Phenomenological Aspects of Wittgenstein's Philosophy Synthese Library

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Phenomenological Aspects of Wittgenstein's Philosophy Synthese Library PHENOMENOLOGICAL ASPECTS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S PHILOSOPHY SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University Editors: DIRK VAN DALEN, University of Utrecht, The Netherlands DONALD DAVIDSON, University of California, Berkeley THEO A.F. KUIPERS, University of Groningen, The Netherlands PATRICK SUPPES, Stanford University, California JAN WOLENSKI, Jagiellonian University, Krakow, Poland VOLUME 268 BYONG-CHUL PARK Pusan University of Foreign Studies, Pusan, Korea PHENOMENOLOGICAL ASPECTS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S PHILOSOPHY id SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A CLP. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-94-010-6165-0 ISBN 978-94-011-5151-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-5151-1 Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1998 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1998 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE Vll CHAPTER I. Wittgenstein's Phenomenology 1 1. Wittgenstein's Phenomenology 1 2. The Background ofWittgenstein's Idea of Phenomenology 8 3. Phenomenology VS. Phenomenalism 18 CHAPTER II. Phenomenology of the Tractatus 25 1. Russell's Influence on the Early Wittgenstein 25 2. The Nature of Tractarian Objects 34 3. Husserl, Russell, and Wittgenstein 41 4. Phenomenology and Solipsism 48 5. Solipsism I 58 6. Phenomenology and Logical Analysis 67 CHAPTER III. The Languages of Phenomenology 79 1. The Shift of Language Paradigms 79 2. Solipsism II 86 3. Wittgenstein's Phenomenology of Time 102 4. Rules, Language-games, and Phenomenology 112 5. Sensations and the Language of Sensations 122 CHAPTER IV. Wittgenstein on Color Concepts 135 1. Wittgenstein on Color Concepts: the Early View 135 2. The Language-game of Color 142 3. Wittgenstein on Color Concepts: the Later View 152 CHAPTER V. Wittgenstein on Aspects 162 1. Wittgenstein's Use of the word 'Aspect' 162 2. Language-games of Aspect 170 VI TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER VI. Is Phenomenology Possible for Wittgenstein? 179 1. Other Phenomenological Interpretations 179 2. Interpretations against Phenomenological Interpretation 194 3. Is Phenomenology Possible for Wittgenstein? 205 LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS 215 NOTES 217 BIBLIOGRAPHY 236 INDEX 245 PREFACE In his writings around 1930, Wittgenstein relates his philosophy in different ways to the idea of phenomenology. He indicates that his main philosophical project had earlier been the construction of a purely phenomenological language, and even after having given up this project he believed that "the world we live in is the world of sense-data,,,l that is, of phenomenological objects. However, a problem is posed by the fact that he does not appear ever to have given a full, explicit account of what he means by his 'phenomenology', 'phenomenological language', or 'phenomenological problems'. In this book, I have tried to unravel the nature of Wittgenstein's phenomenology and to examine its importance for his entire work in philosophy. Phenomenology can be characterized as philosophy whose primary concern is what is immediately given in one's experience. This 'immediately given' is not merely impressions inside one's mind, but includes also the part of objective reality that impinges upon one's consciousness. Thus, an aim of phenomenological enterprise is to grasp this objective reality by attending to immediate experience. Husserl's phenomenology is in fact a case in point. Similarly, Wittgenstein's main attention throughout his entire philosophical career is directed to one's immediate experience. What makes Wittgenstein's phenomenology unusual, however, is the way he views immediate experience. For Wittgenstein, especially the early Wittgenstein, the nature of the immediately given is unique in the sense that the possibility of logic is also based on it. Indeed, the fact that Wittgenstein sees the foundation of logic in immediate experience is what makes his philosophy a kind of phenomenology. In the Tractatus, all logical forms are combinations of logical forms of immediately given objects of experience. Also, immediate experience can only be grasped and understood by means of language, because Wittgenstein views language as the ultimate medium through which we understand the world. Therefore, the important problem for him is Vlll PREFACE the way we use language to describe immediate experience. In my study, I examine Wittgenstein's concern with immediate experience and the way we describe it, a concern which guides his philosophical journey through the phenomenological problems that pervade his work. Chapter one discusses the general problems with regard to Wittgenstein's phenomenology. I widely examine and discuss the philosophical background of Wittgenstein's phenomenology, which should be clearly distinguished from any form of phenomenalism. In order to clarify what Wittgenstein means by his phenomenology, I not only examine the way Wittgenstein uses the words 'phenomenology' and 'phenomenological' in his own writings and other related materials but try to trace the possible influence from which Wittgenstein might have received the usage and the idea of phenomenology. Among many possible influences are those of theoretical physicist Ludwig Boltzmann as well as Heinrich Hertz and Ernst Mach. Chapter two consists of a detailed discussion of Wittgenstein's phenomenology in the Tractatus, the focus being on how Wittgenstein develops his phenomenological ideas, which consist of the Tractarian logic and logical analysis, and on how he comes to modify his earlier view toward the middle period. Most importantly, I discuss Russell's influence on the development ofWittgenstein's early philosophy, and I carefully examine the philosophical interactions between Russell and Wittgenstein with regard to Russell's theory of acquaintance, for Wittgenstein's reaction to Russell's theory results in Wittgenstein's phenomenology. In addition, I discuss the problem of solipsism in relation to the general characteristic of phenomenology, bringing the ideas of Husserl, Russell, and Wittgenstein into interesting comparison, as solipsism occurs in each of these philosophers' epistemological concerns. Wittgenstein's middle-period writings show that Wittgenstein is in transition. Chapter three discusses how he not only rejects some of the most important doctrines of the Tractatus but adopts new logic that eventually grows into the notion of grammar, and how he shifts language paradigms, namely from the phenomenological language of PREFACE IX the Tractatus to the physicalistic language of ordinary use. In light of this shift, I examine his middle-period treatment of solipsism and the problem of phenomenology of time. The change in the language paradigms apparently makes it impossible for Wittgenstein to conduct phenomenological enterprise. In fact, the abandonment of earlier logic, which is phenomenological in nature, waters down the phenomenological aspects of Wittgenstein's philosophy from the middle period on to the extent that he declares "there is no such thing as phenomenology, but there are indeed phenomenological problems.,,2 I examine how Wittgenstein continues to wrestle with these phenomenological problems as he develops the language-game idea. In chapter four I discuss Wittgenstein's treatment of color concepts. The problem of color is very phenomenological for Wittgenstein in the sense that the color he examines is color we immediately experience. I show that Wittgenstein tackles this phenomenological problem of color from the early period through the very last. In the early period colors are the example of Tractarian objects, so that from the beginning, Wittgenstein has no interest in the theory of physical color, a point well presented and supported in his Philosophical Remarks, where he repeatedly says of the theory of color that contains no hypothetical elements. As the language-game idea develops, Wittgenstein directs his concern toward how we can express and describe the color of immediate experience in our language-game, and so I conclude the color chapter with a discussion of the language-game of color. In chapter five I develop the idea that Wittgenstein's use of the word 'aspect' means a phenomenological object. The main purpose of Wittgenstein's frequent use of the word 'aspect' along with 'aspect-seeing' and 'aspect-change' in his late writings is not to entertain Gestalt psychology or philosophy of psychology per se, but deeply related to his earlier ideas of phenomenology. Examining his use of the word in middle and late period writings, I show that Wittgenstein's 'aspect' does not have its familiar meaning of 'side' or 'facet' . For Wittgenstein, the word 'aspect' means a way of x PREFACE appearing, a phenomenological object picked out by logically proper names like 'this' and 'that'. I conclude my study of Wittgenstein's phenomenology with criticism of other phenomenological interpretations presented since the 1950s. Some intend to identify Wittgenstein's phenomenology with Husserlian phenomenology, while others dismiss any claims that Wittgenstein was a phenomenologist. Also, some interpret that Wittgenstein's early and early middle-period
Recommended publications
  • FACING the PROBLEM of ETHICAL SOLIPSISM Sami Pihlström
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 GUILT: FACING THE PROBLEM OF ETHICAL SOLIPSISM Sami Pihlström ABSTRACT: This article deals with the constitutive role played by the emotion of guilt, or the capacity of experiencing such emotions, in our moral life. The deeply personal nature of moral guilt (or remorse) leads to the problem of ethical solipsism: it seems that guilt can in the end concern only me, not anyone else, in a morally profound sense. Echoing Dostoevsky, the truly ethical thinker ought to acknowledge that everyone is guilty in front of the entire mankind, “and I more than anyone else”. This problematic feature of our moral perspectives on the world is examined through comments on a number of authors, including Kant, Wittgenstein, Levinas, Gaita, and Todorov. While we do need to avoid solipsism, there is a “truth” hidden in it: morality is something that we are individually and personally deeply responsible for. 1 Immanuel Kant remarks, in a famous footnote to the First Critique, that [t]he real morality of actions (their merit and guilt), even that of our own conduct […] remains entirely hidden from us. Our imputations can be referred only to the empirical character. How much of it is to be ascribed to mere nature […] no one can discover, and hence no one can judge it with complete justice.1 Although commentators have drawn attention to this important passage,2 its full significance still deserves substantial consideration. So does the significance of another famous Kantian remark, according to which, for each one of us, “the depths of his own heart (the subjective first grounds of his maxims) are to him inscrutable”.3 1 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • The Yogācāra Theory of Three Natures: Internalist and Non-Dualist Interpretation
    Comparative Philosophy Volume 9, No. 1 (2018): 18-31 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org THE YOGĀCĀRA THEORY OF THREE NATURES: INTERNALIST AND NON-DUALIST INTERPRETATION MATTHEW MACKENZIE ABSTRACT: According to Vasubandhu’s Trisvabhāvanirdeśa or Treatise on the Three Natures, experiential phenomena can be understood in terms of three natures: the constructed (parikalpita), the dependent (paratantra), and the consummate (pariniṣpanna). This paper will examine internalist and anti-internalist or non-dualist interpretations of the Yogācāra theory of the three natures of experience. The internalist interpretation is based on representationalist theory of experience wherein the contents of experience are logically independent of their cause and various interconnected cognitive processes continually create an integrated internal world-model that is transparent to the cognitive system that creates and uses it. In contrast, the anti-internalist interpretation begins, not from the constructed nature of experiential objects, but from the perfected nature of mind-world non-duality. This interpretation treats the distinctions between inside and outside, subject and object, mind and world as distinctions drawn within experience rather than between experience and something else. And experience here refers to the continuous dynamic interplay of factors constituting our sentient embodied (nāma-rūpa) existence. Having examined each interpretation, the paper will suggest some reasons to favor the non-dualist view. Keywords: Yogācāra, Buddhist idealism, internalism, non-dualism, three natures of phenomena, Vasubandhu, solipsism 1. INTRODUCTION According to Vasubandhu’s Trisvabhāvanirdeśa or Treatise on the Three Natures, experiential phenomena can be understood in terms of three natures (svabhāva) and three forms of naturelessness (niḥsvabhāvatā). The three natures are the fabricated or constructed nature (parikalpita-svabhāva), the dependent nature (paratantra- svabhāva), and the perfected or consummate nature (pariniṣpanna-svabhāva).
    [Show full text]
  • The Interplay Between Relations, Substances, and Existence By
    The Interplay Between Relations, Substances, and Existence By Andrew Janes A Thesis Submitted to Saint Mary’s University, Halifax, Nova Scotia in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Bachelor of Arts - Honours in Philosophy. April, 2019, Halifax, Nova Scotia Copyright Andrew Janes, 2019 Approved: Scott Edgar Doctor Date: 12/04/19 ​ 2 The Interplay Between Relations, Substances, and Existence by Andrew Janes Abstract This thesis explores the ontology of relations and the implications of it. I make the case that relations between multiple substances are impossible. Furthermore, I argue that existence is a predicate, and can therefore be the predicate of a relation. I do this to push the argument that substances cannot exist in relation to each other. The conclusion I make from this is that only one substance can exist, since otherwise a substance could exist in relation to another substance. This conclusion, I point out, is the doctrine of substance monism. Furthermore, I argue that the self exists, because it is given in experience. Because the self is a substance, and I have argued for substance monism, the self is the only substance there is. This conclusion is idealism, and, in conjunction with substance monism, necessitates solipsism. 12/04/19 3 1. Introduction In this paper, I investigate the commitments one must make when they uphold the Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR),1 which asserts that for every fact, truth, and state of affairs, there is a sufficient reason that explains why it holds. More specifically, I aim to investigate commitments regarding relations. Furthermore, I aim to show why these commitments ultimately lead to an abandonment of substance pluralism2 and realism.3 That is, one must abandon the PSR if they are to believe that substance pluralism or realism holds true, or abandon substance pluralism and realism if they believe the PSR to be true.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Construct Theory: Relativism's Latest Fashion
    Social Construct Theory: Relativism's Latest Fashion Curtis L. Hancock Modern intellectuals dislike being called "relativists" and "subjectivists" as much as politicians dislike being called "liberals." Despite refusal to wear these labels, many modern intellectuals, just like the politicians, speak and behave in ways that betray their allegiance to what, in rhetoric, they abjure. A conspicuous example of this double-think is the modern fashion known in psychology as "social construct theory," aka "personal construct theory." In this essay, I will show that, in spite of their protests to the contrary, social construct theory collapses irretrievably into both moral and epistemological relativism. In fact, it will become clear that social construct theory cannot, if it is to remain consistent, escape solipsism. These and lesser objections included here conspire to demonstrate that social construct theory is incoherent and untenable. It is just another episode in a long-standing romance with irrationalism that has characterized modern epistemologies. If social scientists are treading the path of social construct theory in hope of solving stubborn problems, they are misled; they are walking down a cul-de-sac. The only remedy for their problems is to avoid the cul-de-sac in the first place. They are sorely in need of an alternative epistemology. 1 To assay social construct theory, I will examine the position of Kenneth Gergen, whose work is influential and clearly formulated. Gergen's position is representative of social construct theory at large. Reference to other representatives of social construct theory will not be neglected, but to economize 1 I am indebted to Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Solipsism
    Notes on solipsism P.W. Adriaans, Introduction. Solipsism is a phenomenon that has played a modest role in philosophical theorizing since about 1700. Although few philosophers can be called ‘Solipsist’ in the proper sense, solipsism is treated in many publications as a serious consequence of certain epistemological, metaphysical and ethical positions. This often happens casually, without a thorough examination of the assumptions and concepts involved. One occasionally sees rebuttals of solipsism in publications, but these are usually based on some dubious definitions of what solipsism should be. The result is that quite a few and to my knowledge no recent publications are, engaged in a scientific analysis of the phenomenon of solipsism itself in a more comprehensive perspective of various disciplines such as history, psychology, logic, epistemology, metaphysics, anthropology etc. In this note I give an analysis of the origins and historical development of the term 'solipsism'. In the second part I continue with an analysis of the origins and historical development of the problem or phenomenon of solipsism. The origins and historical development of the term 'solipsism'. The development of the term 'solipsism' is closely related to the development of a group of other terms like 'egotism', 'egoism' and 'Egomism’. These words are relatively young and have emerged during the Enlightenment. In this period of philosophical innovation many neologisms were formed. Traditional philosophical terms are: ego, individualitas, persona. Terms derived from mysticism and rediscovered by the French quietists seem to have been particularly attractive: the prefix "ego" and suffixes like "-ismus' and '-ista'. Some of these words found general acceptance.
    [Show full text]
  • Final Version: O'brien, LF (1996), 'Solipsism and Self-Reference'
    Final Version: O’Brien, L. F. (1996), ‘Solipsism and Self-Reference’, European Journal of Philosophy 4:175-194. Solipsism and Self-Reference ! I. Introduction In this paper I want to propose that we see solipsism as arising from certain problems we have about identifying ourselves as subjects in an objective world. The discussion will centre on Wittgenstein’s treatment of solipsism in his Tractatus Logico- Philosophicus. In that work Wittgenstein can be seen to express an unusually profound understanding of the problems faced in trying to give an account of how we, who are subjects, identify ourselves as objects in the world. We have in his compressed remarks, the kernels of a number of arguments which all come together to form what can be called the problem of self-identification. I want to argue that the solipsism of the Tractatus arises at least in part as a solution to, or – to put it less optimistically – as a symptom or articulation of this problem. In approaching Wittgenstein’s early discussion of solipsism in this way I will obviously be in disagreement with some other interpretations of the work. For example, there are those who think that there is no ‘solipsism of the Tractatus’.1 In fact, the Tractarian arguments presented below as motivating solipsism have been seen as fulfilling the quite opposite function of refuting it. I do not intend in this piece to engage with alternative interpretations. Let me say a little bit about why I have granted myself the licence not to do so. First, the focus of my concern with solipsism is on how it connects with what I have called the problem of self-identification.
    [Show full text]
  • The Solipsism of Religion
    THE SOLIPSISM OF RELIGION BY T. B. STORK until YES : Solipsism, that word of dread, despised and set aside restored to its proper place, rehabilitated by the great bishop in his Priiicihlcs of Kiioi^lcdgc. For Rishop Berkeley showed beyond all criticism that the doctrine of Solipism was in the intellectual world when properly qualified the only philoso])hically sound posi- tion. The knowledge of himself and of his own internal state is all the indubitable knowledge vouchsafed man, all else is inference, con- jecture, more or less assured. Descartes recognized the truth of the doctrine in his Cogifn ergo siiin that certified to a man his own existence bv the only trustworthy evidence, his own consciousness. Just as in the intellectual world so in the spiritual world—per- haps we should say a fortiori—are we shut in upon ourselves. All we really know is the condition of our own soul. And is not that all we are required to know ? A failure to recognize this truth of Solipsism and its equally im- portant qualification is at the root of all the intellectual difficulties of religious discussions. For Berkeley not only announced that all we know certainy is our internal state of consciousness, but he added the qualification that we can know nothing else with equal certainty, the certainty demanded by philosophy. The endless and fruitless discussions of God's dealing with men, of the inconsistencies of nominal Christians, of the thousand and one external facts that seem contradictory of our ethical notions of right and wrong all ignore this great and fundamental truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism: in Concept and Critique
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 2004 Contemporary philosophical naturalism: In concept and critique James Carlin Watson The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Watson, James Carlin, "Contemporary philosophical naturalism: In concept and critique" (2004). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5022. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5022 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Maureen and Mike MANSFIELD LIBRARY The University of Montana Permission is granted by the author to reproduce this material in its entirety, provided that this material is used for scholarly purposes and is properly cited in published works and reports. **Please check "Yes” or "No" and provide signature** Yes, I grant permission No, I do not grant permission Author's Signature: Date: Any copying for commercial purposes or financial gain may be undertaken only with the author's explicit consent. 8/98 Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism: In Concept and Critique by James Carlin Watson B. S. Lee University, Cleveland, TN, 2000 presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts' The University of Montana December 2004 Approved by: Chairperson Dean, Graduate School l** I'OS Date UMI Number.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant Lucien Goldmann
    KANT LUCIEN GOLDMANN k Lucien Goldmann ! London j NLB • ! Atlantic Highlands i HUMANITIES PRESS Immanuel Kant First published as Mensch, Gemeinschaft und Welt in der Philosophie Immanuel Kants by Europa-Verlag, Zürich, 1945 © Europa-Verlag, 1945 New, revised and enlarged edition first published as Introduction ä la Philosophie de Kant by Gallimard, 1967 © Editions Gallimard, 1967 This edition first published 1971 Translated from the French and German by Robert Black © NLB, 1971 NLB, 7 Carlisle Street, London wi Designed by Gerald Cinamon Typeset in Monotype Ehrhardt and printed by Western Printing Services Ltd, Bristol SBN 902308 85 2 TO MADELEINE DUCLOS AND THEOPHILE SPOERRI Acknowledgments 8 Translator's note 9 Preface to the 1967 French edition 13 From the Preface to the first French edition, 1948 17 From the Preface to the original (German) edition, 1945 19 Introduction 21 PART I 1. Classical Philosophy and the Western Bourgeoisie 31 2. The Category of Totality in the Thought of Kant and in Philosophy in General 50 3. The Precritical Period 58 PART II 1. The Critical Philosophy and its Problems 101 2. What Can I Know ? 131 3. What Ought I to Do ? 170 4. What May I Hope for ? 180 The Present - Beauty 182 Eternity - God, Immortality 193 The Future - History 205 Conclusion: What is Man? Kant and Contemporary Philosophy 223 Index 231 Acknowledgments: We would like to thank the following for permission to quote passages from works by Kant published by them: Macmillan & Co. Ltd for Critique of Pure Reason; Manchester University Press for Selected Pre-critical Writings; Cambridge University Press for Kant's Political Writings; The Clarendon Press for Critique of Aesthetic Judgement; Harper & Row for Religion within the limits of reason alone; Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical History of the Embodied Cognitive Research Paradigm a Review of Lawrence Shapiro’S Embodied Cognition
    172 Book Reviews A Critical History of the Embodied Cognitive Research Paradigm A review of Lawrence Shapiro’s Embodied Cognition Author: Lawrence Shapiro Publisher: Routledge Release date: 2011 Number of pages: 233 Kevin Ryan, Department of Philosophy, Villanova University, USA Embodied Cognition by Lawrence Shapiro is a fine text that focuses on the issues of body, embodiment, and the environment in cognitive science, philosophy, and psy- chology. As the title suggests, Shapiro's book offers us a glimpse into the broadly defined, and still growing, research paradigm known as "embodied" cognition. Within this particular paradigm the body and environment are placed in the fore- ground when it comes to both theoretical and empirical work on cognition and the mind. In terms of the audience for this particular text, we suggest that with its combination of systematic rigor, lucid prose, and multiple well structured exam- ples, it is a worthwhile read for scholars, casual readers, or as a useful addition to any course that contains elements of philosophy of mind or a focus on cognitive science. One way of understanding Shapiro's project is by looking at the text in two sec- tions. The first section, equivalent to the first three chapters, lays down the basic foundations in preparation for the heavy theoretical and conceptual work found in the second section. Indeed, a combination of several questions motivating this book – taken in conjunction to make up what Shapiro calls its "meta-theme" – are presented by Shapiro as the following: Does the
    [Show full text]
  • SOLIPSISM – an EXTREME of RATIONALISM
    University of South Bohemia, Ceske Budejovice Faculty of Theology Department of Philosophy and Religious Sciences Bachelor’s Degree Thesis SOLIPSISM – An EXTREME of RATIONALISM Mentor: Daniel HEIDER, Th.D. Author: Pavao HRŠAK, Dipl. Ing. El. Study Programme: Humanities School year: 2010/2011 2011 Declaration of self-reliance Hereby I declare that I have prepared my bachelor’s degree thesis entirely on my own, using as reference sources the literature listed in the section at the end of the paper. I declare that, in concordance with Article 47b of Law 111/1998 Sb of the Legal Code of Czech Republic, I agree with making my bachelor’s degree thesis public, in unabbreviated form (or edited through omission of parts marked as archived by the Faculty of Theology) electronically in the publicly accessible part of STAG database administrated by the University of South Bohemia in Ceske Budejovice on their web pages, and with preservation of my authorial rights on the submitted text of this qualification paper. Furthermore, I agree that through the same electronic access evaluation of the mentor and the opponent would be made public, as well as a record of proceedings and results of the defense of the qualification paper, all in concordance with stipulations of the referenced law 111/1998 Sb. As well I agree with comparison of the text of my qualification paper with the database of qualification papers Theses.cz administrated by National Register of High School Qualification Papers and the system for detection of plagiarism. Date …………………… Author’s signature. ……………………… 1 Acknowledgments When, in rather advanced age and having terminated my professional career in engineering, I decided to try to return to a quite different field of interest of my teen age at the grammar school, it was clear to me that it would be impossible without expert guidance, support and patience of people dedicated to this particular field.
    [Show full text]
  • 5. a Kantian Responds to Santayana
    Page no.66 5. A Kantian Responds to Santayana Dr. Samuel J.M. Kahn Assistant Professor of Philosophy Indiana University-Purdue University, Indianapolis United States ORCID iD: http://orcid.org/0000-0001-6597-7646 Web-address: http://liberalarts.iupui.edu/directory/bio/kahnsa E-Mail: [email protected]/ [email protected] Abstract: In this paper, I have argued that whatever Might be said about his attack on other GerMan philosophers, Santayana’s attack on Kant, despite its subtlety, its force and its intelligence, is fundaMentally Misguided. Teasing out where Santayana’s attack rests on Misunderstandings of Kant’s philosophy is a useful exercise: it is useful for Kantians, for it gives us a chance to show Kant at his best; it is useful for Santayana scholars, for it reMinds us that Santayana, for all his brilliance, was not infallible; and it is useful More generally, for the Mistakes Santayana Makes about Kant are, perhaps in part because of Santayana’s well-deservedly wide influence, still prevalent today. Keywords: Kant; Santayana; The GerMan Mind: a philosophical diagnosis; GerMan philosophy. Vol 3 No 1 (2015) ISSUE – March ISSN 2347-6869 (E) & ISSN 2347-2146 (P) A Kantian Responds to Santayana by Dr. Samuel J.M. Kahn Page No. 66-79 Page no.67 A Kantian Responds to Santayana Introduction In The GerMan Mind: a philosophical diagnosis, Santayana launches an extended attack on Kant and, indeed, German philosophy more generally. This attack centers on the concept of egotism. At the broadest level, the idea behind Santayana’s attack is that egotism is a bad thing --- perhaps the worst thing in Santayana’s eyes --- and it is something of which Kant and other German philosophers are guilty.
    [Show full text]