Kant with Foucault: on the Dangers of the Theoretical Reification Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kant with Foucault: on the Dangers of the Theoretical Reification Of Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 5-6-2016 Kant With Foucault: On The aD ngers Of The Theoretical Reification Of The ubjecS t To Freedom And The eedN For A Practical Psychology Matthew Gordon Valentine Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Valentine, M. (2016). Kant With Foucault: On The aD ngers Of The Theoretical Reification Of The ubjS ect To Freedom And The Need For A Practical Psychology (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/1527 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. KANT WITH FOUCAULT: ON THE DANGERS OF THE THEORETICAL REIFICATION OF THE SUBJECT TO FREEDOM AND THE NEED FOR A PRACTICAL PSYCHOLOGY A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Matthew Valentine May 2016 Copyright by Matthew Valentine 2016 KANT WITH FOUCAULT: ON THE DANGERS OF THE THEORETICAL REIFICATION OF THE SUBJECT TO FREEDOM AND THE NEED FOR A PRACTICAL PSYCHOLOGY By Matthew Valentine Approved April 4, 2016 ________________________________ ________________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Fred Evans, Ph.D Professor of Philosophy and Dean Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ________________________________ Jay Lampert, Ph.D Associate Professor (Committee Member) ________________________________ ________________________________ James Swindal Ronald Polansky, Ph.D Dean, The McAnulty College and Chair, Philosophy Department Graduate School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT KANT WITH FOUCAULT: ON THE DANGERS OF THE THEORETICAL REIFICATION OF THE SUBJECT TO FREEDOM AND THE NEED FOR A PRACTICAL PSYCHOLOGY By Matthew Valentine May 2016 Dissertation supervised by Doctor James Swindal, Ph.D, Dean and Professor In this dissertation I consider the question, “Is it possible to think the subject qua subject or must any theoretical attempt to understand the subject necessarily reify it?” To answer this question, I appealed to Immanuel Kant’s distinction between theoretical and practical reason, noting that practical reason could think the subject as a free soul rather than as a naturally- determined object. I then divided the sciences of the subject into four general types to determine which science could think the subject qua subject. Three sciences were shown to necessarily reify the subject: empirical psychology, rational psychology, and heteronomous ethics. I then paralleled Kant’s insight with Michel Foucault’s analyses of the human sciences, showing the concrete consequences of objectification. Using Foucault’s work on ethical practice and askesis as a guide, I returned to Kant and explained how practical reason can think the subject qua subject only insofar as it considers the subject as something to be made rather than a theoretical object to know. I then posed the question, “What are the necessary conditions for someone to be a subject of possible experience?” which led into a Kantian-inspired theory of love and intersubjectivity. Finally, I concluded that contemporary psychology is mired in an impasse between happiness and freedom, insofar as therapeutic practice is no longer an ethic. I suggest the need for a practical psychology to solve this impasse. iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to acknowledge the members of my committee individually: Ever since the summer of 2007, so many years ago, Doctor James Swindal has taken me under his wing. I was his teaching assistant my first year at Duquesne and was his assistant when Duquesne hosted SPEP Fall of 2008. Much has changed at Duquesne since those days, but Doctor Swindal’s guidance and support has remained a constant. No words are adequate to express my gratitude to him. My interest in Michel Foucault was sparked by Doctor Fred Evans back in the spring of 2008. Fred and I both share a love for both philosophy and psychology, and I found myself, semester after semester, taking his offered courses. Many of the papers I wrote for him were papers that expressed thoughts I still treasure as most mine, and I am grateful to have had the opportunity to study with him, as well as work for him as a Fellow for the Center of Interpretive and Qualitative Research from Fall of 2014 to Spring of 2015. It wasn’t until the Spring of 2008 that I was introduced to the work of Alain Badiou by Doctor Jay Lampert. It may not be evident, but this project was fundamentally shaped by an engagement with Badiou and was originally about Kant and Badiou rather than Kant and Foucault. Without Badiou’s distinction between the True and the veridical, for example, I would likely not have considered Kant’s distinction between theoretical and practical interests of reason, nor the epistemological role of affect, nor considered the possibility that ethics could take on forms other than that of bioethics. Jay has been a consistent source of constructive criticism and has no qualms challenging my arguments, which makes me all the more confident that I have produced a work of merit. I am grateful that he has engaged with my work so thoughtfully and so patiently. But I would like to acknowledge others just as responsible for this work as well: There have been some who were with me as I committed the first words of this dissertation to page. There were some who sat across from me in coffee shops as I pushed through the over four hundred pages of this work. There are those who were with me, in person and in spirit, as I applied the finishing touches to this behemoth. I couldn’t have finished this dissertation without you and will always have a special place in my heart for you. But there are those who were with me and supported me before I ever took up the pen, my parents Deborah and Gordon, and my sisters, Heather and Megan. There are those I grew up with who were like family, David, Mike, and James. Without that bedrock, I would not have ever set out on this unlikely path. Thank you. v Table of Contents Chapter One 1.1 The Ego that is Not: Kant’s Rejection of the Empirical Ego and its Pleasures 1 Introduction 1 Sciences of the Self 2 Kant’s Critiques of Empirical Psychology 3 The Formal Limitations of Inner Sense 6 The Material Limitations of Inner Sense 15 Methodological Limitations of Empirical Psychology 16 Contradictions: Kant’s Position on Empirical Psychology in the Critique of Pure Reason 17 Possible Motives behind the Rejection of the Empirical Ego 20 What is the Empirical Ego? 23 The Status of the Transcendental Ego 28 1.2 Overview 32 Rational Psychology 32 Heteronomy of Choice 38 Chapter Two 2.1 The Faculty of Reason: An Introduction to the Paralogisms 40 2.2 The Predicates of the Soul and Their Derivation 49 2.3 Background Material on the Paralogisms 52 2.4 Background on the Paralogisms in General 56 Christian Wolff 56 Martin Knutzen 59 Alexander Baumgarten 62 Christian August Crusius 68 Leonard Euler 72 Marcus Herz 74 Johann August Eberhard 76 Johann Nicolaus Tetens 79 2.5 Discussion of the Specific Paralogisms and Relevant Background Material 81 The First Paralogism 81 Thinkers Addressed by the First Paralogism 84 The Second Paralogism 86 Thinkers Addressed by the Second Paralogism 88 Christian Wolff 89 Martin Knutzen 90 Alexander Baumgarten 91 Christian August Crusius 91 Marcus Herz 92 The Third Paralogism 93 Thinkers Addressed by the Third Paralogism 94 Johann August Eberhard 95 Johann Nicolaus Tetens 96 The Fourth Paralogism 96 vi Thinkers Addressed by the Fourth Paralogism 99 2.6 Final Words on the Paralogisms 101 Chapter Three 3.1 Heteronomy of Choice: Introduction to the Task of the Chapter 103 3.2 Subjective-External Material Practical Principles 109 Michel de Montaigne’s ‘Education-based’ Moral Theory 112 Bernard Mandeville’s ‘Civil Government’ based Moral Theory 117 3.3 Subjective-Internal Material Practical Principles 122 Epicurus’ ‘Physical Feeling’ based Moral Theory 125 Francis Hutcheson’s ‘Moral Feeling’ based Moral Theory 131 3.4 Intermezzo: From the Subjective to the Objective 146 3.5 Objective-Internal Material Practical Principles 149 The Stoic Perfection-based Moral Theory 150 Stoicism 150 Early Stoicism: Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus 151 Later Stoicism: Seneca and Epictetus 154 Seneca 154 Epictetus 156 Kant’s Account of the Ethical Systems of Antiquity 159 General Reflections on Stoicism as Heteronomy 165 The Wolffian Perfection-based Moral Theory 165 Conclusions regarding Objective-Internal Material Practical Principles 167 3.6 Objective-External Material Practical Principles 167 Crusius’ Divine Command Moral Theory 168 3.7 Final Remarks on Heteronomy and Its Threat to Freedom 169 Chapter Four 4.1 The Table of Heteronomy as Architectonic for Foucaultian Forms of Control 173 4.2 Objective-Internal Forms of Domination: The History of Madness 181 Criteria for the Objective-Internal Form of Domination 181 Foucaultian Epistemology in The History of Madness 182 A History of the Experiences of Madness 184 Renaissance 184 Renaissance Literature: Erasmus and the Humanists 186 Tragic Experience vs. Critical Consciousness 187 The Ship of Fools 189 The Classical Age (The Enlightenment Period) 190 The Domain of Confinement 191 Madness and Bourgeois Standards
Recommended publications
  • A Virtue Ethic for the Twenty-First Century Warrior: Teaching Natural Law Through the Declaration of Independence and the Gettsyburg Address
    Concordia Seminary - Saint Louis Scholarly Resources from Concordia Seminary Doctor of Ministry Major Applied Project Concordia Seminary Scholarship 2-16-2012 A Virtue Ethic for the Twenty-First Century Warrior: Teaching Natural Law Through the Declaration of Independence and the Gettsyburg Address Ryan Rupe Concordia Seminary, St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.csl.edu/dmin Part of the Practical Theology Commons Recommended Citation Rupe, Ryan, "A Virtue Ethic for the Twenty-First Century Warrior: Teaching Natural Law Through the Declaration of Independence and the Gettsyburg Address" (2012). Doctor of Ministry Major Applied Project. 139. https://scholar.csl.edu/dmin/139 This Major Applied Project is brought to you for free and open access by the Concordia Seminary Scholarship at Scholarly Resources from Concordia Seminary. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctor of Ministry Major Applied Project by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Resources from Concordia Seminary. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CONCORDIA SEMINARY SAINT LOUIS, MISSOURI A VIRTUE ETHIC FOR THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY WARRIOR: TEACHING NATURAL LAW THROUGH THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE AND THE GETTSYBURG ADDRESS A MAJOR APPLIED PROJECT SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF DOCTOR OF MINISTRY STUDIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF MINISTRY BY RYAN R. RUPE SAINT LOUIS, MISSOURI 15 DECEMBER 2011 A VIRTUE ETHIC FOR THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY WARRIOR: TEACHING NATURAL LAW THROUGH THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE AND THE GETTSYBURG ADDRESS RYAN R. RUPE 16 FEBRUARY 2012 Concordia Seminary Saint Louis, Missouri ____________________________________ __________________ Advisor Dr. Arthur Bacon DATE ____________________________________ __________________ Reader DATE ____________________________________ __________________ Director, Doctor of Ministry Program DATE Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Applying Virtue Ethics to Business: the Agent-Based Approach
    Applying virtue ethics to business: The agent-based approach By: John Dobson It ca be argued that the presence of what are in a slightly old-fashioned terminology called virtues in fact plays a significant role in the operation of the economic system. - Kenneth Arrow Introduction There are two basic approaches to integrating ethics in business: the action-based approach, and the agent-based approach. The traditional approach is action-based in that it focusses on developing rules or guidelines to constrain management's actions. These rules or guidelines generally manifest themselves in corporate codes-of-conduct, or codes-of-ethics. Contrarily, rather than the action-based focus on rules governing action, the agent-based approach concerns the fundamental character and motivations of the individual agent. Under the agent-based approach, moral behavior is not limited to adherence to a rule or guideline but rather involves the individual rationally pursuing moral excellence as a goal in and of itself. In essence, ethics becomes central to the rationality concept as an objective rather than a constraint: "something positively good, ..something to be sought after" (Ladd, 1991, p. 82). Agent-based approaches generally derive their philosophical foundation from virtue-ethics theory. This theory is attracting increasing interest from business ethicists. In essence, the 'virtue' in virtue-ethics is defined as some desirable character trait, such as courage, that lies between two extremes, such as rashness and cowardice. Thus the 'virtuous' agent is involved in a continual quest to find balance in decision-making. Such an agent does not apply any specific 'rules' in making decisions, but rather attempts to make decisions that are consistent with the pursuit of a particular kind of excellence that in turn entails exercising sound moral judgement guided by such 'virtues' as courage, wisdom, temperance, fairness, integrity, and consistency.
    [Show full text]
  • Lawrence Kohlberg's Stages of Moral Development from Wikipedia
    ECS 188 First Readings Winter 2017 There are two readings for Wednesday. Both are edited versions of Wikipedia articles. The first reading adapted from https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lawrence_Kohlberg's_stages_of_moral_development, and the second reading is adapted from https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ethics. You can find the references for the footnotes there. As you read the article about moral development please think about you answered the Heinz Dilemma in class, and in which stage did your justification lie. I do not plan on discussing our answers to the Heinz Dilemma any further in class. As you read the ethic article, please think about which Normative ethic appeals to you, and why. This will be one of the questions we will discuss on Wednesday. My goal for both of these readings is to help you realize what values you bring to your life, and our course in particular. Lawrence Kohlberg's Stages of Moral Development from Wikipedia Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development constitute an adaptation of a psychological theory originally conceived by the Swiss psychologist Jean Piaget. Kohlberg began work on this topic while a psychology graduate student at the University of Chicago[1] in 1958, and expanded upon the theory throughout his life. The theory holds that moral reasoning, the basis for ethical behavior, has six identifiable developmental stages, each more adequate at responding to moral dilemmas than its predecessor.[2] Kohlberg followed the development of moral judgment far beyond the ages studied earlier by Piaget,[3] who also claimed that logic and morality develop through constructive stages.[2] Expanding on Piaget's work, Kohlberg determined that the process of moral development was principally concerned with justice, and that it continued throughout the individual's lifetime,[4] a notion that spawned dialogue on the philosophical implications of such research.[5][6] The six stages of moral development are grouped into three levels: pre-conventional morality, conventional morality, and post-conventional morality.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Hutcheson and Kant: Moral Sense and Moral Feeling Published In
    1 Hutcheson and Kant: Moral Sense and Moral Feeling Michael Walschots Published in Kant and the Scottish Enlightenment. Edited by Elizabeth Robinson and Chris W. Surprenant. London: Routledge, 2017. pg. 36 – 54. The eighteenth century is a rich and fascinating period in the history of Germany philosophy for a variety of reasons. Not least among these is the fact that German authors of the period somewhat extensively engaged with the writings of those in other European countries and beyond. The extent to which German philosophers engaged with eighteenth century British philosophy is an excellent example. Describing the reception of British philosophy in eighteenth century Germany, Manfred Kuehn writes that The works of Locke, Shaftsbury, Hutcheson, Hume, Smith, Ferguson, and almost every other British philosopher of note were full of problems that needed solutions and observations that needed to be explained, if German philosophy of the traditional sort was to succeed. (Kuehn 2001, 183-4) Although many German philosophers of the period could read English, the wide reception of these British authors was made possible in large part by the, in some cases rapid, translation of their texts into German. This is certainly true of the Scottish philosopher who will be the focus of this paper: Francis Hutcheson (1694-1747). A translation of Hutcheson’s posthumous System of Moral Philosophy, first published in 1755, was published just one year later in 1756. Translations of Hutcheson’s An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions (1728) and An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (1725) followed somewhat soon thereafter, appearing in 1760 and 1762 respectively.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Ethics in A/IS
    The IEEE Global Initiative on Ethics of Autonomous and Intelligent Systems Classical Ethics in A/IS We applied classical ethics methodologies to considerations of algorithmic design in autonomous and intelligent systems (A/IS) where machine learning may or may not reflect ethical outcomes that mimic human decision-making. To meet this goal, we drew from classical ethics theories and the disciplines of machine ethics, information ethics, and technology ethics. As direct control over tools becomes further removed, creators of autonomous systems must ask themselves how cultural and ethical presumptions bias artificially intelligent creations. Such introspection is more necessary than ever because the precise and deliberate design of algorithms in self-sustained digital systems will result in responses based on such design. By drawing from over two thousand years’ worth of classical ethics traditions, we explore established ethics systems, including both philosophical traditions (utilitarianism, virtue ethics, and deontological ethics) and religious and culture-based ethical systems (Buddhism, Confucianism, African Ubuntu traditions, and Japanese Shinto) and their stance on human morality in the digital age.1 In doing so, we critique assumptions around concepts such as good and evil, right and wrong, virtue and vice, and we attempt to carry these inquiries into artificial systems’ decision-making processes. Through reviewing the philosophical foundations that define autonomy and ontology, we address the potential for autonomous capacity of artificially intelligent systems, posing questions of morality in amoral systems and asking whether decisions made by amoral systems can have moral consequences. Ultimately, we address notions of responsibility and accountability for the decisions made by autonomous systems and other artificially intelligent technologies.
    [Show full text]
  • From Zarathustra to the Wisdom of Salomon Wolfgang Leidhold, Cologne [EVS: Panel 2 — Religious Experience : Eric Voegelin and Beyond]
    DRAFT - Seattle 2011 The Noetic Turn: From Zarathustra to the Wisdom of Salomon Wolfgang Leidhold, Cologne [EVS: Panel 2 — Religious Experience : Eric Voegelin and Beyond] Summary: Taking Eric Voegelin‘s theory of experience as a point of departure, this essay examines more closely the logic of experience (and of religious experience in particular). Voegelin‘s main thesis is that, since all ideas and concepts are based on experience, there is no „history of ideas― as an isolated process that is intelligible in itself but ideas must be studied and can only be understood if based on the founding experiences as their intelligible field. In an attempt to go beyond Voegelin‘s achievements, the paper sets ou by analyzing the structure of experience more closely. The results are applied to historic case-studies, starting with the Gathas of Zarathustra; neolithic myth and paleolithic symbolism are studied next; from here the analysis proceeds to Hindu and Daoist traditions, finally to some Old and New Testament sources. In the end, the findings are summarized as a new theory: the structure of experience varies not only regarding compactness and differentiation; but the experiental field itself is changing in terms of horizon, dimensions, and structure. As a consequence, experience and its symbolization are equivalent only if the structure is similar. The difference between „cultures― does not only regard the varying symbolizations of basically equivalent experiences, they are based on different modes of experience. Therefore we have to go one step beyond Eric Voegelin‘s achievements and study the history of experience. 1. Star Gazer One night as a young boy about twelve years of age I sat at home in the kitchen and looked out of the window at the nocturnal sky.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Western Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 12-15-2015 12:00 AM Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics Michael H. Walschots The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Corey Dyck The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Michael H. Walschots 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Walschots, Michael H., "Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3383. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3383 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MORAL SENSE THEORY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF KANT’S ETHICS (Thesis format: Monograph) by Michael H. Walschots Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Michael H. Walschots 2015 Abstract This dissertation investigates a number of ways in which an eighteenth century British philosophical movement known as “moral sense theory” influenced the development of German philosopher Immanuel Kant’s (1724-1804) moral theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence: from Ethics to Policy
    Artificial intelligence: From ethics to policy STUDY Panel for the Future of Science and Technology EPRS | European Parliamentary Research Service Scientific Foresight Unit (STOA) PE 641.507 – June 2020 EN Artificial intelligence: From ethics to policy There is little doubt that artificial intelligence (AI) and machine learning (ML) will revolutionise public services. However, the power for positive change that AI provides simultaneously holds the potential for negative impacts on society. AI ethics work to uncover the variety of ethical issues resulting from the design, development, and deployment of AI. The question at the centre of all current work in AI ethics is: How can we move from AI ethics to specific policy and legislation for governing AI? Based on a framing of 'AI as a social experiment', this study arrives at policy options for public administrations and governmental organisations who are looking to deploy AI/ML solutions, as well as the private companies who are creating AI/ML solutions for use in the public arena. The reasons for targeting this application sector concern: the need for a high standard of transparency, respect for democratic values, and legitimacy. The policy options presented here chart a path towards accountability; procedures and decisions of an ethical nature are systematically logged prior to the deployment of an AI system. This logging is the first step in allowing ethics to play a crucial role in the implementation of AI for the public good. STOA | Panel for the Future of Science and Technology AUTHORS This study has been written by Dr Aimee van Wynsberghe of Delft University of Technology and co-director of the Foundation for Responsible Robotics at the request of the Panel for the Future of Science and Technology (STOA) and managed by the Scientific Foresight Unit, within the Directorate-General for Parliamentary Research Services (EPRS) of the Secretariat of the European Parliament.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Scottish Thought Volume 7
    Journal of Scottish Thought Volume 7 Francis Hutcheson and the Origin of the Aesthetic Published by the Research Institute of Irish and Scottish Studies University of Aberdeen 2016 ISSN 1755 9928 Editor: Endre Szécsényi © The Contributors This volume of The Journal of Scottish Thought developed from a conference hosted by the Research Institute of Irish and Scottish Studies, University of Aberdeen and part-funded by the European Commission by virtue of a Marie Curie Fellowship held at the University of Aberdeen by Endre Szécsényi. The Journal of Scottish Thought is a peer reviewed, open access journal published annually by the Research Institute of Irish and Scottish Studies at the University of Aberdeen. Correspondence should be addressed to The Journal of Scottish Thought, 19 College Bounds, University of Aberdeen, AB24 3UG. Printed and bound by CPI Antony Rowe, Eastbourne. CONTENTS Editorial note v Francis Hutcheson, George Turnbull and the Intersection of Aesthetics and Morals 1 Alexander Broadie ‘What could a Statue or Panegyrick effect?’ A Note on the Abstractness of Hutcheson’s Aesthetics 15 Bálint Gárdos Hutcheson and Reid on Natural Beauty 29 Emily Brady The Experience of Absolute Beauty in Hutcheson: Perception, Reason and Pleasure 52 Richard Glauser Francis Hutcheson’s Aesthetics and his Critics in Ireland: Charles-Louis de Villette and Edmund Burke 81 Daniel Carey Francis Hutcheson and the Aesthetics of Multitude 106 Cairns Craig The Aesthetics of Political Economy: 136 The Case of Francis Hutcheson Michael Brown The Epistemology
    [Show full text]
  • A 2010 Wisdom Bibliography
    Bibliography [email protected] AARP. 2005. Boomers at Midlife: The AARP Life Stage Study Wave 3, 2004. <http://assets.aarp.org/rgcenter/general/boomers_midlife_2004.pdf> Abram, David. 1996. The Spell of the Sensuous. New York: Random House-Vintage. Abukari, Abdulai. 2005, June. Conceptualising Lifelong Learning: A Reflection on Lifelong Learning at Lund University (Sweden) and Middlesex University (UK). European Journal of Education, 40(2), p143-154. Aburdene, Patricia. 2005. Megatrends 2010: The Rise of Cponscious Capitalism. Charlottesville, VA: Hampton Roads. Achenaum, W. Andrew. (1997). The Wisdom of Age—An Historian’s Perspective. University of North Carolina Institute on Aging Distinguished Lecture Series, April 3, 1997. <www.aging.unc.edu/infocenter/resources/1997/achenbaumw.pdf>. accessed 11/7/2004. Achenbaum, W. Andrew. 2004. Wisdom’s Vision of Relations. Human Development (Karger), 47:5, Sept, pp. 300-303. Achenbaum, W. A., & Orwoll, L. (1991). Becoming wise: A Psycho-gerontological interpretation of the book of Job. International Journal of Aging and Human Development, 32 (1), 21-39. Ackoff, Russell L.On Learning and the Systems that Facilitate It. Reflections, Aug 1999, Vol. 1 No. 1, 14-25. Adler, Mortimer J., Ed. in Chief. (1952). Wisdom. The Great Ideas: A Syntopicon of Great Books of the Western World, Vol. II. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica. 1102-1117. Adler, Mortimer J. (n.d.—still looking for this information). Modern Science and Ancient Wis- dom. The Radical Academy website. <http://radicalacademy.com/adlersciwisdom.htm>. 3/21/2005. Ahearn, Frederick L., Ed. 2001. Issues in Global Aging. New York: Haworth Press. Ahern. Gregory S. (1991). Virtue, Wisdom, Experience, Not Abstract Rights, Form the Basis of the American Republic.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue Ethics in the Contemporary Social and Political Realm Sean Cordell Submitted for the Degree of Phd, February 2010. Depart
    Virtue Ethics in the Contemporary Social and Political Realm Sean Cordell Submitted for the degree of PhD, February 2010. Department of Philosophy, University of Sheffield. 1 Abstract This thesis concerns the problem of applying the ideas developed in contemporary virtue ethics to political philosophy. The core of the problem, explained in the opening chapters, is that assessment of right action offered by virtue ethics - in terms of what 'the virtuous person' characteristically does or would do - is focused on individual persons, rather than political principles of government. Accordingly, interpretations of traditional Aristotelianism have struggled to accommodate the putative value of modern value pluralism and manifold conceptions of the 'good life', whilst liberal theories that employ virtue concepts fail to offer a political philosophy that is distinctly virtue ethical. Rather than trying to fit individualistic virtue ethics to political theory in these ways, subsequent chapters start from the viewpoint of individuals and look outward to their social and political environment, arguing that an adequately socio-political virtue ethics requires, and suits, an ethics of social roles. Various virtue ethical approaches to roles, however, fail in different ways to determine what it means to act virtuously in such a role. In response, it is argued that virtue ethics needs a normative account of what specific role-determining institutions should be like. The possibilities for the Aristotelian ergon - function or 'characteristic activity' - serving as a normative criterion for a good institution of its kind are discussed and modified, leading to a positive account of institutional ergon that links the primary function of an institution with the specific and distinct human good or goods that it serves.
    [Show full text]
  • FACING the PROBLEM of ETHICAL SOLIPSISM Sami Pihlström
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 GUILT: FACING THE PROBLEM OF ETHICAL SOLIPSISM Sami Pihlström ABSTRACT: This article deals with the constitutive role played by the emotion of guilt, or the capacity of experiencing such emotions, in our moral life. The deeply personal nature of moral guilt (or remorse) leads to the problem of ethical solipsism: it seems that guilt can in the end concern only me, not anyone else, in a morally profound sense. Echoing Dostoevsky, the truly ethical thinker ought to acknowledge that everyone is guilty in front of the entire mankind, “and I more than anyone else”. This problematic feature of our moral perspectives on the world is examined through comments on a number of authors, including Kant, Wittgenstein, Levinas, Gaita, and Todorov. While we do need to avoid solipsism, there is a “truth” hidden in it: morality is something that we are individually and personally deeply responsible for. 1 Immanuel Kant remarks, in a famous footnote to the First Critique, that [t]he real morality of actions (their merit and guilt), even that of our own conduct […] remains entirely hidden from us. Our imputations can be referred only to the empirical character. How much of it is to be ascribed to mere nature […] no one can discover, and hence no one can judge it with complete justice.1 Although commentators have drawn attention to this important passage,2 its full significance still deserves substantial consideration. So does the significance of another famous Kantian remark, according to which, for each one of us, “the depths of his own heart (the subjective first grounds of his maxims) are to him inscrutable”.3 1 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans.
    [Show full text]