Ontological Trivialism? How to Meinong a Carnap-Quine

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ontological Trivialism? How to Meinong a Carnap-Quine grazer philosophische studien (2016) 1-31 brill.com/gps Ontological Trivialism? How to Meinong a Carnap-Quine Seyed N. Mousavian University of Gothenburg, Sweden, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences (ipm), Iran [email protected] Abstract How hard is it to answer an ontological question? Ontological trivialism, (ot), inspired by Carnap’s internal-external distinction among “questions of existence”, replies “very easy.” According to (ot), almost every ontologically disputed entity trivially exists. (ot) has been defended by many, including Schiffer (1996; 2003; 2006) and Schaffer (2009). In this paper, I will take issue with (ot). After introducing the view in the context of Carnap-Quine dispute and presenting two arguments for it, I will discuss Hofweber’s (2005; 2007) argument against (ot) and explain why it fails. Next, I will introduce a modified version of ontological trivialism, i.e. negative ontological trivialism, (not), defended by Hofweber (2005), according to which some ontologically disputed enti- ties, e.g. properties, (almost) trivially do not exist. I will show that (not) fails too. Then I will outline a Meinongian answer to the original question, namely, ‘How hard is it to answer an ontological question?’ The Carnapian intuition of the triviality of internal questions can be saved by the Meinongian proposal that quantification and reference are not ontologically committing and the Quinean intuition of the legitimacy of inter- esting ontological questions can be respected by the Meinongian distinction between being and so-being. Keywords ontological commitment – meta-ontology – ontology – Carnap – Quine – Meinong 1 The Puzzle Let’s begin with the following meta-ontological question: © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2016 | doi 10.1163/18756735-09303004 0002785279.INDD 1 301935 6/23/2016 5:52:16 AM 2 doi 10.1163/18756735-09303004 | Mousavian O: How hard is it to answer an ontological question? (An ontological question being a question of existence) Thomas Hofweber (2005) argues that (O) is puzzling. The puzzle is that “there seem to be two contrary but equally good answers to the question” (Hofweber 2005, 257): very hard and very easy. Very hard, if one takes the question to be legitimate and, for example, like Quine (1948/2012) tries to read the ontology of the world off of our best overall theory of it as the values of the bound vari- ables of the theory. This project is “at least as hard as coming up with our best overall theory of the world” (Hofweber 2005, 258). Very easy, if one buys the so- called ‘triviality arguments’ and thus accepts ‘ontological trivialism’, (ot). (ot) implies that ontological questions are legitimate and trivial. More particularly, ot: Almost1 every2 ontologically disputed entity trivially (or obviously) exists.3 The debate over (O) goes back, at least, to Carnap (1956/2012)-Quine (1948/2012) dispute. Carnap, roughly speaking, classifies ontological questions as either 1 The modifier ‘almost’ is introduced in order to take into account the “rubbish bin of the non- existent” (see Schaffer 2009, 354), in which very few entities are thrown (such as perhaps contradictory entities). 2 Here ‘every’ should not be read as having ontological commitment, otherwise (ot) would be trivially true. Note that the debate over (ot) is about its non-vacuous truth or falsity. My formulation of (ot) presupposes that the sentence “there are ontologically disputed entities” has a true reading with no ontological commitment to the ontologically disputed entities. One way to accomplish this is to take the quantifier ‘every’ in (ot) to be ontologically neutral (then it can reach ontologically disputed entities even if they do not exist) and put the onto- logical commitment into the predicate ‘exists’. Alternatively, one may appeal to type-token apparatus. Accordingly, (ot) may be reformulated as ot′: “For almost every ontologically dis- puted type of entity, there trivially exists an entity of that type.” Then, even if ‘every’ in (ot′) is ontologically committing, it only brings ontological commitment to the types of entities, not to their tokens that are subject to ontological debate. I will follow the first strategy, for the reasons discussed in §9. 3 Jonathan Schaffer (2009) is explicit on such a formulation: “the contemporary existence de- bates are trivial, in that the entities in question obviously do exist” (Schaffer 2009, 357, origi- nal emphasis). Hofweber (2005) formulates the view similarly: “[A]n answer to the question whether or not there are properties, propositions or numbers follows immediately from the most uncontroversial premises imaginable” (p. 258, emphases are mine). Stephen Schiffer’s (1996, 2003, 2006) formulation of ontological trivialism in terms of “pleonastic Platonism” characterizes numbers and properties, among other things, as “language-created language- independent entities” that trivially exist as “something-from-nothing” entailments suggest. grazer philosophische studien (2016) 1-31 0002785279.INDD 2 301935 6/23/2016 5:52:16 AM Ontological Trivialism? | doi 10.1163/18756735-09303004 3 trivial or epistemically illegitimate, not both. Given a conceptual framework and a kind of entities, Carnap’s internal questions, namely, “the questions of the existence of certain entities of the new kind within the framework” (Car- nap 1956/2012, 17), are trivial and legitimate. Carnap thinks that his internal questions are trivial since they are not metaphysically committing. This is so, in turn, because such questions employ a non-metaphysical conception of reality (ibid). Carnap’s external questions, namely, “questions concerning the existence or reality of the system of entities as a whole” (ibid), are nontrivial but illegitimate. They are illegitimate theoretical questions since they are not theoretical questions in the first place. They are not theoretical since they are questions about the acceptance or denial of conceptual frameworks (or lan- guage structures). Hence, according to Carnap’s meta-ontology, no interesting ontological question is both nontrivial and legitimate. Quine (1948), in contrast, characterizes most ontological questions as nei- ther trivial nor illegitimate: They are not trivial since ontological questions need to be answered according to a theory and a theory is committed to the existence of those entities that the bound variables of the canonical formula- tion of the theory range over. Neither finding the best theory nor its canonical formulation is trivial.4 Moreover, most ontological questions are not illegiti- mate, from Quine’s (1951/1963) point of view. This is so, in turn, because Quine (1951/1961) does not acknowledge the internal-external distinction as charac- terized by reference to Carnapian conceptual frameworks. Otherwise put, for Quine, most ontological questions are nontrivial, in fact hard, and legitimate. (ot), in some sense, stands in between. (ot) describes most ontological questions as trivial and legitimate: (ot) is similar to Carnap’s view in so far as it takes many ontological questions to be ‘trivial’ but differs from that in taking such questions to be ontologically committing. As some recent formulations of (ot) emphasize, e.g. Stephen Schiffer (1996, 2003) and Jonathan Schaffer (2009), numbers, properties, propositions and fictional characters all obvious- ly exist.5 (ot) is similar to Quine’s view in so far as it takes many ontological questions to be legitimate but differs from that in treating them as ‘trivial.’ In this paper, I will take issue with (ot) from a Meinongian point of view. After the introduction, in §2, two sample arguments in defense of (ot) will be introduced. In §3, I will discuss Hofweber’s (2000, 2005, 2007) argument against (ot). In §4, I will explain why it fails. In §5, I will address an objec- tion to my criticism of Hofweber’s argument against (ot). I will then, in §6, 4 See Schaffer (2009) for further discussion. 5 Schiffer’s view makes some distinctions between properties and propositions, on the one hand, and fictional characters and artifacts, on the other hand. See note 7 below. grazer philosophische studien (2016) 1-31 0002785279.INDD 3 301935 6/23/2016 5:52:16 AM 4 doi 10.1163/18756735-09303004 | Mousavian introduce a modified version of trivialism, i.e. negative ontological trivialism (not), advocated by Hofweber (2005). Subsequently, in §7, I will argue that (not) fails too. In §8, I address an objection to my argument against (not). Finally, in §9, I will outline a Meinongian answer to (O), namely, ‘How hard is it to answer an ontological question?’ The intuition behind the Carnapian meta- ontology can straightforwardly be captured by the Meinongian proposal that quantification and singular reference are not ontologically committing. The intuition behind the Quinean meta-ontology can be saved by rejecting (ot). Ontological questions are legitimate but not trivial, given a distinct existence predicate in a Meinongian language. 2 Triviality Arguments: Schiffer and Schaffer As far as I can see, (ot) has never been directly argued for. Instead, the view has been backed by various forms of, what I call, ‘triviality arguments.’ For ex- ample, concerning the existence of numbers, Schaffer (2009, 357) offers the following triviality argument: Start with the debate over numbers. Here, without further ado, is a proof of the existence of numbers: [arg 1:] 1. There are prime numbers. 2. Therefore there are numbers. 1 is a mathematical truism. It commands Moorean certainty, as being more credible
Recommended publications
  • Demystifying the Saint
    DEMYSTIFYING THE SAINT: JAY L. GARFIELDʼS RATIONAL RECONSTRUCTION OF NĀGĀRJUNAʼS MĀDHYAMAKA AS THE EPITOME OF CONTEMPORARY CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY TIINA ROSENQVIST Tampereen yliopisto Yhteiskunta- ja kulttuuritieteiden yksikkö Filosofian pro gradu -tutkielma Tammikuu 2011 ABSTRACT Cross-cultural philosophy approaches philosophical problems by setting into dialogue systems and perspectives from across cultures. I use the term more specifically to refer to the current stage in the history of comparative philosophy marked by the ethos of scholarly self-reflection and the production of rational reconstructions of foreign philosophies. These reconstructions lend a new kind of relevance to cross-cultural perspectives in mainstream philosophical discourses. I view Jay L. Garfieldʼs work as an example of this. I examine Garfieldʼs approach in the context of Nāgārjuna scholarship and cross-cultural hermeneutics. By situating it historically and discussing its background and implications, I wish to highlight its distinctive features. Even though Garfield has worked with Buddhist philosophy, I believe he has a lot to offer to the meta-level discussion of cross-cultural philosophy in general. I argue that the clarity of Garfieldʼs vision of the nature and function of cross-cultural philosophy can help alleviate the identity crisis that has plagued the enterprise: Garfield brings it closer to (mainstream) philosophy and helps it stand apart from Indology, Buddhology, area studies philosophy (etc). I side with Garfield in arguing that cross- cultural philosophy not only brings us better understanding of other philosophical traditions, but may enhance our self-understanding as well. I furthermore hold that his employment of Western conceptual frameworks (post-Wittgensteinian language philosophy, skepticism) and theoretical tools (paraconsistent logic, Wittgensteinian epistemology) together with the influence of Buddhist interpretative lineages creates a coherent, cogent, holistic and analytically precise reading of Nāgārjunaʼs Mādhyamaka philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Dialectic, Rhetoric and Contrast the Infinite Middle of Meaning
    Dialectic, Rhetoric and Contrast The Infinite Middle of Meaning Richard Boulton St George’s, University of London; Kingston University Series in Philosophy Copyright © 2021 Richard Boulton. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Vernon Art and Science Inc. www.vernonpress.com In the Americas: In the rest of the world: Vernon Press Vernon Press 1000 N West Street, Suite 1200 C/Sancti Espiritu 17, Wilmington, Delaware, 19801 Malaga, 29006 United States Spain Series in Philosophy Library of Congress Control Number: 2021931318 ISBN: 978-1-64889-149-6 Cover designed by Aurelien Thomas. Product and company names mentioned in this work are the trademarks of their respective owners. While every care has been taken in preparing this work, neither the authors nor Vernon Art and Science Inc. may be held responsible for any loss or damage caused or alleged to be caused directly or indirectly by the information contained in it. Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been inadvertently overlooked the publisher will be pleased to include any necessary credits in any subsequent reprint or edition. Table of contents Introduction v Chapter I Method 1 Dialectic and Rhetoric 1 Validating a Concept Spectrum 12 Chapter II Sense 17 Emotion 17 Rationality 23 The Absolute 29 Truth 34 Value 39 Chapter III Essence 47 Meaning 47 Narrative 51 Patterns and Problems 57 Existence 61 Contrast 66 Chapter IV Consequence 73 Life 73 Mind and Body 77 Human 84 The Individual 91 Rules and Exceptions 97 Conclusion 107 References 117 Index 129 Introduction This book is the result of a thought experiment inspired by the methods of dialectic and rhetoric.
    [Show full text]
  • A Unifying Field in Logics: Neutrosophic Logic. Neutrosophy, Neutrosophic Set, Neutrosophic Probability and Statistics
    FLORENTIN SMARANDACHE A UNIFYING FIELD IN LOGICS: NEUTROSOPHIC LOGIC. NEUTROSOPHY, NEUTROSOPHIC SET, NEUTROSOPHIC PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS (fourth edition) NL(A1 A2) = ( T1 ({1}T2) T2 ({1}T1) T1T2 ({1}T1) ({1}T2), I1 ({1}I2) I2 ({1}I1) I1 I2 ({1}I1) ({1} I2), F1 ({1}F2) F2 ({1} F1) F1 F2 ({1}F1) ({1}F2) ). NL(A1 A2) = ( {1}T1T1T2, {1}I1I1I2, {1}F1F1F2 ). NL(A1 A2) = ( ({1}T1T1T2) ({1}T2T1T2), ({1} I1 I1 I2) ({1}I2 I1 I2), ({1}F1F1 F2) ({1}F2F1 F2) ). ISBN 978-1-59973-080-6 American Research Press Rehoboth 1998, 2000, 2003, 2005 FLORENTIN SMARANDACHE A UNIFYING FIELD IN LOGICS: NEUTROSOPHIC LOGIC. NEUTROSOPHY, NEUTROSOPHIC SET, NEUTROSOPHIC PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS (fourth edition) NL(A1 A2) = ( T1 ({1}T2) T2 ({1}T1) T1T2 ({1}T1) ({1}T2), I1 ({1}I2) I2 ({1}I1) I1 I2 ({1}I1) ({1} I2), F1 ({1}F2) F2 ({1} F1) F1 F2 ({1}F1) ({1}F2) ). NL(A1 A2) = ( {1}T1T1T2, {1}I1I1I2, {1}F1F1F2 ). NL(A1 A2) = ( ({1}T1T1T2) ({1}T2T1T2), ({1} I1 I1 I2) ({1}I2 I1 I2), ({1}F1F1 F2) ({1}F2F1 F2) ). ISBN 978-1-59973-080-6 American Research Press Rehoboth 1998, 2000, 2003, 2005 1 Contents: Preface by C. Le: 3 0. Introduction: 9 1. Neutrosophy - a new branch of philosophy: 15 2. Neutrosophic Logic - a unifying field in logics: 90 3. Neutrosophic Set - a unifying field in sets: 125 4. Neutrosophic Probability - a generalization of classical and imprecise probabilities - and Neutrosophic Statistics: 129 5. Addenda: Definitions derived from Neutrosophics: 133 2 Preface to Neutrosophy and Neutrosophic Logic by C.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Mathematics: a Study of Indispensability and Inconsistency
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont Scripps Senior Theses Scripps Student Scholarship 2016 The hiP losophy of Mathematics: A Study of Indispensability and Inconsistency Hannah C. Thornhill Scripps College Recommended Citation Thornhill, Hannah C., "The hiP losophy of Mathematics: A Study of Indispensability and Inconsistency" (2016). Scripps Senior Theses. Paper 894. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/894 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Scripps Student Scholarship at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scripps Senior Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Philosophy of Mathematics: A Study of Indispensability and Inconsistency Hannah C.Thornhill March 10, 2016 Submitted to Scripps College in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Bachelor of Arts in Mathematics and Philosophy Professor Avnur Professor Karaali Abstract This thesis examines possible philosophies to account for the prac- tice of mathematics, exploring the metaphysical, ontological, and epis- temological outcomes of each possible theory. Through a study of the two most probable ideas, mathematical platonism and fictionalism, I focus on the compelling argument for platonism given by an ap- peal to the sciences. The Indispensability Argument establishes the power of explanation seen in the relationship between mathematics and empirical science. Cases of this explanatory power illustrate how we might have reason to believe in the existence of mathematical en- tities present within our best scientific theories. The second half of this discussion surveys Newtonian Cosmology and other inconsistent theories as they pose issues that have received insignificant attention within the philosophy of mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Naïve Proof and Curry's Paradox
    Massimilano Carrara Naïve Proof and Curry’s Paradox 1 Introduction In classical first order logic (FOL), trivialism, the truth of all sentences, and explo- sion, the derivability of any sentence, are obtained using the rule ex contradictione quodlibet (ECQ): A, A B. The classical justification for ECQ rests on the alleged ¬ „ evidence that no contradiction can be true, evidence rejected in paraconsistent the- ories, in particular by dialetheists, who hold that there are dialetheiae, i.e. propo- sitions that are both true and false.1 Indeed, dialetheism maintains the thesis that there are true contradictions, i.e. true sentences of form (A A), called dialetheiae. ·¬ More generally, they call dialetheia any sentence that is both true and false. In an extensive series of papers and books (see for example, Priest [1979], Priest [2001], Priest [2002], Priest [2006a], Priest [2006b]), Priest claims that the paradoxical sen- tences obtained from self-reference are dialetheiae.2 In standard natural deduction of FOL, ECQ can be derived using reductio ad ab- surdum (RAA) and other apparently non-problematic rules. It is a standard derived rule of FOL. But if you hold that there are dialetheiae, in order to avoid trivialism, RAA should be immediately rejected. Unfortunately, banishing RAA is insufficient to avoid trivialism: Curry’s paradox, from which trivialism follows, can be gener- ated without using RAA,butwithjustmodus ponens (MP) and the derived rule of Absorption, i.e. ABS: (A (A B)) (A B). In order to save dialethe- æ æ „ æ ism from trivialism, Priest adopts in the Logic of Paradox (LP) (1979) the material conditional, for which he rejects the general validity of MP.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism and Effective Altruism: an Essay on Epistemology and Practical Ethics John Aggrey Odera University of Pennsylvania
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Penn Humanities Forum Undergraduate Research Undergraduate Humanities Forum 2018-2019: Stuff Fellows 5-2019 Pragmatism and Effective Altruism: An Essay on Epistemology and Practical Ethics John Aggrey Odera University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/uhf_2019 Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Odera, John Aggrey, "Pragmatism and Effective Altruism: An Essay on Epistemology and Practical Ethics" (2019). Undergraduate Humanities Forum 2018-2019: Stuff. 2. https://repository.upenn.edu/uhf_2019/2 This paper was part of the 2018-2019 Penn Humanities Forum on Stuff. Find out more at http://wolfhumanities.upenn.edu/annual-topics/stuff. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/uhf_2019/2 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Pragmatism and Effective Altruism: An Essay on Epistemology and Practical Ethics Abstract This paper hopes to provide an American Pragmatist reading of the Effective Altruism philosophy and movement. The criticism levied against Effective Altruism here begins from one of its founding principles, and extends to practical aspects of the movement. The utilitarian leaders of Effective Altruism consider Sidgwick’s ‘point of view of the universe’ an objective starting point of determining ethics. Using Quality Adjusted Life Years (QALYs), a popular measure in contemporary welfare economics, they provide a “universal currency for misery” for evaluating decisions. Through this method, one can calculate exactly the value of each moral decision by identifying which one yields more QALYs, and, apparently, objectively come to a conclusion about the moral worth of seemingly unrelated situations, for example, whether it is more moral to donate money so as to help women suffering from painful childbirth-induced fistulas, or to donate to starving children in famine-ridden areas.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaontological Skepticism
    Metaontological Skepticism Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades der Philosophie an der Ludwigs-Maximilians-Universität München vorgelegt von Walter Swetly Referent: Prof. Godehard Link Korreferent: Professor Karl-Georg Niebergall Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 20.07.2009 Edward Hopper, Gas, Museum of Modern Art, New York Den Eltern zum Dank Acknowledgments This will be short and sweet. For their help by some means or other, I thank Anthony Everett, Andreas Foldenauer, Stasys Hiob, Thomas Hofweber, Herbert Huber, Hannes Leitgeb, Carlos-Ullisses Moulines, Odin Mühlenbein, Jakob Steinbrenner (and, of course, his wife), Brian Weatherson, André Wenzel and Tobias Wilsch. Special thanks go to Karl-Georg Niebergall, influence and nominalist extraordinaire, and Alexander Soutschek, who ran the long course, reading late drafts and participating in whole day meetings. I owe, however, the most and deepest depts to Godehard Link, ∅ystein Linnebo, and Alexander Oldemeier. Especially ∅ystein, and Alex had so much patience and guidance. They were there when work got difficult. Thanks, to my parents, my two sisters, my grandma and my grandpa, who sadly passed too early to see this, and my uncle Rainer and his wife, my aunt Gundi, for their support and love. Finally, thanks to my lovely girlfriend Anna for enduring me for 5 years. Keep on fighting, cinnamon! Contents ________________________________________________________ Chapter 1 Introduction S. 1 1.1 Worrying Questions S. 1 1.2 Metaontology S. 2 1.3 Skepticism S. 3 1.4 Metaontological Skepticism S. 7 1.5 Overview S. 9 Chapter 2 Quantifier Variance S. 11 2.1 Overview S. 11 2.2 An Attempt to Specify the Theory S.
    [Show full text]
  • ISJS - TRANSACTIONS a Quarterly Refereed Online Research Journal on Jainism
    ISSN : 2457-0583 ISJS - TRANSACTIONS A Quarterly Refereed Online Research Journal on Jainism VOL. 3 No. 2 April-June, 2019 HOOL FO SC R L J A A I N N International School for Jain Studies O I S T T A U D N D-28, Panchsheel Enclave I R E E S T SELF STUDY IS THE New Delhi - 110 017, India N SUPREME AUSTERITY I www.isjs.in ISSN: 2457-0583 ISJS – TRANSACTIONS A Quarterly Refereed Online Research Journal on Jainism VOL.3 No.2 April - June, 2019 CHIEF EDITOR Prof. Prakash C Jain Former Professor School for International Studies Jawaharlal Nehru University, New Delhi Email: [email protected] EDITOR Dr. Shrinetra Pandey Joint Director International School for Jain Studies New Delhi Email: [email protected] International School for Jain Studies D-28, Panchsheel Enclave New Delhi – 110017, India Ph: +91-11-4103 3387 Email: [email protected] Website: www.isjs.in ADVISORY BOARD Dr. Shugan Chand Jain, Chairman, International School for Jain Studies, New Delhi. Email: [email protected] Prof. Kamal Chand Sogani, Director, Jain Vidya Sansthan, Jaipur. Email: [email protected] Prof. Kusum Jain, Former Director, Center for Advance Philosophical Research, University of Rajasthan, Jaipur. Email: [email protected] Dr. Sulekh Chand Jain, Former President, JAINA, USA. Email: [email protected] EDITORIAL BOARD Prof. Viney Kumar Jain, Emeritus Professor, Dept. of Yoga and Science of Living, Jain Vishva Bharati Institute, Ladnun-341306, Dist. Nagaur, Rajasthan, India. Email: [email protected] Prof. Christopher Key Chapple, Director, Master of Arts in Yoga Studies, University Hall, Room 3763, Loyola Marymount University, Los Angeles, California-90045, USA.
    [Show full text]
  • Outscoping and Discourse Threat∗ Theodore Sider Inquiry 57 (2014): 413–26
    Outscoping and Discourse Threat∗ Theodore Sider Inquiry 57 (2014): 413–26 Agustín Rayo’s exciting and bold new book can be viewed as continuing Carnap’s debate with Quine over analyticity and mathematical truth.1 Rayo is on Carnap’s side, broadly speaking; but instead of saying that the statements of pure mathematics are analytic, Rayo says that they “demand nothing of the world”. Rayo’s defense of a “trivialist” form of Platonism is accompanied by treatments of surrounding metaphysical, logical, and linguistic issues. The book is an important one. It’s also refreshingly direct and brisk, and honest in its assessment of the strength of the position it defends. It is sure to provoke much discussion, particularly given the recent interest in metaphysical questions about the relation between language and the world. Rayo’s core concept is “just-is”, as in (p. 3): Properties For Susan to instantiate the property of running just is for Susan to run “For A to be the case just is for B to be the case”—for short, “A B”—means that “there is no difference between” A’s being the case and B’s being≡ the case, that when either A or B is true then the other is “thereby” true (p. 4). There is no difference between Susan running and Susan instantiating the property of running, even though only the latter explicitly mentions properties.2 Rayo connects just-is statements to (metaphysical) possibility: the possible worlds are those descriptions of reality that are logically consistent with the totality of true just-is statements.
    [Show full text]
  • (In Some Fictions) Everything Is True
    Australasian Journal of Logic (In some fictions) Everything is true Luis Estrada-Gonz´alez Institute for Philosophical Research, UNAM [email protected] Tout ne figure pas dans le Sottisier. Il y a de l'espoir. { Raymond Queneau 1 Introduction The question I am concerned with here is, roughly, whether there are universal fictions, i.e. fictions within which everything is true. This is important because logical fictions -or logical fantasies, in the terminology of Fine (1982), i.e. fictions where some features of what one takes as the standard logic fail { sometimes are used as (admittedly defeasible) tools to present, study, or even argue for or against, a logic; Priest (1999) and Kapsner's (unpublished) fictionalization of an idea of Dummett (1959) could be examples of this.1 The idea that everything is true, usually known as trivialism in the philosophy of logic, is widely agreed to be wrong, if not unintelligible at all.2 So, as with other logical ideas, fiction can provide a less passionate arena to explore trivialism. Additionally, universal fictions could stimulate some reflections, not only about logic, but about the nature of fiction itself; for example, on the narratological aspects of fiction or the identity criteria for fictions, as has been stressed by Wildman and Folde (2017). The problem is that even if it is more or less clear that there are actual incomplete and inconsistent fictions, it is doubtful that a universal fiction, one where everything is true, is even possible. Routley (1979), Deutsch (1985) and Kapsner (unpublished), although 1The term `logical fiction’ has been used in another sense, namely to denote an item logically constructed out from other items.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Trivialism
    A Defense of Trivialism Paul Douglas Kabay Submitted in total fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 2008 School of Philosophy, Anthropology, and Social Inquiry The University of Melbourne Abstract That trivialism ought to be rejected is almost universally held. I argue that the rejection of trivialism should be held in suspicion and that there are good reasons for thinking that trivialism is true. After outlining in chapter 1 the place of trivialism in the history of philosophy, I begin in chapter 2 an outline and defense of the various arguments in favor of the truth of trivialism. I defend four such arguments: an argument from the Curry Paradox; and argument from the Characterization Principle; an argument from the Principle of Sufficient Reason; and an argument from the truth of possibilism. In chapter 3 I build a case for thinking that the denial of trivialism is impossible. I begin by arguing that the denial of some view is the assertion of an alternative view. I show that there is no such view as the alternative to trivialism and so the denial of trivialism is impossible. I then examine an alternative view of the nature of denial – that denial is not reducible to an assertion but is a sui generis speech act. It follows given such an account of denial that the denial of trivialism is possible. I respond to this in two ways. First, I give reason for thinking that this is not a plausible account of denial. Secondly, I show that even if it is successful, the denial of trivialism is still unassertable, unbelievable, and severely limited in its rationality.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology.Pdf
    Epistemology An overview Contents 1 Main article 1 1.1 Epistemology ............................................. 1 1.1.1 Background and meaning ................................... 1 1.1.2 Knowledge .......................................... 1 1.1.3 Acquiring knowledge ..................................... 5 1.1.4 Skepticism .......................................... 7 1.1.5 See also ............................................ 7 1.1.6 References .......................................... 8 1.1.7 Works cited .......................................... 9 1.1.8 External links ......................................... 10 2 Knowledge 11 2.1 Knowledge ............................................... 11 2.1.1 Theories of knowledge .................................... 11 2.1.2 Communicating knowledge ................................. 12 2.1.3 Situated knowledge ...................................... 13 2.1.4 Partial knowledge ...................................... 13 2.1.5 Scientific knowledge ..................................... 13 2.1.6 Religious meaning of knowledge ............................... 14 2.1.7 See also ............................................ 15 2.1.8 References .......................................... 15 2.1.9 External links ......................................... 16 2.2 Belief ................................................. 16 2.2.1 Knowledge and epistemology ................................. 17 2.2.2 As a psychological phenomenon ............................... 17 2.2.3 Epistemological belief compared to religious belief
    [Show full text]