of the century and developed by researchers such as Ronald Fisher in the 1930s, it became possible to explain both the origination of beneficial characteristics and their survival down the generations, and thus establish a broad Darwinian consensus among most scientists.8 However, critics of Darwinism sometimes complain that natural selection explains nothing, since the survival of the fittest simply means the survival of those fittest to survive, and this principle is an empty, unfalsifiable tautology. Yet, as Gallagher has replied, the theory of evolution (as opposed to this principle) supplies an informative explanation both of variations, of some traits being more advantageous than others, of selection between them, and of the related development of populations and species. Thus while Darwinists from Ruse to Stephen Jay Gould have tried but failed to make the actual principle into a substantive claim, the theory remains a substantive one. If this were not so, it could not be contested by its creationist and other opponents as misguided.9 So the theory of natural selection cannot be written off as lacking any scientific role. Meanwhile the principle effectively tells us to seek explanations of biological survival in the area of an organism’s adaptation to its natural environment; this is a methodological directive, rather than a statement, but one grounded in the theory of natural selection,10 and thus not lightly to be sneezed at. Darwin and his mainstream successors have taken the view that the variations that are important for natural selection are invariably small ones, despite the availability of larger variations, or ‘hopeful monsters’ as he called them; evolution Taylor & Francis. Not for Distribution 5 Ruse, ibid., pp. 22–3. 6 Richard Dawkins (1986), The Blind Watchmaker. 7 Gillian Beer (1983), Darwin’s Plots, pp. 68–71. 8 Ruse, op. cit., pp. 25–6. 9 Kenneth T. Gallagher (1989), ‘“Natural Selection”: A Tautology?,’ International Philosophical Quarterly, 29, 17–31. Gallagher’s stance was substantially anticipated at Karl Popper (1972), Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, pp. 69–70. 10 Gallagher, op. cit., pp. 29–30. Darwinism, Disvalues and Design 111 is a gradual process, without jumps or ‘saltations’.11 Some of his supporters, however, including Thomas Henry Huxley, have regarded saltations as better explaining e.g. the evolution of the eye;12 indeed saltationism remains a minority position among some Darwinians (including distinguished ones such as John Maynard Smith).13 But most regard gradualism as essential to the theory of natural selection, holding that on no other basis can the evolution of biological complexity and adaptedness be explained.14 To this claim we shall be returning (see Chapter Seven, Section 4 below). Gradualism is consistent with the theory of Gould and Niles Eldredge (whatever these authors may have held to the contrary) that evolution consists of long periods of imperceptible change punctuated by episodes where change is rapid (punctuated equilibria), since rapid change could still be due to a rapid sequence of small variations.15 Darwinians also diverge over whether natural selection is the sole cause (or the sole important cause) of most biological phenomena (adaptationism),16 or whether there are other factors at work. Darwin himself firmly expressed the latter view, in the last edition of Origin of Species.17 The view that there are other important factors has been defended by Gould and Richard C. Lewontin. They Distribution argue that just as spandrels (triangular tapering concave surfaces formed by the intersection of two rounded arches at right angles) such as those of St. Mark’s Cathedral at Venice bear designs that make them seem central to the architect’s for purpose, but are in fact inevitable by-products of any building plan involving a dome and arches, so biological phenomena can be by-products of factors other than selection, such as inherited ‘building plans’ that were adaptive for earlier Not stages in life or for earlier generations or for ancestral species (such as homologies in bone structures between birds and mammals).18 Further possibilities are listed; most striking is that of the secondary utilization of parts present for other reasons. (Thus even if blushing is an adaptation for sexual selection in humans, it cannot figure in explanations of why blood is red.19) In a later paper, Gould and Elisabeth 11 Francis. Ruse, op. cit., p. 23. 12 Ruse, ibid., p. 25. & 13 John Maynard Smith (1981), ‘Did Darwin Get it Right?’, London Review of Books, 3.11, 10–11; see also Maynard Smith (1982), Evolution and the Theory of Games; and Ruse, op. cit., p. 30. 14 Ruse, ibid., p. 136; thus Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker. 15 Niles Eldredge and Stephen Jay Gould (1972), ‘Punctuated Equilibria: An Alternative to Phyletic Gradualism’, in T.J.M. Schopf, (ed.), Models in Paleobiology, Taylor 82–115. 16 Elliott Sober (1998), ‘Six Sayings about Adaptationism’, in David L. Hull and Michael Ruse, The Philosophy of Biology, 72–86, p. 72. 17 Darwin (1872), The Origin of Species (Darwin’s last edition), p. 395. 18 Stephen Jay Gould and Richard C. Lewontin (1994), ‘The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme’, in Elliott Sober (ed.), Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology (2nd edn), 73–90. 19 Gould and Lewontin, ibid., p. 85. 112 Creation and Evolution S. Vrba coin the term ‘exaptations’ for features that are fit for their current role but not ‘designed’ and/or selected for it, such as lactation in mammals (granted that lactose-like chemicals probably evolved not for nourishing the young but to kill bacteria) or the supportive role of bones, originally selected as stores for phosphates rather than for rigidity.20 Nevertheless, as Ruse affirms, Gould and his fellow-writers remain Darwinists, recognizing both evolution from a common ancestry, and natural selection as the most important source of biological adaptation and evolution. Gould has himself recently expounded and defended this generic Darwinism,21 which can be combined with a rejection of the kind of sociobiological explanations of human behaviour adopted by Dawkins.22 Yet other Darwinians combine recognition of natural selection with the view that there is much in the realm of biology that lies beyond its scope, such as change at the molecular level, as studied by Motoo Kimura.23 Adaptationists reply to their various critics that the very case of anti-adaptationists turns crucially on secondary adaptation and its preconditions, and can thus be reconciled with the centrality of adaptation.24 Ruse calls this position ‘ultra-Darwinism’,25 because it is more Darwinian than Darwin himself was.
Recommended publications
  • The Fourth Perspective: Evolution and Organismal Agency
    The Fourth Perspective: Evolution and Organismal Agency Johannes Jaeger Complexity Science Hub (CSH), Vienna, Josefstädter Straße 39, 1080 Vienna Abstract This chapter examines the deep connections between biological organization, agency, and evolution by natural selection. Using Griesemer’s account of the re- producer, I argue that the basic unit of evolution is not a genetic replicator, but a complex hierarchical life cycle. Understanding the self-maintaining and self-pro- liferating properties of evolvable reproducers requires an organizational account of ontogenesis and reproduction. This leads us to an extended and disambiguated set of minimal conditions for evolution by natural selection—including revised or new principles of heredity, variation, and ontogenesis. More importantly, the con- tinuous maintenance of biological organization within and across generations im- plies that all evolvable systems are agents, or contain agents among their parts. This means that we ought to take agency seriously—to better understand the con- cept and its role in explaining biological phenomena—if we aim to obtain an or- ganismic theory of evolution in the original spirit of Darwin’s struggle for exis- tence. This kind of understanding must rely on an agential perspective on evolu- tion, complementing and succeeding existing structural, functional, and processual approaches. I sketch a tentative outline of such an agential perspective, and present a survey of methodological and conceptual challenges that will have to be overcome if we are to properly implement it. 1. Introduction There are two fundamentally different ways to interpret Darwinian evolutionary theory. Charles Darwin’s original framework grounds the process of evolution on 2 the individual’s struggle for existence (Darwin, 1859).
    [Show full text]
  • Rolston, Holmes, III. Genes, Genesis and God: Values and %Eir Ongins in Naturctl Including Science and Religion
    "Listening to the Listeners," the author challenges preachers to get into the skin of their audiences and to solicit and covet feedback from them. He rounds out this section with two chapters on preaching about money, providing valuable tips on a sensitive subject around which not a few preachers would rather detour. A strength of this book is the "Questions to Consider" and suggestions for additional reading with which each chapter ends. The questions make excellent fodder for classroom, collegial, or personal reflection, and the reading lists are rich resources for preachers who are sometimes so busy with parish responsibilitiesthat they do not have time to stay abreast of the literature in the field. Another strength of the book is its size. As texts on biblical preaching go, this one is slim. Uzking a Difference in Preaching is only 158 pages. Yet Robinson succeeds in conveying a wealth of information in this brief book, deftly juxtaposing scholarship and his personal experience in the pulpit to provide preachers with useful tools to revive and energize their preaching. His mixture of theory and methodology is refreshingly incisive and instructive. Robinson reveals an understanding of, and resonance with, the concepts he shares, refusing to provide his readers with the pat answers and platitudes that nonpractitioners are prone to proffer. So compelling are the author's ideas and insights, and so cogent and concise his writing, that this reviewer read the book in one sitting. Uctking a Dzfmence in Preaching is a worthy addition to the literature in the field of preaching. Students and practitioners, both lay and paid, should find it immensely helpful as they struggle with the unending task of crafting biblical sermons that hit home.
    [Show full text]
  • Holmes Rolston III Endowed Chair in Environmental Ethics
    Holmes Rolston III Endowed Chair in Environmental Ethics AOS: Environmental Ethics/Philosophy. AOC: open; Philosophy of Science (especially Biology), Science and Religion, or Philosophy of Technology desirable. The Department of Philosophy at Colorado State University invites nominations and applications for the newly inaugurated Holmes Rolston III Endowed Chair in Environmental Ethics. Rank: Associate Professor. Required qualifications: Ph.D. in Philosophy; AOS in Environmental Ethics/Philosophy; strong record of research; national and international scholarly recognition and reputation; demonstrated excellence in teaching; demonstrated commitment to service; ability to work collegially with others. Preferred qualifications: AOC in Philosophy of Science, Science and Religion, or Philosophy of Technology; ability to advance the department’s commitment to diversity and multiculturalism through research, teaching, and outreach with relevant programs, goals, and activities. Teaching load currently is 4 courses per academic year (2 courses per semester). Effective starting date is August 2016. Salary is commensurate with qualifications. Funding for research and conference travel will be available annually. To apply, go to http://jobs.colostate.edu/postings/17356 and create an account. Please submit a complete dossier, including a letter of application detailing qualifications, curriculum vitae, evidence of successful teaching (such as sample teaching evaluations or reviews), writing sample, and three current letters of recommendation. Please contact Gaylene Wolfe at [email protected] if you have questions about the application process. To submit a nomination, send a letter detailing the nominee’s qualifications and promise to Katie McShane at [email protected]. Applications and nominations will be accepted until the position is filled; however, to ensure full consideration nominations should be submitted by October 15, 2015 and applications by November 15, 2015.
    [Show full text]
  • Roundtable on Holmes Rolston, III : a New Environmental Ethics : Life on Earth in the Next Millennium
    [Expositions 6.1 (2012) 9-10] Expositions (online) ISSN: 1747-5376 Introduction to the Roundtable: Holmes Rolston III’s A New Environmental Ethics: The Next Millennium for Life on Earth CHRISTIAN DIEHM University of Wisconsin, Stevens Point In the 1970s, when the contemporary environmental movement was still in its infancy, Holmes Rolston, III began publishing philosophical essays in environmental ethics, and it is no exaggeration to say that his early efforts contributed to establishing this subject as a serious academic field, one in which he has played a leading role ever since. Indeed, over the past five decades Rolston has not only developed and defended one of the most comprehensive and recognizable positions in eco-philosophy, but he has also used it to address some of the most difficult and challenging issues that environmentalism in the modern era has had to face. It should come as no surprise, then, that the appearance earlier this year of his A New Environmental Ethics1 represents both the culmination of a professional lifetime of dedication to the discipline that he helped to create, as well as a guidepost out ahead of those of us who have only recently ventured into the territory that he began to explore so many years ago. Readers familiar with Rolston’s work will quickly recognize that A New Environmental Ethics is at one and the same time both a familiar and a novel text. On the one hand, it straightforwardly presents most of Rolston’s now well-known positions in environmental ethics, positions on things such as the intrinsic value of organisms and the ethical priority of ecological wholes that have changed fairly little over the course of his writing.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, VI-1 | 2014 Popular Science, Pragmatism, and Conceptual Clarity 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy VI-1 | 2014 The Reception of Peirce in the World Popular Science, Pragmatism, and Conceptual Clarity Oliver Belas Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/514 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.514 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Oliver Belas, « Popular Science, Pragmatism, and Conceptual Clarity », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], VI-1 | 2014, Online since 08 July 2014, connection on 16 March 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/514 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.514 This text was automatically generated on 16 March 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Popular Science, Pragmatism, and Conceptual Clarity 1 Popular Science, Pragmatism, and Conceptual Clarity Oliver Belas Introduction 1 One of popular science’s primary functions is to make what would otherwise be inaccessible, specialist knowledge accessible to the lay reader. But popular science puts its imagined reader in something of a dilemma, for one does not have to look very far to find bitter argument among science writers; argument that takes place beyond the limits of the scientific community: witness the ill-tempered exchanges between Mary Midgley and Richard Dawkins in the journal Philosophy in the late seventies and early eighties; or, from the mid-nineties, the surly dialogue of Stephen Jay Gould, Daniel Dennett, and others in The New York Review of Books (see below and Works Cited).
    [Show full text]
  • Adaptationism and the Logic of Research Questions: How to Think Clearly About Evolutionary Causes
    Biol Theory (2015) 10:343–362 DOI 10.1007/s13752-015-0214-2 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Adaptationism and the Logic of Research Questions: How to Think Clearly About Evolutionary Causes Elisabeth A. Lloyd1 Received: 20 March 2015 / Accepted: 29 May 2015 / Published online: 9 July 2015 Ó Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research 2015 Abstract This article discusses various dangers that popular methods, despite its benign reputation. In ‘‘The accompany the supposedly benign methods in behavioral Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm,’’ evolutionary biology and evolutionary psychology that fall Gould and Lewontin (1979) drew attention to several under the framework of ‘‘methodological adaptationism.’’ dangers in using this method. In this article, I present a A ‘‘Logic of Research Questions’’ is proposed that aids in framework for analysis that makes their worries clearer. I clarifying the reasoning problems that arise due to the also warn of further risks of this methodological frame- framework under critique. The live, and widely practiced, work, expanding on the dangers it poses to scientific rea- ‘‘evolutionary factors’’ framework is offered as the key soning in evolutionary biology. At the same time, I comparison and alternative. The article goes beyond the emphasize that I am not attacking the notion of looking for traditional critique of Stephen Jay Gould and Richard C. adaptations in evolutionary studies: I am not anti-adapta- Lewontin, to present problems such as the disappearance of tion. The issues concern which framework is most appro- evidence, the mishandling of the null hypothesis, and priate and fruitful. failures in scientific reasoning, exemplified by a case from As evolutionary biology is usually taught and con- human behavioral ecology.
    [Show full text]
  • A New Defense of Adaptationism
    Prepared for the Northwest Philosophy Conference, Fall 2002 A new defense of adaptationism Mark A. Bedau Reed College, 3203 SE Woodstock Blvd., Portland OR 97202 503-517-7337 http://www.reed.edu/~mab [email protected] Abstract The scientific legitimacy of adaptationist explanations has been challenged by Gould and Lewontin in “The Spandrals of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm.” The canonical response to this challenge is weak, because it concedes that the presupposition that an adaptationist explanation is needed cannot be tested empirically. This paper provides a new kind of defense of adaptationism by providing such a test. The test is described in general terms and then illustrated in the context of an artificial system—a simulation of self-replicating computer code mutating and competing for space in computer memory. It is a cliché to explain the giraffe’s long neck as an adaptation for browsing in tall tree. But the scientific legitimacy of such adaptive explanations is controversial, largely because of the classic paper “The Spandrals of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme” published by Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Lewontin in 1979. The controversy persists, I believe, in part because the fundamental challenge raised by Gould and Lewontin has not yet been met; in fact, it is rarely even acknowledged. This paper addresses this challenge and defends the scientific legitimacy of adaptive explanations in a new and deeper way. First, some terminology.1 I will refer to claims to the effect that a trait is an adaptation as an adaptive hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Adaptationism for Human Cognition: Strong, Spurious Or Weak? Scott Atran
    Adaptationism for Human Cognition: Strong, Spurious or Weak? Scott Atran To cite this version: Scott Atran. Adaptationism for Human Cognition: Strong, Spurious or Weak?. Mind and Language, Wiley, 2005, 20 (1). ijn_00000574 HAL Id: ijn_00000574 https://jeannicod.ccsd.cnrs.fr/ijn_00000574 Submitted on 1 Feb 2005 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Adaptationism for Human Cognition: Strong, Spurious or Weak? SCOTT ATRAN Abstract: Strong adaptationists explore complex organic design as task-specific adapta- tions to ancestral environments. This strategy seems best when there is evidence of homology. Weak adaptationists don’t assume that complex organic (including cognitive and linguistic) functioning necessarily or primarily represents task-specific adaptation. This approach to cognition resembles physicists’ attempts to deductively explain the most facts with fewest hypotheses. For certain domain-specific competencies (folkbiol- ogy) strong adaptationism is useful but not necessary to research. With group-level belief systems (religion) strong adaptationism degenerates into spurious notions of social function and cultural selection. In other cases (language, especially universal grammar) weak adaptationism’s ‘minimalist’ approach seems productive. 1. Introduction In a sense, everyone who isn’t a creationist and who thinks that Darwin’s theory of natural selection isn’t moonshine is an adaptationist when it comes to explaining the origins of human cognition.
    [Show full text]
  • Teleology and Biology: a Defense of Teleological Thinking in Biology
    Teleology and Biology: a defense of teleological thinking in biology Marcelo Domingos de Santis * Abstract: Teleological language refers to a forward-looking discourse, and var- ious biologists are troubled with this issue. In this paper, I will discuss the mis- understandings that both philosophers of science and biologists have made against teleology. Among these misunderstandings, I can mention its relation- ship to anthropomorphism (i.e., a planning agent external to the world refer- ence) and reference to a force immanent to the organisms (“vitalism”) beyond the reach of empirical investigation. I will argue that they are misconceptions and that teleology has shifted its meaning and focus from its pre-evolutionary form. Now it is in the position that it can be used and maintained without vio- lating the principles of modern science. Using an example of the adaptation and function debate, I will discuss how the teleological language is the best interpre- tation of these issues. Key-words: adaptation; evolutionary biology; philosophy of science; teleology Teleologia e Biologia: uma defesa do pensamento teleológico na biologia Resumo: A linguagem teleológica pode ser definida como um discurso pros- pectivo, e isto tem preocupado biólogos em torno desse problema. Neste artigo, discutirei os mal-entendidos que filósofos da ciência e biólogos tiveram acerca da teleologia. Por exemplo, afirmam que a teleologia sofre de antropomorfismo (isto é, um agente de planejamento externo à referência mundial) e se refere a uma força imanente aos organismos (forças vitais ou “vitalismo”) além do al- cance da investigação empírica. Argumentarei que eles estão equivocados e que a teleologia mudou seu significado e foco de sua forma pré-evolutiva, e agora pode ser usada e mantida sem violar os princípios da ciência moderna.
    [Show full text]
  • Front Matter
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-68453-9 - Information and the Nature of Reality: From Physics to Metaphysics Edited by Paul Davies and Niels Henrik Gregersen Frontmatter More information INFORMATION AND THE NATURE OF REALITY © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-68453-9 - Information and the Nature of Reality: From Physics to Metaphysics Edited by Paul Davies and Niels Henrik Gregersen Frontmatter More information © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-68453-9 - Information and the Nature of Reality: From Physics to Metaphysics Edited by Paul Davies and Niels Henrik Gregersen Frontmatter More information INFORMATION AND THE NATURE OF REALITY FROM PHYSICS TO METAPHYSICS Edited by PAUL DAVIES Arizona State University NIELS HENRIK GREGERSEN Copenhagen University © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-68453-9 - Information and the Nature of Reality: From Physics to Metaphysics Edited by Paul Davies and Niels Henrik Gregersen Frontmatter More information University Printing House, Cambridge cb2 8bs, United Kingdom Cambridge University Press is part of the University of Cambridge. It furthers the University’s mission by disseminating knowledge in the pursuit of education, learning and research at the highest international levels of excellence. www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107684539 C P. Davies and N. Gregersen 2010, 2014 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press.
    [Show full text]
  • The Structure of Evolutionary Theory: Beyond Neo-Darwinism, Neo
    1 2 3 The structure of evolutionary theory: Beyond Neo-Darwinism, 4 Neo-Lamarckism and biased historical narratives about the 5 Modern Synthesis 6 7 8 9 10 Erik I. Svensson 11 12 Evolutionary Ecology Unit, Department of Biology, Lund University, SE-223 62 Lund, 13 SWEDEN 14 15 Correspondence: [email protected] 16 17 18 19 1 20 Abstract 21 The last decades have seen frequent calls for a more extended evolutionary synthesis (EES) that 22 will supposedly overcome the limitations in the current evolutionary framework with its 23 intellectual roots in the Modern Synthesis (MS). Some radical critics even want to entirely 24 abandon the current evolutionary framework, claiming that the MS (often erroneously labelled 25 “Neo-Darwinism”) is outdated, and will soon be replaced by an entirely new framework, such 26 as the Third Way of Evolution (TWE). Such criticisms are not new, but have repeatedly re- 27 surfaced every decade since the formation of the MS, and were particularly articulated by 28 developmental biologist Conrad Waddington and paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould. 29 Waddington, Gould and later critics argued that the MS was too narrowly focused on genes and 30 natural selection, and that it ignored developmental processes, epigenetics, paleontology and 31 macroevolutionary phenomena. More recent critics partly recycle these old arguments and 32 argue that non-genetic inheritance, niche construction, phenotypic plasticity and developmental 33 bias necessitate major revision of evolutionary theory. Here I discuss these supposed 34 challenges, taking a historical perspective and tracing these arguments back to Waddington and 35 Gould. I dissect the old arguments by Waddington, Gould and more recent critics that the MS 36 was excessively gene centric and became increasingly “hardened” over time and narrowly 37 focused on natural selection.
    [Show full text]
  • Organism and Mechanism
    ORGANISM AND MECHANISM A Critique of Mechanistic Thinking in Biology Submitted by Daniel James Nicholson to the University of Exeter as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy In September 2010 This thesis is available for Library use on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. I certify that all material in this thesis which is not my own work has been identified and that no material has previously been submitted and approved for the award of a degree by this or any other University. Signature: ………………………………………………………….. ABSTRACT In this thesis I present a critical examination of the role played by mechanistic ideas in shaping our understanding of living systems. I draw on a combination of historical, philosophical, and scientific resources to uncover a number of problems which I take to result from the adoption of mechanistic thinking in biology. I provide an analysis of the historical development of the conflict between mechanistic and vitalistic conceptions of life since the seventeenth century, and I argue that the basic terms of this conflict remain central to current disputes over the nature of the organism as well as the question of how far the theories, concepts, and methods of physics, chemistry, and engineering can ultimately take us in the explanation of life. I offer a detailed critique of the machine conception of the organism, which constitutes the central unifying idea of mechanistic biology. I argue that this notion, despite its undeniable heuristic value, is fundamentally inadequate as a theory of the organism due to a number of basic differences between organisms and machines.
    [Show full text]