T Max M. Ward H O U GCRIME

H Ideology & State Power in Interwar T THOUGHT CRIME T H O U G H asia pacific Asia-­Pacific Culture, Politics, and Society Editors: Rey Chow, Michael Dutton, H. D. Harootunian, and Rosalind C. Morris A Study of the Weatherhead East Asian Institute, Columbia University T T Max M. Ward H O U G H CRIME T Ideology and State Power in Interwar Japan

Duke University Press Durham and London 2019 © 2019 duke university press. All rights reserved Printed in the United States of Amer­i­ca on acid-­free paper ∞ Designed by Courtney Baker Typeset in Arno pro by Westchester Publishing Services

Library of Congress Cataloging-­in-­Publication Data Names: Ward, Max M., [date] author. Title: Thought crime : ideology and state power in interwar Japan / Max M. Ward. Description: Durham : Duke University Press, 2019. | Series: Asia Pacific | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: lccn 2018031281 (print) | lccn 2018038062 (ebook) isbn 9781478002741 (ebook) isbn 9781478001317 (hardcover : alk. paper) isbn 9781478001652 (pbk. : alk. paper) Subjects: lcsh: Lese majesty—­Law and legislation—­Japan—­ History—20th ­century. | Po­litical­ crimes and offenses—­Japan—­ History—20th ­century. | Japan—­Politics and government— 1926–1945. | Japan—­Politics and government—1912–1945. | Japan—­History—1912–1945. Classification: lcc knx4438 (ebook) | lcc knx4438 .w37 2019 (print) lc rec­ord available at https://­lccn​.­loc.​ ­gov​/­2018031281

Cover art: Newspaper clippings from the Yomiuri Shimbun, 1925-1938. Courtesy of the Yomiuri Shimbun. Dedicated to the punks, in the streets and the ivory towers contents

Preface: Policing Ideological Threats, Then and Now ix

Acknowl­edgments xv introduction. The Ghost in the Machine:Emperor System Ideology and the Peace Preservation Law Apparatus ​1

1. Kokutai and the Aporias of Imperial Sovereignty: The Passage of the Peace Preservation Law in 1925 ​21

2. Transcriptions of Power: Repression and Rehabilitation in the Early Peace Preservation Law Apparatus, 1925–1933 ​49

3. Apparatuses of Subjection: The Rehabilitation of Thought Criminals in the Early 1930s ​77

4. Nurturing the Ideological Avowal: ­ Toward the Codification of Tenkō in 1936 ​113

5. The Ideology of Conversion: Tenkō on the Eve of Total War ​145 epilogue. The Legacies of the Thought Rehabilitation System in Postwar Japan 179

Notes ​185 Bibliography ​261 Index 281 Preface. Policing Ideological Threats, Then and Now

In Thought Crime, I analyze the transformations of an interwar Japa­nese an- tiradical law called the Peace Preservation Law (Chianijihō), from its initial passage to suppress and anticolonial nationalism in 1925, to its expansion in the 1930s into an elaborate system to “ideologically convert” (tenkō) and rehabilitate thousands of po­liti­cal criminals throughout the Japa­ nese Empire, to how the law’s rehabilitation policies provided a model for mobilizing the populations of the Japa­nese Empire for total war in the 1940s. I am particularly interested in how the law provides a well-­documented ex- ample of how a modern state deployed a combination of repression and re- habilitation when policing po­liti­cal threats (real or ­imagined), as well as how such efforts reveal the under­lying ideology par­tic­u­lar to the prewar Japa­nese imperial state. My interest in the Peace Preservation Law is therefore two- fold. First, I want to intervene in the defining historical debates over the na- ture of the prewar imperial state and the consolidation of fascism in Japan during the interwar period. Second, I utilize the par­tic­u­lar history of the Peace Preservation Law in order to consider the vari­ous modes of power that states, not just the interwar Japa­nese state, use to police po­liti­cal threats, thus reproducing and redefining their respective national polities in the pro­cess. This latter aspect of my proj­ect became particularly clear to me as I was finishing this book while on sabbatical in in 2015–2016. I would often take breaks from reading arcane interwar Japa­nese Justice Ministry reports by catching up on the latest international news. One par­tic­u­lar news story caught my attention: the arrest of young Somali American men in Minneap- olis, Minnesota, for allegedly trying to join isil in Syria.1 Within the context of the United States’ perpetual state of exception called the war on terror, I was not necessarily surprised by the­ se arrests.2 However, what was especially intriguing was how the Minneapolis case was being framed by a discourse of the radicalization of ideologies from abroad, and how the district court in Minneapolis was considering ways to assess the defendants’ degree of radicalization.3 ­These aspects resonated with what I was reading in Japa­nese documents from the 1920s and 1930s, when justice officials described domes- tic radical politics as the result of dangerous “foreign ideas” (gairai shisō) “in- filtrating” sennyū( ) the Japa­nese Empire and infecting it from within. ­These foreign ideas, it was said, turned imperial Japa­nese subjects into internal agents of a foreign ­enemy (­here, the Soviet Union). Explained in this way, communism, anticolonial nationalism, and other ideologies ­were defined as “thought crime” (shisō hanzai), and by the 1930s, the Japa­nese state had es- tablished an extensive security apparatus to identify, assess, and ultimately rehabilitate thousands of so-­called thought criminals (shisō hannin). ­Today, this logic of external ideas producing internal enemies can be found in the discourse of homegrown terrorism, wherein foreign jihadist ideology ostensibly radicalizes citizens or recent immigrants in Eur­ope and the United States so that they carry out the objectives of foreign enemies. Of course, the sociohistorical contexts and politico-­ideological content of ­these two cases are extremely dif­fer­ent. However, I was struck by the dis- cursive similarities in how the two states defined their respective threats as, essentially, external ideas that ­were/are infecting their respective national polities, and how such a notion allowed the two states to generate fear and mobilize their populations. In par­tic­ul­ar, I became interested in the way such a definition authorized both states to diffuse their policing powers into com- munities, bringing together police, courts, prison officials, families, reli- gious institutions, educators, and employers to assist with reforming thos­ e believed to have been led astray by dangerous foreign ideas. Indeed, at the time of this writing, many Japa­nese ­legal scholars are expressing strong criti- cism of the ­legal reinterpretations being carried out by the cabinet of prime minister Abe Shinzō in the name of the war on terror and national defense, pointing to similarities with prewar le­ gal developments, and the Peace Pres- ervation Law in partic­ u­ ­lar. 4 In both cases, state officials envisioned systems that, with collaboration from the local community, would monitor, assess, and rehabilitate ­those be- lieved to be harboring dangerous ideas. In Japan, this system was actualized in a network of so-­called Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision Cen- ters (Shisōhan hogo kansatsu sho) in 1936. Although much more cursory and experimental than the prewar Japa­nese example, the Minneapolis District Court created a Terrorism Disengagement and Deradicalization Program in March 2016.5 The first step in this new program was to assess the degree of a defendant’s radicalization upon arrest so as to determine a sentence appropri- ate to the level of danger the defendant ostensibly posed. For example, a x Preface Minneapolis district judge, Michael Davis, hired Daniel Koehler of the Ger- man Institute on Radicalization and Deradicalization Studies (girds) to evaluate the degree of radicalization of four out of the nine defendants before they ­were sentenced.6 The MinneapolisStar Tribune summarized Koehler’s charge as to “identify the fa­ ctors that drove the radicalization of the defen- dants, identify their risk of reoffending and specify strategies to steer them away from radical ideologies.”7 As we ­will see in Thought Crime, Koehler’s charge echoes interwar Japa­nese Justice Ministry materials that instructed court procurators (kenji) to assess the danger posed by so-­called thought criminals before their formal indictment or sentencing. Similar to Koehler, Japa­nese procurators produced official reportsjōshinsho ( ) on each thought criminal, assessing the degree of a defendant’s commitment to communist internationalism or anticolonial nationalism, and their potential to be rehabili- tated through a multistage program of ideological conversion (tenkō). In both cases, ideas became the target of inquiry. For example, Koehler explained that his evaluations would assess “if the­ se thoughts and ideas [i.e., jihad] actually determined this be­hav­ior and . . . ​led them to the point where they did something illegal.”8 The Minneapolis defendants had already been found guilty of conspiring to join isil. Thus Koehler’s task was to interrogate the ideas motivating the defendants’ actions in order to assess their reformabil- ity for sentencing.9 Ultimately, Minnesota chief US probation officer Kevin Lowry summarized the objective of this program in this way, using rhe­toric that could have come from the interwar Japa­nese example: “If a radicalized defendant or offender is not properly treated, theyw­ ill continue to infect our communities . . . ​and ­they’ll look to harm the community and martyr themselves if [­they’re not treated] with a balance between rehabilitation and public safety.”10 ­Here the radicalized defendants in Minneapolis embodied the danger of dangerous ideas spreading in their communities, and thus we can imagine that authorities would extend their balance between “rehabilita- tion and public safety” beyond pretrial interventions into postparole reform programs and preemptive monitoring to locate ­others who might be suscep- tible to becoming, in Lowry’s terminology, “infected” by such ideas. The Japa­nese interwar state similarly policed suspects by identifying the ideas that determined a communist’s motives for joining the illegal Japa­nese Communist Party (jcp). In prewar Japan, conventional vio­lence such as riot or lèse-­majesté ­were already criminalized unde­ r the Civil Code or earlier antiradical laws such as the 1900 Public Peace Police Law (Chian keisatsu hō), which set strict par­ameters for po­liti­cal expression, publication, assem- bly, and activities. The 1925 Peace Preservation Law, in contrast, defined a

Preface xi criminal infringement as forming or joining an organi­zation with the objec- tive to “alter the national polity” (kokutai o henkaku) or “reject the private property system” (shiyūzaisan seido o hinin). In both the Japa­nese and US ex- amples, the criminal act was primarily attempting to join an organi­zation, and the burden for procurators and judges was to determine a defendant’s com- mitment to the ideas that motivated him or her to allegedly join or support such groups. As one prominent justice official explained in regard to the Japa­ nese Peace Preservation Law: “The peculiarity of this law is that it makes acts based on certain practical thoughts the object of punishment. The thoughts in thought crimes are not . . . ​theoretical, abstract thoughts, but practical, con- crete thoughts.”11 Furthermore, in both cases, ­these pre-­sentencing ideologi- cal assessments would decide if defendants received a prison sentence or w­ ere paroled into programs where they could be, in ­today’s parlance, deradicalized. Koehler told reporters that his risk assessments would anticipate what to do with the Minneapolis defendants “when they get out [of prison]” a­fter serving their sentences.12 This latter concern also dominated the discussions at Japa­nese Justice Ministry conferences in the mid-1930s, as Japa­nese officials worried that many incarcerated communists would soon complete prison sentences they ­were given in the late 1920s or early 1930s. ­These concerns over ideological recidivism (saihan) led Japa­nese officials in 1936 to establish the system of Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision Centers men- tioned earlier, which coordinated between prisons, prosecutors, community leaders, employers, ­family members, and othe­ rs to assist thought criminals to secure their ideological conversions while they transitioned back to society. Indeed, early in the Minneapolis investigations, the district court considered probation programs to deal with apprehended terror suspects who showed potential for reform.13 In one case, a young man was temporarily released to a halfway ­house before his trial started.14 ­There he received support from a nonprofit community organ­ization which, as the Star Tribune reported, con- nected him with “a team of religious scholars, teachers and other mentors” in order to assess his potential for deradicalization and resocialization.15 In the end, however, District Judge Davis did not expand upon this reha- bilitation experiment. Rather, citing the difficulty of balancing a defendant’s rehabilitation with public safety, Davis ultimately emphasized public safety.16 He sentenced the nine suspects to a range of jail terms—the­ harshest being thirty-­five years in jail, with two othe­ rs receiving thirty-­year prison sen- tences. Only the young man temporarily released to a halfway hous­ e men- tioned above was granted time served for turning state’s witness, and given twenty years of supervised release.17 xii Preface Many ­people involved in counterterrorism in the United States w­ ere watching the Minneapolis case closely.18 The Department of Homeland Security unde­ r the Obama administration had created a counterterrorism program two years earlier in 2014 called the Countering Violent Extremism (cve) program, with pi­lot programs targeting primarily Muslim and im- migrant communities in Boston, Minneapolis, and Los Angeles.19 Thecve program was designed to collaborate with community groups, families, and schools to identify individuals at risk for becoming terrorists, and would pro- vide community and religious ser­vices to c­ounter the appeal of radical ide- ologies. Almost immediately, the cve program was critiqued for stigmatizing Muslim communities, as well as for attempting to turn educators and religious leaders into infor­ ­mants for the state.20 Similar criticisms ­were directed at the Minneapolis Terrorism Disengagement and Deradicalization Program.21 De- spite the­ se criticisms, the Minneapolis program was the first of its kind to so closely assess the beliefs of defendants and to consider methods for deradi- calization. Officials­w ere thus watching the Minneapolis case for aspects that could be incorporated into the national cve program. Following Donald Trump’s election in November 2016 and his promise to take a hard line with suspected terrorists, it is doubtful that the­ se kinds of soft approaches to preventing terrorism ­will be expanded in the US.22 In- deed, in July 2017 the Department of Homeland Security informed vari­ous community organ­izations working to rehabilitate radicals—­both alleged jihadists and white supremacists—­that they would no longer receive fund- ing from the department.23 However, before we celebrate the Obama admin- istration’s approach as a lighter, more community-­oriented way to c­ounter radicalization, we should recognize that, in addition to the community criticisms of the cve program mentioned earlier, the Obama administration escalated targeted drone strikes in Yemen and elsewhere, often killing civil- ians and radicalized American jihadists without the due proc­ ess guaranteed ­under the Fourteenth Amendment of the US Constitution.24 Furthermore, the Obama administration failed to fulfill a campaign promise to close the Guan- tánamo Bay detention camp, one of the most notorious examples of the US’s deployment of extrajudicial repression in its war on terror. Indeed, the Trump administration has broken with convention and is, at the time of this writing, trying individuals in civilian court who have allegedly committed or planning acts of terror, rather than designating them e­ nemy combatants and sending them to Guantánamo Bay.25 In many cases, the Trump administra- tion is enacting policies that go explic­itly against his earlier campaign rhe­ toric of getting tough with terrorists. Ultimately, we should recognize that

Preface xiii the discourse of radicalization legitimated, and continues to legitimate, both repression and rehabilitation, even as the balance between the­ se two shifts between administrations and their rhe­toric on how to adequately deal with so-­called homegrown terrorists. To be clear, the question that I pursue in Thought Crime is not w­ hether repression or rehabilitation is the more effective approach to combat domes- tic radicals. Rather, I am interested in how, at par­tic­u­lar historical conjunc- tures, states define po­liti­cal threats as essentially ideological and foreign in nature, and how such definitions provide the conditions for states to experi- ment with dif­fer­ent combinations of repression and rehabilitation. Ultimately, I am interested in what kinds of policing methods such a definition informs, and how communities are brought within campaigns to ostensibly eradicate ideological influences. Furthermore, I believe such experiments reveal more about the under­lying ideologies informing the varying modes of power that a state deploys than they do about the purported threats they are meant to combat, ­whether we are discussing the prewar Japa­nese imperial state’s inter- war thought crime policy or the United States’ war on terror.26 Thus, as I was completing this book in Tokyo in 2015–2016, I found myself conducting a kind of parallax analy­sis, si­mult­a­neously reading historical documents related to the prewar Japa­nese thought crime system and con­ temporary news reports on the United States’ cve experiments with deradi- calization. I hope that Thought Crime, in addition to contributing to the historical lit­er­a­ture on interwar Japan, can also provide a historical vantage point from which we can consider our own con­temporary moment, and what the current discourse of radicalization might reveal about the ideology under- writing the endless war on terror.

xiv Preface acknowl­edgments

Over the past de­cade, I have received support from many individuals and institutions. My advisers at New York University cultivated my apprecia- tion for the necessity and challenges of critical historical thinking: first and foremost Harry Harootunian, whose generosity and critical acumen remain a source of inspiration. Rebecca Karl constantly pushed me to refine my questions and ideas. Tom Looser taught me how to read texts with attention to the po­liti­cal and theoretical demands of the con­temporary moment. At Waseda University, Umemori Naoyuki provided invaluable support over the years. I thank him and his gradu­ate students for their suggestions and criti- cisms on this proj­ect as it developed. I also thank my undergraduate teachers at uc Berkeley for nurturing my interest in both interwar radical politics and East Asian history, including Margaret Anderson, Andrew Barshay, Alan Tansman, and, in par­tic­ul­ar, Irwin Scheiner. I have many ­people to thank for helping me refine and improve the man- uscript. Takashi Fujitani, Katsuya Hirano, and Louise Young offered sharp criticisms of the manuscript at a workshop sponsored by the President’s Office and the Rohatyn Center for Global Affairs at Middlebury College in January 2017. Colleagues who participated, including Maggie Clinton, Darién Davis, Joyce Mao, Tamar Mayer, Sujata Moorti, Jacob Tropp, Linda White, and Don Wyatt, deserve special thanks. Over the years, friends have kindly read portions of this manuscript and supported my work more generally, in par­tic­u­lar Brian Hurley, Phil Kaffen, Namiko Kunimoto, Matsusaka Hiroaki, Nakano Osamu, Mark Roberts, Viren Murthy, and Robert Stolz. Construc- tive feedback offered at conferences, workshops, and reading groups have helped shape my thinking about many of the prob­lems pursued in the book. I especially thank Catherine Ashcraft, Michael Bourdaghs, Adam Bronson, Kyeong-­Hee Choi, James Dorsey, Mark Driscoll, Robert Eskildsen, Erik Es- selstrom, Clinton Godard, Tom Fenton, Irena Hayter, Reto Hofmann, Ken Kawashima, Aaron S. Moore, Ryan Moran, Alexis Peri, John Person, Leslie Pincus, Stefan Tanaka, Robert Tierney, Gavin Walker, and Mark Williams. Over the years I have also benefited from conversations with Emily Ander- son, Noriko Aso, Deokhyo Choi, Jeff DuBois, Ellery Foutch, Kawamura Sa- tofumi, Robin Kietlinski, Takeshi Kimoto, Elena Lange, George Lazopoulos, Ricky Law, Joyce Liu, Ethan Mark, William Marotti, Wendy Matsumura, Shota Ogawa, Jonas Prida, Yukiko Shigeto, Ken Shima, Kunihiko Terasawa, Brian Tsui, Nori Tsuneishi, Benjamin Uchiyama, Christian Uhl, and Jack Wilson. I am especially grateful for the generous comments and suggestions provided by the reviewers for Duke University Press, which have helped shape this book in significant ways. Ken Wissoker and Olivia Polk at Duke University Press supported and shepherded me through the publication proc­ ess. I thank them and ­others at Duke University Press who helped prepare the manuscript for publication, including Sara Leone, Julie Thomson, Christopher Robinson and, for copy- editing, Karen Fisher. Carol Gluck and Ross Yelsey of the Weatherhead East Asian Institute believed in this proj­ect in its early stages. Research for this book has been supported by an Advanced Social Science Research Fellow- ship from the National Endowment for the Humanities, Japan-­US Friend- ship Commission, a research fellowship from the Japan Foundation, the Northeast Asia Council of the aas, Fulbright iie, and by Middlebury Col- lege. I thank the vari­ous forums that provided me the opportunity to pres­ent my research as it developed, including the School of Languages, Cultures and Socie­ties at the University of Leeds, East Asia Center at the University of ­Virginia, Institute of Japa­nese Studies at The Ohio State University, the Rohatyn Center for Global Affairs at Middlebury College, Center for Japa­nese Religions and Cultures at University of Southern California, Center for East Asian Studies at the University of Chicago, Center of Japa­nese Studies at University of Michigan, the University of Tokyo Center for Philosophy, Cen- ter of East Asian Research at McGill University, as well as the Association of Asian Studies, American Historical Association, Asian Studies Conference Japan, British Association of Japa­nese Studies, Social Science History Asso- ciation, the Modern Japa­nese History Workshop at Waseda University and the Kyoto Asian Studies Group, among othe­ rs. I would also like to thank the faculty at the Inter-­University Center for Japa­nese Language Studies, and in par­tic­u­lar Kushida Kiyomi for her patience and dedication to my language learning. The majority of the materials used in this study are archived in the Japa­nese Library in Tokyo, Waseda University Library, and the Ōhara Institute for Social Research at Hosei University. I would like to thank xvi Acknowl­edgments ­these libraries and their staff, as well as Rachel Manning and the staff of Mid- dlebury College’s Interlibrary Loan office, for their assistance in acquiring materials during the final stages of revising the manuscript. I am fortunate to have supportive and generous colleagues in the History and Japa­nese Studies departments at Middlebury College, and I thank my friends and colleagues for welcoming me into their homes, including Jamie McCallum, Erin Davis and Asa, Febe Armanios, Boğaç Ergene, Maggie Clin- ton, Roger White and Lenni, Adam, Elana and Naomi Dean, Steve Snyder, Linda White, Jonas Prida, Marshall Highet, Kian and Brylea, and in Burling- ton, Haley Renwick, Julian Hackney, Joy Snow, and Samantha van Gerbig. In Tokyo, I thank Osamu, Aya, and Riko-­chan, as well as the Yoshida fa­ mily. I especially look forward to taking many walks with Motoko Jumonji now that this manuscript is complete. I thank John at Carol’s Hungry Mind and Haley at Speeder and Earl’s for keeping me caffeinated. Thanks also to Hayakawa Yugo of Okinawa Shokudō for the delicious food and engaging conversation over the years. During my time in New York City, I was encouraged and supported by a number of teachers and students at nyu and beyond, including Ramona Beltran, Sasha Disko, Feng Miao, Manu Goswami, Greg Grandin, Jane Hay- ward, Franz Hofer, Marilyn Ivy, Jennifer Lee, Soonyi Lee, Andy Liu, Pat- rick Noonan, Lisa Onaga, Hyun Ok Park, Janet Poole, Moss Roberts, Paul Roquet, Nate Shockey, Dexter Thomas, Christophe Thouny, Keith Vincent, Lorraine Wong, Timothy Yang, Marilyn Young, and Qian Zhu. On the picket line I was inspired by my comrades of gsoc/uaw 2110, members of Faculty Democracy, and the wider gradu­ate student ­union movement that supported us during our strike in 2005–2006. Last, I thank my ­mother, Nancy, and late ­father, William, for uncondition- ally supporting my endeavors over the past four de­cades including m­ usic, activism, and academia; my si­ ster Michele for inspiring me with her strength and resilience; and to the international diy punk scene, including my prior bandmates, for continuing to demonstrate that alternative forms of commu- nity are pos­si­ble. Up the punks.

Parts of chapters have been published elsewhere: portions of the introduc- tion and chapter 3 pertaining to Louis Althusser’s theory of Ideological State Apparatuses are derived from “Ideology and Subjection in Ōshima Nagisa’s Kōshikei (1968)” in “Perspectives on Ōshima Nagisa,” utcp-Uehiro­ Pamphlet, no. 7 (2015). Sections on the idea of thought war in chapter 5 come from

Acknowl­edgments xvii “Displaying the Worldview of Japa­nese Fascism: The Tokyo Thought War Exhibition of 1938,” Critical Asian Studies 47, no. 3 (Sept. 2015); “Crisis Ideol- ogy and the Articulation of Fascism in Interwar Japan: The 1938 Thought War Symposium,” Japan Forum 26, no. 4 (December 2014).

xviii Acknowl­edgments introduction

The Ghost in the Machine:Emperor System Ideology and the Peace Preservation Law Apparatus

In early 1938, Hirata Isao, the director of the newly established Tokyo Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision Center (Tōkyō shisōhan hogo kansatsu sho), stood before a group of military officers and other of- ficials to promote the Japa­nese Justice Ministry’s decade-lon­ g effort to sup- press domestic communists. Hirata was a key architect of the imperial state’s anticommunist policies: he helped or­ga­nize the first major roundups of sus- pected communists ­under the 1925 Peace Preservation Law (Chianijihō) in 1928 and 1929, assisted in the prosecution of central committee members of the Japa­nese Communist Party (jcp) in a high-pr­ ofile trial in 1931–1932, and experimented with urging incarcerated communists to defect from the jcp in the early 1930s with some success.1 This latter experiment developed into the official policy of ideological conversiontenkō ( ) in 1936, which Hirata and ­others w­ ere now implementing in the empire-w­ ide network of Protec- tion and Supervision Centers. Hirata most likely recognized that many in the audience ­were ardent anticommunists and thus would be suspicious of any leniency ­toward incarcerated or paroled po­liti­cal criminals. Indeed, in its 1927 The­ ses, the jcp advocated to “abolish the emperor system” (kunshusei haishi)—th­ at is, the essence of the imperial state—as a central objective for communist revolution in Japan.2 However, Hirata not only defended the re- habilitation of communists but he also argued that their ideological conver- sion provided a model for the spiritual purification and mobilization of the Japa ­nese Empire, particularly ­after Japan’s invasion of China in July 1937 (the so-­called China Incident). In his speech, titled “Overcoming Marxism” (“Marukishizumu no koku- fuku”), Hirata tailored his comments to the military officials in the audience by equating the swift arrests of domestic communists with the Imperial Army’s sweeping military victories in China, and compared the po­liti­cal reform policies he was overseeing in the Tokyo Protection and Supervision Center with the Imperial Army’s pacification of the Chinese population in occupied territories. In what he referred to as a thought war (shisōsen) raging through- out East Asia and the world, Hirata explained that he and his fellow thought reform officials­ were ­doing work similar to the pacification units senbun-( han) in occupied China. He emphasized that instead of punitive repression and punishment, thought reform officers w­ ere benevolently guiding detain- ees through the conversion proc­ ess ­toward a self-­awakening (jikaku) as true Japa­nese (hontō no nihonjin). He celebrated the fact that many of the com- munists who reformed ­under the guidance of the Protection and Supervi- sion Centers w­ ere now demonstrating their loyalty to the empire through productive ­labor in society. The underly­ ing princi­ple of the­ se centers, Hirata argued, was imperial benevolence, which exemplified how criminal reform was the institutional expression of the unique “Japa­nese spirit within the Jus- tice Ministry system,” a spirit that was also guiding the military campaigns in China.3 Hirata concluded his lecture by presenting the ex-­communist ideo- logical convert, or tenkōsha, as a model for a renovated and mobilized Japan, arguing, “The ­people who should effect tenkō are not only ­those defendants from the Communist Party, that is, the thought-­criminals, but we—thi­ s may be rude to say—we, from ­here forward, must [also] carry out a ­grand tenkō.” 4 Indeed, Hirata was attempting to refigure a policy initially developed to suppress and eradicate communism and anticolonial nationalism from the Japa­nese Empire into a general princip­ le for the spiritual mobilization of the empire for the war effort in China. A de­cade earlier, such a claim would have been unthinkable. In the 1920s, state officials warned about the infiltrationsennyū ( ) of dangerous foreign ideologies into the empire and the need to eradicate such ideologies before they poisoned the national polity (kokutai) from within. For them, domestic communists and other po­liti­cal radicals embodied this foreign ideological threat, a threat that needed to be extracted from society and imprisoned so as to contain its spread.5 Now, in 1938, one of the key architects of the state’s anticommunism campaign presented reformed ex-­communists as exem- plars for all imperial subjects to follow. In this refiguring, Hirata portrayed

2 Introduction the parole of reformed ex-­communists as a means to purify the local com- munity from dangerous Western influences. This vision of using converts to shore up the nation’s spiritual resolve dovetailed with and informed war­time campaigns such as the National Spirit Mobilization Movement (Kokumin seishin sōdōin undō) that ­were created to mobilize the general populace for total war.6 What allowed Hirata Isao and other justice officials to promote the re- formed ex-­communist as a model for all imperial subjects to emulate in the late 1930s? How did state policies targeting communists and other po­litical­ radicals evolve from suppression and incarceration in the 1920s, to include rehabilitation, conversion, and parole in the 1930s? Most impor­tant, what do ­these transformations reveal about imperial state ideology and its relation- ship to the transforming modes of state power during the interwar period? Thought Crime explores the­ se questions by reading the interwar Japa­nese state’s po­liti­cal crime policies as an index of imperial state ideology—­first and foremost, the ideology of imperial sovereignty and the relationship between sovereign and subject—­and how this ideology informed and trans- formed within the expanding apparatus to police po­liti­cal crime in the 1930s. I recuperate what English-l­anguage scholars once referred to as Japan’s pre- war emperor system (tennōsei) and ­will read the Peace Preservation Law as an extensive security apparatus that formed one impor­tant component of that system, both institutionally and ideologically.7 I utilize the meta­phor of the ghost in the machine to emphasize the dynamic relationship between the ideology of the imperial sovereign (the ghost as it ­were) that both informed, and was itself refined and disseminated through, the expanding institutional apparatus (the machine) to police po­liti­cal criminals in the Japa­nese Empire during the 1930s. Before elaborating this meta­phor, however, it is first neces- sary to review previous scholarship on the Peace Preservation Law in order to clarify the critical-­theoretical intervention that I hope to make in our un- derstanding of the interwar period in Japan.

The Peace Preservation Law as History The Japa­nese state’s thought reform policy developed from a notorious anti- radical law called the Peace Preservation Law (Chianijihō).8 Passed in 1925, this law was utilized to arrest over seventy thousand ­people in the Japa­nese metropole and tens of thousands more in Japan’s colony of colonial ­Korea, ­until repealed by Allied Occupation authorities in October 1945.9 The law was initially proposed as a le­ gal instrument to suppress domestic communists

Introduction 3 and anticolonial activists that ­were said to be threatening imperial sover- eignty, but in the 1930s the law was extended to other academic, po­liti­cal, and religious groups who ­were seen as challenging imperial orthodoxy. Not only was the purview of the law expanded, but the policies that w­ ere developed for administering the law transformed and intensified. By the late 1930s, the law had become a complex institutional apparatus for the continuing sur- veillance, assessment, reform, and ultimately ideological conversion—or tenkō—of po­liti­cal criminals, informed by the ideology of the loyal imperial subject. For ­these reasons, the law’s extension and increasing institutional com- plexity provides a unique archive in which to study the prewar imperial state and its transformations in the 1930s. In conventional scholarship, the Peace Preservation Law is commonly portrayed as an explicit instrument of repression used by the prewar emperor system against progressive social forces.10 That the law was an instrument of repression is, of course, undeni- able, but such a characterization implies that the law was clearly understood by state officials and implemented in a uniform manner across the Japa­nese Empire over its twenty-­year history. As I demonstrate in Thought Crime, of- ficials continually questioned how to interpret the law’s central categories and experimented with dif­fer­ent policies based on the changing po­liti­cal circumstances in the Japa­nese Empire.11 Nor does the conventional repres- sion thesis adequately explain the logic that informed the l­ater rehabilita- tion policies such as ideological conversion. To be sure, in the early 1930s a detainee’s rehabilitation was initiated with po­liti­cal defection from the jcp, and thus officials understood recantation as one weapon in their arsenal to suppress communism. However, as I explore in ­later chapters, such experi- ments moved well beyond urging a detainee to merely defect, to encompass welfare ser­vices, spiritual guidance, employment training, ­family counseling, and the prolonged assessment of imperial loyalty for years ­after parole. Of- ficials continually explained this expanded rehabilitation system as reflecting the majesty of the august emperor and the benevolence of his imperial state ­toward wayward subjects, even as arrests continued. By the 1970s, scholars such as Okudaira Yasuhiro and Richard Mitchell recognized the complexity of the law, and started to reveal the interministe- rial debates between the Home and Justice Ministries, as well as how the law included both repressive and reform meas­ ures, what Mitchell referred to as an expression of Japan’s unique “Janus-­faced” form of justice.12 Okudaira approached this complexity through a normative understanding of modern jurisprudence, explaining that, by including the term “kokutai” (national

4 Introduction polity or essence) in the Peace Preservation Law (wherein the central in- fringement of the law was joining or forming an organi­zation that sought to “alter the kokutai”), legislators had contaminated (konkō) the realm of ­legal rationality with an extra-jur­ idical term with sentimental (jōchoteki) as- sociations.13 Area studies scholars translated this binary into the moderniza- tion theory paradigm, in which this juridical excess was explained as a vestige of traditional Japa­nese culture continuing into, and conflicting with, modern Western institutions.14 Consequently, in the area studies lit­er­a­ture, the Peace Preservation Law was explained as having incorporated specifically Japa­nese cultural ele­ments (symbolized in the term kokutai), forming a uniquely Japa­ nese way of dealing with the po­liti­cal tumult that attends modernization.15 Such cultural explanations of the Peace Preservation Law reinforce a more general characterization that the modern imperial state implemented a par­ tic­ul­ar Japa­nese form of governance dating back to the Tokugawa period (1603–1868), what Sheldon Garon has identified in the discourse of “moral suasion” (kyōka).16 Certainly, the imperial state legitimated the suppression of po­liti­cal activ- ists as protecting Japan’s timeless cultural traditions or, ­later, celebrated its rehabilitation policies as expressions of Japan’s unique imperial benevolence ­toward wayward subjects. However, we should not confuse the rhe­toric of ­these cultural claims with the ideological forms through which the imperial state exercised its power, for when we do, our analytical explanations rep- licate the very claims that officials used to legitimize ­these policies.17 As I argue in Thought Crime, in essence, the Japa­nese campaigns to suppress and rehabilitate po­liti­cal criminals ­were based on modes of power that vari­ous modern states utilize in periods of po­liti­cal crisis, including attempts to guide social morality and be­hav­ior. Emphasizing the ideological forms and modes of state power that con- stituted the interwar security apparatus, Thought Crime argues that the complexities of the Peace Preservation Law need to be understood, not as cultural or extrajuridical effects, but as articulations of the ideological foun- dations of the imperial state within the realm of law and penal policy—­first and foremost, of the august emperor, which grounded the logics of both repression and rehabilitation. Imperial sovereignty was the penultimate object to be defended from ideological threats and, at the same time, the benevolent source from which to reform po­liti­cal criminals as loyal impe- rial subjects. The ideological nature of such campaigns becomes particularly apparent when we recognize that the Peace Preservation Law was applied si­mul­ta­neously across the dif­fer­ent ­legal systems of Japan’s colonial empire,

Introduction 5 raising questions about the extension of imperial sovereignty to the colonies, particularly to colonial Kor­ ea, as well as how to l­ater reform colonial activists as imperial subjects.18 Thought Crime draws upon the recent work conducted by Mizuno Naoki, Hong Jong-­wook, and othe­ rs in order to reveal the dif­fer­ ent articulations of imperial ideology and modalities of state power between the Japa­nese metropole and colonial ­Korea.19 In this regard, Thought Crime reads the Peace Preservation Law as an index of the aporias of imperial state ideology and their dif­fer­ent articula- tions across the Japa­nese Empire during the 1920s and 1930s. Following Fredric Jameson’s distinction between contradiction and aporia, I am using the term “aporia” in order to emphasize the unresolvable nature of the para- doxes that constituted imperial sovereignty (both in theory and practice) as well as how the­ se aporias w­ ere generative within the field of state ideology and its institutionalization.20 As an index of the aporias of imperial ideology, the conceptualization and implementation of the Peace Preservation Law provides an impor­tant win­dow into the ideological transformations of the imperial state in the 1930s. The nature of the prewar state has been a central question for scholars of Japan: from Maruyama Masao’s early thesis that in prewar Japan all value was exteriorized into the emperor, allowing for the state to spread a “many-­ layered, though invisible, net over the Japa­nese pe­ ople,” to Fujita Shōzō’s analysi­ s of the emperor system as a dialectic between the par­tic­ul­ar insti- tutional forms of the imperial state and the princip­ les with which it ruled society, to Takeda Kiyoko and Walter Skya’s respective analyses of the double structure of the emperor system in which the oligarchs presented the emperor as both divine, mythical and absolute, and at the same time as a constitutional monarchy, what Takeda calls the enduring “dual image” of the emperor, and what Skya finds as the grounding problematic that informed prewar constitutional theory.21 While ­these studies focus largely on develop- ments at the state or constitutional level, other scholarship has explored how the emperor system was disseminated and reproduced at the level of society: from Carol Gluck’s groundbreaking work on the circulation of Meiji ideol- ogy at the local level, to Takashi Fujitani’s study of the symbolic construction of the emperor through public pageantry and the circulation of imperial im- agery, to Yoshimi Yoshiaki’s thesis of popul­ar “imperial consciousness” and “grassroots fascism” in the 1930s and 1940s, to Sheldon Garon’s research on how social ele­ments reciprocated, if not actively collaborated, with the state to manage certain social be­hav­iors and practices.22 And fi­nally, recent schol- arship has sought to understand the new modalities of power emerging in

6 Introduction the mid-­Meiji-­period prison and police systems, including Umemori Naoyu- ki’s pioneering research on the “colonial mediations” during the formation of the modern penal system, and Daniel Botsman’s study of the radical break that occurred in punishment between the late Tokugawa and mid-­Meiji periods.23 Thought Crime engages with this research by reading the Peace Preservation Law apparatus as indexing the transformations of imperial state ideology across the interwar period, as combining multiple modes of power in order to police po­liti­cal crime, and how the apparatus functioned to re- produce and circulate imperial ideology to the wider community through its ­later ideological conversion policy.24 My intervention in the historiography on the Peace Preservation Law and the prewar imperial state begins by drawing upon critical theories of state power and ideology in order to analyze the material practices through which imperial ideology was reproduced, transformed, and circulated in the 1930s. I contend that this type of critical-­theoretical approach reveals the general forms of state power operating in the par­tic­ul­ar historical circumstances of interwar Japan, and thus qualifies earlier studies that have portrayed the interwar state as manifesting traditional characteristics unique to Japa­nese statecraft. ­Toward this end, each chapter of Thought Crime is framed by a theoretical question related to state power and ideology, which informs an analy­sis of a specific development within the Peace Preservation Law over its twenty-­year history. At the same time, the Peace Preservation Law provides a rich historical archive in which to reflect on the limits or lacunae in specific theories of state power and ideology. Before outlining the chapters of Thought Crime, it is necessary, first, to ex- plain the meta­phorical through line of the ghost in the machine in regard to the prewar Japa­nese imperial state and, second, to elaborate how my analy­sis of the Peace Preservation Law is informed by critical theories of ideology, subjection, and state power.

The Tennōsei as Ghost in the Machine The sovereign power of reigning over and of governing the State, is inherited by the Emperor from His Ancestors, and by Him bequeathed to His posterity. All the dif­fer­ent legislative as well as executive powers of State, by means of which He reigns over the country and governs the ­people, are united in this Most Exalted Personage, who thus holds in His hands, as it w­ ere, all the ramifying threads of the po­liti­cal life of the coun- try, just as the brain, in the h­ uman body, is the primitive source of all me­ ntal activity manifested through the four limbs and the dif­fer­ent parts of the body. For unity is just as

Introduction 7 necessary in the government of a State, as double-­mindedness would be ruinous in an individual. —­itō hirobumi, commenting on the in 1889 I utilize the meta­phor of the ghost in the machine in order to analyze how the ideology of the emperor system (tennōsei) was articulated in, and trans- formed through, the institutional efforts to suppress and reform po­liti­cal criminals. The meta­phor of the ghost in the machine derives from Gilbert Ryle’s classic text The Concept of Mind (1949), in which Ryle attempted to subvert the Cartesian distinction/conjunction of mind and body, in which the mind, Ryle argued, is assumed to be a “spectral machine” inside the phys- ical body, an “interior governor-­engine” that animates the body, but obeys “laws . . . ​not known to ordinary engineers.”25 Ryle’s target was the concept of mind in philosophy, but tellingly, he made passing mention of Thomas Hobbes’s Cartesian conception of sovereignty in Leviathan (1651), in which the sovereign was to the commonwealth as the mind was to the parts of the body.26 Indeed, in the epigraph above, we see the recognized author of the 1889 Meiji Constitution, Itō Hirobumi, drawing upon this Cartesian analogy in order to explain imperial sovereignty as outlined in the 1889 Con- stitution and the supposed unity it brought to the new Meiji state.27 Ryle’s intention was not to reduce mind to ­matter or vice versa, but tof­ ree philoso- phy of the ideology of mind so that philosophy could elaborate a “correct logic of mental-­conduct concepts” appropriate to the “facts of ­mental life.”28 And yet, in the judgment of A. J. Ayer, although Ryle had “succeeded in reduc[ing] the empire of the mind over a considerable area” of philosophical inquiry, the “ghost . . . ​still walks, and some of us are still haunted by it.”29 Indeed, the meta­phor of the ghost in the machine was pop­u­lar­ized by Arthur Koestler, who, in a 1967 book that took the meta­phor as its title, argued that in “the very act of denying the existence of the ghost in the machine,” Ryle and ­others may “incur the risk of turning it into a very nasty, malevolent ghost.”30 Evidently, exorcising the ghost from philosophy proved to be more difficult than Ryle originally im­ agined, a paradox that was replicated as the meta­phor was extended to other disciplines in order to exorcise their own respective assumptions. Scholars in po­liti­cal theory have deployed the ghost in the machine meta­ phor in order to discard what they believe to be the analytical ambiguities produced by terms such as “sovereignty” and the “state.” In one well-­known example, David Easton critiqued state theory, which, in his estimation, fig- ured the state as “some kind of undefined and undefinable essence, a ‘ghost in the machine,’ knowable only through its variable manifestations.”31 The

8 Introduction issue for Easton was that the vari­ous proponents of the state, ­whether liberal, conservative, or Marxist, w­ ere all assuming that the­ re was a single, “easily identifiable” locus of authority or power that could be discerned in the wider field of po­liti­cal practice. He countered that his concept of “po­liti­cal system” took into consideration the complexity and diversity of the po­liti­cal field without having to rely on the assumption of a ghostly essence (i.e., the state) determining the field of po­liti­cal practice.32 However, Timothy Mitchell has countered that Easton and one could say by extension Ryle w­ ere asking the wrong question: before exorcising the ostensible ghost from their respective fields, they must first account for why the machine operates as if ­there was a ghost animating it.33 Mitchell argues that criticisms such as Easton’s “ignore the fact that this is how the state very often appears in practice. The task of a critique of the state is not just to reject such metaphysics, but to explain how it has been pos­si­ble to produce this practical effect, so characteristic of the modern po­liti­cal order.”34 Thought Crime is an attempt to understand how this metaphysics was produced through and animated the par­tic­u­lar policies and practices of the Peace Preservation Law apparatus.35 By using the meta­phor of the ghost in the machine, I seek to illuminate how the “practical effect” (Mitchell) of the sovereign emperor and the radiant Japa­nese spirit (nihon seishin) w­ ere reproduced, transformed, and dissemi- nated through the institutional practices of the Peace Preservation Law. As a kind of ghostly presence that was both ostensibly transcendent of secular politics and si­mul­ta­neously their sovereign origin, the august emperor was invoked in, firstly, the Diet deliberations over the use of kokutai (national polity or essence) in the 1925 Peace Preservation Law as something unde­ r existential threat from foreign ideologies, and then in the day-­to-­day inter- rogations, court decisions, and rehabilitation programs that constituted the administrative application of the Peace Preservation Law. In fact, two corol- lary ghosts ­were conjured in the operations of the Peace Preservation Law: the imperial sovereign that the law was protecting, and the imperial subject (shinmin) that reformed ex–­political criminals ­were to manifest during their rehabilitation.36 By the late 1930s, justice and police officials continuously in- voked the Japa­nese spirit as animating their institutional practices: as a 1940 thought police manual explained, the “prime mover of police power” (keisat- suryoku no chūshin dōryoku) was the “spirit of the police” which “elucidates [tōtetsu] the fundamental princip­ les of our kokutai.”37 Rather than dismiss- ing them, Thought Crime approaches such claims as revealing the imperial ideology that informed, and was transformed through, the institutional prac- tices of the Peace Preservation Law apparatus in the 1930s.

Introduction 9 To be clear, I am not arguing that hidden be­ hind the operations of the security apparatus was the active monarch at the helm of the state; rather, I am arguing that the security apparatus and, by extension, the imperial state, functioned as if the august sovereign was animating the security apparatus since he was continually referenced as the ostensible sovereign source of all imperial law as well as the object to be protected from political-ide­ ological threats. Nor am I arguing that detained communists ­were rehabilitated back to an original imperial subjectivity. Rather, I am arguing that, as so-­called ideological converts (tenkōsha) set out to confirm their conversions and find purposeful work in their communities, they drew upon established tropes of the Japa­nese spirit and imperial loyalty to give their activities meaning. This shifts the problematic away from conventional questions such as “Did com- munists ­really convert and embrace imperial ideology?” to understanding how their practices made it appear as if they had become loyal imperial subjects. In other words, I am interested in how the ideology of the emperor was inscribed in the practical, institutional, and juridical operations of the prewar Peace Preservation Law apparatus, and how this ideology informed and was disseminated through the practice of ideological conversion in the 1930s. As I explore in chapter 1, state officials initially infused the expanding institutional apparatus to suppress po­liti­cal radicalism with the sovereign ghost by using the term “kokutai” (national polity or essence) in the Peace Preservation Law, identifying a po­liti­cal crime as anyone who formed or joined an organ­ization with the intention to “alter the kokutai” (kokutai o henkaku).38 Legislators defined their use of kokutai in the law as signifying that sovereignty resided in the “line of Emperors unbroken for ages eternal” as stipulated in Article 1 of the Meiji Constitution, and thus po­liti­cal crime was identified as the intention to alter imperial sovereignty. Consequently, in their continuing legislative debates over the use of kokutai in the law, officials­w ere not only arguing about how the term defined an infringement to be punished, but ­were sim­ ult­a­neously and inadvertently addressing the ostensible sovereign essence of the Japa­nese Empire itself. Then ­later, in the emerging rehabilitation policies of the Peace Preservation Law apparatus, of- ficials and detainees ruminated on imperial subjectivity as criminal reform was mea­sured by the degree to which a po­liti­cal criminal (re)identified as an imperial subject, the spectral cognate to the imperial sovereign. Indeed, throughout the 1930s, officials such as Hirata Isao and reformed ­lpo itical­ activists continuously wrote on the significance of ideological conversion and, in the pro­cess, reflected on the essence of imperial subjectivity. As I ­will

10 Introduction explore in chapter 5, this was a particularly vexed endeavor in colonial Kor­ ea, where anticolonial activists, although not ethnically Japa­nese (minzoku), ­were urged to reform as loyal nationals (kokumin) of the Japa­nese Empire. Despite ­these challenges, by the late 1930s, officials in metropolitan Japan abstracted the policy of ideological conversion from the Protection and Supervision Centers and re-pr­ esented it as an imperative for all impe- rial subjects to practice, effectively turning tenkō into an ideology in its own right. In chapter 5, I demonstrate how tenkō became a generalized ideology of thought purification and spiritual mobilization, which provided a model for the total-­war mobilization campaigns of the late 1930s and early 1940s. If the imperial ghost initially animated the machine to repress po­liti­cal threats against the sovereign in the 1920s, and if po­liti­cal criminals invoked their own subjective ghost as they converted as loyal subjects of the emperor in the mid-1930s, then the spiritual mobilization campaigns modeled on the tenkō policy in the late 1930s and 1940s envisioned imperial Japan as a war machine animated by the ghost of the Japa­nese spirit (nihon seishin).

The Peace Preservation Law as Combined Repressive and Ideological State Apparatus Power would be a fragile ­thing if its only function ­were to repress. —­michel ­foucault, “Body/Power” In order to illuminate the ideological and institutional transformations of the Peace Preservation Law in the 1930s, Thought Crime draws upon the theoreti- cal investigations of Louis Althusser, Michel Foucault, and, to a lesser extent, Nicos Poulantzas concerning the differing modalities of state power and the effective operations of ideology.39 Although Althusser and Foucault are con- ventionally read as theoretical adversaries, ­there have been recent attempts to read them together, opening new, productive lines of inquiry into the complex proc­esses of state power and subjection.40 Poulantzas’s ­later state theory serves to mediate between Foucault and Althusser, for, as Bob Jessop has explored, Poulantzas attempted to bring aspects of Foucault’s theory of power as dispersed at the microlevel of society into a structural-­Marxist the- ory of the state and how the state intervenes and reproduces the relations of capi­ ­tal­ist production.41 To begin with, both Althusser and Foucault reject the conventional theory of ideology, since this is predicated upon the assumption of, as Fou- cault explains, a preconstituted liberal “­human subject . . . ​endowed with a

Introduction 11 consciousness which power is then thought to seize on.”42 In contrast, as Warren Montag has summarized, for both Althusser and Foucault “the indi- vidual was not given, but constituted or produced as [a] center of initiatives, an effect, not a cause of the conflictual proc­esses of ideology or power.”43 Furthermore, although Foucault did not use the term “ideology,” both he and Althusser rejected idealist theories of how power or ideology seize upon or mystify the consciousness of an individual, what Althusser deemed “the ideology of ideology.”44 We can find this ideology informing prior studies of the tenkō phenomenon in interwar Japan, whereby tenkō is explained as when the state, through external force, coerced an individual to change his or her internal ideas. Most studies of tenkō thus track the ostensible change in thought of an individual, overlooking the extensive institutional appa- ratus that provided the models through which the individual experienced and practiced conversion. Tellingly, converts described their conversion as a uniquely personal experience of introspection, even though their experi- ences followed a predictable sequence and produced almost identical biographical forms. Althusser and Foucault, each in his own way, shift our attention to the mechanisms or diagrams of power (Foucault) and practices ritualized within specific apparatuses (Althusser) through which the subject is constituted as such. My objective in Thought Crime is to elaborate the logic at work in the ensemble of apparatuses that the imperial state developed to reform po­liti­cal criminals as loyal and productive imperial subjects. In the prewar Japa­nese context, this entails, as Harry Harootunian re- minds us, that we recognize how ­these apparatuses worked to interpellate individuals “as subjects (not primarily imperial subjects—­shinmin—­even though this was obviously included in the formulation, but as subjects—­ shutai or shukan).”45 Indeed, as I ­will demonstrate, it was through the tropes of imperial subjectivity that a reformed po­liti­cal criminal would, in Althusser’s terms, “(freely) accept his subjection . . . ​in order that he sh­ all make the gestures and actions of his subjection ‘all by himself.’ ”46 Thought Crime analyzes how vari­ous modalities of power combined within the Peace Pres- ervation Law, transforming it into an apparatus that functioned to reform po­litical­ criminals as imperial subjects that would work “all by themselves” (Althusser) without threat of reprimand. Indeed, by the mid-1930s we find justice officials and converts alike celebrating the practice of “indirect reha- bilitation” (kansetsu hogo) in the Peace Preservation Law, in which detained thought criminals converted ostensibly on their own volition and continued to demonstrate their loyalty a­fter parole with only minor oversight by the state.47

12 Introduction From Foucault, I explore the transformations of the Peace Preservation Law apparatus through his tripartite schema of sovereign-­juridical power, disciplinary power, and governmentality.48 In the 1930s, the Peace Preserva- tion Law apparatus transformed from its initial function as a law to juridically repress po­litical­ threats to imperial sovereignty in the mid-1920s, to estab- lishing semiofficial organ­izations that experimented with disciplinary meth- ods to safely release reformed po­liti­cal criminals back into imperial society in the early 1930s, to fin­ ally codifying and intensifying the earlier reform experiments into a multistage pro­cess of ideological conversion (tenkō) so that released ex–­political criminals would morally govern themselves in the late 1930s. Foucault’s tripartite schema allows us to distinguish the vari­ ous modalities of power that combined within the Peace Preservation Law by the mid-1930s, while at the same time allowing us to understand the­ se modes of power, not as unique vestiges of premodern Japa­nese statecraft but as general forms of power that modern states exercise to some degree and combination in par­tic­u­lar moments of po­liti­cal crisis.49 Moreover, the Peace Preservation Law provides a unique example through which to recon- sider Foucault’s threefold schema of power, not as a series of three unique historical forms (which is sometimes how Foucault is read), but rather as the simultaneous configuration of three modes of power—­“sovereignty-­ discipline-­government” (Foucault)—­into a single security complex that had impor­tant influences and effects in interwar Japa­nese society.50 I engage with Althusser’s theory of Ideological State Apparatuses (isas) in order to analyze how the Peace Preservation Law apparatus, by the mid-1930s, included par­tic­u­lar reform procedures that functioned to re- habilitate individuals as loyal and productive imperial subjects. Althusser distinguished between a (single) state apparatus—­the Repressive State Ap- paratus (rsa), which primarily functions by vio­lence—­and the plural ap- paratuses that function primarily by ideology, including schools, ­family, law, and so on, which Althusser calls the (plural) isas. Althusser contends that all “State Apparatuses function both by repression and by ideology,” with one ele­ment predominating over the other in the last instance.51 Poulantzas qual- ified Althusser’s functional distinction, arguing that, depending on the situ- ation, “a number of apparatuses can slide from one sphere to the other and assume new functions ­either as additions to, or in exchange for, old ones.”52 Indeed, we ­will see how, as a fully elaborated apparatus in the 1930s, the Peace Preservation Law combined both repressive and ideological functions, and “slid” (Poulantzas) between one function over the other depending on loca- tion and changing po­liti­cal conditions. According to ­Althusser, however, it

Introduction 13 is ideology that secures the internal coherence between the apparatuses, and thus presumably the state apparatus itself. And while the repressive function of the rsa may serve as the ultimate horizon of state power—­dealing with what Althusser called “bad subjects” (mauvais sujets) or thos­ e rare occasions when the local police are overwhelmed by events—­repression alone cannot explain how the relations of the social formation are reproduced, or the coherence between the multiple state apparatuses.53 As we see he­ re, Althusser expands the ideological function of the state—­ and thus the state itself—­beyond the conventional state/society divide, finding educational institutions, churches, families, religious groups, and other entities functioning to interpellate individuals as subjects. In this way, Althusser provides an impor­tant corrective to Foucault and ­others who reject the analytical purchase of the state as a critical category. Indeed, as Nicos Poulantzas has noted, Foucault and othe­ rs rejected the term “state” specifically ­because they retained a surprisingly “narrow, juridical definition of the State” that was “limited to the public kernel of army, police, prisons, courts, and so on.” Poulantzas argues that this allowed Foucault and ­others to argue “that power also exists outside the State as they conceive it. But in fact, a number of sites of power which they imagine to lie wholly outside the State (the apparatus of asylums and hospitals, the sports apparatus, ­etc.) are all the more sites of power in that they are included in the strategic field of the State.”54 In Thought Crime, I reveal how the Japa­nese state collaborated with Buddhist ­temples, municipal employment agencies, ­family members, and other community groups in order to rehabilitate po­liti­cal criminals and secure their ideological conversion. Each institution had its own unique function, what Althusser would call their respective “secondary ideologies,” whereby ­temples provided spiritual guidance, schools educated students, training centers provided industrial reskilling to workers, and so on. But when taken together and overseen by the imperial state, they functioned to reconfigure po­liti­cal criminals as loyal imperial subjects, what Althusser would see as their “primary” ideological function.55 Disregarding Althusser’s more problematic theory of interpellation, I w­ ill focus specifically on Althusser’s concept ofisa s in order to explore the op- erations of the Peace Preservation Law apparatus.56 In his approach to isas, Althusser argues that ideology is not ideational, but rather “always exists in an apparatus, and its practice, or practices. This existence is material.”57 Subverting the causality of the ideational thesis, Althusser argues that “the ‘ideas’ of a h­ uman subject exist in his[/her] actions” and that ­these actions

14 Introduction themselves are “inserted into practices” that “are governed by the rituals in which ­these practices are inscribed, within the material existence of an ideo- logical apparatus.” 58 Althusser’s theory of isas requires that we move beyond the conventional problematic regarding to what degree did ideological con- verts truly come to believe in imperial ideology in the 1930s, and to focus on the forms and practices ritualized within po­liti­cal reform groups through which thought criminals acted as if they ­were loyal imperial subjects. Attentive to the impor­tant theoretical differences that exist between Althusser and Foucault, as well as the lacunae that exist in their respective theories of ideology and power, each chapter of Thought Crime reflects on a specific question posed by one of ­these theorists and pursues this question through an analy­sis of a par­tic­u­lar development in the Peace Preservation Law apparatus.

Chapter Outline Chapter 1 begins by exploring the Japa­nese state’s efforts to pass antiradi- cal laws earlier in the 1920s, and then conducts an in-­depth analy­sis of the drafting and legislative debates that led to the passage of the Peace Preser- vation Law in 1925. I demonstrate that while most officials and politicians agreed on the need to pass meas­ures that would suppress radical po­liti­cal movements, they struggle­ d to define the object that was threatened by such movements. Officials ultimately decide­ d upon the term “kokutai” to iden- tify the bill’s object of protection, defining a po­liti­cal crime as forming or joining an organi­zation that had the intention to “alter the kokutai” (kokutai o henkaku). Whereas existing scholarship portrays the inclusion of kokutai in the law as the contamination of juridical rationality by the irrational and ambiguous category of kokutai, chapter 1 shows how lawmakers continually referred to kokutai as signifying imperial sovereignty as stipulated in the 1889 Meiji Constitution. Drawing upon critical theories of sovereignty, I argue that if the inclusion of kokutai in the law was irrational or ambiguous, it was an irrationality that emerged from the concept of sovereignty and the par­ tic­u­lar form that this took in the prewar Japa­nese Empire. Consequently, by utilizing the term “kokutai,” legislators inadvertently brought questions related to the form and content of imperial sovereignty into debates over the law, infusing the law’s emerging institutionalization with the ghostly spec- ter of the sovereign emperor. This chapter reveals how­ these kinds of issues are most clearly seen in the discussions over how to implement the Peace

Introduction 15 Preservation Law in colonial ­Korea, where, at least initially, colonial courts defined kokutai as referring largely to the territorial integrity of Japan’s colo- nial empire. Chapter 2 traces the proc­ ess of how reform and rehabilitation protocols slowly emerged from a law that was initially intended as a le­ gal instrument to repress threats to imperial sovereignty. Drawing upon Foucault’s theoreti- cal distinction between sovereign and disciplinary power, I argue that, by the early 1930s, the initial repressive application of the Peace Preserva- tion Law was so successful in metropolitan Japan that justice officials ­were faced with the prob­lem of how to manage thousands of detained po­liti­cal criminals. Through a contingent pro­cess of trial and error, officials in Tokyo arrived at the solution of reforming repentant po­liti­cal criminals, drawing upon disciplinary meas­ ures that ­were developed earlier to reform delinquent youth. While prior scholarship has recognized this complex combination of repression and reform in the law, it does not consider the functional rela- tionship between ­these two modes of state power, explaining it simply as the schizophrenic, Janus-­faced justice unique to prewar Japan.59 In contrast, chapter 2 reveals how imperial ideology mediated the functional relation- ship between repression and rehabilitation: for example, repression was le- gitimated as protecting the imperial sovereign, while reform was increasingly portrayed as an expression of the unique benevolence of the Japa­nese impe- rial ­house. And although reform was institutionalized in colonial ­Korea as well, repression continued to constitute the primary application of the law in the colony into the mid-1930s, demonstrating how the colonial articula- tion of imperial sovereignty differed from the metropole. This functional but differential combination of repression and disciplinary reform in the Peace Preservation Law apparatus provides a historical example through which to reconsider Michel Foucault’s logical and historical distinction between sovereign-­juridical and disciplinary power. In chapter 3, I explore the oft-­overlooked network of semiofficial reha- bilitation groups that facilitated the ideological conversion (tenkō) of ex-­ communists and their reintegration into society. This chapter focuses on the most impor­tant group in this network—­the Tokyo-­based Imperial Renova- tion Society (Teikoku Kōshinkai)—a­ nd the early contributions of one of its staff members, the ex-­communist convert Kobayashi Morito. Originally es- tablished in 1926 as a semiofficial support group for detainees awaiting crimi- nal indictment, by the mid-1930s the Imperial Renovation Society oversaw the ideological conversion of hundreds of ex-­rank-­and-­file jcp members, es- tablishing protocols for other thought crime reform groups throughout the

16 Introduction empire. Tenkō is commonly defined as when a po­litical­ criminal spontane- ously changed his or her thought unde­ r the coercion of state power. This overlooks the fact that an institutional network predated the phenomenon referred to as tenkō. Drawing upon Louis Althusser’s theory of isas intro- duced above, this chapter argues that it was in such semiofficial support groups that the corollary ghost of the imperial subject was starting to take shape, who, once paroled would, to paraphrase Althusser, make the gestures and actions of his or her continuing subjection all by him or herself.60 Groups such as the Imperial Renovation Society enlisted Buddhist chaplains, fa­ mily members, employers, educators, and civic leaders in assisting with the reha- bilitation of po­liti­cal criminals, thereby serving as impor­tant sites of ideo- logical mediation between the imperial state and the wider community. Chapter 4 traces how, following a wave of defections from the jcp in 1933–1934, the Justice Ministry attempted to formalize and extend admin- istrative policies for reforming detained and paroled po­litical­ criminals, culminating in the 1936 Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision Law (Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō). This chapter focuses on two impor­tant devel- opments within this pro­cess between 1934 and 1936. First, I explore how as justice officials and reformed ex-­communists ruminated on the significance and practice of po­litical­ rehabilitation, they increasingly drew upon the te- nets of imperial ideology to define ideological conversion, thereby refining the figure of the ghost of imperial subjectivity informingthe ­ se conversions. I understand this development through Louis Althusser’s distinction between primary and secondary ideologies at work in isas: in this case, the mandate to reform criminals (secondary ideology) guiding groups like the Imperial Renovation Society was increasingly yoked to imperial loyalty and national veneration (the primary ideology). The second development I focus on in chapter 4 is the emerging concern for securing a po­liti­cal convert’s conversion ­after he or she was released. With an increasing number of converts being re- leased, counselors and justice officials sought a new ethic, most often in Bud- dhist self-­negation, for converts to return to and function in society with- out constant state oversight. I contend that this objective introduced a new complementary mode of power to the Peace Preservation Law apparatus—­ what Foucault theorized as governmentality—a­ mode of power whereby the population of converts would govern themselves in their everyday practices as productive subjects of the imperial polity.61 This addition of governmen- tality complemented the sovereign and disciplinary modes of power that converged earlier in the 1930s. And as the state codified­the se practices in the 1936 Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision Law, we can understand

Introduction 17 this development as “the ‘governmentalization’ of the state” (Foucault).62 The chapter also points to how, althoughthe­ re had been far fewer cases of ideological conversion in colonial ­Korea than in the metropole before 1936, once established, the Protection and Supervision Center apparatus facili- tated a sudden increase of conversion in Kor­ ea in the latter half of the de­ cade, raising new questions about how Korean colonial subjects, although not ethnically Japa­nese, could ideologically convert as nationals of the Japa­ nese imperial nation-­state. The fifth and final chapter analyzes the transformation in ideological conversion during the early years of the China Incident. Immediately ­after Japan’s invasion of China in 1937, tenkōsha mobilized in support of war as a means to demonstrate their rehabilitation as patriotic imperial subjects. This was a natur­al extension of the practices taking place in the newly established Protection and Supervision Centers. At the same time, reform officials ab- stracted from the practices within the centers and presented tenkō to the general public as a model for how all subjects—­not just po­liti­cal criminals—­ could purify their thoughts and spiritually mobilize for war. The convergence in the changing practices and repre­sen­ta­tion of tenkō refigured ideologi- cal conversion as an ideology—w­ hat I call the ideology of conversion—­ applicable to the general population. The ideology of conversion was most explicit in the portrayal of reformed ex-­communists and anticolonial nation- alists as the vanguard of an empire-­wide spiritual awakening, presaging ­later war mobilization campaigns. However, in colonial ­Korea, where conversion started to become a more widespread phenomenon in 1937, officials ru- minated on the inherent limitations of colonial conversion, thus revealing specific aporia in imperial ideology and its articulation in the colony. Chapter 5 concludes by reviewing the passage of an extensive revision to the Peace Preservation Law in 1941, which demoted the earlier empha- sis on reform with a policy of indeterminate detention called preventative detention (yobō kōkin), returning the function of the law to an emphasis on repression of suspected threats against the state during war­time. By this time, however, the notions of thought purification and spiritual mobilization that ­were developed within the Peace Preservation Law earlier in the 1930s had become general princip­ les to mobilize society, most clearly exemplified in the National Spirit Mobilization Movement (Kokumin seishin sōdōin undō). In the epilogue, I reflect on the transwar legacies of the Peace Pres- ervation Law and ruminate on pos­si­ble lines of inquiry for further research into the revived rehabilitation practices in the early postwar period.

18 Introduction Before beginning, three qualifications are necessary. First,Thought Crime does not address the individual experiences of activists who underwent the practice of conversion, or the effect the Peace Preservation Law had on the interwar socialist, communist, and anticolonial movements. ­There are volumes of research on ­these aspects of interwar history, to which I refer in the endnotes. Rather, my analytical focus is on what the Peace Preservation Law reveals about imperial state ideology and how this ideology was in- scribed in state apparatuses to police so-­called thought crime.63 Second and relatedly, my objective is not to inquire into the Peace Preservation Law’s success or failure in policing thought per se, but rather the ­legal, institutional, and ideological conditions within which the discourse of thought crime and ideological conversion emerged and transformed. For thos­ e interested in criminological approaches to the interwar law, I refer to many secondary sources in the endnotes. Last and most importantly, although Thought Crime touches upon the ways in which the Peace Preservation Law was interpreted and implemented differently in colonial ­Korea, the complexity of the colonial institution and the dif­fer­ent experience of colonial tenkōsha require much further research. Where necessary, I refer to scholarship in the endnotes that has started to illuminate ­these complexities, including the groundbreaking work of Mizuno Naoki and more recently Hong Jong-­wook’s excellent study of tenkō in colonial ­Korea. I hope that by illuminating the complex logic and institutional operations of the Peace Preservation Law, Thought Crime ­will inspire new research into the­ se areas as well as a broader reconsideration of the complex po­liti­cal and ideological transformations across the Japa­nese Empire during the 1930s.

Introduction 19 notes

Preface 1. For an overview of ­these cases, see Laura Yuen, Mukhtar Ibrahim, and Sasha Aslanian, “Called to Fight: Minnesota’s isis Recruits,” Minnesota Public Radio News, March 25, 2015, http://­www.​ ­mprnews​.org­ ​/­story​/­2015​/­03​/­25​/­minnesota​-­isis#ayusuf. 2. Giorgio Agamben, State of Exception, trans. Kevin Attell (Chicago: Chicago Uni- versity Press, 2005). 3. On the concept of radicalization, see Arun Kudnani, “Radicalisation: The Journey of a Concept,” Race and Class 54, no. 2 (September 2012): 3–25. 4. Uchida Hirofumi, for example, has argued that current ­legal developments reflect the changes to the ­legal system in the 1920s and 1930s that prepared Japan for total war. See Uchida Hirofumi, Keihō to sensō: Senji chian hōsei no tsukurikata (Tokyo: Misuzu shobō, 2015). In par­tic­u­lar, Uchida and ­others have pointed to the Peace Preservation Law when critiquing the inclusion of “criminal conspiracy” (kyōbōzai) in the revised 2017 Or­ga­nized Crime Law (Soshikiteki hanzai shobatsu hō) that proponents argue is neces- sary for investigating and prosecuting supposed terrorism cases. See Uchida Hirofumi, Chianijihō to kyōbōzai (Tokyo: Iwanami, 2017); and Hōgaku Seminaa Henshūbu, ed., Kyōbōzai hihyō: Kaisei soshikiteki hanzai shobatsu hō no kentō (Tokyo: Nihon hyōronsha, 2017). On the passage of this controversial “conspiracy law” see: Colin Jones, “­Will Japan’s New Conspiracy Law Lead to ‘Thought Crime’?”The Diplomat, July 17, 2017, https://­ thediplomat​.­com​/­2017​/­07​/­will​-­​-­new​-­conspiracy-​ ­law​-­lead​-­to​-­thought​-­crime/. 5. Brendan I. Koerner, “Can You Turn a Terrorist Back into a Citizen? A Contro- versial New Program Aims to Reform Homegrown isis Recruits Back into Normal Americans,” Wired, January 24, 2017, https://­www​.­wired​.­com​/­2017​/­01​/­can​-­you​-­turn​ -­terrorist​-­back​-­into​-­citizen​/­. 6. See Mukhtar Ibrahim and Laura Yuen, “Judge ­Orders Study of Terror Defen- dants before Sentencing,” Minnesota Public Radio News, March 2, 2016, https://w­ ww​ .­mprnews​.­org​/­story​/­2016​/­03​/­02​/­judge​-­outlines​-­steps​-­to​-­divert​-­mn​-­terror-​ ­defendants​ -­islamic​-­state​-­isis​-­recruitment. See also Stephen Montemayor, “Terror Suspects ­Will Test Deradicalization Program,” Minneapolis Star Tribune, March 2, 2016, http://­ www​.­startribune​.­com​/­judge​-­orders​-­de​-­radicalization​-­study​-­for-​ ­4​-­terror​-­defendants​ /3­ 70806141. See also the announcement on the girds website: “girds Contracted to Design New Deradicalization Program in the United States,” girds, April 3, 2016, http://­girds​.org­ ​/­news​/­girds​-­contracted​-­to​-­design​-­new​-­deradicalization​-­program​-­in​ -­the​-united­ -​ states.­ 7. Montemayor, “Terror Suspects ­Will Test Deradicalization Program.” I thank Stephen Montemayor for meeting with me to discuss ­these cases in November 2016. 8. Daniel Koehler, cited in Stephen Montemayor, “Deradicalization Expert Con- cludes Testimony in Minnesota isil Case Evaluations,” Minneapolis Star Tribune, September 21, 2016, http://­www​.­startribune​.­com​/­deradicalization​-­expert​-­concludes​ -­testimony-​ ­in​-minnesota­ -​ ­isil-​ case­ ​-evaluations­ ​/­394354591​/­. 9. Koehler also met with chief probation officer Kevin Lowery and ten of his officers, training them “for counseling extremists.” See Koerner, “Can You Turn a Terrorist Back into a Citizen?” 10. Kevin Lowry, cited in Montemayor, “Deradicalization Expert Concludes Testimony.” 11. Ikeda Katsu, Chianijihō, in Shinhōgaku zenshū (Nihon Hyōronsha, 1939), vol. 19, 24. En­glish translation (amended) from Patricia G. Steinhoff, “Tenkō and Thought Control,” in Japan and the World: Essays on Japa­nese History and Politics in Honour of Ishida Takeshi, ed. Gail Lee Bern­stein and Haruhiro Fukui (New York: St. Martin’s, 1988), 79. 12. Montemayor, “Deradicalization Expert Concludes Testimony.” 13. Mila Koumpilova, “Minnesota Officials Envision Probation Program forP ­ eople Facing Terror Charges,” Minneapolis Star Tribune, January 9, 2016, http://­www​ .startribune­ .​ com­ ​/­minnesota​-officials­ -​ ­envision​-­a​-­probation​-­program​-for­ -​ ­people​-facing­ ​ -­terror-​ charges­ ​/­364754521​/­. 14. Koerner, “Can You Turn a Terrorist Back into a Citizen?” 15. Koumpilova, “Minnesota Officials Envision Probation Program.” See also Mon- temayor, “Terror Suspects ­Will Test Deradicalization Program.” 16. Judge Davis was influenced by Koehler’s pessimistic assessments of the defen- dants’ varying potential for deradicalization. See Koerner, “Can You Turn a Terrorist Back into a Citizen?” 17. Stephen Montemayor and Faiza Mahamud, “De­cades in Prison for Final 3 Sen- tenced in Minnesota isil Conspiracy Case,” Minneapolis Star Tribune, November 16, 2016, http://­www.​ startribune­ ​.com­ ​/­final-​ ­3-​ of­ ​-­minnesota-​ s­ -​ ­isil-​ defendants­ -​ ­appear-​ for­ ​ -­sentencing​/­401501085​/­. See also Laura Yuen and Doualy Xaykaothao, “Third isis Sen- tence of the Day: 10 Years,” Minnesota Public Radio News, November 15, 2016, https://­ www.​ mprnews­ .​ org­ ​/­story​/­2016​/­11​/­15​/­day-​ ­2-​ of­ -​ ­isis-​ ­trial. 18. Stephen Montemayor, “All Eyes on Minnesota Federal Judge before Sentencing in Nation’s Biggest isil Recruitment Case,” Minneapolis Star Tribune, November 12, 2016, http://­m.​ startribune­ .​ com­ ​/­all-​ eyes­ -​ on­ ​-minnesota­ ​-federal­ -​ ­judge​-before­ ​-sentencing­ -​ ­in​ -nation­ ​-s­ -​ biggest­ -​ ­isil-​ recruitment­ ​-case­ ​/­400955075​/­. 19. The US Department of Homeland Security cve website has since been revised. US Department of Homeland Security, “Terrorism Prevention Partnerships,” accessed April 17, 2018, https://­www.​ ­dhs.​ gov­ ​/­terrorism​-­prevention​-­partnerships. 20. See Brennan Center for Justice, “Countering Violent Extremism (cve): A Re- source Page,” November 2015, https://­www.​ brennancenter­ .​ org­ ​/­analysis​/­cve​-­programs​ -­resource​-­page.

186 Notes to Preface 21. See Mukhtar Ibrahim, “Community Response to Feds’ MN Anti-­terror Recruiting Efforts,”Minnesota Public Radio News, February 23, 2016, https://­www.​ mprnews­ .​ org­ ​ /­story​/­2016​/­02​/­23​/­somali​-community­ ​-­response​-­anti​-­terror​-­recruiting. 22. For one example, see “Full Text: Donald Trump’s Speech on Fighting Terror- ism,” Politico, August 15, 2016, http://­www.​ ­politico.​ com­ ​/­story​/­2016​/­08​/­donald-​ ­trump​ -­terrorism​-speech­ ​-­227025. 23. See Jennifer Hansler, “dhs Shifts Focus of Funding to ­Counter Violent Extrem- ism,” cnn, July 4, 2017, http://­edition​.cnn­ .​ com­ ​/­2017​/­07​/­01​/­politics​/­cve​-funding­ ​ -changes­ ​/­index.​ ­html. 24. See Adam Taylor, “The U.S. Keeps Killing Americans in Drone Strikes, Mostly by Accident,” Washington Post, April 23, 2015, https://­www.​ ­washingtonpost​.­com​ /­news​/­worldviews​/­wp​/­2015​/­04​/­23​/­the​-u­ ​-s­ ​-­keeps-​ ­killing-​ ­americans-​ ­in​-drone­ ​-strikes­ ​ -­mostly​-­by​-­accident​/­​?­utm​_­term​= ​.­ ­9f197c6e3949. A secret Justice Department memo from 2011 outlined the justification for killing American-­born jihadists, specifically arguing that such killings do not violate the citizen’s right to due proc­ ess as stated in the Fourth Amendment. On this memo, see Greg Miller, “­Legal Memo Backing Drone Strike That Killed American Anwar al-­Awlaki Is Released,” Washington Post, June 23, 2014, https://­www.​ ­washingtonpost​.com­ ​/­world​/­national-​ security­ ​/­legal-​ memo­ ​ -backing­ -​ drone­ ​-­strike​-­is-​ released­ ​/­2014​/­06​/­23​/­1f48dd16​-faec­ -​ ­11e3–8176​-f2c941cf35f1­ ​ _­story.​ ­html?​ ­tid​= a­ ​_­inl&utm​_­term​= ​.­ ­31c20c5dca38. Since taking office, President Trump has loosened the rules governing drone strikes. See Ken Dilanian, Hans Nich- ols, and Courtney Kube, “Trump Admin Ups Drone Strikes, Tolerates More Civilian Deaths: U.S. Officials,” nbc News, March 14, 2017, http://­www.​ nbcnews­ .​ com­ ​/­news​ /­us-​ news­ ​/­trump-​ ­admin​-ups­ -​ drone­ ​-strikes­ ​-­tolerates​-more­ ​-­civilian​-deaths­ -​ n733336;­ Eric Schmitt and Matthew Rosenberg, “C.I.A. Wants Authority to Conduct Drone Strikes in Af­ghan­i­stan for the First Time,” New York Times, September 15, 2017, https://­ www.​ nytimes­ .​ ­com​/­2017​/­09​/­15​/­us​/­politics​/­cia-​ drone­ ​-strike­ ​-­authority-​ ­afghanistan​ .­html. 25. See Peter Baker, “Trump Abandons Idea of Sending Terror Suspect to Guantá- namo,” New York Times, November 2, 2017, https://­www.​ nytimes­ .​ com­ ​/­2017​/­11​/­02​/­us​ /­politics​/­trump-​ new­ -​ york­ -​ ­terror-​ ­attack.​ ­html; Rebecca Ruiz, Adam Goldman, and Matt Apuzzo, “Terror Suspect Brought to U.S. for Trial, Breaking from Trump Rhe­toric,” New York Times, July 21, 2017, https://­www.​ nytimes­ .​ com­ ​/­2017​/­07​/­21​/­world​/­europe​/­al​ -qaeda­ -​ suspect­ -​ court­ ​-­trump-​ sessions­ -​ guantanamo­ .​ ­html. 26. In each case, the under­lying ideologies informing the­ se programs ­were thrown into sharp relief when each state confronted acts of nationalist vio­lence: for example, the Japa­nese imperial state strug­gled to apply its thought crime policy to rightist terrorists who killed industrialists and politicians in the name of the emperor in the 1930s, whereas the Trump administration is currently (summer 2017) hesitant to call the vio­lence carried out by white supremacists and neo-­Nazis acts of terrorism so as not to alienate some of its most vocal supporters. See Liam Stack, “Charlottesville Vio­ lence and Trump’s Reaction Draw Criticism Abroad,” New York Times, August 17, 2017, https://­www.​ nytimes­ .​ com­ ​/­2017​/­08​/­17​/­world​/­charlottesville​-­trump-​ ­world-​ reaction­ ​ .­html.

Notes to Preface 187 Introduction 1. ­These events are discussed in more detail in chapters 1 and 2. Hirata Isao oversaw the jailed communist Mizuno Shigeo, who, with ­others, critiqued the jcp from jail, and upon being paroled, formed a breakaway communist group that recognized the em- peror. See Itō Akira, “Tenkō mondai no ikkōsatsu: Nihonkyōsantō rōdōshaha to Hirata Isao,” Chiba kōgyō daigaku kenkyū hōkoku, no. 31 (February 1994): 29–41. 2. The 1927 ­Theses used the term “kunshusei” (literally, monarchical system). It was not ­until the 1932 ­Theses that the jcp and Comintern started using the specific term “emperor system” or tennōsei. For an En­glish translation of the 1927 ­Theses and 1932 ­Theses, see George M. Beckmann and Genji Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 1922–1945 (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1969), 295–308, 332–351, respectively. 3. Hirata Isao, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” in Shisōsen kōshūkai kōgi sokki, vol. 3, ed. Naikaku Jōhōbu (Tokyo: Naikaku Jōhōbu, 1938), 205–236, 228. 4. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 236. 5. Following Carl Schmitt’s political-­ontological distinction of friend/enemy, Michael Dutton analyzes the policing of politics in China and notes that the identification of a threat ultimately functions to define po­liti­cal subjectivity: “Enemies . . . ​take pre­ce­ dence for they are what defines us. Just as a­le gal trial has meaning only as a result of a breach in the law, or criminal law begins not with a deed but with a criminal misdeed, so too are we defined by our opposite.” Michael Dutton,Policing Chinese Politics: A History (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2005), 6. Dutton’s analy­sis of the policing of politics in the twentieth c­ entury is at the same time an attempt to bring Hannah Ar- endt’s po­litical­ ontology into conversation with Schmitt’s. See Dutton,Policing Chinese Politics, 9–11. 6. On the National Spirit Mobilization Movement, see Thomas R. H. Havens,Valley of Darkness: The Japa­nese ­People and World War Two (New York: Norton, 1978), 11–33, 36–37. 7. Although Japa­nese scholars still find analytical and theoretical purchase in the term “tennōsei,” “emperor-­system” is rarely used in recent En­glish language scholarship on Japan. Sheldon Garon has questioned the analytical value of the term “emperor system,” noting that in the conventional scholarship it has been used in an ahistorical manner without any institutional or historical dynamism, and that it incorrectly suggests that all suppression stemmed from the omnipotent imperial state. Garon argues that scholars who have used the term overlook how social groups proactively collaborated with the state to manage other sectors of society. See Sheldon Garon, Molding Japa­nese Minds: The State in Everyday Life (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1995), 61–63. My objective is to restore the institutional, practical, and ideological complexity of the em- peror system by showing how its po­liti­cal security apparatus combined vari­ous modes of power over time, how its ideological underpinning changed, and how it drew upon volunteers in the community to police as well as reform po­liti­cal criminals. 8. For the canonical study of the Peace Preservation Law, see the updated edition of Okudaira Yasuhiro, Chianijihō shōshi (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2006).

188 Notes to Introduction 9. An analy­sis conducted by the Ōhara Institute for Social Research reports 75,681 ­people ­were arrested unde­ r the law. See Ōhara Shakai Mondai Kenkyūsho, ed., Taiheiyō sensōka no rōdō undō (Tokyo: Rōdō Junpōsha, 1965), 131. Richard Mitchell cites a 1943 Justice Ministry Criminal Bureau report that lists 65,921 persons arrested between 1928 and 1941. See Richard H. Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1976), 142. No complete rec­ord exists for arrests in colonial ­Korea, particularly in the 1940s. However, both Hong Jong-­wook and Mizuno Naoki have shown that already by 1933, over 15,000 arrests had been made. See Hong Jong-­wook, Senjiki chō­ sen no tenkōsha-t­achi: Teikoku / shokuminchi no tōgō to kiretsu (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2011), 47; Mizuno Naoki, “Chianijihō to Chōsen: Oboegaki,” Chōsen kenkyū 188, no. 4 (1979): 46. 10. Exemplary of this approach is Matsuo Hiroshi, Chianijihō: Danatsu to teikō no reki- shi (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shūppansha, 1971); Matsuo Hiroshi, Chianijihō to tokkō keisatsu (Tokyo: Kyōikusha, 1979). 11. Indeed, Herbert Bix has suggested that the “vari­ous state organs” of the Peace Preservation Law “became entangled with the trend ­towards bureaucratically con- trolled mass-­mobilization” specifically ­because state officials “lack[ed] . . . ​confidence in the intellectual efficacy of as the sole support for emperor worship, but also, more importantly, from fear that, even in the absence of self-pr­ ofessed revolu- tionary forces, the domestic situation in a time of exceedingly rapid economic change remained highly volatile and fraught with contradictions.” Herbert Bix, “Rethinking ‘Emperor-­System Fascism’: Ruptures and Continuities in Modern Japa­nese History,” Bulletin of Concerned Asian Scholars 14, no. 2 (June 1982): 8. 12. Richard H. Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice: Po­liti­cal Criminals in Imperial Japan (Ho- nolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1992); Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan; Okudaira Yasuhiro, Chianijihō shōshi, new ed. (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2006). I engage with this lit­er­a­ture more extensively in chapters 1 and 2. 13. Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Shiryō kaisetsu,” in Gendaishi shiryō 45: Chianijihō, ed. Okudaira Yasuhiro (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 1973), xx; Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 104. For another example, see Richard H. Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925: Its Origins and Significance,”Monumenta Nipponica 28, no. 3 (autumn 1973): 317–345. More recently, Uchida Hirofumi has analyzed the Peace Preservation Law from a ­legal standpoint, emphasizing that the law undermined ­legal protections and was used to suppress movements for ­legal rights. See Uchida Hirofumi, Chianijihō no kyōkun: Kenri undō no seigen to kenpō kaisei (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 2016). 14. For a narrative example of this combination/confrontation, see Richard H. Mitchell, “Legacies,” in Mitchell, Janus-Faced­ Justice, 1–35. 15. For example, Richard Mitchell argues, “by [the] inclusion of ‘kokutai’ the govern- ment was telegraphing to all subjects its intention to preserve the Japa­nese way of life in the face of rapid change. Therefore, the new peace law should be viewed as a strong effort ­toward integration.” Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925,” 343. 16. Garon argues that “moral suasion” was “influenced by traditional forms of state- craft.” Garon,Molding Japa­nese Minds, xiv. 17. Indeed, Herbert Bix goes so far as to call Richard Mitchell’s study of the Peace Preservation Law an “apologia” for the prewar state’s repression. See Herbert Bix,

Notes to Introduction 189 “Kawakami Hajime and the Organic Law of Japa­nese Fascism,” Japan Interpreter 12, no. 1 (winter 1978): 130. 18. In this regard, Thought Crime is inspired by Andre Schmid’s call to move beyond national histories and consider the prewar Japa­nese Empire as one imperial unit. See Andre Schmid, “Colonialism and the ‘­Korea Prob­lem’ in the Historiography of Modern Japan: A Review,” Journal of Asian Studies 59, no. 4 (November 2000): 951–976. One of the earliest studies of the Peace Preservation Law in colonial ­Korea was Park Kyong-­sik, “Chianijihō ni yoru chōsenjin danatsu” (1976), in Tennōsei kokka to zainichi chōsenjin (Tokyo: Shakai Hyōronsha, 1986), 87–130. 19. Mizuno Naoki, “Nihon no chōsen shihai to chianijihō,” in Chōsen no kindaishi to nihon, ed. Hatada Takeshi (Tokyo: Yamato Shobō, 1987), 127–140; Mizuno Naoki, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no tekiyō,” in Shokuminchi teikoku nihon no hōteki kōzō, ed. Asano Toyomi and Matsuda Toshihiko (Tokyo: Shinzansha Shuppan, 2004), 417–459; Suzuki Keifu, Chōsen shokuminchi tōchihō no kenkyū: Chianhō ka no kōminka kyōiku (Sapporo: Hokkaidō Daigaku Tosho Kankōkai, 1989); Hong Jong-­wook, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-t­achi: Teikoku / shokuminchi no tōgō to kiretsu (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2011); Keongil Kim, “Japa­nese Assimilation Policy and Thought Conversion in Colonial Kor­ ea,” in Colonial Rule and Social Change in ­Korea, 1910–1945, ed. Hon Yung Lee, Yong Chool Ha, and Clark W. Sorensen (Seattle: Center for Korean Studies, University of Washington Press, 2013), 206–233. 20. On Jameson’s conceptual distinction between contradiction, which could be dialectically resolved (i.e., Aufheben) through praxis, and aporia, which necessarily “gen- erates a ­whole more properly narrative apparatus,” see Fredric Jameson, The Politi­ ­cal Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1981), 50, 82–83. 21. Maruyama Masao, “Theory and Psy­chol­ogy of Ultra-­nationalism” (1946), in Thought and Behaviour in Modern Japa­nese Politics, ed. Ivan Morris (London: Oxford University Press, 1963), 1, 8–10. For an insightful critique of Maruyama’s influential the- sis, see the introduction to Reto Hofmann, The Fascist Effect: Japan and Italy, 1915–19­ 52 (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2016). Fujita Shōzō, “Tennōsei” (1954), reprinted in Fujita Shōzō, Tennōsei kokka no shihai genri (Tokyo: Miraisha, 1966), 161–169. Fujita began by arguing that the vari­ous and wide usage of the term “tennōsei” was not one of categorical ambiguity, but in fact represented the “complexity” of the emperor system itself. He distinguished three basic usages of the term: first, that the emperor existed as sovereign; second, that tennōsei referred to the “regime” that became “the po­liti­cal structure of modern Japan” in which bureaucrats exercised authority in the name of the imperial sovereign in­de­pen­dent of the Diet. Fi­nally, Fujita noted “a kind of meta­phorical usage” of the term “tennōsei” as a “par­tic­u­lar social phenomenon” that signified the unique “forms” through which the tennōsei governed society. Fujita, “Tennōsei,” 161–162. See also Fujita Shōzō, “Tennōsei kokka no shihai genri” (1956), reprinted in Fujita, Tennōsei kokka no shihai genri, 6–115. See Takeda Kiyoko, Tennōkan no sōkoku: 1945nen zengo (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1978). En­glish translation: Kiyoko Takeda, The Dual-­Image of the Japa­nese Emperor, trans. Ian Nash (New York: New York University Press, 1988). Walter Skya argues that Shintō ideology was inscribed in the

190 Notes to Introduction Meiji Constitution and was continually reconceptualized in constitutional and po­liti­cal theory in the 1910s, 1920s, and 1930s. See Walter A. Skya, Japan’s Holy War: The Ideology of Radical Shintō Ultranationalism (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2009). 22. See Carol Gluck, Japan’s Modern Myths: Ideology in the Late Meiji Period (Prince­ ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1987); T. Fujitani, Splendid Monarchy: Power and Pageantry in Modern Japan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1996); Yoshimi Yoshiaki, Grassroots Fascism: The War Experience of the Japa­nese ­People, trans. Ethan Mark (New York: Columbia University Press, 2015); Garon, Molding Japa­nese Minds. See also: Barak Kushner, The Thought War: Japa­nese Imperial Propaganda (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 2006). 23. Umemori Naoyuki, “Modernization through Colonial Mediations: The Estab- lishment of the Police and Prison System in Meiji Japan” (PhD diss., University of Chicago, 2002); Daniel V. Botsman, Punishment and Power in the Making of Modern Japan (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 2007). In many ways, Thought Crime is an attempt to extend Umemori and Botsman’s respective studies of power in modern Japan into the 1920s and 1930s. 24. My focus on the transforming ideological nature of the Peace Preservation Law is informed by the recent work of Ogino Fujio and Itō Akira, who, in their own ways, have considered the complexities of the Peace Preservation Law in relation to the ideology of the prewar emperor system. See Ogino Fujio, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1993); Itō Akira, Tenkō to tennōsei: Nihon kyōsanshugi undō no 1930nendai (Tokyo: Keisō Shobō, 1995). 25. Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind (London: Penguin, 2000), 21. Ryle argued that Cartesian dualism—­what he called the “Official Doctrine”—­posits that “­every h­ uman being is both body and mind,” where although the body is situated in the space of an external world and thus governed by mechanical laws and observable, minds do not exist in space but are rather “invisible, inaudible” and have “no size or weight,” rendering them unknowable to ­others (14). And yet, in this dualism, minds are still categorized as “­things, but dif­fer­ent sorts of ­things from bodies”; “­mental pro­cesses are ­causes and effects, but dif­fer­ent sorts of ­causes and effects from bodily movements” (20). Ryle be- lieved this to be a “category ­mistake” in which “the facts of ­mental life” are represented “as if they belonged to one logical type or category” applicable to the facts of physical life “when they actually belonged to another” (17). 26. As is well known, Leviathan begins with the section “Of Man,” in which Hobbes formulated a theory of the mind in relation to the world of bodies; only afterward does Hobbes extrapolate from this a theory of the commonwealth and sovereignty. See Thomas Hobbes,Leviathan (New York: Penguin Classics, 1982). 27. One could say that Itō’s 1889 Commentaries on the Meiji constitution was an at- tempt to work through the paradox that although the collective minds of Itō’s consti- tutional committee drafted the Meiji Constitution, the document was presented as an expression of the timeless and unbroken reign of emperors. 28. Ryle, The Concept of Mind, 24, 17. 29. A. J. Ayer, “An Honest Ghost?,” in Ryle, A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Oscar P. Wood and George Pitcher (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1970), 73. Cited in Daniel C.

Notes to Introduction 191 Dennett, “Introduction: Re-­introducing The Concept of Mind,” in Ryle, The Concept of Mind, xiii. 30. Arthur Koestler, The Ghost in the Machine (London: Penguin, 1989), 202. Con- sequently, Koestler followed Ryle insofar as rejecting the assumption that the mind is some ghostly, nonmaterial entity inhabiting the material body, but implicitly retained Cartesian dualism by locating the ghost in the neurophysiological evolution of the ­human brain. See his chapter “The Three Brains,” 267–296. 31. David Easton, “The Po­liti­cal System Besieged by the State,” Po­litical­ Theory 9, no. 3 (August 1981): 316. Impor­tantly, Easton was targeting Nicos Poulantzas’s state theory and the influence it enjoyed in Eu­ro­pean and North American po­liti­cal science circles in the 1970s. 32. Easton, “The Po­liti­cal System Besieged by the State,” 305–306. 33. See Timothy Mitchell, “The Limits of the State: Beyond Statist Approaches and Their Critics,”American Po­liti­cal Science Review 85, no. 1 (March 1991): 77–96; Timothy Mitchell, “Society, Economy, and the State Effect,” inState/Culture: State-Formation­ ­after the Cultural Turn, ed. George Steinmetz (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1999), 76–97. In regard to extending this critique to Ryle, Daniel C. Dennett has implied such an interpretation when, pursuing a dif­fer­ent question, he argued that the under­ lying questions of Ryle’s The Concept of Mind “are about what ­people do,” and not about “how brains make it possi­ ­ble for ­people to do what they do” (italics in original). I would argue that this emphasis opens into questions related to social practice (i.e., ­doing) and how such practices appear as if ­there is a spectral mind that makes ­people “do what they do.” See Dennett, “Introduction,” xiii. 34. Mitchell, “Society, Economy, and the State Effect,” 85. 35. Mitchell’s criticism can be extended to one of the theoretical inspirations for Thought Crime, Michel Foucault. Foucault famously argued that scholars have yet “to cut off the King’s head” when studying forms of power, by which he meant that we remain trapped by theories of “sovereignty” and state repression, thus overlooking other modes of power operating beyond the par­ameters of the sovereign state. Michel Foucault, “Truth and Power,” in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writ- ings, 1972–1977, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Vintage, 1980), 121. Similar to Timothy Mitchell’s critique of David Easton, however, Mitchell Dean has argued that in Foucault’s attempt to move beyond state theories of sovereignty, “the prob­lem remains of how is it that this headless body often behavesas if it indeed had a head.” Mitchell Dean, Critical and Effective Histories: Foucault’s Methods and Historical Sociology (London: Routledge, 1994), 156. For more on this critique of Foucault, see also Thomas Lemke,Foucault, Gov- ernmentality, and Critique (Boulder, CO: Paradigm, 2012), 12. Indeed, Nicos Poulantzas was moving ­toward exploring this paradox in his last book, which, tellingly, Easton does not include in his critique mentioned above. See Nicos Poulantzas, State, Power, Social- ism, trans. Patrick Camiller (London: Verso, 2014). In this last work, Poulantzas noted the curious resonance between Foucault’s aversion to the state and North American po­liti­cal scientists like Easton. See Poulantzas, State, Power, , 44. As I elaborate in more detail below, this is why it is impor­tant to pair Foucault’s analy­sis of the “micro- physics” of power dispersed throughout society with Louis Althusser’s theory of isas,

192 Notes to Introduction so that we can account for how the operations of power that Foucault finds dispersed throughout society do in fact circulate through and congeal in certain institutions and juridical-­penal practices to produce what Timothy Mitchell has called “the state-­effect,” ­whether or not such institutions or practices are juridically defined as belonging to the state. ­Here I follow Bob Jessop and Thomas Lemke, who each in their own way under- stand par­tic­u­lar operations of power in society as within the strategic field of the state. Bob Jessop, State Power: A Strategic-­Relational Approach (Cambridge: Polity, 2008); and Lemke, Foucault, Governmentality, and Critique. 36. I seek to ­counter the well-­known “god that failed” thesis of communist disillu- sion and defection, for, beyond the strategic errors of the Communist International that Poulantzas and ­others have analyzed, if the god of communism failed, it was partly ­because other gods ­were at work against communism: in this case, quite literally the purportedly divine emperor and the Japa­nese spirit (nihon seishin). The meta­phor of the god that failed comes from a collection by the same name: Richard Crossman, ed., The God That Failed (New York: Bantam, 1950). It should be noted that among the contributors to this volume is Arthur Koestler of “ghost in the machine” fame. For the strategic failures of the Comintern policies to combat the rise of fascism, see Nicos Poulantzas, Fascism and Dictatorship: The Third International and the Prob­lem of Fascism, trans. Judith White (London: Verso, 1979). 37. Nihon Keisatsusha, ed., Shisō keisatsu tsūron, rev. ed. (Tokyo: Nihon Keisatsusha, 1940), 1. 38. For a history of the term “kokutai” in modern Japan, see Konno Nobuyuki, Kindai nihon no kokutairon (Tokyo: Perikansha, 2008). 39. See Louis Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes ­Towards an Investigation),” in Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2001), 85–126; and Louis Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism: Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses, trans. G. M. Goshgarian (London: Verso, 2014); Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Vintage, 1995); Michel Foucault, The Punitive Society: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1972–­1973, trans. Graham Burchell (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015); Michel Foucault, “Society Must Be Defended”: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975– 1976, trans. David Macey (New York: Picador, 2003); Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism. 40. See Warren Montag, “ ‘The Soul Is the Prison of the Body’: Althusser and Fou- cault, 1970–1975,” Yale French Studies, no. 88 (1995): 53–77; Warren Montag, “Althusser and Foucault: Apparatuses of Subjection,” in Althusser and His Contemporaries: Philoso- phy’s Perpetual War (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2013). My analy­sis has also been influenced by Jason Read,The Micro-­Politics of Capital: Marx and the Prehistory of the Pres­ent (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003); and Jan Rehmann, Theories of Ideology: The Powers of Alienation and Subjection (Chicago: Haymarket, 2013). 41. Jessop, State Power. As Stuart Hall reminds us, however, Poulantzas’s attempt to craft a new theory of the state by bringing together Althusser’s structuralist Marxism and Foucault’s poststructural theory of power produces its own unique (and for Hall, insurmountable) prob­lems. See: Stuart Hall, “Nicos Poulantzas: State, Power, Social- ism” in Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism, vii–­xvii.

Notes to Introduction 193 42. Michel Foucault, “Body/Power” in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977, 58. Indeed, as I discuss in chapter 3, this assumption has informed conventional explanations of the ideological conversion phenomenon in interwar Japan, in which it was explained that the state’s ability to successfully coerce activists to change their ideas indicated the weakness of liberal subjectivity (shutaisei) in prewar Japan. 43. Montag, “ ‘The Soul Is the Prison of the Body,’ ” 59. 44. See Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 114. Althusser calls theories of ideology that rest upon idealist dualities of mind and body, ideas and real­ity, the “ideology of ideology.” He points to how the­ se kinds of dualisms lead to a theory of ideology as the mystification of the mind that distorts or inverts an objec- tive, external real­ity. In eighteenth-­century Enlightenment theories of ideology, this mystification was attributed to despots; in the nineteenth c­ entury, Althusser tells us, Ludwig Feuerbach and the early writings of Karl Marx attributed this mystification to the par­tic­u­lar forms of social existence. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 110–111. 45. Harry Harootunian, “ Redux,” Critical Asian Studies 33, no. 4 (2001): 609. I consider this point further in chapter 3. 46. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 123. Italics in the original. 47. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 123. 48. I thank Tak Fujitani for his insightful suggestions regarding Foucault’s threefold schema of power in relation to my research. 49. On governmentality, see Michel Foucault, “Governmentality,” in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), 87–104. My reading of Foucault’s tripartite theory of power has been influenced by Lemke,Foucault, Governmentality, and Critique. 50. Foucault, “Governmentality,” 102. ­Here, I am influenced by Takashi Fujitani who, in his first book,Splendid Monarchy (1996), argued that, in contrast to Foucault’s his- torical narrative in Discipline and Punish, monarchical and disciplinary power converged in Meiji Japan: that is, the monarch was the vis­i­ble sovereign of the new polity, as well as the observer who disciplined society through his panoptic gaze. See Fujitani, Splendid Monarchy, 141–145. Fujitani’s more recent work finds Foucault’s theory of governmen- tality manifest in the colonial governance of ­Korea in the 1930s, particularly ­after 1937, when “colonial power began to constitute Koreans as a population that in the aggregate should be healthy, reproductive, and long lived.” Takashi Fujitani, “Right to Kill, Right to Make Live: Koreans as Japa­nese and Japa­nese as Americans during WWII,” Represen­ ­ ta­tions 99, no. 1 (summer 2007): 16. 51. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 96, 97, 100. 52. Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism, 33. 53. On “bad subjects,” see Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 123. I pursue this theoretical question further in a forthcoming article, Max Ward, “Cin- ema of ‘Bad Subjects:’ The Limits of the Kafkaesque Subject in Ōshima Nagisa’s Death by Hanging (1968)” forthcoming in CineEast: Journal of East Asian Cinemas. 194 Notes to Introduction 54. Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism, 37. On Poulantzas’s theory of the “strategic field” of the state, see Jessop,State Power, 123–126. Interestingly, when Poulantzas turns his attention to Althusser, he seems to replicate Foucault’s general critique of theories that reduce the operation of state power to repression alone. For example, Poulant- zas argues that Althusser’s thesis “rests on the idea of a State that acts and functions through repression and ideological inculcation, and nothing ­else. It assumes that the State’s efficacy somehow lies in what it forbids, rules out, and prevents; or in its capac- ity to deceive, lie, obscure, hide, and lead ­people to believe what is false.” Revealing Foucault’s influence, Poulantzas c­ ounters, “the State also acts in a positive fashion, cre- ating, transforming and making real­ity.” Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism, 30. However, as I argue, Althusser’s isa theory allows for such productive aspects of power. 55. On Althusser’s distinction between secondary and primary ideologies, see Al- thusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism, 83–84. 56. I thank Katsuya Hirano for suggesting that I make this theoretical distinction more explicit. As many critics have argued, Althusser failed to adequately theorize inter- pellation as well as the connection between the practical operations of the isas and the always already interpellated subject. However, my objective in Thought Crime is to understand how the vari­ous institutions within the Peace Preservation Law apparatus functioned to rehabilitate po­liti­cal criminals, and how we might read the ideological forms and practices inscribed in ­these apparatuses as indexing the transformation of imperial ideology in the 1930s. Therefore, I­w ill disregard Althusser’s psychoanalyti- cal theory of interpellation and focus on his theory of isas. For critiques of Althusser’s theory of interpellation, see Judith Butler, “Conscience Doth Make Subjects of Us All: Althusser’s Subjection,” in The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997), 106–131; Slavoj Žižek, The Sublime Object of Ideology (London: Verso, 2008), 42–43. For a recent counter-­argument which I be- lieve provides a more persuasive and productive reading of Althusser’s theory of isas and ideology, see Matthew Lampert, “Resisting Ideology: On Butler’s Critique of Althusser” in Diacritics Vol. 43, No. 2 (2015), 124–147. 57. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 112. 58. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 114. Montag contends that this is not a linear or causal sequence in which a preexisting ideology creates the­ se apparatuses and their constitutive ritualized practices, but rather that “ideology is immanent in its apparatuses and their practices, it has no existence apart from the­ se apparatuses and is entirely coincident with them.” Montag, “ ‘The Soul Is the Prison of the Body,’ ” 63. 59. Mitchell, Janus-Faced­ Justice. 60. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 123. 61. Foucault, “Governmentality,” 87–104. 62. Foucault, “Governmentality,” 103. 63. I believe that my critical-­theoretical analy­sis of the official documents does not reproduce the errors that Herbert Bix faults Richard Mitchell for committing: namely that by only using official sources, Mitchell has written a history of the Peace Preserva- tion Law from a “ruling class perspective.” See Bix, “Kawakami Hajime and the Organic Law of Japa­nese Fascism,” 131. Notes to Introduction 195 Chapter 1. Kokutai and the Aporias of Imperial Sovereignty 1. For studies of the Peace Preservation Law, see Matsuo Hiroshi, Chianijihō: Danatsu to teikō no rekishi (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1971) and Matsuo Hiroshi, Chianijihō to tokkō keisatsu (Tokyo: Kyōikusha, 1979); Ushiomi Toshitaka, Chianijihō (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1977); Okudaira Yasuhiro, Chianijihō shōshi, new ed. (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2006); Richard H. Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925: Its Origins and Significance,”Monumenta Nipponica 28, no. 3 (autumn 1973), 317–345; Richard H. Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1976); and Ogino Fujio, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1993). For the relationship between po­liti­cal parties and the Peace Preservation Law, see Nakazawa Shunsuke, Chianijihō: Naze seitō seiji ha “akuhō” o unda ka (Tokyo: Chūōkō Shinsho, 2012). For a ­legal analy­sis of the Peace Preservation Law, see Uchida Hirofumi, Chianijihō no kyōkun: Kenri undō to kenpō kaisei (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 2016). On the application of the Peace Preservation Law in colonial ­Korea, see Mizuno Naoki, “Nihon no chōsen shihai to chianijihō,” in Chōsen no kindaishi to nihon, ed. Hatada Takeshi (Tokyo: Yamato Shobō, 1987), 127–140; Mizuno Naoki, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no tekiyō,” in Shokuminchi teikoku nihon no hōteki kōzō, ed. Asano Toyomi and Matsuda Toshihiko (Tokyo: Shinzansha Shuppan, 2004), 417–459; Suzuki Keifu, Chōsen shokuminchi tōchihō no kenkyū: Chianhō ka no kōminka kyōiku (Sap- poro: Hokkaidō Daigaku Tosho Kankōkai, 1989); Hong Jong-­wook, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-tachi­ (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2011). 2. Okudaira Yasuhiro argues that the only previous appearance of kokutai in a law was in the 1873 Newspaper Ordinance (Shimbunshi hakkōjōme), signifying something akin to national prestige (kokui). See Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 60. 3. For a complete En­glish translation of the Meiji Constitution, see Appendix X in George M. Beckmann, The Making of the Meiji Constitution: The Oligarchs and the Con- stitutional Development of Japan, 1868–1891 (Westport, CT: Greenwood, 1957; reprint, 1975), 150–156. 4. On an earlier pro­cess of refiguring neo-­Confucian categories to speak to new geopo­litical­ circumstances, see Bob Tadashi Wakabayashi, Anti-­foreignism and Western Learning in Early Modern Japan: The New ­Theses of 1825, Harvard East Asian Mono- graphs 126 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992). 5. For the full En­glish translation of the Rescript, see Wm. Theodore de Bary, Carol Gluck, and Arthur E. Tiedemann, eds., Sources of Japa­nese Tradition, vol. 2: 1600–2000, Part Two, 1868–2000 (New York: Columbia University Press), 108–109. For the early debates over interpreting the Rescript, see Sharon Nolte, “National Morality and Universal Ethics: Onishi Hajime and the Imperial Rescript on Education,” Monumenta Nipponica 38, no. 3 (autumn 1983): 283–294. 6. On ­these debates, see Walter A. Skya, Japan’s Holy War: The Ideology of Radical Shintō Ultranationalism (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2009). 7. For an overview of theories of kokutai in modern Japan, see Konno Nobuyuki, Kindai nihon no kokutairon (Tokyo: Perikansha, 2008). 8. Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Shiryō kaisetsu,” in Gendaishi shiryō 45: Chianijihō, ed. Oku- daira Yasuhiro (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 1973), xx, cited ­here ­after asgss 45. Okudaira 196 Notes to Chapter 1 points to kokutai’s usage in early modern Kokugaku writings as signifying “national customs” (kuniburi) and its appearance in the Imperial Rescript on Education and State Shinto education. See also Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Some Preparatory Notes for the Study of the Peace Preservation Law in Pre-­war Japan,” Annals of the Institute of Social Science 14 (1973): 49–69; and Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 56–65. 9. Okudaira, “Shiryō kaisetsu,” xv. See also Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 104. 10. Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925,” 343. Drawing upon Durkheim’s so­cio­log­i­cal understanding of law as a means of social integration, Patricia Steinhoff argues that kokutai signified both “the­le gal and constitutional structure of the nation and its spiritual and cultural structure centering around the emperor system and the ­family system.” Thus, by defining a crime as “changing [or altering] thekokutai ,” the law was meant to defend “the po­liti­cal system, traditional social relationships, and the central symbols of the nation.” Patricia Steinhoff,Tenkō: Ideology and Societal Integration in Prewar Japan (New York: Garland, 1991), 33. 11. For examples of how this assumption has informed analyses of the law in the colo- nies, see Chulwoo Lee, “Modernity, Legality, and Power in ­Korea ­under Japa­nese Rule,” in Colonial Modernity in ­Korea, ed. Gi-­Wook Shin and Michael Robinson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 21–51, especially Lee’s discussion of kokutai, 45–46. 12. For an example of this distinction in the area studies paradigm, see Richard H. Minear, Japa­nese Tradition and Western Law: Emperor, State, and Law in the Thought of Hozumi Yatsuka (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1970). 13. Ogino, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei, 14. Ogino’s use of maryoku recalls Tsurumi Shunsuke’s earlier thesis of the “amuletic use of words” during the interwar period, in which kokutai served as one of Tsurumi’s prime examples. For Tsurumi, this meant that ­these terms ­were invoked without a clear sense of what they meant and allowed the masses to be misled by the state. Tsurumi’s thesis was premised upon a faith that words could be concretely understood, which would undermine their ideological uses. See Tsurumi Shunsuke, “Kotoba no omamoriteki shiyōhō ni tsuite,” Shisō no kagaku 1 (May 1946); En­glish translation, F. J. Daniels, “Mr. Tsurumi-­Syunsuke on the ‘Amuletic’ Use of Words: A Translation, with Commentary,” Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, University of London 18, no. 3 (1956): 514–533. 14. Ogino, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei, 30, 31, 34, and 4–5. 15. For instance, see William Scheuerman’s analy­sis of Locke’s argument for a liberal “rule of law.” William Scheuerman, Between the Norm and the Exception: The Frankfurt School and the Rule of Law (Cambridge, MA: mit Press, 1994), 68–70. 16. Robert H. Jackson, Sovereignty: Evolution of an Idea (Cambridge: Polity, 2007), ix. 17. Hans Kelmo and Quentin Skinner, “Introduction: A Concept in Fragments,” in Sovereignty in Fragments: The Past, Pres­ent and ­Future of a Contested Concept, ed. Hans Kelmo and Quentin Skinner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 3–4. 18. Jens Bartelson, Sovereignty as Symbolic Form (London: Routledge, 2014), 4. 19. Jens Bartelson, A Genealogy of Sovereignty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 51. 20. Bartelson’s primary concern is with the epistemological conditions for concep- tualizing sovereignty in po­liti­cal theory. However, his observations can also apply to Notes to Chapter 1 197 po ­liti­cal practices that invoke sovereignty as their condition of possibility. This kind of inquiry has been pursued along a dif­fer­ent theoretical trajectory by Guillaume Sibertin-­Blanc, and his reconsideration of Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari in rela- tion to Marxist theories of the state. See Guillaume Sibertin-­Blanc, State and Politics: Deleuze and Guattari on Marx, trans. Ames Hodges (Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2016), in par­tic­u­lar chapter 2, “Capture: For a Concept of Primitive Accumulation of State Power,” 45–83. 21. This paradox of sovereignty as a “composite of inside and outside” of the nation-­ state can, when shorn of its Kantian basis, perhaps be considered along with Gavin Walker’s theory of the paradox of primitive or original cap­it­al­ist accumulation, in which capital reproduces and redemarcates an outside internal to itself as the condition for its own reproduction. This returns Bartelson and ­others’ discursive analyses to the socio- historical—in other words, the material—­practices and social relationships constitutive of cap­i­tal­ist modernity. See Gavin Walker, The Sublime Perversion of Capital: Marxist Theory and the Politics of History in Modern Japan (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2016). 22. As is well known, Schmitt argued that the constitutional norm is grounded upon a constituent power that is not completely prescribed by constitutional norms. In contrast to ­legal positivism, which assumed a pure realm of juridical rationality, Schmitt posited the primacy of the po­liti­cal state and the sovereign, which, in a decision to sus- pend the constitution during a crisis, exposes the ontological ground of le­ gal rationality, what Schmitt called “concrete life.” It was not the substantive qualities of the sovereign decision conjured during the exception that interested Schmitt, but rather the notion of the decision itself and how it revealed the po­litical­ ontology of a constitutional order. Carl Schmitt,Po ­liti­cal Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, trans. George Schwab (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985). On recent theorists, see Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, trans. Daniel Heller-­ Roazen (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1998); Giorgio Agamben, State of Exception, trans. Kevin Attell (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005); David Dyzenhaus, “The Politics of the Question of Constituent Power,” inThe Paradox of Constitutionalism: Constituent Power and Constitutional Form, ed. Martin Loughlin and Neil Walker (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). 23. For a provocative reading of Schmitt with Marx, see Gavin Walker, “Primitive Accumulation and the Formation of Difference: On Marx and Schmitt,”Rethinking Marxism 23, no. 3 (2011): 384–404. 24. In other words, it is a perpetual “event” inscribed in the constitutional order, which is assumed as its origin. See the editors’ introduction to Martin Loughlin and Neil Walker, eds., The Paradox of Constitutionalism: Constituent Power and Constitutional Form (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 2. 25. William E. Connolly, “The Complexities of Sovereignty,” inGiorgio Agamben: Sovereignty and Life, ed. Matthew Calarco and Steven DeCaroli (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2007), 24. 26. Appendix X in Beckmann, The Making of the Meiji Constitution, 150. 27. Jean-­Jacques Rousseau, cited in Connolly, “The Complexities of Sovereignty,” 24.

198 Notes to Chapter 1 28. Itō Hirobumi, Commentaries on the Constitution of the , 2nd ed., trans. Miyoji Ito (Tokyo: Chūō Daigaku, 1906), 2–3. 29. On this point of the presuppositions of the sovereign state, see Guillaume Sibertin-­Blanc, “Aporia in the Origin of the State: Impossible Genesis and Untraceable Beginning,” and “The Movement of Self-­Presupposition of the Urstaat: Antinomic His- tory of the State-­Form,” in Sibertin-­Blanc, State and Politics, 24–31, and 31–38. 30. See Takashi Fujitani, “The Constitution’s Promulgation,” inSplendid Monarchy: Power and Pageantry in Modern Japan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1996), 107–111. 31. Agamben, Homo Sacer, 26. 32. See Schmitt,Po liti­ ­cal Theology, 6–7; the editors’ introduction to Loughlin and Walker, The Paradox of Constitutionalism, 2–4; Agamben, State of Exception, particularly chapter 1. 33. Addressing a dif­fer­ent problematic, Poulantzas argues, “The activity of the State always overflows the banks of law, since it can, within certain limits, modify its own law. The State is not the ­simple repre­sen­ta­tion of some eternal law, be it a universal prohibi- tion or a law of nature. If such ­were the case—­and this needs to be made clear—­law would have de jure primacy over the State.” Nicos Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism, trans. Patrick Camiller (London: Verso, 2014), 85. In another direction, Guillaume Sibertin-­Blanc has explored this through Deleuze and Guattari’s idea of theUrstaat , a state form that pres­ents itself as its own its condition of possibility. See Sibertin-­Blanc, State and Politics, 22. 34. Mizuno Naoki, “Chianijihō to Chōsen: Oboegaki,” Chōsen kenkyū 188, no. 4 (1979): 46. For an overview of the dif­fer­ent ­legal systems in Japan’s empire, see Edward I-te Chen, “The Attempt to Integrate the Empire: ­Legal Perspectives,” in The Japanese­ Colonial Empire, 1895–1945, ed. Ramon H. Myers and Mark R. Peattie (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1984), 240–274. 35. For an overview of the Morito Incident, see Miyachi Masato, “Morito Tatsuo jiken: Gakumon no jiyū no hatsu no shiren,” in Nihon seiji saiban shiroku 3: Taishō, ed. Wagatsuma Sakae (Tokyo: Daiichi Hōki Shuppan, 1969), 228–272; Richard Mitchell, Censorship in Imperial Japan (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1983), 182–189. Article 42 of the Newspaper Law stated that the author, editor, or publisher of any printed material that “profanes the majesty of the imperial ­house­hold” (kōshitsu no songen o bōtoku), calls to “change the state form” (seitai no henkai), or “subverts the laws of the state” (chōken o binran) can be imprisoned for up to two years. See Miyachi, “Morito Tatsuo Jiken,” 239. Article 23 of this 1909 law also defined an infringement as publishing material that “disturbs the public peace” (annei chitsujo o midashi) or “dam- ages customs” (fūzoku o gai suru). 36. The decision, along with the vari­ous appeals, is reprinted in Miyachi, “Morito Tatsuo Jiken,” 253–271. 37. On the Rice Riots, see Michael Lewis, Rioters and Citizens: Mass Protest in Impe- rial Japan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990); on the Rice Riots in relation to security laws, see Matsuo, Chianijihō, 80–82. On the March First Movement, see Frank Baldwin, “Participatory Anti-impe­ rialism: The 1919 Inde­ ­pende­ nce Movement,”

Notes to Chapter 1 199 Journal of Korean Studies 1 (1979): 123–162. For the Japa­nese Government-­General’s re- sponse to the March First movement, see Mark E. Caprio, Japa­nese Assimilation Policies in Colonial ­Korea, 1910–1945 (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 2009), chapters 3 and 4. 38. Naimushō keihokyoku, “Kagekishugi torishimarihō (amerika, furansu, doitsu, berugii, roshia, burajiru, igirisu, itaria),” September 1921, reprinted in Ogino Fujio, ed., Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1 (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 56–73. 39. Existing laws such as the 1909 Newspaper Law (Shimbunshihō) used to prosecute Morito and Ōuchi criminalized the publication and distribution of any print material that “disrupts the public peace” (annei chitsujo binran) or “subverted the laws of the state” (chōken o binran), among other offenses. Another existing law, the 1900 Public Peace Police Law, established a registration system for po­liti­cal groups, thus restricting the formation and assembly of any groups that ­were not first cleared with the police. This 1900 law also granted the police powers to interrupt speeches or assemblies that ­were interpreted as threatening the public peace (annei chitsujo) and allowed the to pursue suspected secret po­liti­cal organ­izations. The 1922 Antiradical Bill inherited some of the language of ­these laws, as well as their emphasis on distributing or propagating subversive materials. ­Because of this, many legislators questioned why a new law was necessary if ­these other laws already covered similar crimes. 40. On this 1922 bill, see Matsuo Takayoshi, “Kageki shakaishugi undō torishi- mari hōan ni tsuite: 1922nen dai45gikai ni okeru,” Jinbun Gakuhō 20 (October 1964): 247–267. 41. Naimushō, “Kageki shakai undō torishimari hōritsuan keika” (January 1923), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 23. 42. For an overview of ­these three security mea­sures in colonial ­Korea, see Mizuno Naoki, “Chianijihō no seitei to shokuminchi Chōsen,” Jinbun Gakuhō 83 (March 2000): 99–100, 101–105, and 105–107, respectively. See also Lee, “Modernity, Legality, and Power in ­Korea ­under Japa­nese Rule,” 42–43. 43. Mizuno, “Chianijihō no seitei to shokuminchi Chōsen,” 105; Lee, “Modernity, Legality, and Power in ­Korea unde­ r Japa­nese Rule,” 43. 44. This variety of public peace ordinances in colonial­Kor ea would ­later produce a significant amount of debate concerning when to apply the Peace Preservation Law over other ordinances. For an overview of ­these ordinances in relation to the Peace Preservation Law, see the May 1939 Justice Ministry report by Yoshida Hajime, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” Shisō jōsei shisatsu hōkokushū (Sono 6), in Shisō kenkyū shiryō: Tokushū dai 69 gō, ed. Shihōshō keijikyoku, reprinted in Shakai mondai shiryō sōsho: Dai 1 shū (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1971), 1–2. 45. The bill was delivered by Justice Minister Ōki Enkichi and Home Minister To- konami Takejirō. The preliminary drafts of the bill are reproduced in Ogino,Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 25–38. 46. Cited in gss45, 6. The Chian keisatsu hō is reproduced in Ogino,Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 17–19. 47. Article 6 of the bill extended coverage to the activities of Japa­nese nationals outside of the country. See gss45, 4; and Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925,” 331.

200 Notes to Chapter 1 48. gss45, 7. 49. gss45, 7. 50. En­glish translation in Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925,” 331. Translation amended. Original Japa­nese can be found in gss45, 3–4. Also in Shihōshō keijikyoku shisōbu, ed., Dai45kai teikoku gikai: Kageki shakai undō torishimari hōan giji sokkiroku narabini iinkai giji sokkiroku. Shisō kenkyū shiryō, Tokushū dai 10 gō (Shihōshō keijikyoku, 1934), republished by Shakai mondai shiryō kenkyūkai, vol. 1, no. 8 (Tokyo: Tōyōbunkasha, 1972), 1–2. Hereafter this collection cited as smskk, vol. 1, no. 8. 51. Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925,” 331. Translation amended. Article 2 applied to anyone who formed a society or meeting in order to carry out the propaganda activities listed in Article 1. Article 4 criminalized anyone who gave finan- cial support to such activities; Article 5 stipulated leniency to thos­ e who cooperated; and Article 6 stated that the above crimes applied to Japa­nese subjects who engaged in such activities abroad. 52. gss45, 6. 53. smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 46–47. In response to a question concerning the meaning of chōken binran, Hayashi pointed to earlier uses of the term and argued that it meant “to illegally destroy the fundamental laws of the state.” smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 34–35. 54. On kokutai in Hozumi Yatsuka’s early constitutional interpretations, see Skya, Japan’s Holy War, 63–64. On the constitutional debate between Uesugi Shinkichi and Minobe Tatsukichi over the term “kokutai,” see Skya, Japan’s Holy War, 158; Minear, Japa­nese Tradition and Western Law, 64–71; and Frank O. Miller, Minobe Tatsukichi: Interpreter of Constitutionalism in Japan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1965), 60–72. 55. Historians disagree about which bill was more ambiguous. Richard Mitchell argues that the term “chōken” used in the 1922 Antiradical Bill was a much clearer category than kokutai and could have averted the “­legal Hydra” that was created when kokutai was used in the 1925 bill. See Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 67. In contrast, Elise Tipton argues that “the phrases ‘attempt to change thekokutai ’ and ‘denial of the private property system’ [in the ­later Peace Preservation Law] represented Home Ministry officials’ attempts to limit and clarify the scope of the law, for they ­replaced traditionally used but vague phrases, such as ‘subvert the Constitution and laws of the state’ and ‘public peace and order.’ ” Elise Tipton, The Japa­nese Police State: The Tokkō in Interwar Japan (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1990), 112. 56. smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 63. 57. smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 63. 58. The edited bill is reprinted in smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 198–199. 59. smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 49. However, the Home Ministry had already defined ­these terms in a report before the bill was presented to the Diet in February 1922. In this document, drafted by Police Bureau commissioner Kawamura Teishirō, it is explained that “is an ideology that rejects state authority” and “does not recognize the existence of the state.” In regard to communism, Kawamura explained that it is “an ideology that calls for abolishing the system of private property—the­ basis of our current economic organi­zation—a­ nd that property . . . ​be socialized [shakai no kyōyū].”

Notes to Chapter 1 201 Naimushō, “Kageki shakai undō torishimari hō shakugi” written by Kawamura Teishirō, February 1922, reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 46, 46–47. Kawamura extended the potential application of this law to other po­liti­cal movements as well, noting that Article 1 would apply to anarchism, syndicalism, Bolshevism, and republicanism; Articles 1 and 3 would apply to communism, syndicalism, and guild socialism; and Article 3 would apply to state socialism. See Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 46. 60. Ogino Fujio has shown that even though “anarchism” and “communism” ­were deleted from the bill, ­these remained the intended targets that threatened “the laws of state” and “fundamental structure of society” respectively. See Ogino, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei, 17–18. This would also inform the targets of the Peace Preservation Bill, in which kokutai was said to target anarchism, and “private property system” would apply to communism (32). 61. See Nijō Atsumoto’s summary of the changes to the law by the time it reached the Lower House: smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 199–207. 62. The revised bill deliberated in the is reproduced in smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 320–321. See the subsequent explanation by Tokonami Takejirō about ­these revi- sions: smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 326–327, 328–330. 63. Translation of Article 1 from Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 48, trans- lation amended. 64. This is in reference to the activities of Kondō Eizō, who went to Shanghai in May 1921 to meet with Comintern agents. He returned to Japan with a large amount of money and was subsequently detained by the police in Shimonoseki. Lacking evidence, the police released Kondō and upon his arrival in Tokyo he formed a communist group among radicals from the Enlightened P­ eople’s Society (Gyōminkai). The police arrested members distributing leaflets in October 1921, rounding up the rest of the members in November. This came to be known as the Enlightened ­People’s Communist Party Incident (Gyōmin kyōsantō jiken). See George M. Beckmann and Genji Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 1922–1945 (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1969), 32–35. 65. On law in the formation of the Japa­nese Empire, see the essays collected in Asano Toyomi and Matsuda Toshihiko, eds., Shokuminchi teikoku nihon no hōteki tenkai (Tokyo: Shinzansha, 2004). 66. Chen, “The Attempt to Integrate the Empire,” 241–242. 67. Naimushō, “Kageki shakai undō torishimari hō shakugi,” 47. It should be noted that early Home Ministry drafts of what became the Antiradical Bill explic­itly contained terms that Kawamura had used to explain the phrase “to subvert the laws of state.” For instance, see the ordinance draft chokureian( ) of August 20, 1922, in which Article 1 reads in part, “individuals who engage in activities in order to subvert the laws of state such as to overthrow the government or seizing part of the realm [seifu o tenpuku shi mata ha hōdo o sensetsu] ­shall be sentenced to up to ten years in prison.” Reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 31. 68. Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no tekiyō,” 420. The only hint of this kind of interpretation appeared in passing, when, in a House of

202 Notes to Chapter 1 Peers committee meeting on March 14, Home Minister Tokonami Takejirō declared, “Recently in our country socialists have contacted the communist party of Rus­sia and are spreading extremism. They have received funds directly from the worker-­farmer government of Rus­sia in order to establish a Bolshevik movement [sekka undō]. Fur- thermore, Koreans have served as go-­between, and are using the Bolshevik movement for the objective of Korean inde­ ­pen­dence.” However, Tokonami was emphasizing the po­liti­cal context in which the bill was drafted, and did not specifically make the connec- tion between “subverting the laws of the state” and calling for Korean in­de­pen­dence. To- konami Takejirō, in the fifth committee meeting of the House of Peers on March 14, 1922, reprinted in smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 119. See also Mizuno, “Chianijihō no seitei to shokumin- chi Chōsen,” 111; Matsuo, “Kageki shakaishugi undō torishimari hōan ni tsuite,” 248–249. 69. Naimushō, “Kageki shakai undō torishimari hō shakugi,” 52. Cited in Mizuno, “Chianijihō no seitei to shokuminchi Chōsen,” 111–112. 70. Itō Sukehiro and Miyagi Chōgorō’s exchange is reprinted in smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 110. Also cited in Mizuno, “Chianijihō no seitei to shokuminchi Chōsen,” 112. 71. Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925,” 332. 72. Mitchell summarized the February 21 Tokyo edition of an Asahi Shimbun edito- rial. See Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925,” 332. 73. For example, see Yuasa Kurahei’s continuing criticism of the ambiguity of this bill in the House of Peers on March 23, in smskk, vol. 1, no. 8, 332–339. 74. On the first formation of the jcp, its suppression and self-­dissolution, see Beck- mann and Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 48–78; Odanaka Toshiki, “Dai ichi kyōsantō jiken: Nihon kyōsantō sōritsu to chianijihō jidai zenya no saiban,” in Wagat- suma, Nihon seiji saiban shiroku 3, 339–378; Richard H. Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice: Po­ liti­cal Criminals in Imperial Japan (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1992), 36–40. 75. On the Peace Preservation Law in the context of establishing diplomatic relations with the Soviet Union, see Kobayashi Yukio, “Nisso kihon jōyaku daigojō to chianijihō” (1959), in Nisso seiji gaikōshi: Roshia kakumei to Chianijihō (Tokyo, Yūhikaku, 1985), 309–352. 76. On the Universal Male Suffrage Bill and thel­ ater 1928 general election, see Thomas Havens, “Japan’s Enigmatic Election of 1928,”Modern Asian Studies 11, no. 4 (1977): 543–555. It is often argued that since universal male suffrage and the Peace Pres- ervation Law ­were passed within months of each other, they serve as a kind of carrot-­ and-stick­ (ame to muchi) approach used by the state in dealing with reform movements. However, Okudaira, Nakazawa, and Mizuno have all critiqued this explanation since the two laws originated in­de­pen­dently from each other and developed through their own ministerial and legislative pro­cesses. See Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 49–56; Naka- zawa, Chianijihō, 44–46; Mizuno, “Nihon no chōsen shihai to chianijihō,” 128–129. 77. See Mizuno, “Chianijihō no seitei to shokuminchi Chōsen,” 109. 78. On the earthquake, see J. Charles Schencking, The Gr­ eat Kanto Earthquake and the Chimera of National Reconstruction in Japan (New York: Columbia University Press, 2013). 79. See Nimura Kazuo, “Kantō daishinsai to kameido jiken,” Rekishi Hyōron 281 (Octo- ber 1973): 39–69; Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice, 41–43.

Notes to Chapter 1 203 80. See Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice, 45–49; Tamiya Hiroshi, “Amakasu jiken: Kenpei ni gyakusatsu sareta museifushugisha Ōsugi Sakae,” in Wagatsuma, Nihon seiji saiban shiroku 3, 412–438. 81. On ­these pogroms, see J. Michael Allen, “The Price of Identity: The 1923 Kantō Earthquake and Its Aftermath,”Korean Studies 20 (1996): 64–96. 82. See Sonia Ryang, “The­Gr eat Kantō Earthquake and the Massacre of Koreans in 1923: Notes on Japan’s Modern National Sovereignty,” Anthropological Quarterly 76, no. 4 (Autumn 2003): 731–748; Takashi Fujitani, “Right to Kill, Right to Make Live: Koreans as Japa­nese and Japa­nese as Americans during WWII,” Represen­ ta­ tions­ 99, no. 1 (summer 2007): 13–39. 83. See Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 55–56. The ordinances and the subsequent debate to extend the ordinances are reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 82–85, 85–132. 84. On the Toranomon Incident and trial of Nanba Daisuke, see Tanaka Tokihiko, “Toranomon jiken: Kōtaishi o sogeki shita Nanba Daisuke,” in Wagatsuma, Nihon seiji saiban shiroku 3, 439–483; Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice, 49–51. 85. See: Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 33–46. 86. For instance, compare the flowcharts that Ogino has outlined concerning the pro­cess of drafting the Antiradical and Peace Preservation bills: Ogino Fujio, “Kaisetsu: Chianijihō seiritsu • ‘kaisei’ shi,” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 526 and 547, respectively. 87. See Okudaira, “Some Preparatory Notes,” 62. 88. Ogino, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei, 20–22; see the vari­ous Justice Ministry drafts collected in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 151–154. 89. Naimushō, “Chianijihō shingi zairyō” (1924), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 172–173; 172. For a discussion of this document, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 203. 90. None of the original documents remain of this draft ordinance, but Mizuno Naoki has culled from newspaper reports the basic motivation for and outline of the ordinance. He speculates that this work was in response to increasing ­labor activism and the formation of groups influenced by communism in 1924. See Mizuno, “Chianijihō no seitei to shokuminchi Chōsen,” 108–110. 91. Naimushō, “Chianijihōan narabini shōan” (1924), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol 1., 154–155. 92. The only exception was a January 24, 1925, proposed revision put forth by the Cabinet Legislation Bureau. See Ogino, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei, 22–27. 93. Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no tekiyō,” 421. 94. Historians generally agree that this new bill was better written and its advocates ­were better prepared to field questions during committee and Diet deliberations. Ad- ditionally, as indicated above, ­there had been more preparatory communication and collaboration between ministries. Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 45–47; Tipton, The Japa­ nese Police State, 22. 95. The first version of the bill presented to the Fiftieth Imperial Diet is reprinted in gss45, 51.

204 Notes to Chapter 1 96. ­These two concepts appear in the constitutional interpretations of Hozumi Yatsuka, Minobe Tatsukichi, and Uesugi Shinkichi. See Miller, Minobe Tatsukichi, 27–38, 65–67; Minear, Japa­nese Tradition and Western Law, 64–71; Skya, Japan’s Holy War, 62–64, 158. For an in­ter­est­ing reconsideration of kokutai as a mode of modern sub- jectivization, see Satofumi Kawamura, “The National Polity and the Formation of the Modern National Subject in Japan,” Japan Forum 26, no. 1 (2014): 25–45. Kawamura’s reconsideration of kokutai resonates with my analy­sis in ­later chapters of how the Peace Preservation Law became an apparatus for the rehabilitation of po­liti­cal criminals as loyal imperial subjects. 97. See Naimushō, “Chianijihōan ryakkai” (February 1925), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, 179–182; 180. 98. See Naimushō, “Chianijihō seitei no riyū oyobi kaishaku gaiyō” (February 1925), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, 182–183; 182. The German terms Sta- atsform and Regierungsform are rendered in roman characters in the text and can be roughly translated as “national polity” and “state form” respectively. 99. Shihōshō, “Kokutai, Seitai, Shiyūzaisan seido ni kansuru mondō” (Febru- ary 1925), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, 183–185; 183–184. 100. Naimushō, “Chianijihō seitei no riyū oyobi kaishaku gaiyō,” 183. 101. See Okudaira, “Some Preparatory Notes,” 62. 102. gss45, 52. As mentioned above, diplomatic relations w­ ere established with the Soviet Union in February. In addition to materials on the relationship between the Peace Preservation Law and diplomatic relations with the Soviet Union referenced above, see Kobayashi Yukio, Nisso seiji gaikōshi: Roshia kakumei to Chianijihō (Tokyo: Yūhikaku, 1985). 103. gss45, 52. 104. gss45, 53. 105. gss45, 54–55. 106. This includes the debates over “the system of private property” shiyūzaisan( seido) phrase as well. For instance, Hoshijima asked ­whether public works funded by the government, such as public utilities or the national rail system, constituted a repu- diation of the private property system. See gss45, 55. 107. gss45, 64. 108. gss45, 56. 109. gss45, 57. 110. gss45, 57. 111. gss45, 57. 112. See Maeda Yonezō’s explanation of the revisions in gss45, 92–99. 113. See Maeda’s explanation (gss45) and the arguments presented by Yokoyama Kintarō, Nakamura Keijirō, and Yamazaki Tatsunosuke to the March 6 committee in ­favor of deleting “seitai” from the bill. See gss45, 88–91. 114. The debates from March 7 are reprinted in Kōtō Hōin Kenjikyoku, ed.,Chianijihō teian tōgi: Teikoku gikai ni okeru shitsugi ōtō giji (Tokyo: Kōtō Hōin Kenjikyoku Shisōbu Hensan, 1928), 57. This collection cited asctt hereafter. 115. ctt, 65–66.

Notes to Chapter 1 205 116. ctt, 66–67, 72. 117. Kikuchi Kenjirō’s questions are reprinted in ctt, 69–71. 118. ctt, 72 119. ctt, 72. 120. Sawayanagi’s comments are reprinted in ctt, 138–143. 121. ctt, 138. 122. ctt, 139. 123. ctt, 144. 124. See for instance the exchange between Baron Den Kenjirō and Yamaoka Man- nosuke from the Justice Ministry in the Fourth Committee Meeting of the House of Peers on March 17. Reprinted in Shakai mondai shiryō kenkyūkai, ed., Chianijihōan giji sokkiroku narabi ni iin kaigi roku: Dai 50 kai teikoku gikai (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1972), 698–699. For a concise discussion of the geographic application of the law, see Mizuno, “Chianijihō to Chōsen,” 49–50. 125. See Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu ni taisuru chianijihō no tekiyō,” 421. See also Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 203. 126. ­These imperial decrees are reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 167–168. It should be noted that in addition to Japan’s formal colonies, the law was used to arrest Japa­nese radicals in Shanghai as well. See the reports drafted by the Japa­nese Consulate General in Shanghai covering the period 1927–1937, reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 566–574. 127. En­glish translation from Mitchell, “Japan’s Peace Preservation Law of 1925,” 339–340; and Mitchell, Thought Control in Imperial Japan, 63–64. Translation amended. For the final version that became law, seegss 45, 51. 128. This pamphlet was a transcript of an instructional lecture that Furuta gave to a police training group in 1925. See Furuta Masatake, Keisatsu kyōyō shiryō. Dai ippen: Chianijihō (Tokyo: Keisatsu Kōshū Jogaku Yūkai, 1925). 129. Furuta, Keisatsu kyōyō shiryō, 8–9. 130. Furuta, Keisatsu kyōyō shiryō, 9. 131. Furuta, Keisatsu kyōyō shiryō, 10. 132. See the four editorials from the Tokyo Asahi Shimbun collected in gss45, 100–104. 133. Kiyose’s essay “Chianijihō o ronzu” (1926) is reprinted in gss45, 104–112. 134. See gss45, 110–112. 135. Mizuno, “Chianijihō to Chōsen,” 52–53.

Chapter 2. Transcriptions of Power 1. On Althusser’s distinction between the Repressive State Apparatus and Ideological State Apparatuses, see Louis Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes T­ owards an Investigation),” in Lenin and Philosophy and other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2001), 85–126. I w­ ill discuss this distinc- tion in detail in chapter 3. 2. On arrests in the metropole, see Odanaka Toshiki, “San • ichigo, yon • ichiroku jiken: Chianijihō saiban to hōtei tōsō,” in Nihon seiji saiban shiroku, vol. 4: Shōwa • zen,

206 Notes to Chapter 1 ed. Wagatsuma Sakae (Tokyo: Daiichi Hōki Shuppan, 1968–1970), 148. Okudaira tallies a total of 14,622 arrests for 1933. See Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Chianijihō ihan jiken nendo betsu shori jinin hyō,” in Gendaishi shiryō 45: Chianijihō, ed Okudiara Yasuhiro (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 1973), 646–649, hereafter cited asgss 45. See also Nakazawa Shunsuke, Chianijihō: Naze seitō seiji ha “akuhō” o unda ka (Tokyo: Chūōkō Shinsho, 2012), 131. On the expansion of the law beyond the jcp, see Okudaira Yasuhiro, Chianijihō shōshi, new ed. (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2006), 138–147, 147–154, 192–239; Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 130–133; Matsuo Hiroshi, Chianijihō: Danatsu to teikō no rekishi (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1971), 156–163. 3. On Kobayashi Takiji and the proletarian lit­er­a­ture movement, see Donald Keene, “Japa­nese Lit­er­a­ture and Politics in the 1930s,” Journal of Japa­nese studies 2, no. 2 (summer 1976): 225–248; Heather Bowen-­Struyk, “Rethinking Japa­nese Prole- tarian Lit­er­a­ture” (PhD diss., Department of Comparative Lit­er­a­ture, University of Michigan, 2001). 4. For a discussion about the relatively high rate of indictment in the colony, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 204–207. 5. ­There are debates on ­whether any executions ­were carried out ­under the Peace Preservation Law. ­There w­ ere executions of Korean activists, but as Okudaira, Mizuno, and Mitchell note, ­these sentences drew upon other laws in addition to the Peace Preservation Law. On this debate, see Richard H. Mitchell, Janus-Faced­ Justice: Politi­ ­cal Criminals in Imperial Japan (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1992), 162–164. 6. Performing investigative and prosecutorial functions similar to district attorneys, procurators w­ ere assigned to district courts by the Justice Ministry. For brief histories of the procuracy in modern Japan, see Atsushi Nagashima, “The Accused and Society: The Administration of Criminal Justice in Japan” (excerpt), in The Japa­nese ­Legal System: Introductory Cases and Materials, ed. Hideo Tanaka (Tokyo: University of Tokyo Press, 1976), 541–547; Meryll Dean, Japa­nese ­Legal System: Text, Cases and Materials, 2nd ed. (London: Cavendish, 2002), 114–115. 7. Procurators ­were responsible for producing the Decision of the Preliminary Hear- ing (Yoshin shūketsu kettei sho), which was sent to the trial judge and served as the state’s case against a suspect. On this pro­cess, see Patricia Steinhoff,Tenkō: Ideology and Societal Integration in Prewar Japan (New York: Garland, 1991), 37. 8. On thought procurators, see Ogino Fujio, Shisō kenji (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2000). On the specific responsibilities and practices of thought procurators, see Tozawa Shigeo, “Shisō hanzai no kensatsu jitsumu ni tsuite” (1933), reprinted in Gendaishi Shiryō 16: Shakaishugi undō 3, ed. Yamabe Kintarō (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 1963), 15–36. On Japa­nese thought procurators in war­time colonial ­Korea, see Mizuno Naoki, “Shisō kenji-­tachi no ‘senchū’ to ‘sengo’: Shokuminchi shihai to shisō kenji,” in Nihon no Chōsen • Taiwan shihai to shokuminchi kanryō, ed. Matsuda Toshihiko and Yamada Atsushi (Kyoto: Shibunkaku Shuppan, 2009), 472–493. 9. The only study to focus on the role of Hirata Isao is Itō Akira, “Tenkō mondai no Ikkōsatsu: Nihonkyōsantō rōdōshaha to Hirata Isao,” Chiba kōgyō daigaku kenkyū hōkoku, no. 31 (February 1994): 29–41. In regard to the En­glish lit­er­a­ture, Hirata Isao re- ceives passing mention in Richard Mitchell’s pioneering studies (referred to as ­“Hirata

Notes to Chapter 2 207 Susumu”). See Richard H. Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan (Ithaca, NY: Cor- nell University Press, 1976), 171–172; and Mitchell, Janus-Faced­ Justice, 73–74, 77–78. 10. See Matsuo, Chianijihō. 11. For instance, Matsuo does not mention the tenkō policy in his history of the Peace Preservation Law. See Matsuo, Chianijihō. 12. By the 1930s, however, the Justice Ministry also implemented the law largely through administrative mea­sures rather than judicial proceedings. For instance, Okud- aira argues that ­because procurators and judges relied on the police to investigate and apprehend thought criminals, over time “the Ministry of Justice itself was inclined more to administrative regulations rather than to judicial ones.” Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Some Preparatory Notes for the Study of the Peace Preservation Law in Pre-­war Japan,” Annals of the Institute of Social Science 14 (1973): 58. 13. On the Special Higher Police, see Elise Tipton, The Japa­nese Police State: The Tokkō in Interwar Japan (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1990). 14. For example, Elise Tipton argues that the practices of the Special Higher Police in the 1930s reflected “rule by law” in which ­the“ re is a formal commitment to administra- tion ­under the law but a lack of ­legal limitation on policy formation.” Tipton notes that even rule by law was not fully implemented, leaving the police “substantially outside the control of justiciable law.” Tipton, The Japa­nese Police State, 53. 15. Mitchell, Janus-Faced­ Justice, 156–157. See also Patricia Steinhoff’s 1969 dissertation, reprinted as a book in 1991, in which tenkō is portrayed as an expression of “cultural pat- terns” of Japa­nese society. Steinhoff,Tenkō , 6. 16. Mitchell argues that while police from the Home Ministry often brutalized de- tainees illegally, continuing a long tradition dating back to the Meiji period, judges and procurators from the Justice Ministry defended the “procedural rights” of detainees and thus respected the “rule of law.” Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice, xii, 70. 17. See Michel Foucault, The Punitive Society: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1972–1973, trans. Graham Burchell (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015); Michel Foucault, Disci- pline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Vintage, 1977). Foucault allows us to ask dif­fer­ent questions in contrast to conventional studies of the Peace Preservation Law, including the legal-­administrative approach (e.g., Mitchell, Okudaira) as well as the integrative-­functionalist approach (e.g., Steinhoff, Hoston). 18. See Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 194. See also Michel Foucault, “Society Must Be Defended”: Lectures at the Collège de France, trans. David Macey (New York: Picador, 2003), lecture on January 14, 1976, 23–41. As I ­will argue in chapter 3, the path for Fou- cault’s intervention had already been cleared by Louis Althusser’s famous 1969–1970 article on ideology and ideological state apparatuses. See Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 85–126. 19. See for example the section “The Control of Activity” in Foucault,Discipline and Punish, 149–156. 20. Recently, scholars have argued that Foucault’s theory of disciplinary power re- veals impor­tant aspects of how power operates in cap­i­tal­ist society. See Jason Read, The Micro-­politics of Capital: Marx and the Prehistory of the Pres­ent (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003), in par­tic­ul­ar 83–90.

208 Notes to Chapter 2 21. This is derived from Jason Read’s concise summary of Foucault. See Read,The Micro-­politics of Capital, 85. 22. I refer to the En­glish translations of ­these works: Foucault, Discipline and Punish; and Michel Foucault, History of Sexuality, vol. 1: An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Vintage, 1978). 23. Foucault, The History of Sexuality, vol. 1, 144. For secondary studies on Fou- cault’s theory of law, see Alan Hunt and Gary Wickman, Foucault and Law: ­Towards a Sociology of Law as Governance (London: Pluto, 1994); Carole Smith, “The Sover- eign State v Foucault: Law and Disciplinary Power,” Socio­ log­ ­i­cal Review 48 (2000): 283–306. 24. Nicos Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism (London: Verso, 2014), 77. Poulantzas continues that Foucault “fails to understand the function of the repressive apparatuses (army, police, judicial system, e­ tc.) as means of exercising physical vio­lence that are located at the heart of the modern State. They are treated instead as mere parts of the disciplinary machine which patterns the internalization of repression by means of normalization” (77). 25. My objective is not to correct the reading of Foucault, but rather to emphasize specific points at which his more nuanced contemplations in his lectures generate new ways to consider the relationship between juridical and disciplinary power. ­Here I draw upon readings that have attempted to rethink the relationship between juridical and disciplinary modes of power in Foucault’s work. See, for instance, Ben Golder and Peter Fitzpatrick, Foucault’s Law (New York: Routledge, 2009). Jan Goldstein contends that Foucault “was never fully in control of his views on this issue and never arrived at a completely consistent formulation” of the relationship between law and discipline. Jan Goldstein, “Framing Discipline with Law: Prob­lems and Promises of the Liberal State,” American Historical Review 98, no. 2 (April 1993): 369. 26. See Foucault, The Punitive Society, 107, 110, 140. 27. See Goldstein, “Framing Discipline with Law.” 28. Foucault, “Society Must Be Defended,” 37. 29. Foucault, The Punitive Society, 178. Following his genealogical method, Foucault contends that criminology emerges from this transcription: that is, as a discourse that “assures the juridico-­medical transcription” of the criminal—­the target of juridical power—as, at the same time, the “delinquent” that requires disciplinary examination and rehabilitation (178). 30. Summarizing Foucault’s distinction, Jason Read has noted that “one can always fall short of a norm—­thus ­there is the possibility for an infinite intervention, continual surveillance, and improvement.” Read, The Micro-­politics of Capital, 85. 31. Foucault, The Punitive Society, 34, 131. 32. On the transition from repression to reform, I have in mind Serizawa Kazuya’s early work, in which he suggests that in the debates over law, sovereignty, and democ- racy in the 1920s, state power was effectively “freed” from the discourse of law and constitutionality, allowing for more authoritarian theories to emerge in the 1930s. See Serizawa Kazuya, “Hō” kara kaihō sareru kenryoku: Hanzai, kyōki, hinkon soshite taishō demokurashii (Tokyo: Shinyōsha, 2001).

Notes to Chapter 2 209 33. Gakuren members ­were also involved in the earlier Enlightened ­People’s Com- munist Party Incident (Gyōmin kyōsantō jiken) of 1923, which involved many lecturers, gradu­ates, and students from Waseda University. See George M. Beckmann and Genji Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 1922–1945 (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1969), 32–35. 34. On Gakuren, see Henry Smith, Japan’s First Student Radicals (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972), chapter 4. 35. Matsuo Kōya, “Kyōto gakuren jiken: Hatsudō sareta chianijihō,” in Nihon seiji saiban shiroku, vol. 4: Shōwa • zen, ed. Wagatsuma Sakae (Tokyo: Daiichi Hōki Shup- pan, 1968–1970), 74. 36. On this incident, see Matsuo, “Kyōto gakuren jiken,” 64–96; Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 74–92; Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 70–77; Steinhoff,Tenkō , 38–40. 37. Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 84. Another case in which the private property clause was applied in metropolitan Japan was in November 1927: the so-­called Hokkaidō Collectivist Party Incident (Hokkaidō shūsantō jiken). See Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 72–74. 38. This claim comes from Matsuo, “Kyōto gakuren jiken,” 64. For a comparative consideration of the­ se first two applications of the Peace Preservation Law, see Ogino Fujio, “Kaisetsu: Chianijihō seiritsu • ‘kaisei’ shi,” in Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, ed. Ogino Fujio (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 570–574. 39. For instance, Mizuno has shown how in a case brought against members of the Shinkankai (a socialist national liberation group formed in 1927), charges ranged from violations of the publication law, Ordinance No. 7 (discussed in chapter 1), to a high court decision in 1930 arguing for the application of the Peace Preservation Law. See Mizuno Naoki, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” in Shoku- minchi teikoku nihon no hōteki kōzō, ed. Asano Toyomi and Matsuda Toshihiko (Tokyo: Shinzansha Shuppan, 2004), 431–434. 40. Kōtōhōin Kenjichō, “Chianijihō no tekiyō ni kansuru ken” (June 1925), cited in Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 423. The discre- tion when to use this law rather than earlier ordinances such as Ordinance No. 7 was left to procurators. See chapter 1 for an overview of the security ordinances in effect in colonial Kor­ ea at the time the Peace Preservation Law was enacted. 41. For a discussion of how officials consider the application of the kokutai clause in the colony, see Ogino Fujio, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppan- sha, 1993), 72–74. Mizuno Naoki has analyzed how procurators in Japan continued to debate how to apply the Peace Preservation Law against Korean nationalists agitating in the metropole. See Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 437–451. For the application of this clause to noncommunist nationalist groups, see Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 424–425. For a general overview of the vari­ous in­de­pen­dence groups in ­Korea during the 1920s, see Michael Robinson, “Ideological Schism in the Korean Nationalist Movement, 1920–1930: Cultural Nationalism and the Radical Critique,” Journal of Korean Studies 4 (1982–1983): 241–268.

210 Notes to Chapter 2 42. For information on the early arrests and prosecutions ­under the Peace Preserva- tion Law in colonial ­Korea, see the 1929 report written by the Procuracy of the Chōsen Supreme Court: Chōsen kōtōhōin kenjikyoku, “Chōsen chianijihō ihan chōsa: 1,” reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 258–266. 43. The Keijō District Court decision in the Korean Communist Party Incident case, February 13, 1928, cited in Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 428. 44. The Keijō District Court decision in the Kantōshū Communist Party Incident, December 27, 1928, cited in Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 428. We can interpret this explicit declaration of cap­i­tal­ist property relations in colonial ­Korea as a kind of implicit recognition of the primacy of territory, extraction, and cap­it­al­ist social relations to Japan’s colonial enterprise. 45. For an overview of cases brought to trial in colonial ­Korea in the late 1920s, see the report issued by the procuracy of the Chōsen High Court: Chōsen kōtō hōin kenjikyoku, “Chōsen chianijihō ihan chōsa: 1,” 258–266. In this report, the procuracy identified four illegal ideologies in Chōsen at that time: anarchism, communism, nationalism, and the combination of communism and nationalism (260). 46. The 1927 ­Theses called for a two-­stage revolution, explaining, “The bourgeois-­ democratic revolution of Japan ­will rapidly grow into a socialist revolution precisely ­because the con­temporary Japa­nese state, with all its feudal attributes and relics, is the most concentrated expression of Japa­nese capitalism, embodying a ­whole series of its most vital nerves; to strike at the state is to strike at the cap­i­tal­ist system of Japan as a ­whole.” En­glish translation from Beckmann and Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 298. See also Germaine A. Hoston, Marxism and the Crisis of Development in Prewar Japan (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1986), chapter 3; Matsuo, Chianijihō to tokkō keisatsu, 119–122. For an analy­sis of the emperor system in jcp and prewar Comintern ­theses, see Fukunaga Misao, Kyōsantōin no tenkō to tennōsei (Tokyo: Sanichi Shobō, 1978), chapter 4. 47. On ­these arrests and the subsequent prosecutions that followed, see Odanaka, “San • ichigo, yon • ichiroku jiken,” 123–257. For information on ­these arrests in relation to the Peace Preservation Law, see Ushiomi Toshitaka, Chianijihō (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1977), 42–43; Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice, 53–56; Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, chapter 4; Matsuo, Chianijihō to tokkō keisatsu, 117–129. 48. Ogino, Shisō kenji, 31–32. 49. In April, the Home Ministry banned the Labor-Farmer Party (Rōdōnōmintō), the All-­Japan Proletarian Youth League (Zen nihon musan seinen dōmei), and the Japan ­Labor Union Council (Nihon rōdō kumiai hyōgikai). Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 97. 50. For summaries of this expansion, see Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 88–94; Tipton, The Japa­nese Police State, 23–25; Matsuo, Chianijihō to tokkō keisatsu, 129–131. 51. Ogino, Shisō kenji, 8. 52. See Steinhoff’s summary of a May 1928 directive sent to thought procurators. Steinhoff,Tenkō , 40–42.

Notes to Chapter 2 211 53. For the government’s explanation of the necessity for this revision, see gss45, 179–180. Preliminary reports reveal that officials believed the revision was necessary in light of information gathered from the March 15 arrests; in par­tic­u­lar, that the jcp was agitating ­under the slogan “abolish the monarchy” as outlined in the Comintern’s 1927 ­Theses. See Shihōshō keijikyoku, “Chianijihō chū kaisei hōritsuan riyū” (April 26, 1928), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 270–271. See also the Jus- tice Ministry’s explanation ­after the revision that “our flawless kokutai”kinō ( muketsu no waga kokutai) was threatened by a “foreign ideological threat” (shisōteki gaikanzai). “Chianijihō chū kaisei chokureian riyū setsumeisho,” reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 308–309. For an overview of the March arrests and the revision, see Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 579–584. 54. The revision is reprinted ingss 45, 114. On the role of Suzuki Kisaburō (Home Minister up ­until May 1928) and Justice Minister Hara Yoshimichi in preparing the 1928 revision, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 99–100. 55. On the format of passing the revision as an emergency imperial ordinance, see Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 584–592. 56. For deliberations in the Privy Council in 1928 and the following Imperial Diet in 1929, see gss45, 115–146 and 146–178 respectively. 57. See the graph in Ogino, Shisō kenji, 59. See also Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 579. 58. On this addition, see Steinhoff,Tenkō , 46. Anyone convicted of joining an organ­ ization with the objective of altering the kokutai or anyone who was not a member but still “acted in order to further its aims” (kessha no mokuteki kōi no tame ni suru kōi o tame shitaru) would receive a minimum of two years in prison. Similarly, for anyone to not only form or join an organ­ization with the objective of “rejecting the private property system” but also to “act in order to further its aims” was now punishable with a sentence of up to ten years. The revised law is reprinted ingss 45, 114. On the importance of this emphasis on “furthering the aims” in the revision, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 95–96. 59. See Tanaka’s statements to the Privy Council in gss45, 120, 121. See also Tanaka’s public statements on the 3.15 Incident arrests, translated in Beckmann and Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 156. 60. gss45, 121. Note that Mochizuki’s phrase “the glory of our kokutai” was a reference to the 1890 Imperial Rescript on Education (see chapter 1). 61. gss45, 121. 62. Other platforms of the 1927 Comintern The­ ses ­were establishing a ­people’s republic, eliminating parliament, repealing antilabor and antifarmer laws, the confisca- tion of all lands held by the imperial ­house­hold, to defend Soviet Rus­sia, a noninterfer- ence policy in the Chinese revolution, and in­de­pen­dence for all colonial ­people. For a translation of the 1927 ­Theses, see Appendix D in Beckmann and Okubo, The Japanese­ Communist Party, 295–308. For a discussion of the often-­fraught relationship between the jcp and the Comintern, see Hoston, Marxism and the Crisis of Development in Prewar Japan, 57–98. 63. As with the initial passage of the law in 1925, the Justice Ministry’s Criminal Af- fairs Bureau conducted comparative research on the revision (as an emergency imperial ordinance) in February 1929 in preparation for Diet deliberation. See Shihōshō keiji-

212 Notes to Chapter 2 kyoku, “Chianiji rippō rei hikaku” (February 15, 1929), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 320–329. 64. Cited in gss45, 147. 65. gss45, 147. 66. A common form of critique was to press Justice Minister Hara and other advo- cates to clearly distinguish between this emergency ordinance and the Civil Distur- bance Ordinance (Nairanzai) of the Criminal Code. See, for instance, Saitō Takao’s comments (gss45, 162–165) and Taketomi Wataru’s comments (gss45, 148–150). 67. Okudaira, “Some Preparatory Notes,” 67–68. 68. On the vari­ous responses to the revision by the po­liti­cal parties, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 95–118. 69. On the jcp during ­these years of mass arrests, see chapters 6 and 7 of Beckmann and Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 138–196. 70. For number of arrests per year in Japan ­under the Peace Preservation Law, see Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 132–135. For colonial ­Korea, see the graphs in Hong Jong-­ wook, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi: Teikoku / shokuminchi no tōgō to kiretsu (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2011), 47 and 63. 71. For an overview of Peace Preservation Law arrests in ­Korea between 1925 and 1930, see Park Kyong-­sik, “Chianijihō ni yoru chōsenjin danatsu” (1976), in Tennōsei kokka to zainichi chōsenjin (Tokyo: Shakai Hyōronsha, 1986), 100–102. 72. The 1929 Sapporo Appellate Court and the 1931 Tokyo Appellate Court decisions are reprinted in gss45, 577–581 and 581–583 respectively. See also Ogino, Shōwa tennō to chiantaisei, 52–60, 66. 73. See Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 431–436. 74. Chōsen High Court ruling, July 21, 1930, cited in Mizuno, “Shokuminchi doku- ritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 433. 75. Decision in the Chōsen Student Vanguard League Incident (Chōsen gakusei zenei dōmei jiken) case, June 25, 1931, cited in Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 435. 76. Recall that ­there was a ­legal distinction between naichi—­referring to the territory of Japan at the time of the promulgation of the Meiji Constitution in 1889—a­ nd gaichi, or outer territories, which referred to its subsequent colonial acquisitions. On this, see Edward I-te Chen, “The Attempt to Integrate the Empire: ­Legal Perspectives,” in The Japa­nese Colonial Empire, 1895–19­ 45, ed. Ramon H. Myers and Mark R. Peattie (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1984), 241–242. 77. Mizuno, “Shokuminchi dokuritsu undō ni taisuru chianijihō no unyō,” 436. 78. See gss45, appendix 1, 646–647. See also Ogino Fujio, Tokkō keisatsu (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2012), 66. 79. Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 130–131. 80. See Hong, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi, 47. For comparative statistics on the changing application of ordinances in colonial ­Korea in the 1920s, see Suzuki Keifu, Chōsen shokuminchi tōchihō no kenkyū: Chianhō ka no kōminka kyōiku (Sapporo: Hokkaidō Daigaku Tosho Kankōkai, 1989), 182.

Notes to Chapter 2 213 81. Additionally, Ogino notes that 15,111 ­were arrested in Kor­ ea by 1934 ­under the law. For ­these figures, see Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 606. For a short summary of the law’s applica- tion in Taiwan and Kantōshū, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 207–208. 82. See Erik Esselstrom, Crossing Empire’s Edge: Foreign Ministry Police and Japa­nese Expansionism in Northeast Asia (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 2009), chap- ters 4 and 5, especially 108–115. 83. Louise Young, Japan’s Total Empire: Manchuria and the Culture of War­time Imperi- alism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998), 143–144. 84. Thomas Dubois has called a “quasi-­sovereign” or “inauthentic” sovereign state. See Thomas David Dubois, “Inauthentic Sovereignty: Law and ­Legal Institutions in Manchukuo,” Journal of Asian Studies 69, no. 3 (August 2010): 749–770. 85. See Manshūkoku seifu, Ordinances No. 80 and 81 (September 10, 1932), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 427–429. Also see Manshūkoku seifu, “Chian keisatsu hō” (September 12, 1932), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 429–431. See also Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 209. 86. For a helpful summary of the vari­ous security laws and police organ­izations that advised and/or operated in Manchukuo in the 1930s, see Ogino, “Kaisatsu,” 748–764. 87. On the establishment of the Thought Division (Shisōbu) in the Procuracy, see Ogino, Shisō kenji, 29–33. 88. Sano Manabu was captured by the consular police in Shanghai on June 16. See Esselstrom, Crossing Empire’s Edge, 109–111. See also Yamamoto Katsunosuke, Nihon kyōsanshugi undōshi (Tokyo: Seki Shobō, 1950), 189–191. For a dramatic account of how Sano and ­others ­were captured, see Suzuki Takeshi, Sano manabu ichimi o hōtei ni okuru made (Tokyo: Keiyūsha, 1931). For the prosecution’s case against Sano Manabu, see Shihōshō keijikyoku shisōbu, “Nihon kyōsantō chūōbu kankei hikokunin ni taisuru tōkyō chihō saibansho hanketsu,” in Shisō kenkyū shiryō Tokushū No. 2, ed. Shihōshō Keijikyoku (Tokyo: Shihōshō Keijikyoku, 1932), 294–299. 89. The official ­orrec d of ­these prosecutions is: Shihōshō keijikyoku shisōbu, “Nihon kyōsantō chūōbu kankei hikokunin ni taisuru tōkyō chihō saibansho hanketsu.” On ­these tr­ ials, see Odanaka, “San • ichigo, yon • ichiroku jiken,” 145–220; Ueda Seikichi, Shōwa saibanshi ron: Chianijihō to hōritsukatachi (Tokyo: Ōtsuki Shoten, 1983), 1–84; Beckmann and Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 215–221; Mitchell, Thought Con- trol in Prewar Japan, 104–109. 90. Odanaka, “San • ichigo, yon • ichiroku jiken,” 218–220. 91. Ogino, Shisō kenji, 36–38, 43. 92. Ogino cites an article by the Tokyo procurator Ikeda Katsu, who notes that beginning in 1931, “moral suasion” (kyōka) started to be an impor­tant topic discussed by officials administering thought crime cases. See Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 615–617. 93. Kawai distributed a letter titled “Boku ga nihon kyōsantō yori dattō o ketsuishi jihaku suru ni itaru katei” in March 1929; Mizuno published a letter titled “Nihon kyōsantō dattō ni saishi tōin shokun ni” in May. See Shimane Kiyoshi, “Nihon kyōsantō rōdōsha-h­ a: Mizuno shigeo,” in Kyōdō kenkyū: Tenkō, vol. 1, ed. Shisō no kagaku kenkyūkai (Tokyo: Heibonsha, 1959), 154 and 152–157. On Kawai, Mizuno, and the ­later ­Labor Faction, see Beckmann and Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 183–187.

214 Notes to Chapter 2 94. The following summary of Mizuno’s critique is derived from Fukunaga Misao, Kyōsantōin no tenkō to tennōsei (Tokyo: Sanichi Shobō, 1978), 19–27. 95. Cited in Shimane, “Nihon kyōsantō rōdōsha ha,” 152. 96. Itō Akira has argued that Mizuno’s critique was an expression of a general “sense of defeat.” See Itō Akira, “Tenkō mondai no Ikkōsatsu: Nihonkyōsantō rōdōshaha to Hirata Isao,” Chiba kōgyō daigaku kenkyū hōkoku, no. 31 (February 1994): 30. 97. On the role of procurators in drafting and disseminating ­these critiques, see the reflections of the ex–­Labor Faction member Asano Akira: Asano Akira and Kageyama Masaharu, Tenkō-­Nihon e no kaiki: Nihon kyōsantō kaitōha shuchō (Tokyo: Akatsuki Shobō, 1983), 219–232. 98. Although Kawai was critiqued as part of the Dissolutionist Faction, he did not follow Mizuno in forming the ­Labor Faction. He continued to be po­liti­cally ac- tive ­until a second arrest in 1934. See the biographical entry for Kawai in Kobayashi Morito, “Tenkōki” no hitobito: Chianijihōka no katsudōka gunzō (Tokyo: Shinjidaisha, 1987), 305. 99. Nihon Kyōsantō Chūōiinkai, “Shakai fashisuto kaitōha o funsai seyo!,” Mushin Panfuretto, no. 10 (September 1931), collected by the Kyōdo Minyō Kenkyūkai, Tokyo. See also Germaine A. Hoston, “Emperor, Nation and the Transformation of Marxism to National Socialism in Prewar Japan: The Case of Sano Manabu,”Studies in Compara- tive Communism 18, no. 1 (spring 1985): 25–47. On the failure of the Communist Inter- national’s social-­fascism line, see Nicos Poulantzas, Fascism and Dictatorship: The Third International and the Prob­lem of Fascism, trans. Judith White (London: Verso, 1979). 100. For instance, see Germaine A. Hoston, The State, Identity, and the National Ques- tion in China and Japan (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1994), 327–360. I briefly address how the national question has been explained in area studies in Max Ward, “Historical Difference and the Question of East Asian Marxism(s),” inEast Asian Marxisms and Their Trajectories, ed. Joyce Liu and Viren Murthy, Interventions Series (London: Routledge, 2017), 88–91. For more nuanced analyses of the national question in Japa­nese Marxism, see Itō Akira, Tennōsei to shakaishugi (Tokyo: Keisō Shobō, 1988); Gavin Walker, The Sublime Perversion of Capital: Marxist Theory and the Politics of History in Modern Japan (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2016); Katsuhiko Endo, “The Science of Capital: The Uses and Abuses of Social Science in Interwar Japan” (PhD diss., New York University, 2004). 101. See Asano’s reflections in Asano and Kageyama,Tenkō- ­Nihon e no kaiki, 230. 102. On the national question in Marxist theory and communist po­liti­cal strategy, see Walker Connor, The National Question in Marxist-­Leninist Theory and Strategy (Prince­ ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1984). 103. For a reflection on Mizuno’s defection and its impact in the 1930s, see Nabeyama Sadachika, “Mizuno shigeoron ni shokuhatsu sareta,” Ronsō 4:10, no. 19 (Novem- ber 1962): 215–221. For a biography of Mizuno’s work ­after the war, including his tenure as president of Japan Broadcasting Comp­ any (nhk), see Ōya Shōichi, “Mizuno shigeo-­ ron,” Bungei shunju 33, no. 22 (December 1955): 124–135. 104. Itō Akira, Tenkō to tennōsei: Nihon kyōsanshugi undō no 1930nendai (Tokyo: Keisō Shobō, 1995), 25–28; Asano and Kageyama, Tenkō-­Nihon e no kaiki, 220–223.

Notes to Chapter 2 215 105. Itō Akira contends that while Mizuno and Hirata prob­ably had a heated theoreti- cal debate, the point for Hirata was not “the total rejection of Marxian thought, [but rather] pressing the single point of the kokutai.” Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 27. 106. Asano and Kageyama, Tenkō-­Nihon e no kaiki, 225–226. 107. Asano Akira quoted in Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 25. 108. Asano and Kageyama, Tenkō-­Nihon e no kaiki, 226. Asano argues that Hirata was “95%” responsible for the defections that occurred at this time (223). 109. Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 26, 21, 40; see also Itō, “Tenkō mondai no Ikkōsatsu,” 30. 110. Hirata Isao, cited in Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 29. 111. See Kobayashi Morito’s biographical account of his conversion, written ­under the pen name Ono Yōichi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made (Tokyo: Daidōsha, 1932). This text is analyzed in chapter 3. 112. Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 141. 113. For early youth reformatories, see David Ambaras, Bad Youth: Juvenile De- linquency and the Politics of Everyday Life in Modern Japan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2006), 44–65 and 104–105. See also Moriya Katsuhiko, Shōnen no hikō to kyōiku: Shōnen hōsei no rekishi to genjō (Tokyo: Keisōshobō, 1977), chapter 3. For early parolee “protection” ser­vices, see Uchida Hirofumi, Kōsei hogo no tenkai to kadai (Kyoto: Hōritsu Bunkasha, 2015), 1–8 and 9–26. On this early history of reform, see also Kōsei Hogo Gojūnen Shi Henshū Iinkai, ed., Kōsei hogo gojūnen shi: Chiiki shakai to tomo ni ayumu kōsei hogo (Tokyo: Zenkoku Hogoshi Renmei, 2000), vol. 1: 3–7. 114. On the new Juvenile Law of 1922, see Moriya, Shōnen no hikō to kyōiku, chapter 4; Ambaras, Bad Youth, chapter 4. 115. This law is reprinted in Uchida,Kōsei hogo no tenkai to kadai, 10–16. For the le­ gal debates over this law, see 17–19. 116. Uchida, Kōsei hogo no tenkai to kadai, 20. 117. Ambaras, Bad Youth, 107–108. 118. For an early explanation of reform related to ­these new suspension policies, see “Kiso yūyosha shikkō yūyosha no hogo ni tsuite,” Hōsei kaihō 10, no. 3 (June 1926): 4–11. On the rise of hogoshugi in regard to youth crime in prewar Japan, see Moriya, Shōnen no hikō to kyōiku, 61–151. 119. On criminal rehabilitation in general in prewar Japan, see Suzuki Kazuhisa, “Waga kuni no kōsei hogo jigyō no hatten to kokusaiteki hanzaisha shogū no dōkō,” in Kōsei hogo no kadai to tenbō: Kōsei hogo seido shikō 50shūnen kinen ronbunshū (Tokyo: Nihon Kōsei Hogo Kyōkai, 1999), 131–160. 120. Miyake Masatarō, An Outline of the Japa­nese Judiciary, 2nd ed., rev. (Tokyo: Japan Times and Mail), 25. 121. Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 158. However, the number of Suspended Indictments remained relatively low during this period; for instance, only sixteen cases in 1928 and twenty-­seven in 1929. It was not ­until 1930 that procurators started to use this more (292 cases in 1930), and subsequently, with the establishment of Charges Withheld in 1931. See the graph in Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 142. 122. An excerpt of Directive No. 270 is reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 539–540.

216 Notes to Chapter 2 123. For a brief summary of ­these policies in the early 1930s, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 137–141. 124. Ogino, Shisō kenji, 60–61. 125. This procedure was formalized in Directives No. 1527 (1928), No. 1637 (1928), and No. 1637 (1929). See Shihōshō Keijikyoku Shisōbu, ed., “Shisō jimu ni kansuru kunrei tsūchoshū,” in Shisō kenkyū shiryō, Tokushū 1 gō (September 1932): 15–19. 126. See Shihōshō keijikyoku shisōbu ed., “Shisō jimu ni kansuru kunrei tsūchoshū,” 19–35. 127. Regulation No. 2006, “Shisōhannin taisuru ryūho shobun toriatsukai kitei” (December 26, 1932), reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 1, 541–542. See also: Ogino Shisō kenji, 60–61. 128. This protocol is reviewed in Ogino,Shisō kenji, 61; Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 160. 129. “Shisōhannin taisuru ryūho shobun toriatsukai kitei,” 541. 130. Okudaira reports that over 80 ­percent of guarantors ­were ­family members of the suspect. Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 160. 131. An observation made by Poulantzas is suggestive he­ re: “The massive accumula- tion of paper in the modern state organ­ization is not merely a picturesque detail but a material feature essential to its existence and functioning.” Poulantzas attributes this function of the accumulation of paper to the “intellectuals-­functionaries,” which we could apply to thought procurators (shisō kenji) like Hirata Isao. See Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism, 59. 132. Hong, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi, 47. 133. This percentage is derived from the graph in Mitchell,Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 142. 134. On reform efforts targeting Koreans who committed conventional crime, see Kim Songon, “Chōsenjin no shihō hogo ni tsuite,” Hogo Jihō 14, no. 12 (Decem- ber 1934): 32–37. The disparity between metropolitan and colonial implementations of the Peace Preservation Law is also noted in Chulwoo Lee, “Modernity, Legality and Power in ­Korea ­under Japa­nese Rule,” in Colonial Modernity in ­Korea, ed. Gi-­Wook Shin and Michael Robinson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 48. 135. Yoshida Hajime, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” Shisō jōsei shisatsu hōkokushū (Sono 6), in Shisō kenkyū shiryō: Tokushū dai 69 gō, ed. Shihōshō keijikyoku, reprinted in Shakai mondai shiryō sōsho: Dai 1 shū (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1971), 9. 136. Mizuno, “Chianijihō to chōsen • Oboegaki,” 50–51. 137. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 251. 138. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 251. 139. Recall Poulantzas’s qualification of Louis Althusser’s distinction between Repres- sive State Apparatuses and Ideological State Apparatuses in the introduction, wherein he argues that specific apparatuses can “slide” between repressive and ideological func- tions. Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism, 33. 140. See “Chianijihō ihan jiken nendo betsu shori jinin hyō,” in gss45, 647. Although ­there are some minor differences in the exact numbers, see also Mitchell,Thought Con- trol in Prewar Japan, 142; Steinhoff,Tenkō , 47; Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 130–131. According

Notes to Chapter 2 217 to a Special Higher Police (Tokkō) report, over the Peace Preservation Law’s twenty-­ year history, while 67,431 persons ­were arrested ­under the law in the home islands, only 5,595 (8.3 ­percent) individuals ­were prosecuted. See Yūgami Kōichi, “Jidai haikei ni tsuite,” in Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 270.

Chapter 3. Apparatuses of Subjection 1. The title of this chapter derives from Warren Montag, “Althusser and Foucault: Ap- paratuses of Subjection,” in Althusser and His Contemporaries: Philosophy’s Perpetual War (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2013). 2. Louis Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes ­Towards an Investigation),” in Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2001), 85–126. A few scholars have suggested the theoreti- cal purchase of Althusser’s theory of the isas to understand the emperor system in modern Japan. For example, Harry Harootunian has drawn upon Althusser’s theory and argued that the imperial institution has functioned to interpellate Japa­nese “as subjects (not primarily imperial subjects—­shinmin—­even though this was obviously included in the formulation, but as subjects—­shutai or shukan)” in both the pre-­ and postwar periods. Harry Harootunian, “Hirohito Redux,” Critical Asian Studies 33, no. 4 (2001): 609. Ultimately, Harootunian critiques Althusser’s assumption that the­ re is a nonideological outside from which science can illuminate the operations of ideology. For this reason, he turns to Slavoj Žižek’s qualification of Althusser’s theory of interpel- lation (609–611). For Žižek’s theory of ideology, see Slavoj Žižek, The Sublime Object of Ideology (London: Verso, 2008); Slavoj Žižek, “The Spectre of Ideology,” inMapping Ideology, ed. Slavoj Žižek (New York: Verso, 1994), 1–33. In regard to the 1930s in par­ tic­u­lar, James Dorsey has suggested in passing that the ideological conversions of the 1930s “­were prompted by a combination of what Althusser has called ‘Ideological State Apparatuses and Repressive State Apparatuses.’ ” James Dorsey, “From Ideological Lit­ er­a­ture to a Literary Ideology: ‘Conversion’ in War­time Japan,” in Converting Cultures: Religion, Ideology and Transformations of Modernity, ed. Dennis Washburn and A. Kevin Reinhart (Leiden: Brill, 2007), 466. Following ­these suggestions, my objective in this chapter is to more fully elaborate the operations of imperial state ideology through the lens of Althusser’s theory of isas. 3. The canonical text on tenkō in En­glish is Patricia Steinhoff’s 1969 PhD disserta- tion, ­later published as: Tenkō: Ideology and Societal Integration in Prewar Japan (New York: Garland, 1991). Similar to Richard Mitchell’s early studies of the Peace Preserva- tion Law, Steinhoff explains tenkō as addressing the need for social integration during a particularly turbulent period of Japa­nese modernization. 4. For examples of tenkō as an intellectual phenomenon, see Yamaryō Kenji, Tenkō no jidai to chishikijin (Tokyo: Sanichi Shobō, 1978); Andrew Barshay, State and Intel- lectual in Imperial Japan: The Public Man in Crisis (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988). In the case of colonial ­Korea, see Matsuda Toshihiko, “Shokuminchi makki chōsen ni okeru tenkōsha no undō: Kang Yŏng-­sŏk to nihon kokutai gaku • tōa renmei undō,” Jinbun Gakuhō 79 (March 1997): 131–161. Two exceptions to this intellectual

218 Notes to Chapter 2 approach are Patricia Steinhoff’s early so­cio­log­i­cal analysi­ s of tenkō as state policy and Itō Akira’s study of tenkō in the social history of the prewar communist movement. See Steinhoff,Tenkō ; Itō Akira, Tenkō to tennōsei: Nihon kyōsanshugi undō no 1930nendai (Tokyo: Keisō Shobō, 1995). 5. For a thought-pr­ ovoking attempt to understand the historical and po­liti­cal connec- tions between Taishō democracy and Shōwa fascism, see Andrew Gordon, ­Labor and Imperial Democracy in Prewar Japan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992). 6. For instance, see Yamaryō, Tenkō no jidai to chishikijin. Andrew Barshay and Carl Friere have pointed out how, in the early postwar period, tenkō “served both narrowly as a moral litmus test in evaluating the ­careers of intellectuals active before and a­ fter the war and more broadly as a meta­phor for the collective experience of an entire generation of Japa­nese.” Andrew Barshay and Carl Friere, “The Tenkō Phenomenon,” in Sources of Japa­nese Tradition, 2nd ed., vol. 2: 1600 to 2000, ed. Wm. Theodore de Bary, Carol Gluck, and Arthur E. Tiedemann (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005), 940. 7. Sano Manabu and Nabeyama Sadachika, “Kyōdō hikoku dōshi ni tsuguru sho” (1933), in Sano Manabu chosakushū, vol. 1, by Sano Manabu (Tokyo: Sano Manabu chosakushū kankōkai 1959), 3–20. For an En­glish translation, see Sano Manabu and Nabeyama Sadachika, “A Letter to Our Fellow Defendants,” trans. Andrew Barshay and Carl Freire, in Sources of Japa­nese Tradition, 2nd ed., vol. 2, ed. Wm. Theodore de Bary, Carol Gluck, and Arthur E Tiedman (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005), 940–947. For the jcp’s reaction to the Sano-­Nabeyama statement, see Sekki (Red Flag), June 16, July 1, and July 11, 1933. Fukunaga Misao argues that the distinguishing feature in the Sano-­Nabeyama letter compared to Mizuno Shigeo’s earlier critique of the jcp was their claim that the party had taken on a petit bourgeois character following the mass arrests of 1928–1929. See Fukunaga Misao, Kyōsantōin no tenkō to tennōsei (Tokyo: Sanichi Shobō, 1978), 29–30. 8. The first newspaper reports on Sano and Nabeyama’s change in direction­w ere in the morning editions on June 10. The letter was first published in its entirety in the July 1933 issue of the journal Kaizō and again in August in Chūōkōron. See Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 139–140. For a biographical recollection about how the letter was distributed in jail by procurators, see Hayashida Shigeo, “Tenkō būmu,” in Gokuchū no shōwashi: Toyotama keimusho, ed. Kazahaya Yasoji (Tokyo: Aoki Shoten, 1986), 102–106. 9. According to an article in the Asahi Shimbun, authorities distributed the letter to six hundred detained jcp members on June 13. Then on June 15 procurator Hirata Isao and chief procurator Miyagi Chōgorō met with Sano and Nabeyama at Ichigaya Prison in order to assess the situation among jcp members (“Tenkō dōi no kiun, jochō ni noridasu,” Asahi Shimbun, June 15, 1933, eve­ning ed., 2). Similarly, Chaplain Fujii Eshō published a series of articles in the June 14, 15, and 17 editions of the morning Yomiuri Shimbun explaining “How Did Sano Manabu and the ­Others Convert?” (“Ika ni shite Sano Manabu-­shi ra ha tenkō shita ka”) (see figure 3.3). 10. Patricia Steinhoff calculates that by the end of July, 548 other detained communists—​ 133 convicted jcp members and 415 of ­those awaiting trial—­had formally defected from the party, 31 pe­ rcent (548) of the 1,762 communists in custody. Steinhoff,Tenkō ,

Notes to Chapter 3 219 6. Okudaira confirms this number: Okudaira Yasuhiro,Chianijihō shōshi, new ed. (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2006), 155. Ushiomi Toshitaka cites a 1936 report stating that 73 ­percent of ­those indicted ­under the Peace Preservation Law had committed tenkō by 1936. Ushiomi Toshitaka, Chianijihō (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1977), 100. 11. Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, chapter 5; Nakazawa Shunsuke, Chianijihō: Naze seitō seiji ha “akuhō” o unda ka (Tokyo: Chūōkō Shinsho, 2012), 141–144. 12. George Beckmann and Okubo Genji date the orga­nizational death of the jcp to arrests that occurred in fall 1932. See George M. Beckmann and Genji Okubo, The Japa­nese Communist Party, 1922–1945 (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1969), 237–238, 239–253. 13. As I ­will explain ­later in this chapter, Sano and Nabeyama did use the term “tenkō” in a subsequent addendum to the letter, but in a negative, pejorative, sense. 14. For example, see the original letter published inKaizō , July 1933, 191–199. 15. For example, a headline in the June 10, 1933, morning edition of Yomiuri Shimbun declared that Sano and Nabeyama had “discarded communism and converted to fas- cism” (fassho ni tenkō). See figure 3.1. 16. See Regulation No. 2006, “Shisōhannin taisuru ryūho shobun toriatsukai kitei,” December 26, 1932, in Ogino Fujio, ed., Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), vol. 1, 541–542. See also Ogino Fujio, Shisō kenji (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2000), 60–61. 17. On the increased reform efforts made by the Justice Ministry, see Ogino,Shisō kenji, 72–76. 18. Sano Manabu and Nabeyama Sadachika, “Kinpaku seru naigai jōsei to nihon minzoku oyobi sono rōdōsha kaikyū sensō oyobi naibu kaikaku no sekkin o mae ni shite komintaan oyobi nihon kyōsantō o jiko hihan suru,” Shisō shiryō, May 1933. This extremely rare hand-­copied document was circulated to prisons throughout Japan as “Useful Materials for Thought Guidance,” or “Shisō kyōka no kōzairyō.” This document contains both Sano and Nabeyama’s longer explanation of their critique (1–118) as well as the letter to their fellow defendants (119–132). 19. ­There are debates over to what degree the authorities influenced the wording of this document. For a description of how Sano and Nabeyama came to draft this letter, see Nakano Sumio, “Sano, Nabeyama tenkō no shinsō,” Kaizō, July 1933, 200–204. Elsewhere, Yoshimoto Takaaki disagrees with Honda Shūgo’s argument that Sano and Nabeyama’s letter bears the mark of state pressure, and rather argues that he believes “the intellectual content of the statement to be in­de­pen­dent of the pro­cess that created it.” Yoshimoto Takaaki, “On Tenkō, or Ideological Conversion” (1958), trans. Hisaaki Wake, in Translation in Modern Japan, ed. Indra Levy (London: Routledge, 2011), 103. 20. For example, the entry for tenkō in the authoritative Kodansha Encyclopedia of Japan tells us that the “term was coined in 1933 by Sano Manabu and Nabeyama Sadachika” when they “announced from prison that they had made a po­liti­cal ‘change of direction’ and ­were breaking their ties with the Communist Party.” Entry for “tenkō” in Kodansha, ed., Kodansha Encyclopedia of Japan, vol. 8 (Tokyo: Kodansha, 1983), 6–7. 21. For instance, see Tokuoka Kazuo, Chianijihō ihan jiken no saihan ni kansuru kenkyū (Tokyo: Shihōshō Keijikyoku, 1938).

220 Notes to Chapter 3 22. For instance, see Shimane Kiyoshi, Tenkō: Meiji ishin to bakushin (Tokyo: Sanichi Shobō, 1969); Takeuchi Yoshimi, “What Is Modernity? (The Case of Japan and China)” (1948), in What Is Modernity? Writings of Takeuchi Yoshimi, by Takeuchi Yoshimi, trans. Richard F. Calichman (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005), 53–81, esp. 74–76. This tendency to see tenkō as a constitutive princi­ple in Japa­nese modernity continues ­today. For instance, in his attempt to distinguish between what he calls the “Taishō-­ thing” and “Shōwa-­thing” (Taishōteki na mono, Shōwateki na mono), Karatani Kōjin finds multiple conversions (tenkō) occurring in the prewar period, which he theorizes as when writers and intellectuals posit an other/otherness (tasha/tashasei) to be internalized and/or overcome, including God in mid-­Meiji Chris­tian­ity (e.g., Uchimura Kanzō), through naturalism, to the otherness of the masses (taishū) informing proletar- ian lit­er­a­ture, and fi­nally the West in the discourses of “returning to Japan” (nihon kaiki) and “overcoming modernity” (kindai no chōkoku). See Karatani’s essay: “Kindai nihon no hihyō: Shōwa senki,” in Kindai nihon no hihyō, 1, ed. Karatani Kōjin (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1997), 13–44, in par­tic­u­lar, 39–41. 23. For instance, see two collections of essays: Saotome Yūgorō, ed., Tenkōsha no shuki (Tokyo: Daidōsha, 1933); and Kobayashi Morito, ed., Tenkōsha no shisō to seikatsu (Tokyo: Daidōsha, 1935). I ­will analyze ­these two works ­later in this chapter and in chapter 4. For the officially recognized motivations for tenkō, see the reports summa- rized in Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 143; also Steinhoff,Tenkō , 99–127. 24. For instance, see Hirata Isao, “Kyōsantōin no tenkō ni tsuite,” mimeograph of lecture, February 8, 1934, archived at the Ōhara Institute for Social Research, Hōsei University, Tokyo. 25. Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 135. 26. For an overview of ­these debates, see Victor J. Koschmann, Revolution and Subjec- tivity in Postwar Japan (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996). 27. On Science of Thought, see Adam Bronson,One Hundred Million Phi­los­ophers:­ Science of Thought and the Culture of Democracy in Postwar Japan (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 2016). 28. Tsurumi Shunsuke, “Tenkō no kyōdō kenkyū ni tsuite,” in Kyōdō kenkyū: Tenkō, vol. 1, ed. Shisō no Kagaku Kenkyūkai (Tokyo: Heibonsha, 1959), 6. See also Tsurumi Shunsuke, An Intellectual History of War­time Japan, 1931–1945 (London: kpi Limited, 1986), 12–13. 29. Tsurumi, An Intellectual History of War­time Japan, 12. See also Tsurumi, “Tenkō no kyōdō kenkyū ni tsuite,” 5–7. 30. For just a few examples of the continuing influence of Tsurumi’s definition, see Patricia G. Steinhoff, “Tenkō and Thought Control,” inJapan and the World: Essays on Japa­nese History and Politics in Honour of Ishida Takeshi, ed. Gail Lee Bern­stein and Har- uhiro Fukui (New York: St. Martin’s, 1988), 78–94; and, extended to the case of colonial ­Korea, Hong Jong-­wook, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi: Teikoku / shokuminchi no tōgō to kiretsu (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2011), 2–6. 31. Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Some Preparatory Notes for the Study of the Peace Preser- vation Law in Pre-­War Japan,” Annals of the Institute of Social Science, no. 14 (1973): 53. Okudaira went on to write the foundational studies on the Peace Preservation Law.

Notes to Chapter 3 221 However, by approaching tenkō solely as an administrative policy in the prewar Japa­ nese justice system, Okudaira and ­others necessarily set aside questions of ideology, power, and subjection and did not analyze the myriad ways individuals practiced and experienced tenkō ­under the guidance of the state. When tenkō is mentioned in ­these institutional studies, it is often explained as a uniquely Japa­nese mode for dealing with po­liti­cal crime. For instance, Richard Mitchell argues that the tenkō policy “was a humane method of ­handling communist po­liti­cal criminals” that “fit in so snugly with traditional values.” See Richard H. Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice: Po­liti­cal Criminals in Imperial Japan (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 1992), 156–157. 32. Nabeyama Sadachika, “Tenkō o megutte,” inKataritsugu shōwashi, vol. 1, ed. Itō Takashi (Tokyo: Asahi Bunko, 1990), 215. It could be argued that Nabeyama was trying to justify his defection by emphasizing internal spontaneity. However, we can find this emphasis in other theories of tenkō as well. For instance, in his 1958 essay “On Tenkō,” Yoshimoto Takaaki argues that the Sano-­Nabeyama statement contains positions written from “internal conviction” and thus rejects the argument that “compulsory force and oppression by the authorities ­were the most significant ele­ments among the external conditions of Japa­nese ideological conversion.” However, even though he grants Sano and Nabeyama “internal conviction,” Yoshimoto argues that they ­were, ultimately, “backwater intellectuals” (inaka interi) who failed to confront the dual social structure of modern Japan, which consisted of both modern ele­ments and feudal remnants. Consequently, Yoshimoto argues that, having abandoned the modern social theory of Marxism, their conversion represented an “unconditional surrender to the dominant ele­ments of Japa­nese feudalism.” Yoshimoto Takaaki, “Tenkōron” (1958), in Yoshimoto Takaaki Zenhūsen, vol. 3: Seiji shisō (Tokyo: Daiwa Shobō, 1986), 15, 19. En­glish ­translation: Yoshimoto Takaaki, “On Tenkō, or Ideological Conversion” (1958), trans. Hisaaki Wake, in Translation in Modern Japan, ed. Indra Levy (London: Rout- ledge, 2011), 106, 109. 33. See Nabeyama, “Tenkō o megutte,” 236–240, 227–230. In the 1990s, Tsurumi published an essay in which he recognized that Shisō no kagaku kenkyūkai’s study failed to take into consideration the par­tic­u­lar circumstances of the jcp in the 1930s. See Tsu- rumi Shunsuke, “Kokumin to iu katamari ni umekomarete,” in Tenkō sairon, by Tsurumi Shunsuke, Suzuki Tadashi, and Iida Momo (Tokyo: Heibonsha, 2001), 7–30. 34. See Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 114. 35. For an outline of ideology in Althusser’s theoretical trajectory leading up to the isas article, see Gregor McLennan, Victor Molina, and Roy Peters, “Althusser’s Theory of Ideology,” in On Ideology, ed. Center for Con­temporary Cultural Studies (London: Hutchinson University Library, 1978), 77–105. TheLa Pensée article combined portions of draft notes that Althusser had written in 1969 and 1970, in which he was starting to elaborate a theory of the determinations of law, ideology, and the state in the reproduc- tion of capitalism. The­ se notes ­were published posthumously as Louis Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism: Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (London: Verso, 2014). Balibar has called ­these notes a “partial montage” of a more systematic theory that was, by its very nature, “unfinishable.” Étienne Balibar, “Althusser and the ‘Ideo- logical State Apparatuses,’ ” in Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism, ix. See also

222 Notes to Chapter 3 Warren Montag, Althusser and His Contemporaries: Philosophy’s Perpetual War (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2013), 142. 36. As I noted in the introduction, I am purposely disregarding Althusser’s problem- atic theory of interpellation, which he develops from Lacan, and rather ­will focus on his theory of isas in order to analyze the policies and practices developed in criminal reform groups like the Imperial Renovation Society. 37. Some have critiqued Althusser for extending the state beyond its conventional par­ameters. For instance, see Perry Anderson, “The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci,” New Left Review, no. 100 (November–­December 1976): 35–36. 38. In an interview, Foucault explained a dispositif as “a thoroughly heterogeneous ensemble consisting of discourses, institutions, architectural forms, regulatory deci- sions, laws, administrative mea­sures, scientific statements, philosophical, moral, and philanthropic propositions—in short, the said as much as the unsaid. Such are the ele­ments of the apparatus [dispositif]. The apparatus itself is the system of relations that can be established between ­these ele­ments.” Michel Foucault, “Confession of the Flesh” (interview with Ornicar?, July 10, 1977), in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon, 1980), 194. Foucault elaborated that a dispositif is a “formation which has as its major function at a given his- torical moment that of responding to an urgent need. The apparatus thus has a dominant strategic function” (195). Foucault theorizes a dispositif as animated by two strategic tendencies: first, the apparatus is functionally overdetermined as its effects resonate throughout its other ele­ments, and second, Foucault notes, “­there is a perpetual pro­cess of strategic elaboration” that alters the strategic direction of the apparatus (195). On Foucault’s theory of dispositif, see Giorgio Agamben, What Is an Apparatus? And Other Essays, trans. David Kishik and Stefan Pedatella (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2009). 39. In a 1970 postscript to the isa essay, Althusser attempted to distinguish between the function of ideology in reproduction and the constitutive exploitation of cap­i­tal­ist social relations more generally. See Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Appara- tuses,” 124. 40. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 96, 97. In his draft notes on isas, Althusser succinctly explained, “An Ideological State Apparatus is a system of defined institutions, organ­izations, and the corresponding practices. Realized in the­ se institutions, organ­izations, and practices of this system is all or part (generally speaking, a typical combination of certain ele­ments) of the State Ideology. The ideology realized in an isa ensures its systemic unity on the basis of an ‘anchoring’ in material functions specific to each isa; ­these functions are not reducible to that ideology, but serve it as a ‘support.’ ” Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism, 77. 41. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 101. 42. Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism, 70. 43. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 114. 44. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 115. Warren Montag points out that Pascal’s “hy­po­thet­i­cal libertine . . . ​poses more complicated prob­lems” since the libertine desires to believe in God but only encounters emptiness. Montag

Notes to Chapter 3 223 argues that while Pascal is presenting a “theory of the conditioning of the mind through the body that makes the soul a mere reflection of the body without substance or mate- rial form,” Althusser “has set for himself the directly opposite objective: to demonstrate the material existence of ideas, beliefs, and consciousness.” Montag, Althusser and His Contemporaries, 153–154. 45. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 116–117. On this point, see Judith Butler, “Conscience Doth Make Subjects of Us All: Althusser’s Subjection,” in The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997), 112. For an incisive critique of Butler’s reading of Althusser, see Matthew Lampert, “Resist- ing Ideology: On Butler’s Critique of Althusser” in Diacritics 43, no. 2 (2015): 124–147. 46. Althusser likens interpellation to a police officer’s hail on the street corner—­ “Hey, you ­there!”—­which we naturally respond to since we recognize that, of course, the hail was meant for us. Hailing is not an empirical sequence but rather an internal logic of ideology; it does not happen out ­there but is simultaneous and constitutive of ideology. Althusser recognizes the impossibility of the “temporal succession” constitu- tive of his theory of interpellation, noting that “in real­ity ­these ­things happen without any succession. The existence of ideology and the hailing or interpellation of individu- als as subjects are one and the same ­thing.” Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 118. Furthermore, as many theorists have noted, Althusser’s theory rests upon a subtle but necessary theoretical impossibility: that is, the notion of a presub- jected “concrete individual” (118). Judith Butler notes, “If the­ re is no subject except as a consequence of this subjection, the narrative that would explain this requires that the temporality not be true, for the grammar of that narrative presupposes that the­ re is no subjection without a subject who undergoes it.” See Butler, “Conscience Doth Make Subjects of Us All,” 117, 111–112. In addition to Lampert’s critique of Butler mentioned earlier, see also: Pierre Macherey, “Judith Butler and the Althusserian Theory of Subjec- tion,” trans. Stephanie Bundy, Décalages 1, no. 2 (2013): 1–22. 47. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 115, 123. 48. Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 123. 49. On this question, see Butler, “Conscience Doth Make Subjects of Us All,” 106–131. 50. Critiquing Poulantzas, Laclau argues that the multiple and overdetermined nature of ideological interpellations renders the pro­cess in which a fully interpellated class sub- ject is formed “never . . . ​complete: it ­will always have an ambiguity.” From this, Laclau asks “how are ideologies transformed?” to which he answers, “through class struggle­ , which is carried out through the production of subjects and the articulation/disarticulation of discourses.” Ernesto Laclau, “Fascism and Ideology,” in Capitalism, Fascism, Pop­ulism:­ Politics and Ideology in Marxist Theory (London: Verso, 1977), 109. For Poulantzas’s pass- ing mention of disarticulation, see Nicos Poulantzas, “Internationalization of Cap­i­tal­ist Relations and the Nation-­State,” in The Poulantzas Reader: Marxism, Law and the State, ed. James Martin (London: Verso, 2008), 253, 258. 51. See Hong, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi. Also Keongil Kim, “Japa­nese Assimila- tion Policy and Thought Conversion in Colonial ­Korea,” in Colonial Rule and Social Change in ­Korea, 1910–1945, ed. Hon Yung Lee, Yong Chool Ha, and Clark W. Sorensen (Seattle: Center for Korean Studies, University of Washington Press, 2013), 206–233.

224 Notes to Chapter 3 52. If anything, this decision would constitute an act of what Jean-­Paul Sartre had called “bad faith,” in which consciousness negates both the freedom and the deci- sion upon which someone chooses from a given range of options. On “bad faith,” see Jean-­Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness: A Phenomenological Essay on Ontology, trans. Hazel E. Barnes (New York: Washington Square, 1953), 47–70. 53. On so-­called gisō-­tenkō, see Steinhoff,Tenkō , 195–196. 54. Itō Akira makes this argument. See Itō, “ ‘Hyōmen no ito’ no tsuikyū to tenkō no yarinaoshi,” in Tenkō to tennōsei, 274–287. 55. Foucault was not willing to reduce power to a function of cap­i­tal­ist exploitation, what he ­later critiqued as the “economism” in liberal and Marxian theories of power. See Michel Foucault, “Two Lectures,” in Power/Knowledge, 88–89. However, Althusser directly argued, “Every­thing that happens in a cap­i­tal­ist social formation, including the forms of state repression that accompany it . . . ​is rooted in the material base of cap­i­tal­ist relations of production, which are relations of cap­i­tal­ist exploitation, and in a system of production in which production is itself subordinated to exploitation and thus to the production of capi- tal on an extended scale.” Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism, 33, italics in original. 56. On tenkō lit­er­a­ture, see: Yukiko Shigeto, “The Politics of Writing: Tenkō and the Crisis of Repre­sen­ta­tion” (PhD diss., University of Washington, 2009); George Sipos, “The Lit­er­a­ture of Po­liti­cal Conversion (Tenkō) of Japan” (PhD diss., University of Chicago, 2013). The Rōdō undōshi kenkyūkai ­L( abor Movement History Research Group) is one of the few groups to have noted Kobayashi’s impor­tant role in the tenkō phenomenon. Kobayashi delivered a series of closed lectures to this research group in the mid-1970s. Drafts of ­these lectures ­were distributed within the Rōdō undōshi kenkyūkai ­under the title “Nihon shakai undōshi hishi.” Chapters 4 through 7 are archived at Ohara shakai mondai kenkyūsho at Hosei University, Tokyo. Portions of ­these lectures ­were published as “Waga hansei no kaisō” in Rōdō undōshi kenkyū, no. 9 (1972). ­Later ­these lectures w­ ere revised and published as Kobayashi Morito, “Tenkōki” no hitobito: Chianijihōka no katsudōka gunzō (Tokyo: Shinjidaisha, 1987). For secondary research on Kobayashi Morito conducted by members of the Rōdō undōshi kenkyūkai, see Itō, Tenkō to Tennōsei; Ishidō Kiyotomo, “Kobayashi Morito no tadotta michi,” in Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 253–267. 57. A short biographical summary of Kobayashi Morito’s life can be found in Tsu- nazawa, Nō no shisō to nihon kindai (Nagoya: Fubaisha, 2004), 10–13. For Kobayashi’s reflections on his life trajectory, see Kobayashi,“Tenkōki” no hitobito, 12–27. 58. For information on the 1928 general elections, see Thomas Havens, “Japan’s Enig- matic Election of 1928,” Modern Asian Studies 11, no. 4 (1977): 543–555. 59. Kobayashi Morito (Ono Yōichi, pseud.), Kyōsantō o dassuru made (Tokyo: Daidōsha, 1932), 1. 60. Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 20. 61. Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 21. This use of tenkō is anachronistic for the pe- riod Kobayashi is recounting; it would be a few more years before tenkō came to signify an act of defection or apostasy. 62. For the prosecution’s case against Kobayashi Morito and twelve other suspects, see “Kobayashi Morito hoka jūnimei chianijihō ihan hikoku jiken yoshin shūketsu

Notes to Chapter 3 225 kettei sho,” inShakaishugi undō, vol. 3: Gendaishi shiryō 16, ed. Yamabe Kentarō (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 1965), 540–546. 63. For a short biography on Miyagi, see Ko Miyagi Moto Shihō Daijin Kenpi Jikkōiin Jimusho, ed., Miyagi Chōgorō shōden (Tokyo: Ko Miyagi Moto Shihō Daijin Kenpi Jikkōiin Jimusho, 1950). For Fujii, see Yamashita Zongyō, “Fujii Eshō,” in Nihon keiji seisakushi jō no hitobito kenkyūkai, ed. Nihon Keiji Seisaku Kenkyūkai (Tokyo: Nihon Kajo Shuppan, 1989). 64. In an interview with Patricia Steinhoff in December 1967, a tenkōsha named Ka- wasaki Tateo reports that while the leadership of the jcp w­ ere held in Ichigaya Prison, many rank-­and-­file members ­were held in Toyotama Prison. See Steinhoff,Tenkō , 149. For documents and reflections written by activists held in Toyotama Prison, see the first part: “Gokuchū no ki,” in Kazahaya, Gokuchū no shōwashi, 5–107. 65. Tellingly, in the postwar Kobayashi narrates his experiences in prison and at the Imperial Renovation Society as a series of encounters with fate (innen) and destiny (shukuen), particularly meeting Chaplain Fujii and Chief Procurator Miyagi while serv- ing his prison sentence in Tokyo. See Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 24–26. 66. In a 1933 publication, Kobayashi is listed as an “Imperial Renovation Society Re- habilitation Counselor” (Teikoku kōshinkai hogo iin). See Kobayashi Morito, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya: Teikoku kōshinkai ni okeru jiken ni motozuite,” Hogo Jihō 17, no. 6 (June 1933): 16–24, reprinted in Ogino Fujio, ed., Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3 (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 13–18. Ogino lists this essay as published in the May issue. Despite this, the pagination I reference comes from the Ogino collection. 67. Other rehabilitation groups at the time focused on parolees (karishakuhō) or ­those who had finished their full prison sentences. For a discussion of the Imperial Renovation Society in comparison to other hogo dantai, see Ko Miyagi Moto Shihō Daijin Kenpi Jikkōiin Jimusho ed., Miyagi Chōgorō shōden, 153–160. 68. Miyagi was an early proponent of hogoshugi within the Justice Ministry, and spent his entire life advocating for the importance of rehabilitation, particularly in relation to juvenile delinquents. See Akira Morito, “Taishō shōnenhō no shikō to ‘shihō hogo’ no gainen,” Hanzai Shakai Kenkyū 20 (1997): 64–86; Kasagi Nihaya, “Miyagi Chōgorō no shōnenhō shisō,” Takada Hōgaku, no. 4 (March 2005): 1–16; Ko Miyagi Moto Shihō Daijin Kenpi Jikkōiin Jimusho ed., Miyagi Chōgorō shōden; Yamada Kenji, “Miyagi Chōgorō,” Tsumi to batsu 34, no. 1 (1996): 47–53. For Miyagi’s writings on the relation- ship between thought crime and hogo, see Miyagi Chōgorō, Hōritsuzen to hōritsuaku (Tokyo: Dokusho Shinpōsha Shuppanbu, 1941), part 5. 69. See Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya,” 17; Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 120. 70. On the­ se funding sources, see Ko Miyagi Moto Shihō Daijin Kenpi Jikkōiin Jimusho ed., Miyagi Chōgorō shōden, 155–156. 71. Based on a report from 1935, Itō Akira provides the following numbers of thought criminals ­under supervision at the center: 1931–1932, 8 ­people; 1932–1933, 43 ­people; 1933–1934, 143 ­people; and 1934–1935, 178 ­people. Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 228. Kobayashi reports that on any given day, upwards of fourteen or fifteen ­people would be looking for employment counseling. Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 225.

226 Notes to Chapter 3 72. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made. 73. Looking back on the importance of this text, Kobayashi’s advisee and colleague Chaplain Fujii Eshō recounts that ­after this book was published, the Imperial Renova- tion Society soon found itself assisting over two hundred paroled thought criminals. See Fujii Eshō, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” Hogo Jihō 19, no. 1 (Janu- ary 1935): 16. 74. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 75, 172, 161, 150, and 159 respectively. ­These are just a few of the terms that Kobayashi uses to signify his conversion proc­ ess throughout the text. 75. Consider for instance the title of the work—U­ p ­until Leaving the Communist Party. On one level, this suggests a temporal logic of narrative closure. That is, it is not ­whether Kobayashi discarded communism, but rather an explanation—­and thus an instructional aid—­for how one abandons radical politics. At the same time, this also reflects Althusser’s theory of the retroactive temporality at work in ideological subjec- tion discussed earlier. 76. Chapters 1 through 5 are titled as follows: “The 3.15 Incident,” “The Sprouts [mebae] of Marxism,” “The Leveller’s Movement,” “A Friend to the Small Cultivators,” and “Marxist Vanguard.” 77. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 56. 78. On the idea of the vanishing mediator, see Fredric Jameson, “The Vanishing Me- diator: Narrative Structure in Max Weber,” New German Critique, no. 1 (winter 1973): 52–89. 79. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 66. In an insightful interpretation, Tsu- nazawa understands the function of mountains, rivers, and rice fields in Kobayashi’s writing as symbolizing the space of the village as a site of healing: “Even in the world of the village, replete more so than anywhere ­else with poverty and contradiction, [the vil- lage] performs a sufficient function as a space where wounds are mended.” Tsunazawa, Nō no shisō to nihon kindai, 21. 80. See Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 74–76. 81. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 81. 82. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 88. 83. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 122. 84. Kobayashi reports that he was influenced by a book by Kobayashi Sanzaburō to explore the connection between mind and body, spiritual and physical health. See Kobayashi Sanzaburō, Seimei no shinpi: Ikiru chikara to ijutsu no gacchi (Kyoto: Seizasha, 1922). 85. This sequence of Kobayashi’s reunification of mind and body unfolds through a series of chapters titled “Injury of Flesh” (“Ketsuniku e no nayami”), “The First Step in the Change in Direction,” “Madness? Death?,” “The Mystery of Life,” “The Body’s Rehabilitation” (“Nikutai no fukkatsu”), and fi­nally, “The Erasure of Marxism.” 86. This notion of unification (gacchi) w­ ill be a continuing ideological trope in Kobayashi’s ­later writings. It is predicated on Kobayashi’s claim that unlike West- ern materialism, Japa­nese thought conceives of mind and body, ideas and m­ atter, as inseparably connected, what he understands through the Buddhist princip­ le “busshin

Notes to Chapter 3 227 ichinyo” (roughly: “­matter and mind are one”). See Kobayashi’s­l ater writing: Tenkōsha no shisō to seikatsu, 10. 87. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 52. This is a common trope in tenkō biogra- phies; we ­will see how another convert, Kojima Yuki, explained the appeal of the jcp in this way l­ater in this chapter. 88. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 150–151. 89. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 176–180. On the use of “self” (jiga, jibun, jiko) in conversion biographies, see Steinhoff,Tenkō , 132. 90. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 181. 91. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 180. 92. In this schema, society was no longer understood as constituted by class conflict, but had become a multiplicity of ­wills that w­ ere sublimated at a higher plane. Kobayashi argued that without the­ se multiple ­wills and their sublimation, “this world would perish into mere scientific existence” Kyōsantō( o dassuru made, 153). ­These ­wills provided the drive for self-­betterment, but required their mediation at a higher plane through what he sees as a transcendental “blind ­will” (mōmokuteki ishi)—­that is, the domain of Buddha’s mercy. ­Here Kobayashi argued that “Buddhist faith is the fusion [yūgō] of our egos [wareware no shōga]; it is ­here that our world has formed” (153). 93. In the preface to the text, Kobayashi writes, “Unable to discover personal solace in Marxism, in the end I have arrived at religion,” again emphasizing socialist activism as a search for individual peace. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 4. 94. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 169. 95. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 169. 96. Chapter 7 is titled “The First Step ­toward a Change in Direction” (“Hōkōtenkan e no dai-­ippo”). 97. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 75, 162. 98. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 75. We can read Kobayashi’s critique as indirectly related to the prob­lems of Comintern policies in the 1920s concerning the dif­ fer­ent conditions and po­litical­ situations in each country. This proved catastrophic with the rise of fascism and the belated shift to a popul­ar front strategy. See Nicos Poulant- zas, Fascism and Dictatorship: The Third International and the Prob­lem of Fascism, trans. Judith White (London: Verso, 1979). 99. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 162–163. 100. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 162–163. 101. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 163. 102. In the postwar, Maruyama Masao would explain tenkō as signifying “an escape from the tensions of self-­regulation imposed according to a theory (or formula); like the release of a tightly coiled spring, tenkō brought about an instantaneous return to a ‘natu­ral’ world of ‘inclusivity.’ ” Maruyama Masao, Nihon no shisō (Tokyo: Iwanami Shinsho, 1961), 15. En­glish translation from James Dorsey, “From Ideological Lit­er­a­ture to a Literary Ideology: ‘Conversion’ in War­time Japan.” in Converting Cultures: Religion, Ideology and Transformations of Modernity, edited by Dennis Washburn and A. Kevin Reinhart (Leiden: Brill, 2007), 472. 103. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 163.

228 Notes to Chapter 3 104. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 163. See Tsunazawa’s analy­sis of this aspect of Kobayashi’s thought in Tsunazawa, Nō no shisō to nihon kindai, 22–23. 105. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 164. For an analy­sis of the debates over this passage from the Communist Manifesto, see Roman Rosdolsky, “The Workers and the Fatherland: A Note on a Passage in the ‘Communist Manifesto,’ ” Science and Society 29, no. 3 (1965): 330–337. 106. Steinhoff refers to a report delivered by Kōji Konaka in a thought administrators’ conference in 1938, where Kōji refers to three types of tenkō categorized by the Imperial Renovation Society: po­liti­cal (seijiteki), citizen (shiminteki), and religious (shūkyōteki). See Steinhoff,Tenkō , 129. It is impor­tant to recognize that not only did the state’s categories change over time, but also that such conceptual developments are implicated in the phenomenon we seek to analyze; namely, the transformations in emperor system ideology in the 1930s. 107. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 257. 108. Kobayashi, Kyōsantō o dassuru made, 258. 109. The editors ofHogo Jihō translated its title into En­glish as Aid and Guidance: The Bulletin of the Central Ex-­Prisoners’ Aid Association of Japan. 110. The publicationHoseikai Kaihō was in print from 1917 to 1929. Representing the dominant discourse of hogo (protection) in justice circles in the mid-1920s, the bulletin changed its name to Hogo Jihō in 1929. Similarly, the bulletin’s demise in 1939 signals how resources ­were directed to the war effort following Japan’s invasion of China in 1937, and the parallel eclipse of rehabilitation by total-­war mobilization mea­sures. I discuss this transformation in criminal reform mea­sures in the late 1930s in chapter 5. 111. Before 1933, a few articles had been published intermittently inHogo Jihō address- ing thought crime and reforming thought criminals. But it was not un­ til 1933 that this became a dominant topic in the bulletin. Kobayashi’s first essay inHogo Jihō was pub- lished in September 1932, on his experience with what he called “indirect rehabilitation” (kansetsu hogo) at the Imperial Renovation Society. See Kobayashi Morito, “Kansetsu hogo taiken o kataru,” Hogo Jihō 16, no. 9 (September 1932): 43–47. 112. Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya.” 113. In addition to this article, a March 3, 1933, Tokyo Asahi Shimbun article in the eve­ning edition reports that a “Rare Suspended Sentence is Given to a Converted Party Member” (“Tenkō tōin ni shikkō yūyo: mezurashii sokketsu,” 2). 114. See “Tenkō shisōhannin ni hogo gakari shinsetsu: Shihōkan kaigi ni tōshin,” Yomiuri Shimbun, eve­ning ed., May 23, 1933, 2. 115. Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya,” 14. 116. ­Here Kobayashi admitted that while rehabilitation groups should not too strongly reject a convert’s po­liti­cal commitments or activities, they must “guard against the dangers” (kikensei o yobō) that this continued activity presented. Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya,” 14. 117. Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya,” 14–15. 118. Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya,” 15. Kyōka is translated in En­glish variously as “influence,” “indoctrination,” or “moral suasion.” On kyōka in the

Notes to Chapter 3 229 formation of the modern Japa­nese nation-­state, see Carol Gluck, Japan’s Modern Myths: Ideology in the Late Meiji Period (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1987), 12, 103, 279; Sheldon Garon, Molding Japa­nese Minds: The State in Everyday Life (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1997), xiv, 7. 119. Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya,” 16. 120. In chapter 4, we ­will see how this concern for moral guidance ­will develop into what Michel Foucault has theorized as a distinct mode of power, which he calls governmentality. 121. Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya,” 21. 122. ­Here Kobayashi distinguished between the vari­ous employment opportunities for the dif­fer­ent classes of tenkōsha, including, for intellectuals, finding work as report- ers, in publishing, and in libraries; for laborers, recognizing the difficulties they faced by finding industrial work­ after being jailed; and many othe­ rs, who, unable to find employ- ment, ­were attempting to establish small shops or find other sources of income. See Kobayashi, “Shisōhan no hogo o ika ni subeki ya,” 16–17. Kobayashi notes the impor­tant role of the Japan Red Support Group (Nihon Sekishoku Kyūenkai), a po­liti­cal prisoner support group started in 1927 and which continued in dif­fer­ent formations into the postwar period. Kobayashi was envisioning another kind of group that would c­ ounter such socialist-­inspired groups by publishing anti-­Marxist or religious materials in order to urge a prisoner to convert (17). On the Japan Red Support Group, see Takizawa Ichirō, Nihon sekishoku kyūenkai shi (Tokyo: Nihon Hyōronsha, 1993). 123. Hirata Isao in Hōritsu Shimbun, August 20, 1933, cited in Ogino, Shisō kenji, 66. 124. The rec­ord for this event is published as “Shisōhan ni kansuru hogo jigyō kōshūkai,” Hogo Jihō 17, no. 7 (July 1933): 51–65. Sano and Nabeyama appropriated the name of Stalin’s “socialism in one country” and called their new national socialism ikkoku shakaishugi. See Sano Manabu and Nabeyama Sadachika, eds., Nihonkyōsantō oyobi komintaan hihan: Ikkoku shakaishugi ni tsuite (Tokyo: Musansha, 1934). Also, Ger- maine A. Hoston, “Emperor, Nation and the Transformation of Marxism to National Socialism in Prewar Japan: The Case of Sano Manabu,”Studies in Comparative Com- munism 18, no. 1 (spring 1985): 25–47, and Germaine A. Hoston, “Ikkoku shakai-­shugi: Sano Manabu and the Limits of Marxism as Cultural Criticism,” in Culture and Identity: Japa­nese Intellectuals during the Interwar Years, ed. J. Thomas Rimer (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1990), 168–186. 125. Around this time, other endeavors ­were taking place that addressed dangerous thought. For instance, in April 1933, two months before the Sano-­Nabeyama defection, it was announced that a cabinet-­level committee would be formed, staffed with officials from the Home, Justice, and Education Ministries as well as prison wardens, military officials, and ­others, in order to develop a national thought policy (shisō taisaku). This committee met between July and October 1933, issuing policy proposals such as “Education and Religion,” “Correcting Thought,” “Regulating Thought,” and “Social Policy.” As its mandate stated, such a broad thought policy required, first, the further “clarification and spread fukyū[ tettei] of the Japa­nese spirit that is the guiding princi­ ple of the state” and second, the “investigation of unhealthy thought and a plan for its correction [zesei].” On the formation of this committee, see Monbushō shisōkyoku, ed.,

230 Notes to Chapter 3 Shisōkyoku yōkō, November 1934. Itō cites this report and provides a general summary of the committee meeting. See Itō,Tenkō to tennōsei, 156. 126. For a list of the lectures, including individual synopses, see “Shisōhan ni kansuru hogo jigyō kōshūkai,” 52, 58–63. 127. See the synopsis of Akamatsu Katsumaro’s lecture “Nihon seishin to gendai shakai undō,” in “Shisōhan ni kansuru hogo jigyō kōshūkai,” 59–60. For an analysi­ s of Akamatsu’s po­liti­cal transformations in the 1930s see: Stephen Large, “Buddhism and Po­liti­cal Renovation in Prewar Japan: The Case of Akamatsu Katsumaro,”The Journal of Japanese­ Studies 9, no. 1 (Winter, 1983): 33–66. 128. See the itemized list: “Shisōhan ni kansuru hogo jigyō kōshūkai,” 63–64. 129. Saotome, Tenkōsha no shuki. 130. At the time of writing this piece in October 1933, Shiono Suehiko (1880– 1949) was head of the Corrections Division in the Justice Ministry (Shihōshō gyōkeikyokuchō). For a short biographical sketch of Shiono, see Ogino, Shisō kenji, iv. 131. Shiono Suehiko, “Jo,” in Saotome, Tenkōsha no shuki, 1–2; Preface 1. 132. Shiono, “Jo,” Preface 1. 133. Shiono, “Jo,” Preface 2. 134. Saotome, “Hensha no kotoba,” in Saotome, Tenkōsha no shuki, 1. 135. Saotome, “Hensha no kotoba,” 1. 136. Saotome, “Hensha no kotoba,” 2. 137. See Saotome’s concluding remarks: Saotome, “Hensha no kotoba,” 2. 138. Additionally, many of the contributors found lower or midtier employment upon being released, including driving a taxi, working on the ­family farm, ­running a used bookstore, and one contributor becoming a hous­ e­wife. See the biographical sketches in Saotome, Tenkōsha no shuki, 4–6. 139. ­These names are most likely pseudonyms in order to protect the identity of the parolees. 140. For instance, the industrial laborer Uchimura Shigeru joined the military in 1932, whereas the intellectual Murai Hisashirō was employed by a major newspaper. 141. A biographical sketch of Kojima notes that she joined the movement as a student, and was arrested and sent to Ichigaya Prison. Upon converting, her sentence was suspended and she was released from prison. She married and was living in Akita Prefecture at the time. See Saotome, Tenkō no shuki, 4. 142. Kojima Yuki, “Daihi no ote ni sugaru made,” in Saotome, Tenkō no shuki, 43–73. On the ideology of ryōsai kenbo in twentieth-­century Japan, see Kathleen Uno, “The Death of ‘Good Wife, Wise M­ other’?,” in Postwar Japan as History, ed. Andrew Gordon (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), 293–322. 143. Kojima, “Daihi no ote ni sugaru made,” 51. 144. Kojima, “Daihi no ote ni sugaru made,” 52. Her full explanation is as follows: “My power as one person was small. But this small power, through its connection with this large group [idai shūdan], would become ­great, or, by integrating with this ­grand power, my own power would become ­grand. And through my own power, I could carry out impor­tant work. . . . ​­Here, in one stroke [ikkyoshuittōsoku] was the influence of the Japa­nese Communist Party.” Kojima, “Daihi no ote ni sugaru made,” 52.

Notes to Chapter 3 231 145. Kojima, “Daihi no ote ni sugaru made,” 55–56. 146. Itō Akira argues that such concerns cited to explain one’s defection (such as love for one’s ­family) did not just suddenly emerge at the moment of imprisonment but ­were felt by activists as they participated in the communist movement. It was only a­ fter the mass arrests and the increasing sense of defeat that struck the communist move- ment that the ­family became an excuse for defection. See Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 141–144. 147. Kojima, “Daihi no ote ni sugaru made,” 63. 148. For another essay in Tenkōsha Memoirs that links filial love and Buddhist com- passion, see Murai Hisashirō, “Fubo ha saijō no kami nari,” in Saotome, Tenkōsha no shuki, 74–94. 149. Kojima, “Daihi no ote ni sugaru made,” 73. 150. Kobayashi Morito (Ono Yōichi, pseud.), “Marukisuto ha gokuchū ika ni shūkyō o taiken shita ka,” in Saotome, Tenkō no shuki, 240. As with his earlier biography, Ko- bayashi starts with a review of the Marxist critique of religion as the negation of real­ity, moving through a reassessment of religion while in jail, and ultimately his religious experience (shūkyōteki na taiken), which caused him to have total faith (zettaiteki na shinkō) in Buddhism. He concluded, “It is not when we theoretically demonstrate religion, but only when we enter into a life of faith [shinkō no seikatsu] that religion be- comes our flesh and blood” (233, 240). Kobayashi outlined three princip­ les that under- lay a religious conversion, which we can interpret as princi­ples that guided Kobayashi’s efforts in the Imperial Renovation Society. First, he began by drawing upon a central tenet of True Pure Land Buddhism by arguing that “the possibility of establishing true faith begins from faith in Other-­Power” (tariki no shinkō) (241). This rendered tenkō not an act of one’s own ­will, but the very negation of this ­will in the Other-­Power of Buddhist grace. This also con­ve­niently provided an explanation for the counseling Ko- bayashi received from Chaplain Fujii as well as his own efforts advising ex-­communists in the Imperial Renovation Society. From this princi­ple derived the second: the “notion of reciprocal compassion” (kanjō hōon no nen), which, Kobayashi explained, constituted all ­human relations, ­whether interpersonal, familial, or social. A social praxis that de- nied this spirit, such as materialism, could not capture this “feeling of compassion” and thus lacked an ethos to justify social engagement (242). The third and last princi­ple was that “total salvation [issai no kyūsai] emerges from the fundamental princip­ le of benefit- ing oneself by benefiting othe­ rs [jiri rita]” (243). Collectively, ­these three princi­ples infused his efforts to rehabilitate po­liti­cal criminals at the Imperial Renovation Society with Buddhist ethics of compassion and selfless dedication ­toward ­others. 151. This essay collected a three-­part series of articles that Kobayashi had written for Hogo Jihō ­under the same title, “Tenkōsha ha doko ni iku.” See the September 1933, January 1934, and April 1934 issues of Hogo Jihō. Kobayashi Morito, “Tenkōsha ha doko ni iku,” in Saotome, Tenkōsha no shuki, 245–260. The main portion of Kobayashi’s essay reports his recent visit to a small collective farm in Gunma Prefecture started by Ya- maguchi Hayato. Yamaguchi was a religious tenkōsha whom Kobayashi had mentored through the auspices of the Imperial Renovation Society. ­After being released from jail, Yamaguchi returned to Gunma and or­ga­nized the cooperative farm ­under the Zen Bud- dhist Baizhang Huaihai’s (720–814) slogan “­Those who don­ ’t work, don­ ’t eat” (ichinichi

232 Notes to Chapter 3 nasazareba, ichinichi kurawazu, 一日不作一日不食). See Kobayashi, “Tenkōsha ha doko ni iku,” 247. Although Yamaguchi’s rural collective retained private property, it communally managed ­labor and consumption. At this time in 1933, the­ re ­were roughly twenty members in the cooperative, with Yamaguchi acting as director. To Kobayashi, Yamaguchi’s collective farm provided an example of how tenkōsha could continue to be committed to social reform (­here, rural revitalization), while also continuing to reform themselves as patriotic subjects—­a theme that he would continue to emphasize in ­later writings. See Yamaguchi’s contribution to Tenkōsha Memoirs: Yamaguchi Hayato, “Kyōsanshugi yori shūkyō e,” in Saotome, Tenkōsha no shuki, 1–42. See also Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 222–223. 152. Kobayashi, “Tenkōsha ha doko ni iku,” 259. 153. For some contributors like Kojima, the conversion narrative concluded with her religious awakening and a return to a quiet life as a ­house­wife. Other contributors like Yamaguchi Hayato and Kobayashi Morito concluded their essays by describing a continued commitment to social reform. One essay by Murai Hisashirō concluded with a more explicit expression of imperial ideology, with Murai arguing, “If the vari­ ous Western states are based on Hegelian philosophy and its ‘ideal ethical state,’ then, we can begin to grasp our Japa­nese Empire as ‘an ideal religious state’ [shūkyōteki risō kokka], based on the Japa­nese kokutai that the left rejects.” Murai, “Fubo ha saijō no kami nari,” 94. 154. As noted in chapter 2, the tenkō phenomenon appeared at the same time that arrests peaked ­under the Peace Preservation Law. For instance, in 1933 alone, 14,622 individuals ­were arrested. See Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 133. For a procurator’s consideration of tenkō in relation to the continuing arrests, see Tozawa Shigeo, “Shisō hanzai no kensatsu jimu ni tsuite” (1933), in Gendaishi shiryō 16: Shakaishugi undō, vol. 3, ed. Yamabe Kentarō (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 1965), 15–36. 155. Itō Akira cites a 1935 report that gives the following statistics on tenkō: out of the 650 jcp members in jail, 505 had or ­were in the pro­cess of declaring tenkō; only 145 prisoners ­were reported to not have declared tenkō. Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 133. 156. Itō cites a 1936 report by procurator Ikeda Katsu: Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 142. 157. See Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 87–88. On the relationship between zainichi Koreans and the jcp, see Mun Gyong Su, “Nihon kyōsantō to zainichi chōsenjin,” in Zainichi chōsenjin mondai no kigen (Musashino: Kurein, 2007), 132–136. Also Nishikawa Hiroshi, “Zainichi chōsenjin kyōsantōin • dōchō no jittai: Keihokyoku shiryō ni yoru 1930nen- dai zenhanki no tōkeiteki bunseki,” Jinbun Gakuhō 50 (March 1981): 31–53. In regard to conversion in colonial Kor­ ea, the Charges Withheld policy was extended to colonial ­Korea around the same time, although, as Keongil Kim suggests, officialsw ­ ere reluctant to apply the policy. Kim, “Japa­nese Assimilation Policy and Thought Conversion in Colonial ­Korea,” 213. To support this claim, Kim refers to a 1996 master’s thesis written by Chi Sŭngjun. See n. 33, 230. 158. Writing in 1935, Kobayashi mentions that the Imperial Renovation Society had recently taken on forty Korean converts seeking assistance. See Kobayashi Morito, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” inTenkōsha no shisō to seikatsu, ed. Kobayashi Morito (Tokyo: Daidōsha, 1935), 76–79.

Notes to Chapter 3 233 159. One report lists 955 parolees receiving some kind of assistance from the Imperial Renovation Society in mid-1934. Shakai undō tsūshin, May 9, 1935, cited in Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 228. 160. Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 28–30; Kobayashi Morito, “Shōwa jūichinen ni okeru wareware no kibō,” Tensei, February 1936, 10–11, cited in Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 229. 161. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 66.

Chapter 4. Nurturing the Ideological Avowal 1. On arrest statistics, see Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Chianijihō ihan jiken nendo betsu shori jinin hyō,” in Gendaishi shiryō 45: Chianijihō, ed. Okudaira Yasuhiro (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 1973), 646–649. Hereafter cited asgss 45. 2. Nakazawa Shunsuke, Chianijihō: Naze seitō seiji ha ‘akuhō’ o unda ka (Tokyo: Chūōkō Shinsho, 2012), 147. Richard H. Mitchell has argued that, at this time, the Peace Preservation Law “had the gait of a peglegged sailor. Investigation, interrogation, and prosecution—­the strong leg—­were ­going well; but the other leg—­conversion and rehabilitation—­was weak.” Richard H. Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1976), 121. However, as I argue in chapter 2, con- version and rehabilitation ­were proposed in response to the very success of the “strong leg” in producing a large population of detainees. Even if momentarily out of balance, we need to account for the functional relationship between the two modes of power. 3. On the establishment of the Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision system, see Uchida Hirofumi, Kōsei hogo no tenkai to kadai (Kyoto: Hōritsu Bunkasha, 2015), chapter 3, “Shisōhan hogo katsu hō no seitei to hogokansatsu seido,” 27–48. 4. On Althusser’s distinction between secondary and primary ideologies, see Louis Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism: Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses, trans. G. M. Goshgarian (London: Verso, 2014), 83–84. 5. ­Later, Althusser calls the primary ideology “State Ideology.” See Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism, 77, 81. 6. Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism, 77. As I mentioned in chapter 3, I have reservations about Althusser’s theory of interpellation and therefore am not argu- ing that interpellation was successful or a seamless pro­cess in the Peace Preservation Law apparatus. Rather, I am interested in how this apparatus functioned on the logic of interpellation. 7. Michel Foucault, “Governmentality,” in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmen- tality, ed. Graham Burchell, Colon Gordon, and Peter Miller (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), 102. 8. Foucault, “Governmentality,” 102. 9. Michel Foucault, “Technologies of the Self” (1982), in Essential Works of Foucault 1954–1984, vol. 1: Ethics, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: Penguin, 1997), 249, 242. We might think of Buddhism’s emphasis on self-­negation as what Foucault called elsewhere the “renunciation of the self.” 10. Foucault, “Governmentality,” 100. 11. Foucault, “Governmentality.”

234 Notes to Chapter 3 12. Foucault, “Governmentality,” 103. Foucault explains that, rather than a new mode of power initiated and disseminated from the state, governmentality “is at once internal and external to the state, since it is the tactics of government which make pos­si­ble the continual definition and redefinition of what is within the competence of the state and what is not” (103). The pro­cess by which reform was formalized in the 1930s brought such tactics ­under the purview of the state, thus redefining what was within its sover- eign sphere. 13. See Max Ward, “Crisis Ideology and the Articulation of Fascism in Interwar Japan: The 1938 Thought-­War Symposium,” Japan Forum 26, no. 4 (2014): 462–485. Indeed, before Japan’s invasion of China, it was common for justice officials to discuss the Peace Preservation Law functioning, as what one procurator claimed in 1934, as the “prepara- tory construction for general state mobilization” (kokka sōdōin no junbi kōsaku). See the comments by Tokyo Procurator Ikeda Katsu (1934), cited in Ogino Fujio, Shisō kenji (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2000), 79. 14. See Althusser, On the Reproduction of Capitalism, 83–84. In regards to the title for this section, it is pos­si­ble to find vari­ous officials noting a shift from conversion to rehabilitation taking place in 1935. This par­tic­u­lar iteration (tenkō jidai yori hogo jidai e) comes from Honjō Tetsuzō, “Tenkō to hogo ni kansuru kōsai,” Hogo Jihō 19, no. 1 (Janu- ary 1935): 29. 15. On the Taikōjuku kenkyūsho, see Kobayashi Morito, “Tenkōki” no hitobito: Chianijihōka no katsudōka gunzō (Tokyo: Shinjidaisha, 1987), 115–116. 16. On the Kokumin shisō kenkyūsho and its journal, Kokumin Shisō, see Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 116–119, 126–131; Itō Akira, Tenkō to tennōsei: Nihonkyōsanshugiundō no 1930nendai (Tokyo: Keisō Shobō, 1995), 209–211. Kobayashi reports that he was responsible for assisting with both centers. Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 118. 17. For example, the inaugural issue of Tensei contained articles titled “Renovating One’s View of Life and Awakening to the Nation,” “The Errors of Marx’s Theory of Value,” “World Thought and the Divine Way,” and “The Hope of World Thought,” as well as more personal essays recounting experiences with prison and conversion. The ­table of contents from the inaugural issue of Tensei from August 1935 is reprinted in Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 127–129. 18. For example, see the September 1934 roundtable discussion with Ikeda Katsu, Miyagi Chōgorō, Tozawa Shigeo, and many other officials: “Shisōhan tenkōsha o ika ni suru ka,” Hogo Jihō 18, no. 10 (October 1934): 23–30. 19. Fujii Eshō, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” Hogo Jihō 19, no. 1 (Janu- ary 1935): 13–28. 20. Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 15. Fujii notes that 449 thought criminals had been paroled between January 1930 and June 1934. ­These statistics are limited to metropolitan Japan. 21. Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 27. 22. Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 16–17. 23. Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 17. 24. Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 18.

Notes to Chapter 4 235 25. Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 19, 20. 26. Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 19. 27. Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 22–23. 28. Fujii also provided examples of how the Imperial Renovation Society responded to the par­tic­u­lar needs of female and student converts: In regard to the former, the society had recently formed a ­Women’s Section (Fujinbu) in order to restore the morals of ­those ­women who, by joining the jcp, had “lost the traditional Japa­nese ideal of chas- tity” (nihon korai no teisō kannen o torisatta). In regard to student converts, Fujii argues that, having spent many years in jail, ­these thought criminals ­were unable to return to school to finish their degrees, but at the same time,­w ere unwilling to be reeducated to become “engineers or laborers.” This was posing par­tic­u­lar challenges for the Imperial Renovation Society. See Fujii, “Shisōhan shakuhōsha no hogo hōhō,” 25–26. 29. Michel Foucault, Wrong-­Doing, Truth-­Telling: The Function of Avowal in Justice, trans. Stephen W. Sawyer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014), 24. 30. Foucault, Wrong-Doing,­ Truth-Telling­ , 17. 31. Kobayashi Morito, ed., Tenkōsha no shisō to seikatsu (Tokyo: Daidōsha, 1935). This second volume of tenkōsha biographies was advertised in daily newspapers, which may indicate a stronger effort to publicize the volume to the general public. See for instance the advert for Tenkōsha no shisō to seikatsu and the new magazine Tensei on the front page of the morning edition of Yomiuri Shimbun, December 1, 1935. 32. Kobayashi Morito, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” in Kobayashi, Tenkōsha no shisō to seikatsu, 3–98. 33. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 5. 34. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 8. Recall that, along with the educational apparatus, Louis Althusser identifies the­fa mily as the primary isa in the modern era. See Louis Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes ­towards an Investigation),” in Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2001), 104. 35. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 16, 15. Kobayashi claimed that “the Japa­nese nation emerged and developed from the ­family, becoming its form today”­ (8). 36. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 19–20. 37. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 7. 38. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 8. 39. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 12. 40. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 89. 41. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 40. H­ ere Kobayashi is implicitly critiquing theorists, such as Minobe Tatsukichi, who would delimit impe- rial sovereignty within a constitutional framework. I discuss Minobe’s so-­called organ theory (kikan setsu ron) of the state and the Minobe Incident ­later in the chapter. 42. Sano Manabu and Nabeyama Sadachika, eds., Nihonkyōsantō oyobi komintaan hihan: Ikkoku shakaishugi ni tsuite (Tokyo: Musansha, 1934). 43. For Kobayashi’s close reading and critique of Sano and Nabeyama, see Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 20–36. Although Kobayashi remained

236 Notes to Chapter 4 critical of the revolutionary politics espoused by both the ­Labor Faction (also known as the Kaitō-ha, analyzed in chapter 2) and Sano and Nabeyama, he argued that when the ­Labor Faction presented their critique in 1930–1931, such a stance was extremely difficult to make. This was an attempt to take the bravado out of Sano and Nabeyama’s decision to defect in 1933 (11). 44. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 31–32. 45. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 35. 46. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 38. 47. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 39. 48. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 39. 49. This point recalls a similar move in area studies and in some forms of postcolonial studies to identify the source of contradiction outside of Eu­rope, not in cap­i­tal­ist ex- ploitation and unevenness, but in a purported disjuncture between (Western) capital- ism and non-­Western culture. On this point, see Max Ward, “Historical Difference and the Question of East Asian Marxism(s),” in East Asian Marxisms and Their Trajectories, ed. Joyce Liu and Viren Murthy, Interventions Series (London: Routledge, 2017), 87–102. 50. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 40. Through this cultural prism, Kobayashi was forgetting that the Peace Preservation Law also protected the “system of private property”—­code for the ­legal forms that expressed and mediated cap­i­tal­ist social relations. Recall that earlier in the de­cade the procurator Hirata Isao was willing to accept the defections of the Labor ­Faction even though they still called for the overthrow of capitalism. 51. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 40, 41. In a ­later section titled “Concerning Concrete Issues” (“Gutaiteki mondai ni tsuite”), Kobayashi strug­ gled to negotiate between the exacerbated social contradictions of the mid-1930s and his elevation of the Japa­nese spirit as an integrating force: “We have said that in the true Japa­nese spirit ­there is no class-­consciousness. This is true. But in real­ity, in certain aspects [bubunteki ni], we cannot deny that vari­ous contradictions exist. We must try as hard as pos­si­ble to integrate [tōitsu] ­these contradictions” (52). 52. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 41. 53. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 42. Kobayashi discusses the vari­ous social stations that tenkōsha ­were now returning to (38–44). 54. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 53. Kobayashi believed that national education could guide national integration by expunging received Western forms such as liberalism and Marxism from curriculum and emphasizing the Japa­nese essence (44). 55. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 44. 56. Kobayashi summarized six princi­ples of this new standpoint: (1) the unity of em- peror and subject that constitutes Japan’s unique family-­nation-­state structure; (2) the historical singularity of the imperial kokutai; (3) Japan’s “ability to embrace” (hōyōsei) and assimilate foreign ele­ments; (4) the rejection of class divisions based on Japan’s unique ­family structure; (5) the unique fusion of spirit and ­matter busshin( ichinyo) in Japa­nese thought; and (6) the “realization of Japan’s new mission” (nihon kokumin no

Notes to Chapter 4 237 shin- ­shimei no jikaku). ­These princi­ples are outlined in Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 46–49. 57. On Koreans active in the interwar Japa­nese communist movement, see Mun Gyong Su, “Nihon kyōsantō to zainichi chōsenjin,” in Zainichi chōsenjin mondai no kigen (Musashino: Kurein, 2007), 131–150, in par­tic­u­lar 132–136. Also Nishikawa Hiroshi, “Zainichi chōsenjin kyōsantōin • dōchō no jittai: Keihokyoku shiryō ni yoru 1930nendai zenhanki no tōkeiteki bunseki,” Jinbun Gakuhō 50 (March 1981): 31–53. 58. For example, see “Chōsenjin saishō no tenkōsha arawareru,” Tokyo Asahi Shim- bun, September 10, 1933, eve­ning edition, 11. (Figure 4.1) 59. See Sim Kil-­bok (沈吉福), “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan hogo jigyō no kensetsu no tame ni,” in Kobayashi, Tenkōsha no shisō to seikatsu, 396–406. Interest- ingly, Sim Kil-­bok discusses the necessity for tenkō in the colony through the logic of territorial sovereignty that was discussed in chapters 1 and 2. For instance, he argues that the importance of thought reform policies in ­Korea was ­because ­Korea occupied “an impor­tant space between Manchukuo and Japan [naichi].” In other words, Sim understood the significance of Korean tenkō in strategic, geopo­liti­cal terms (402). 60. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 78. 61. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 49. 62. In a ­later section, Kobayashi somewhat qualified his call to discard the terms “Japa­nese” and “Korean,” urging his readers not to overlook impor­tant differences in circumstances: “along with recognizing that . . . ​­there is increasing assimilation and an increasingly closer relationship between Japa­nese and Korean culture, we must also fully recognize the par­tic­u­lar circumstances [tokushu jijō] of the domestic Koreans.” Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 78. 63. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 50. 64. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 50. 65. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 49. 66. This theme is reiterated by the Korean contributor toThought and Lives of Tenkōsha, Sim Kil-­bok. See Sim, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan hogo jigyō no kensetsu no tame ni,” 396–406. 67. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 76–78. 68. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 76. 69. On ­these policies in colonial ­Korea, see Michael Robinson, “Forced Assimila- tion, Mobilization, and War,” in ­Korea Old and New: A History, ed. Car­ter J. Eckert, Ki-­baik Lee, Young Ick Lew, Michael Robinson, and Edward W. Wagner (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 305–326; Mark Caprio, Japa­nese Assimilation Policies in Colonial ­Korea, 1910–19­ 45 (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 2009). In relation to assimilation policies in Taiwan, see Leo T. S. Ching, Becoming Japanese:­ Colonial Taiwan and the Politics of Identity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2001). 70. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 67–75. Kobayashi notes the society’s collaboration with vari­ous employment agencies in Tokyo, including the Employment Division of the Tokyo City Social Office (Tōkyōshi shakaikyoku

238 Notes to Chapter 4 shokugyōka tōkyōku) and the Tokyo Government Employment Offices (Tōkyōfu shōkaisho) (69). 71. The termonshi designates an imperial donation. For information on this farm, see Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 83–84; Kobayashi,“Tenkōki” no hitobito, 121–122; Miyagi, Miyagi chōgorō shōden, 156–172. 72. Elsewhere, Director Miyagi Chōgorō wrote in a Justice Ministry report that the “farm is the hospital for the soul and body—­one must not be forced into [­labor] and overworked. One must have the opportunity to appreciate flowers, to pat a cow, to commune with nature.” Miyagi quoted in Yamada Kenji, “Miyagi Chōgorō,” Tsumi to batsu 34, no. 1 (1996): 51. 73. Kobayashi provided an extensive list of the private groups that w­ ere working to support tenkōsha: Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 62–63. For one of the few analyses of this network, see Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 200–217. Regarding the Wind of Light Society, see Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 77–78. ­Here Kobayashi reports that while the Special Higher Police held roundtable discussions to address the issue of supporting and reforming Korean thought criminals, groups like the Wind of Light Society would carry out such work with more care and instruction. This reaffirms how the repression of the Special Higher Police would com- plement the moral guidance being cultivated in smaller support groups. See Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 78. 74. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 64–65. 75. Kobayashi, “Nihon kokumin to shite no jikaku ni tatte,” 66. 76. Ikeda Katsu, “Shisō hannin kyōka no keiken hihan,” Keisatsu Kenkyū, Novem- ber 1936, cited in Ogino, Shisō kenji, 82. Elsewhere, I proposed the tripartite schema of protection/prevention/production for understanding the changing operations of the Peace Preservation Law apparatus into the late 1930s: i.e., from protecting the kokutai in the 1920s, through the prevention of recidivism in the early 1930s, to fi­nally the produc- tion of imperial subjects in the late 1930s. See Max Ward, “The Prob­lem of ‘Thought’: Crisis, National Essence and the Interwar Japa­nese State” (PhD diss., New York University, 2011). 77. See Ogino Fujio, “Kaisetsu: Chianijihō seiritsu • ‘kaisei’ shi,” in Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, ed. Ogino Fujio (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 611–613. 78. See the t­able consisting of figures from a January 1943 Justice Ministry report in Ogino, Shisō kenji, 73. 79. Ogino cites an earlier 1930 Tokyo Procuracy Thought Section report that ­emphasized prevention of thought crime (not recidivism) as a central objective. Ogino, Shisō kenji, 44–45. On the prevention of recidivism (saihan bōshi) in the early 1930s, see Okudaira Yasuhiro, Chianijihō shōshi, new ed. (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2006), 158. For an extensive review of the question of ideological recidivism, see Tokuoka Kazuo, Chianijihō ihanjiken no saihan ni kansuru kenkyū (Tokyo: Shihōshō Keijikyoku, 1938). I analyze Tokuoka’s study in chapter 5. For official discussions of how to identify, ad- minister, and secure tenkō, see the proceedings of the Shisō jimukai: “Tenkō ni kansuru jikō” (May 1934), in Shakai mondai shiryō kenkyūkai, ed., Shisō jimukai dō gijiroku (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1976), 128–139.

Notes to Chapter 4 239 80. For example, see Ogino’s summaries of Justice Ministry reports from this time: Ogino, Shisō kenji, 74–76. 81. ­These reports are collected in Ogino Fujio, ed., Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2 (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 13–30. For an overview of ­these reports and the subsequent Diet deliberations on the revision proposals, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 145–152. 82. See the first draft proposal developed by the Justice Ministry’s Criminal Divi- sion: Shihōshō keijikyoku, “Chianijihō kaisei hōritsuan” (December 13, 1933), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 30–33. In addition to proposals developed by the bureaucracy, thought policy proposals ­were also issued by po­liti­cal parties. See, for in- stance, the proposals drafted by the Minseitō (July 1933) and Seiyūkai (December 1933) in gss45, 198–199 and 201–203 respectively. 83. For the government’s accepted revision proposal from February 1934 and the subsequent revisions made in the Lower House and House of Peers in March 1934, see Seifu, “Chianijihō [Kaisei hōritsuan],” and Shūgiin, “Chianijihō kaisei hōritsuan,” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 33–36 and 41–45 respectively. In regard to the 1934 bill presented in committee of the Sixty-­Fifth Imperial Diet and the result- ing debates: “Chianijihō kaisei hōritsuan giji soku kiroku narabi ni iinkai giroku,” in gss45, 204–250. For Justice Ministry reference materials that attended this revision proposal, see Shihōshō, “Chianijihōan sankō shiryō” and “Shisō gyōkei sankō shiryō” (both February 1934), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 77–95 and 95–99 respectively. 84. On the topic of retroactive application, see Suzuki Keifu, Chōsen shokuminchi tōchihō no kenkyū: Chianhō ka no kōminka kyōiku (Sapporo: Hokkaidō Daigaku Tosho Kankōkai, 1989), 180–181. As we ­will see, retroactive application was included in the 1936 Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision Law. For a concise overview of the 1934 revision proposal, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 146. For a summary of the attempts to revise the Peace Preservation Law in both 1934 and 1935, see Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 178–182. On preventative detention in the 1934 revision proposal, see Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Chianijihō ni okeru yobō kōkin,” in Fashizumuki no kokka to shakai 4: Senji nihon no hōtaisei, ed. Tokyo Daigaku Shakai Kagaku Kenkyūsho (Tokyo: Tokyo Daigaku Shuppansha, 1979), 173–191. 85. See Koyama’s explanation of the revision bill, in “Chianijihō kaisei hōritsuan giji soku kiroku narabi ni iinkai giroku,” in gss45, 207–210. 86. I refer to portions of ­these deliberations collected in gss45 and Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2. A full rec­ord of the 1934 Diet deliberations is collected in Shakai mondai shiryō kenkyūkai, ed., Chianijihō ni kansuru giji sokkiroku narabi ni innkai giroku: Dai65kai teikoku gikai, 3 vols. (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1975). 87. Concerning the constitutionality of preventative detention, see for example Mikami Hideo’s question during a February 16 Lower House deliberation: “Chianijihō kaisei hōritsuan giji soku kiroku narabi ni iinkai giroku,” in gss45, 210–212. On the clarification of tenkō, see “Tenkō mondai,” in Ogino,Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 48–50. On the debates over preventative detention in the revision proposal, see Okud- aira, “Chianijihō ni okeru yobō kōkin,” 180–191.

240 Notes to Chapter 4 88. On ­these incidents, see Stephen Large, “Nationalist Extremism in Early Shōwa Japan: I­noue Nisshō and the ‘Blood-­Pledge Corps Incident,’ 1932,” Modern Asian Studies 35, no. 3 (2001): 533–564. Justice officials had been addressing the issue of the right-w­ ing thought movement in earlier ministerial and committee meetings. For example, see the section “Uyoku shisō jiken ni kansuru jikō,” in the November 7, 1934, proceedings of the Shisō jimukai, in Shakai mondai shiryō kenkyūkai, ed., Shisō jimukai dō gijiroku (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1976), 104–108. 89. To meet ­these nationalist threats, some in the Diet advocated for inserting the phrase “altering the state form” (seitai henkaku). Recall that “seitai” was stricken from the original 1925 Peace Preservation Bill. See the Home Ministry’s official response to such a proposal: Naimushō, “Chianijihōchū ni ‘seitai henkaku’ ni kansuru kitei o mōbeku shi to suru an ni taisuru hantai riyū” (1934), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 41. See also Ogino, Shisō kenji, 76–78. 90. See Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 147–151. For Soeda Kenichirō’s question on March 16, see “Chianijihō kaisei hōritsuan giji soku kiroku narabi ni iinkai giroku,” in gss45, 226–229. 91. John Person, “Between Patriotism and Terrorism: The Policing of Nationalist Movements in 1930s Japan,” Journal of Japa­nese Studies 43, no. 2 (summer 2017): 289–318. A similar debate over the application of the law to rightists occurred in a May 1934 meeting of thought procurators between Hirata Isao and Moriyama Takeichirō. See Ogino, Shisō kenji, 77–78. 92. Recall that Althusser posited that two isas are central to the cap­i­tal­ist social formation: the educational isa and the ­family isa. Although he elaborated on the former, Althusser does not discuss the ­family apart from a few passing observations. See Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” 96, fn8. 93. Iwata Chūzō speaking in the House of Peers, March 17, 1934: “Chianijihō kaisei hōritsuan giji soku kiroku narabi ni iinkai giroku,” in gss45, 230. 94. Iwata was citing a newspaper article about a rightist “imperial reverence commu- nist group” (sonnō kyōsanshugi dantai), which was apparently composed of tenkōsha. He cited their platform, which called for the eradication of the class privileges protected by corrupt po­liti­cal parties, “liberation from world capitalism and the establishment of a socialist state.” gss45, 231. 95. In a ­later Upper House deliberation, Uzawa Fusaaki posed a similar question in relation to the construction of a socialist state on the rejection of individual property rights, which assumedly would indicate a major transformation of the kokutai. See gss45, 236–237. 96. gss45, 235. Koyama recalled that although ­there had been talk about adding a clause about rightists at the time that the revision was drafted, this was ultimately rejected. He reminded the Diet that “the Peace Preservation Law was first issued in order to suppress so-­called leftists,” but as far as right-­wing groups ­were concerned, “the government is still researching this issue.” In light of the recent right-­wing actions, he tried to calm fears by reminding Diet members that when rightists acted through vio- lent means, the regular Civil Code could be applied to suppress them. As John Person has argued, under­neath such technical issues was the more fundamental prob­lem that

Notes to Chapter 4 241 radical rightist groups ­were carry­ing out assassinations in the name of the very ­thing that the Peace Preservation Law was supposed to protect: the imperial kokutai. See Person, “Between Patriotism and Terrorism.” 97. See Justice Ministry notes as well as the official version of the bill issued on March 4, 1935: “Shihōshō no kisō sakugyō” and “Chianijihō (kaisei hōritsuan),” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 222–224 and 224–226 respectively. For Justice Ministry reference materials that attended the 1935 revision proposal, see Shihōshō keijikyoku, “Chianijihō kaiseian sankō shiryō” (March 8, 1935) and “Chianijihō kaisei iinkai yōkyū shohyō” (March 9, 1935), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 228–237 and 238–251 respectively. 98. Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 151–152. For the separate bill pertaining to current right-­ wing incidents, see Seifu, “Fuhō danketsu nado shobatsu ni kansuru hōritsuan,” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 226–227. Nakazawa notes that the Home Ministry did not agree with this separate bill: Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 152. For the Justice Ministry’s explanation for erasing preventative detention from the 1935 revision bill, see Shihōshō, “Kaisei chii hōan kara yobō kōkinsei o sakujo” (September 1934) and “Chianijihō kaisei an: Gikai teishutsu ni kettei, ‘Yobō kōkin’ ha sakujo” (January 1935), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 222, 222–223 respectively. 99. Suzuki, Chōsen shokuminchi tōchihō no kenkyū, 181. 100. As Ogino has noted, ­these reports w­ ere made pos­si­ble by the increased funding in the Justice Ministry of mea­sures to “prevent thought crime” (shisō hanzai bōatsu). See Ogino, Shisō kenji, 72–76. The­ se 1935 reference materials also included two surveys of thought crime in colonial ­Korea and one on Taiwan. For the Korean surveys, see Takumushō Kanrikyoku, “Chōsen ni okeru shisō hanzai chōsa shiryō” (two parts, both issued March 1935), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 257–285 and 286–317. For the Taiwan survey, see Takumushō Kanrikyoku, “Taiwan ni okeru shisō undō chōsa shiryō” (March 1935), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 317–323. 101. The following references to Diet deliberations are derived from “Chianijihō kaisei • fuhō danketsu nado shobatsu ni kansuru hōritsuan giji sokkiroku narabi ni iinkai giroku” in gss45, 250–267. 102. On the Minobe Incident, see Miyazawa Toshiyoshi, Tennō kikansetsu jiken: Shiryō ha kataru, 2 vols. (Tokyo: Yūhikaku, 1997); and Walter A. Skya, Japan’s Holy War: The Ideology of Radical Shintō Ultranationalism (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2009), chapter 3. For discussions concerning the 1935 revision’s failure in relation to the Minobe Incident, see Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 152–154; Ushiomi Toshitaka, Chianijihō (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1977), 106; Matsuo Hiroshi, Chianijihō to tokkō keisatsu (Tokyo: Kyōikusha, 1979), 169. On the influence of the Minobe Incident in Justice ­Ministry thought crime policies, see Ogino, Shisō kenji, 81. John Person has a forth­ coming article on Minoda Muneki’s role in creating this incident. 103. Retired Imperial Army General Kikuchi Takeo critiqued Minobe’s theory in the House of Peers on February 15, 1935. Kikuchi believed Minobe’s theory rejected Japan’s kokutai and called for the government to ban his work. Minobe was called to the House of Peers to explain his theory on February 25. With rightist criticism continuing, Minobe stepped down from the House of Peers in September; Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 153.

242 Notes to Chapter 4 104. See Monbushō, ed., Kokutai no Hongi (Tokyo: Monbushō, 1937), translated as Kokutai no Hongi: The Cardinal Princi­ples of the National Entity of Japan, trans. John Owen Gauntlett (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1949). Alan Tansman has argued that the “interest of the . . . ​[Kokutai no hongi] lies less in its content than in its formal qualities as an example of a fascist aesthetic that shared similar sensibility with other, more nuanced, works of the period. . . . ​Its prestige would seem to have grown out of its very abstruseness, its ability to persuade readers that they could ‘get’ the es- sence of its ‘venerable’ words and phrases without discerning their precise meanings. It was, in essence, a performative document.” Alan Tansman, The Aesthetics of Japa­nese Fascism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008), 152. 105. I refer to portions of ­these deliberations collected in gss45 and Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2. A full rec­ord of the 1935 Diet deliberations is collected in Shakai mondai shiryō kenkyūkai, ed., Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō ni kansuru sokkiroku: Dai69kai teikoku gikai (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1973). 106. ­Here, Makino cites Minobe as arguing that “kokutai is a concept that expresses the historical fact that [­there has been] unbroken imperial rule from the founding of the empire, as well as the ethical fact that the national ­people are incomparably loyal and re- vere the emperor. [However] this is not indicated in the current constitutional system. The reason for [positing] kokutai in the current constitutional system, is to emphasize the universality [bannō] of imperial sovereignty, which is a complete misunderstanding of the spirit of the Constitution.” Minobe Tatsukichi, quoted by Makino on March 20, 1935, in Lower House session: “Chianijihō kaisei • fuhō danketsu nado shobatsu ni kansuru hōritsuan giji sokkiroku narabi ni iinkai giroku,” in gss45, 253. 107. Minobe, quoted by Makino, in gss45, 253. Makino’s citation of Minobe contin- ues: “Monarchy or republic are clearly ­legal concepts that are connected to currently applied [theories] of constitutional ­orders. In other words, they are terms that refer to con­temporary constitutional systems. Moreover, the meaning [of such terms] does not refer to a past history, nor any sense of the nation’s ethical sentiments [rinriteki kanjō]. Although a country may be called a monarchy [kunshusei], this is nothing to do with that country’s history, nor the feelings of the ­people ­toward the monarch. This is a completely separate issue” (254). 108. See Ohara’s inquiry: gss45, 254. 109. Interestingly, Nakatani became the president of Japan Motion Pictures (Nik- katsu) in 1934 and oversaw a major restructuring of the com­pany at the time. Jasper Sharp, Historical Dictionary of Japa­nese Cinema (Lanham, MD: Scarecrow, 2011), 181. 110. Exchange between Matsuda Genji and Nakatani Sadayori on March 22 in the Lower House: “Chianijihō kaisei • fuhō danketsu-ra shobatsu ni kansuru hōritsuan giji sokkiroku narabi ni iinkai giroku,” in gss45, 259. 111. gss45, 259. 112. gss45, 259. 113. See Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 152. 114. At the same time, officials had to answer concerns that they had been too lenient on ex-­communists. For instance, in 1934 Diet committee deliberations over the 1934 revision bill, some officials expressed doubts that tenkō was merely camouflage for

Notes to Chapter 4 243 dangerous po­liti­cal activists, as well as concern over Sano Manabu and Nabeyama Sadachika’s new politics of socialism in one country. See “Tenkō mondai,” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 48–50. Also, while the Home Ministry collaborated with the Justice Ministry on the 1934 and 1935 revision bill drafts, they did not support the Justice Ministry’s proposal for the 1936 Thought Criminal Protection and Supervi- sion bill. See Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 157. 115. A 1935 Justice Ministry Criminal Division report gives the following statistics between 1928 and 1934: out of 10,353 individuals not released ­after their initial inter- rogation, 4,059 ­were indicted, 3,869 received Suspended Indictments, and 2,425 ­were placed in Charges Withheld (a policy formalized in 1931). See Shihōshō keijikyoku, “Chianijihō kaiseian sankō shiryō” (March 8, 1935), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 229. 116. Ogino interprets the application of the law beyond suspected communist groups as signaling that the law was no longer “targeting just social movements that harmed the peace [chian o gai suru], but now was directed ­toward anyone that harmed the social order and public tranquility [shakai chitsujo naishi shakai no seihitsu].” Ogino, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei, 75. On the suppression of Ōmotokyō in the 1930s and more generally, see Ogino, Shōwa tennō to chian taisei, 75–79; Garon, Molding Japa­nese Minds, 60–87; Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 222–234. For excerpts from police summaries on the 1935 Ōmotokyō Incident, see Keihokyoku, “Ōmotokyō chianijihō ihan narabini fukei jiken gaiyō” (November 1935) and Keihokyoku, “Ōmotokyō higisha chōshusho sakusei yōkō” (May 14, 1936), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 403–406 and 406– 410 respectively. On the trial of Ōmotokyō, see Miyachi Masato, “Dai ni ji Ōmotokyō jiken: Senjika shūkyō danatsu no kiten,” in Nihon seiji saiban shiroku 5: Shōwa • go, ed. Wagatsuma Sakae (Tokyo: Daiichi Hōki Shuppan, 1969), 95–140. On the extension of the Peace Preservation Law to Popu­lar Front groups including the Rōnō-ha, see Okud- aira, Chianijihō shōshi, 203–222. For a police summary of the suppression of Popu­lar Front groups, see Keihokyoku, “Jinmin sensen undō no hontai” (January–­February 1938), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 2, 410–417. On the ­trials of Popu­lar Front groups, see Odanaka Toshiki, “Jinmin sensen jiken: Hansen • hanfashizumu seiryoku e no danatsu,” in Wagatsuma, Nihon seiji saiban shiroku 5, 273–328. 117. Yoshida Hajime, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” in Shisō jōsei shisatsu hōkokushū (Sono 6), in Shisō kenkyū shiryō: Tokushū dai 69 gō, ed. Shihōshō keijikyoku, reprinted in Shakai mondai shiryō sōsho: Dai 1 shū (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1971), 1–47. Hong Jong-­wook cites this source in Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­ tachi: Teikoku/shokuminchi no tōgō to kiretsu (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2011), 52. 118. Keongil Kim, “Japa­nese Assimilation Policy and Thought Conversion in Colonial Korea,”­ in Colonial Rule and Social Change in ­Korea, 1910–1945, ed. Hon Yung Lee, Yong Chool Ha, and Clark W. Sorensen (Seattle: Center for Korean Studies, University of Washington Press, 2013), 213, and 230, fn34. 119. Suzuki, Chōsen shokuminchi tōchihō no kenkyū, 182. Suzuki demonstrates how by 1930 the Peace Preservation Law had overshadowed the application of other security laws when prosecuting in­de­pen­dence activists in the late 1920s (e.g., the 1907 Public Peace Law and 1919 Ordinance No. 7) (140).

244 Notes to Chapter 4 120. See for example the two-­part series by a procurator in Osaka: Adachi Katsukiyo, “Shisōhansha no hogo taisaku,” Hogo Jihō 19, no. 6 (June 1935): 4–12; and Hogo Jihō 19, no. 7 (July 1935): 9–18. In such discussions, officials advocated for the passage of the Peace Preservation Law revision bills ­under deliberation in the Diet at the time or, ­later, the Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision Law, which was developeda ­ fter the other revision failed. See, for example, Yamagata Nirō, “Nanzan no shisōhan hogo kansatsu hōan,” Hogo Jihō 20, no. 2 (February 1936): 9–18. 121. For instance, Fujii Eshō, Hirata Isao, and Kobayashi Morito held a discussion for female tenkōsha in Tokyo to describe their experiences and hardships: “Tenkō fujin no nayami o kiku kai,” Hogo Jihō 18, no. 10 (October 1934): 11–18. 122. Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 253. On the limits of ­these early groups and the challenges tenkōsha ­were experiencing, see Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 129–134. ­These challenges are reflected in the increasing number of paroled thought criminals seeking membership in the Imperial Renovation Society: whereas only eight ex-­ communists became members of the society in 1931, 278 ­were admitted in 1934. ­These numbers come from Fujii Eshō, “Shisōhan hogo jigyō no tenbō: Hogo kansatsu no jicchi o hikaete,” Hogo Jihō 20, no. 2 (February 1936): 11–15. Fujii reports that in 1932 and 1933, 43 and 143 thought criminals ­were admitted, respectively. ­These statistics do not include ­those paroled ex-­communists who came to the society for temporary assistance. 123. The Shōtokukai was an incorporated foundation zaidan( hōjin). See Shōtokukai, “Zaidan hōjin shōtokukai gaiyō” (August 1936), in Ogino Fujio, ed., Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3 (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 31. Also see Ogino, Shisō kenji, 68. 124. A ­later Justice Ministry report in support of passing this law replicated the argu- ments that Moriyama presented in this meeting. See Shihōshō, “Shisōhan hogokansatsu seido no hitsuyō” (April 15, 1936), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 44–46. 125. Uchida, Kōsei hogo no tenkai to kadai, 30. 126. Foucault, “Governmentality,” 103. 127. Moriyama Takeichirō, “ ‘Shisō hogo kansatsu seido’ ni tsuite” (November 1935), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 38–39. 128. Moriyama explained that this new law would apply to four dispositions related to the Peace Preservation Law—­Suspended Indictment, Suspended Sentence, parolees, and ­those who had fully served their sentences. Similar to the juvenile rehabilita- tion policies, a reformee would be placed ­under the supervision of a guidance officer (hogoshi). Moriyama, “ ‘Shisō hogo kansatsu seido’ ni tsuite,” 39. Notice that Moriyama does not make reference to Charges Withheld. This was­be cause with the passage of this proposed bill, the conventional Suspended Indictment of the Japa­nese Criminal Code would replace Charges Withheld administered specifically for thought criminal cases since 1931. We can assume that the widely applied Charges Withheld disposition was included in Moriyama’s reference to Suspended Indictment. 129. Moriyama, “ ‘Shisō hogo kansatsu seido’ ni tsuite,” 39. 130. See Shihōshō, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hōan yōkō” (January 8, 1936), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 40. For the Justice Ministry’s official summary of the

Notes to Chapter 4 245 bill, see Shihōshō, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hōan riyūsho,” submitted with “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hōan” (April 1936), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 42. For a history of the passage of this bill, see Kikuta Kōichi, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō no rekishiteki bunseki,” parts I and II, Hōritsu Ronsō 44, nos. 5–6 (October 1971): 95–132, and Hōritsu Ronsō 45, no. 1 (January 1972): 85–126, respectively. 131. Hayashi Raizaburō, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hōteian riyū setsumei,” in gss45, 273. 132. On the retroactive application of this law, see Kikuta, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō no rekishiteki bunseki, II,” 89. 133. Hayashi Raizaburō, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hōteian riyū setsumei,” in gss45, 273. 134. gss45, 273. 135. See Seifu, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō shikō kijitsu no ken” (Ordinance 400), “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō shikō rei” (Ordinance 401), “Hogo kansatsu sho kansei” (Ordinance 403), and “Hogo kansatsu shinsakai kansei” (Ordinance 405), all issued on November 14, 1936, in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 47–51. For a detailed collection of all materials related to the establishment of the law, including its relation to other civil codes, see Kido Yoshio, Shisōhan hogokansatsuhōki shū (Tokyo: Gansuidō Shoten, 1937). 136. For colonial Kor­ ea, see Seifu, “Chōsen sōtokufu hogo kansatsu rei,” “Chōsen sōtokufu hogo kansatsu sho kansei,” and “Chōsen sōtokufu hogo kansatsu shinsa kaikansei” (all issued December 12, 1936), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 52–53. For analy­sis of the application of this law in colonial ­Korea, see Suzuki, Chōsen shokuminchi tōchihō no kenkyū, 181–183. For the implementation of this law in colonial ­Korea and the Kwantung Leased Territory, see Ogino Fujio, “Kaisetsu: Chianijihō seiritsu • ‘kaisei’ shi,” in Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, ed. Ogino Fujio (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 686–690. 137. For the ordinances related to the Kwantung Leased Territory, including establish- ing a Protection and Supervision Center in Dalian, see Seifu, “Kantōshū shisō hogo kansatsu rei” (No. 793), “Kantōshū hogo kansatsusho kansei” (No. 794), and “Kantōshū hogo kansatsu shinsakai kansei” (No. 795), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 53–55. The law was not issued in Taiwan, Karafuto, or the South Sea Islands. 138. See Ogino, “Kaisetsu: Chianijihō seiritsu • ‘kaisei’ shi,” 686–687. See also Ogino, Shisō kenji, 92. For a rec­ord of location and staff of the Protection and Supervision Centers in colonial ­Korea, see Chōsen Sōtokufu, “Hogo kansatsu sho shokuin haichi hyō” (December 1936), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 510–511. Hong reports that the 1,160 cases overseen by the Keijō Protection and Supervision Center ­were distinguished as follows: 328 Suspended Indictments, 198 Suspended Sentences, 608 individuals who had served their full sentences, and 26 who w­ ere paroled. Hong Jong-­wook, “Senjiki chōsen ni okeru shisōhan tōsei to Yamato-­juku,” Kankoku chōsen bunka kenkyū, no. 16 (March 2017): 44. 139. Hong, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi, 50. 140. Masunaga Shōichi (January 1937), cited in Ogino, “Kaisetsu: Chianijihō seiritsu • ‘kaisei’ shi,” 687.

246 Notes to Chapter 4 141. Ushiomi Toshitaka notes that the Thought Criminal Protection and Supervision Law was a “revision of the Peace Preservation Law which changed its formal structure.” Ushiomi Toshitaka, Chianijihō (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1977), 107. 142. For example, in the July 1936 issue of Hogo Jihō dedicated to this new law, Kobayashi Morito relayed the concerns he was hearing from other converts, includ- ing how the state was expecting to extract conversion from ­those who had, up to that point, refused to tenkō, and concern over w­ hether the new law would increase police intervention into the daily lives of tenkōsha, which would cause unnecessary hardships that might in fact have a negative result in securing conversion. Kobayashi Morito, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsuhō ni taisuru jakkan no kōsatsu: Hitotsu tenkōsha to shite,” Hogo Jihō 20, no. 7 (July 1936): 16–21, in Aomori hogo kansatsusho, ed., Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō (1937), collected in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 73–76. Chaplain Fujii Eshō conveyed similar concerns surrounding the protocols outlined in the new law: Fujii Eshō, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō ni tsuite: Jitsumuka no tachiba kara,” Hogo Jihō 20, no. 7 (July 1936): 13–16, reprinted in Aomori hogo kansatsusho, ed., Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō (1937), collected in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 76–78. 143. For example, at a 1936 roundtable attended by forty-­three tenkōsha and thought reform officials, it was common for tenkōsha to describe the difficulties that police sur- veillance caused once they ­were paroled. See Hankan Gakuryō, ed., Hankan Gakuryō shisōhan tenkōsha zadankai kiroku (Tokyo: Hankan Gakuryō Tōkyō Jimusho, 1936). 144. See “Shisōhan hogokansatsu hō tekiyō mondai” and “Shisōhan hogokansatsu hō ni tsuite,” Chōsen Nippō, June 11 and June 14, 1936, in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 86–88. 145. See Itō’s discussion of concerns raised by the Osaka-­based Dōyūkai: Itō, Tenkō to tennōsei, 259–260. 146. Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 139. Statistics on recidivism in colonial ­Korea exist up ­until 1935, averaging 10 ­percent, with most cases occurring early in the 1930s. See Hong, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi, 52. 147. Jan Goldstein reconsiders the logical relationship between sovereign law and disciplinary power in Foucault’s theory and has called this the “framing of discipline by law.” Jan Goldstein, “Framing Discipline with Law: Prob­lems and Promises of the Liberal State,” American Historical Review 98, no. 2 (April 1993): 364–375.

Chapter 5. The Ideology of Conversion 1. Hirata Isao, “Hogo kansatsu sho no shimei” (December 14, 1936), in Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō, ed. Aomori Hogo Kansatsu Sho (1937), reprinted in Ogino Fujio, ed., Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3 (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 79–80. 2. Hirata explicated that the Japa­nese spirit was symbolized in the mythical three imperial regalia—­the mirror, jewel, and sword—in which the sword represented justice and the jewel benevolence, and the mirror reflected and combined­the se two into one. In Hirata’s ideological analogy, the Peace Preservation Law combined justice and benevolence: justice was exacted against dangerous threats against the imperial state,

Notes to Chapter 4 247 and benevolence was expressed in the reform of thought criminals as loyal imperial subjects. Hirata, “Hogo kansatsu sho no shimei,” 78–79. 3. Hirata, “Hogo kansatsu sho no shimei,” 79–80. 4. On this 1939 law, see Uchida Hirofumi, Kōsei hogo no tenkai to kadai (Kyoto: Hōritsu Bunkasha, 2015), 67–69; Kōsei Hogo Gojūnen Shi Henshū Iinkai, ed., Kōsei hogo gojūnen shi: Chiiki shakai to tomo ni ayumu kōsei hogo (Tokyo: Zenkoku Hogoshi Renmei, 2000), vol. 1, 192–193. Distinguishing between protection (hogo) and supervi- sion (kansatsu), Kato Michiko has argued that, despite the emphasis on protection in ­these two laws (1936 and 1939), in actuality, the power of supervision was extended and overshadowed the function of protection. See Kato Michiko, “Senzen kara sengo fukkōki ni okeru hogo kansatsu seido no dōnyū to hensen,” Ōyō shakaigaku kenkyū, no. 55 (2013): 223–226. At this time the system for youth protection (shōnen hogo kikō) was also expanded. See Moriya Katsuhiko, Shōnen no hikō to kyōiku: Shōnen hōsei no rekishi to genjō (Tokyo: Keisōshobō, 1977), 132–151; David Ambaras, Bad Youth: Juvenile Delinquency and the Politics of Everyday Life in Modern Japan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2006), 166–191. 5. Hirata, “Hogo kansatsu sho no shimei,” 78, 80. 6. As was noted in chapter 4, centers ­were established in colonial ­Korea in December 1936. 7. For a detailed discussion concerning the meaning of tenkō in relation to ­these new centers, see the meeting of the newly appointed directors in Shihōshō, “Dai ikkai hogo kansatsu shochō kaidō gijiroku” (November 25–6, 1936), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 89–169. 8. Moriyama Takechirō, Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō kaisetsu (Tokyo: Shōkadō Shoten, 1937), 62–65. This famous definition of tenkō is cited in Nakazawa Shunsuke, Chianijihō: Naze seitō seiji ha “akuhō” o unda ka (Tokyo: Chūōkō Shinsho, 2012), 160; Ogino Fujio, Shisō kenji (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2000), 90; Ushiomi Toshitaka, Chianijihō (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1977), 96–97. 9. I thank Tak Fujitani for suggesting that I emphasize this relation between societal mobilization and penal repression during war­time. 10. In November 1941, ­there ­were eleven guidance officialshodōkan ( ) overseeing the network, assisted by forty-­five rehabilitation officers and thirty-­nine clerks. See Shihōshō, “Hogo kansatsu sho no kakujū,” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 353. For the list of the twenty-­two centers, the basic structure of the system, see Appendix 2, Chart 2, “Justice Ministry Protection and Supervision System in 1936,” in Richard H. Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1976), 198. 11. For Kwantung-­related ordinances, see Seifu, “Kantōshū shisōhan hogo kansatsu rei” (December 18, 1938), which includes “Kantōshū hogo kansatsusho kansei” and “Kantōshū hogo kansatsu shinsakai kansei,” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 53–55. 12. See Seifu, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō shikō kijitsu no ken” (Ordinance 400), “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō shikō rei” (Ordinance 401), “Hogo kansatsu sho kansei” (Ordinance 403), and “Hogo kansatsu shinsakai kansei” (Ordinance 405), all issued on November 14, 1936, in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 47–51. For a detailed

248 Notes to Chapter 5 collection of all materials related to the establishment of the law, including its relation to other civil codes, see Kido Yoshio, Shisōhan hogokansatsuhōki shū (Tokyo: Gansuidō Shoten, 1937). 13. For an example and explanation of ­these reports, see Shihōshō, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō shikō rei dai san jō ni okeru tsūchi yōshiki ni kansuru ken” (February 4, 1937), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 60–61. 14. See Shihōshō, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō shikō rei dai san jō ni okeru tsūchi yōshiki ni kansuru ken,” 61. Nakazawa cites a late 1933 Prison Bureau report that distin- guishes between (1) tenkōsha, identified as ­those who had “renounced revolutionary thought” and had ­either “broken with the social movement” or planned to participate in the “­legal social movement”; (2) juntenkōsha, identified as ­those who ­were reconsid- ering “revolutionary thought” and moving ­toward “renunciation” or ­those who, while still holding “revolutionary ideas,” had broken with the “social movement”; and (3) hitenkōsha. See summary: Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 142. 15. Moriyama Takeichirō, “Hogo kansatsu no yōhi kettei no hyōjun,” inShisōhan hogo kansatsu hō, ed. Aomori Hogo Kansatsusho (1937), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 70–71. 16. Matsuo Hiroshi, Chianijihō to tokkō keisatsu (Tokyo: Kyōikusha, 1979), 170. 17. On the Virtuous Brilliance Society, see chapter 4. For example, a review of the Tokyo Protection and Supervision Center’s activities reveals close coordination with the Imperial Renovation Society and its members. See Tokyo Hogo Kansatsu Sho, Jimu seiseki hōkoku sho (1937), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 175–224. In addition to reporting on the center’s activities, this report includes extensive information on groups affiliated with the center as well as its liaison with other centers throughout Japan. 18. Yamagata Jirō, “Shisōhan hogo kansatsu hō no unyō ni kansuru yōbō,” in Hogo Jihō 21, no. 1 (January 1937): 34–36. He divided the target (taishō) of the Protection and Super­ vision Law into four categories: (1) ­those who had “completely converted and have a secure foundation in their daily lives”; (2) ­those who, although having converted, “have in- stability in their lives”; (3) thos­ e whose thoughts are “insecure” (dōyō) but who have stable lives; and fi­nally (4) ­those who lack stability in both their thought and daily lives (35–36). 19. For the ordinances related to colonial ­Korea, see Hogo Jihō 21, no. 2 (Febru- ary 1937): 48–51. For rec­ords of national meetings of reform officials, seeHogo Jihō 21, no. 2 (February 1937): 51–57. 20. Tokuoka Kazuo, Chianijihō ihan jiken no saihan ni kansuru kenkyū (Tokyo: Shihōshō Keijikyoku, 1938), 179. 21. Tokuoka, Chianijihō ihan jiken no saihan ni kansuru kenkyū, 179–180. 22. See Hogo Jihō 21, no. 10 (October 1937). 23. See the report: Kaku Hogo Kansatsusho Hoka, “Nicchū sensōka no shisōhan hogo kansatsu” (1937–1938), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 342–352. 24. Richard Mitchell implies that the initiative to link tenkō to the war came from Prime Ministers Konoe Fumimaro (1937–39) and Hiranuma Kiichirō (1939). Rich- ard H. Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1976), 164–166. Patricia Steinhoff argues: “the use oftenkōsha for patriotic propaganda was but one small aspect of a full-­scale nationalistic drive throughout the country.”

Notes to Chapter 5 249 Patricia G. Stienhoff,Tenkō: Ideology and Societal Integration in Prewar Japan (New York and London: Garland Publishing 1991), 209. It is impor­tant to recognize, however, that officials and tenkōsha w­ ere already representing conversion in terms of national thought defense well before July 1937, which I have outlined in earlier chapters. This demonstrates a much more organic relationship between thought criminal rehabilita- tion and ­later war­time mobilization. 25. For an early example of how criminal rehabilitation was being reconsidered in the context of the China Incident, see Hoseikai, ed., Jihen ni yomigaeru hanzaisha (Tokyo: Hoseikai, 1937). This pamphlet concludes with an article on the patriotic activities of tenkōsha, 57–59. See also the 1938 pamphlet by the head of the Hoseikai, Matsui Kazuyoshi: Kokka sōryokusen to shihō hogo jigyō (Tokyo: Hoseikai, 1938). 26. On Konoe Fumimaro, see Yoshitake Oka, Konoe Fumimaro: A Po­liti­cal Biography (Tokyo: University of Tokyo Press, 1983); and Kazuo Yagami, Konoe Fumimaro and the Failure of Peace in Japan, 1937–1­941 (Jefferson, NC: McFarland, 2006). 27. For instance, see the reports from 1937–1938 collected in the section “Nicchū sensōka no shisōhan hogo kansatsu sho” (342–353), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 342–353. 28. Seimeikai, ed., Shisō tenkōsha ha ika ni katsudō shite iru ka (Osaka: Seimeikai, 1937). The pamphlet reports that the Seimeikai consisted of sixty out of the over one thousand tenkōsha unde­ r supervision by the Osaka Center (1). 29. Seimeikai, Shisō tenkōsha ha ika ni katsudō shite iru ka, 3. 30. Seimeikai, Shisō tenkōsha ha ika ni katsudō shite iru ka, 3. 31. See Seimeikai, Shisō tenkōsha ha ika ni katsudō shite iru ka, 10–14. As if the message was not clear enough, the pamphlet concluded with contact information for ­people at Osaka Asahi Shimbun and Osaka Mainichi Shimbun who ­were collecting donations. 32. See for instance this 1938 pamphlet: Ishii Toyoshichirō, Shihō hogo sōsho dai 17 shū: Saiban to hogo (Tokyo: Zen Nihon Shihō Hogo Jigyō Renmei, 1938), in par­tic­u­lar 23–28. 33. Ishii, Shihō hogo sōsho dai 17 shū, 25. 34. Kokumin Seiji Keizai Kenkyūsho, ed., “Kokunai bōkyō” Sensen no sankyotō: Shiono, Suetsugu, Araki (Tokyo: Kokumin Seiji Keizai Kenkyūsho, 1938), 16–22. 35. Shihō Hogo Jigyō Renmei, ed., Shihō hogo sōsho dai 19 shū: Kōa no soseki (Tokyo: Zen Nihon Shihō Hogo Jigyō Renmei, 1939). 36. Jikyoku taiō zenchō shisō hōkoku renmei founding statement (July 1938), cited in Mizuno Naoki, “Nihon no chōsen shihai to Chianijihō,” in Chōsen no kindaishi to nihon, ed. Hatada Takeshi (Tokyo: Yamato Shobō, 1987), 139. On the formation of the Jikyoku taiō zenchō shisō hōkoku renmei and its orga­nizational structure, see Hong Jong-w­ ook, “Senjiki chōsen ni okeru shisōhan tōsei to Yamato-­juku,” Kankoku chōsen bunka kenkyū, no. 16 (March 2017): 46–47 and 49. 37. Michael Robinson claims that by “the 1940s, e­ very Korean was associated with at least one mass organ­ization.” Michael Robinson, “Ideological Schism in the Korean Na- tionalist Movement, 1920–1930: Cultural Nationalism and the Radical Critique,” Journal of Korean Studies 4 (1982–1983): 316. 38. Ogino Fujio, “Kaisetsu: Chianijihō seiritsu • ‘kaisei’ shi,” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 689; Hong, “Senjiki chōsen ni okeru shisōhan tōsei to Yamato-­

250 Notes to Chapter 5 juku,” 47. Hong also reports that the­ re w­ ere efforts to make this league in­de­pen­dent from its metropolitan counter­parts in Japan (47). 39. Hong Jong-­wook cites ­these numbers from a 1936 Justice Ministry report. See Hong, “Senjiki chōsen ni okeru shisōhan tōsei to Yamato-­juku,” 44. 40. Hong Jong-­wook, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-t­achi: Teikoku/shokuminchi no tōgō to kiretsu (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2011), 50, 46–64. 41. Tokuoka, Chianijihō ihan jiken no saihan ni kansuru kenkyū, 191. This recalls the decisions in which Korean courts rationalized the application of the Peace Preservation Law—­initially envisioned as a law to be used against communists—to nationalist activ- ists in the colonies (see chapter 2). 42. Naoki Sakai, “Ethnicity and Species: On the Philosophy of the Multiethnic State and Japa­nese Imperialism,” in Confronting Capital and Empire: Rethinking Kyoto School Philosophy, ed. Viren Murthy, Fabian Schafer, and Max Ward (Leiden: Brill, 2017), 148. See also Mark Driscoll, “Conclusion: Postcolonialism in Reverse,” in Yuasa Katsuei, Kannani and Document in Flames: Two Japa­nese Colonial Novels, trans. Mark Driscoll (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2005). 43. See: T. Fujitani, Race for Empire: Koreans as Japa­nese and Japa­nese as Americans during World War II (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2011), 7. Fujitani notes that this was a “strategic disavowal of racism” for war mobilization (12). 44. Tokuoka, Chianijihō ihan jiken no saihan ni kansuru kenkyū, 192. Mizuno Naoki analyzes Tokuoka’s report along with other studies in order to consider the application of the Peace Preservation Law and its ­later tenkō policy in colonial ­Korea. See Mizuno, “Nihon no chōsen shihai to Chianijihō,” 137–138. 45. Yoshida Hajime, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” in Shisō jōsei shisatsu hōkokushū (Sono 6), in Shisō kenkyū shiryō: Tokushū dai 69 gō, ed. Shihōshō Keijikyoku, in Shakai mondai shiryō sōsho: Dai 1 shū (Tokyo: Tōyō Bunkasha, 1971), 1–47. 46. Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 7. The­ se suspects ­were arrested in the Fifth Kantō Communist Party Incident in 1930–1931. How- ever, since the defendants ­were prosecuted with a variety of dif­fer­ent laws, their execu- tion was not sentenced ­under the Peace Preservation Law. On this, see Mizuno Naoki, “Chianijihō to chōsen • Oboegaki,” Chōsen Kenkyū 188, no. 4 (1979): 50–51; Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 206. Richard H. Mitchell, Janus-­Faced Justice: Po­liti­cal Criminals in Imperial Japan (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1992), 163–164. 47. Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 7–8. 48. Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 9–11. Indeed, it was common for reports of conventional crime in colonial Kor­ ea to include asides about the “par­tic­u­lar nature” of crime in ­Korea due to Korean culture, cus- toms, and feudal vestiges that distinguished it from the metropole. For example, see Terada Seiichi, “Chōsen ni okeru hanzai genshō no tokuchō,” Hōseikai kaihō 4, no. 3 (May 1920): 1–36. 49. Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 9. ­These concerns w­ ere also articulated by mobilized tenkōsha associations as well. See Hong, “Senjiki chōsen ni okeru shisōhan tōsei to Yamato-juk­ u,” 49.

Notes to Chapter 5 251 50. Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 9–10. On this point, see Mizuno, “Nihon no chōsen shihai to Chianijihō,” 136. 51. Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 10–12. Yoshida notes that, in the 655 indictments in 1937, over half of the cases involved forming or join- ing an illegal organ­ization (153 and 249 cases respectively; see the ­table on page 11). 52. See Yoshida’s review of tenkō statistics, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei nara- bini ruihan jōkyō,” 12–13. 53. Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 13. 54. See Yoshida’s comparative reflections of tenkō, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 12–14. 55. Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 14. 56. As mentioned above, Hong Jong-­wook has argued that we must understand the vicissitudes of tenkō cases in colonial ­Korea in relation to the changing geopo­liti­cal context in regard to both Comintern policy as well as Japan’s position in East Asia. Hong, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi, 46–64. 57. From Tokkō keisatsuhō, no. 3 (year unknown), cited in Mizuno, “Nihon no chōsen shihai to Chianijihō,” 138. 58. See the extended citation in Yoshida, “Chōsen ni okeru shisōhan no kakei narabini ruihan jōkyō,” 45–46. 59. See Matsuda Toshihiko, “Shokuminchi makki chōsen ni okeru tenkōsha no undō: Kang Yŏng-­sŏk to nihon kokutai gaku • tōa renmei undō,” Jinbun Gakuhō 79 (March 1997): 131–161; Matsuda Toshihiko, Tōa renmei undō to chōsen • chōsenjin: Nicchū sensōki ni okeru shokuminchi teikoku nihon no danmen (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2015). For the mobilization of zainichi Koreans, see Park Kyong-­sik, Tennōsei kokka to zainichi chōsenjin (Tokyo: Shakai Hyōronsha, 1986), 148–270. 60. On the Yamato-­juku, see Hong, “Senjiki chōsen ni okeru shisōhan tōsei to Yamato-­juku,” 43–67. 61. A summary of a 1942 article, cited in Hong, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-t­achi, 50. Mizuno Naoki posits that the Yamato Society was at the center of the “purification of thought” (shisō jōka) in the colony during war­time. Mizuno Naoki, “Senjiki chōsen ni okeru chian seisaku: ‘Shisō jōka kōsaku’ to Yamato-juk­ u o chūshin ni,” Rekishigaku Kenkyū, no. 777 (2003): 1–11. 62. On the concept of thought war, see Barak Kushner, The Thought War: Japa­nese Imperial Propaganda (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 2006); and Max Ward, “Crisis Ideology and the Articulation of Fascism in Interwar Japan: The 1938 Thought War Symposium,” Japan Forum 26, no. 4 (December 2014): 463–465. 63. On the Cabinet Information Division, see the study in two installments: Fukushima Jūrō, “Senji genron tōsei kikan no saikenshō ‘jōhōkyoku’ e no dōtei 1: Naikaku jōhō iinkai setsuritsu to sono haikei,” Janarizumu kenkyū 23, no. 1 (1986): 98–109; and Fukushima Jūrō, “Senji genron tōsei kikan no saikenshō ‘jōhōkyoku’ e no dōtei 2: Naikaku jōhōbu no jidai,” Janarizumu kenkyū 23, no. 2 (1986): 68–77. See also Uchikawa Yoshimi, “Naikaku jōhōkyoku no setsuritsu katei: Nihon fashizumu keis- eiki no masu media soshikika seisaku,” in Masu mediahō seisakushi kenkyū (Tokyo: Yuhikaku, 1989), 193–237. The Cabinet Information Division was staffed by so-­called

252 Notes to Chapter 5 renovationist bureaucrats (kakushin kanryō), a new breed of imperial officials who believed it was their duty to alleviate the dislocations endemic to capitalism, replace the inefficient ­lpo iti­cal pro­cess, streamline colonial development, and completely remake the Japa­nese Empire through rational planning and bureaucratic interven- tion. On the renovationist bureaucrats, see Hashikawa Bunzō, “Kakushin kanryō,” in Kenryoku no shisō: Gendai nihon shisō taikei 10, ed. Kamishima Jirō (Tokyo: Chikuma Shobō, 1965), 251–273. 64. This section is derived from Ward, “Crisis Ideology and the Articulation of Fas- cism in Interwar Japan.” On this symposium, see Satō Takumi, “The System of Total War and the Discursive Space of the Thought War,” inTotal War and “Modernization,” ed. Yamanouchi Yasushi, J. Victor Koschmann, and Ryuichi Narita (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University East Asia Program, 1998), 289–313. ­There ­were two more annual symposia, held in 1939 and 1940. 65. See the lecture transcript of the Chief of the Police Bureau in the Home Ministry: Tomita Kenji, “Shisōsen to keisatsu,” in Shisōsen kōshūkai kōgi sokki, ed. Naikaku Jōhōbu (Tokyo: Naikaku Jōhōbu, 1938), vol. 3, 113–136. On the history of the thought prob­lem in interwar Japan, see Max Ward, “The Prob­lem of ‘Thought’: Crisis, National Essence and the Interwar Japa­nese State” (PhD diss., New York University, 2011). 66. Hirata reported that roughly 10 ­percent of detainees still believed in Marxism, while another 10 ­percent had “truly overcome Marxism” by “grasping the Japa­nese spirit.” The remaining 80 ­percent ­were thus at vari­ous stages of “completing tenkō.” Hi- rata Isao, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” in Shisōsen kōshūkai kōgi sokki, ed. Naikaku Jōhōbu (Tokyo: Naikaku Jōhōbu, 1938), vol. 3, 206. 67. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 228. Hirata contrasted the Japa­nese centers to the German po­liti­cal concentration camps (Konzentrationslager) and the Kuomintang’s repentance centers in China (what Hirata referred to as Hansei-in­ ; liter- ally, reflection centers; 227). 68. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 228, 227. 69. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 214. 70. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 210–211. 71. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 215. 72. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 223. 73. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 228. 74. Hirata, “Marukishizumu no kokufuku,” 236. 75. Nakamura Yoshirō, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” Kyōiku Panfuretto, no. 323 (November 1938), 2. 76. Nakamura cites Hirata Isao’s explanation of the centers as embodying Japan’s unique familial structure. Hirata explained that, in the centers, po­liti­cal criminals ­were “collectively disciplined [tōsei ni fuku suru] based on the ­family princi­ple” and ­were able to “grow unde­ r the guidance of familial affection.” Hirata Isao, quoted by Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 4–5. 77. Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 5. 78. Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 14. 79. Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 19.

Notes to Chapter 5 253 80. Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 19. In this context, guidance officials like Nakamura would carry out their duties with the “sentiment of a parent t­oward one’s own child.” Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 20. 81. Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 21. 82. Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 24. 83. Nakamura, “Genka ni okeru shisōtaisaku,” 25. 84. Nakamura Yoshirō, “Tenkō o yōsei sarete iru mono ha shisō jiken kankeisha nomi de nai,” Kakushin, December 1938, 171–180. For example, Nakamura writes that he was often asked if converts had truly converted, and if conversion was just “camouflage” for their continued dangerous activities (172). ­Later in the article he cites Moriyama Takeichirō’s five stages of conversion analyzed above in order to explain the pro­cess of conversion (174–175). 85. Nakamura, “Tenkō o yōsei sarete iru mono ha shisō jiken kankeisha nomi de nai,” 173. 86. Nakamura, “Tenkō o yōsei sarete iru mono ha shisō jiken kankeisha nomi de nai,” 173, 172, 173–174. 87. For example, Nakamura uses the term “recognition of crisis” (jikyoku ninshiki) throughout this piece. 88. Nakamura, “Tenkō o yōsei sarete iru mono ha shisō jiken kankeisha nomi de nai,” 173. On this group, see Mizuno Naoki, “Senjiki chōsen ni okeru chian seisaku: ‘Shisō jōka kōsaku’ to yamato-juk­ u o chūshin ni,” Rekishigaku kenkyū, no. 777 (July 2003): 8. 89. Nakamura, “Tenkō o yōsei sarete iru mono ha shisō jiken kankeisha nomi de nai,” 173. 90. Nakamura, “Tenkō o yōsei sarete iru mono ha shisō jiken kankeisha nomi de nai,” 175. 91. Nakamura, “Tenkō o yōsei sarete iru mono ha shisō jiken kankeisha nomi de nai,” 175. 92. Nakamura, “Tenkō o yōsei sarete iru mono ha shisō jiken kankeisha nomi de nai,” 178, 180. 93. I have analyzed this exhibition at length in Max Ward, “Displaying the Worldview of Japa­nese Fascism: The Tokyo Thought War Exhibition of 1938,”Critical Asian Studies 47, no. 3 (2015): 414–439. ­Here I focus on how the Justice Ministry presented their tenkō policy and the Protection and Supervision Center network in the event. 94. Naikaku Jōhōbu, ed., Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan (Tokyo: Naikaku Jōhōbu, 1938), 1. 95. Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 135. ­These numbers are most likely exaggerated. 96. The exhibition was held at the following department stores: Takashimaya, Tokyo; Takashimaya, Osaka; Marubutsu, Kyoto; Tamaya, Fukuoka; Tamaya, Sasebo; Tamaya, Saga-­city; Sentoku, Fukumoto City; Tokiha, Ōita; Imai, Sapporo; and Mitsukoshi in Keijō. Prefectural and local municipal governments financially sponsored the event outside Tokyo, illustrating the coordination between the Cabinet Information Division, the Home Ministry, municipal offices, local business, and the Korean Government-­ General. See Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 135. 97. Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 25.

254 Notes to Chapter 5 98. See Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 30 and 11. 99. On the economic crisis in interwar Japan, see Takafusa Nakamura, “Depression, Recovery and War, 1920–1945,” in Cambridge , vol. 6: The Twentieth ­Century, ed. Peter Duus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 451–493. 100. Yokomizo Mitsuteru, “Shisōsen ni tsuite,” in Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, ed. Naikaku jōhōbu (Tokyo: Naikaku Jōhōbu, 1938), 1–3. 101. Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 32. 102. Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 32. 103. Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 32. 104. Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 31. 105. Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 35. 106. This poster included statistics concerning students involved in “thought incidents”: out of a total of 1,128 arrested, 148 students ­were indicted, 598 ­were given Suspended Indictments (Kiso yūyo), and 381 ­were placed in reserved indictments (Kiso ryūho). Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 36. 107. Naikaku Jōhōbu, Shisōsen tenrankai kiroku zukan, 36. 108. On the earlier proposals and l­ater implementation of preventative detention, see: Okudaira Yasuhiro, “Chianijihō ni okeru yobō kōkin,” in Fashizumuki no kokka to shakai 4: Senji nihon no hōtaisei, ed. Tokyo Daigaku Shakai Kagaku Kenkyūsho (Tokyo: Tokyo Daigaku Shuppansha, 1979), 165–229. 109. See for instance the proceedings from the May 1940 meeting of thought procu- rators: Shihōshō Keijikyoku, “Shisō jimuka kaidō gijiroku” (May 1940), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 19. 110. The following is derived from Shihōshō Keijikyoku, “Shisō jimuka kaidō gi- jiroku” (May 1940), 19–63. 111. Officials pointed to the ­cac ep­tance of the popu­lar front strategy at the Seventh World Congress of the Communist International in August 1935 as proof of the­ se organ­ izations’ communist intentions. 112. On the Peace Preservation Law and the suppression of new religions such as Ōmotokyō, see Okudaira Yasuhiro, Chianijihō shōshi, new ed. (Tokyo: Iwanami, 2006), 222–239. See also Sheldon Garon, “Defining Orthodoxy and Heterodoxy,” in Molding Japa­nese Minds: The State in Everyday Life (Prince­ton, NJ: Prince­ton University Press, 1997), 60–87. On Tenrikyō and Tenri honmichi, see Robert Kisala, “Schisms in Japa­nese New Religious Movements,” in Sacred Schisms: How Religions Divide, ed. James R. Lewis and Sarah M. Lewis (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 83–93. 113. Shihōshō Keijikyoku, “Shisō jimuka kaidō gijiroku” (May 1940), 20–22. 114. Other issues that emerged during the drafting of the revision bill ­were further separating the kokutai and private property system offenses since the kokutai was some- thing absolute (zettaisei) while private property was not. See Hirata Isao’s contribution to the May 1940 meeting: Shihōshō Keijikyoku, “Shisō jimuka kaidō gijiroku,” 24. 115. The bill is reprinted in Okudaira Yasuhiro, ed.,Gendaishi shiryō 45: Chianijihō (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 1973), 277–284, hereafter cited asgss 45. For an overview of the 1941 bill and its discussion in the Diet, see Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 166–170.

Notes to Chapter 5 255 116. See Miyake Masatarō’s pre­sen­ta­tion to a committee of the Seventy-­Sixth Imperial Diet on February 12, 1941, reprinted in gss45, 284–289. 117. gss45, 289. 118. For the po­liti­cal context within the Imperial Diet and state at the time, see Naka- zawa, Chianijihō, 175–177. For overviews of the system ­after 1941, see Matsuo,Chianijihō to tokkō keisatsu, 198–206; Okudaira, Chianijihō shōshi, 250–262. 119. For the final text of this law and its promulgation, see Seifu, “Shin chianijihō” (March 10, 1941), and Seifu, “Chian ijihō kaisei hōritsu shikō kijitsu no ken” (May 14, 1941), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 69–75 and 105 respectively. Also gss45, 523–533. 120. Translations amended from the abbreviated En­glish translation of the 1941 law: appendix 4, “Peace Preservation Law, 1941, Articles 1–16,” in Mitchell, Thought Control in Prewar Japan, 201–203. For an extensive analy­sis of the new crimes defined in the law, see Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 703–711. For an extensive le­ gal analy­sis of the proposal, passage and application of the New Peace Preservation Law, see Uchida Hirofumi, Chianijihō no kyōkun: Kenri undō no seigen to kenpō kaisei (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 2016), 450–497 121. Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 105 and 106 respectively. The or- dinances establishing the Preventative Detention system are reprinted in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 109–110. 122. Uchida Hirofumi, Keihō to sensō: Senji chian hōsei no tsukurikata (Tokyo: Misuzu Shobō, 2015). Provocatively, Uchida argues that con­temporary ­legal changes (2018) being carried out by the Abe Shinzō regime reflect developments that prepared Japan for total war in the 1930s. 123. I thank Louise Young for reminding me of ­these parallel developments in Man- chukuo. For an extensive overview of security laws and institutions in Manchukuo, see Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 748–764. 124. Nakazawa refers to an April 1941 report drafted by the Kwantung Military’s Staff Section (Kantōgun sanbōbu) that cites concern about infiltration by Soviet and Chi- nese communists. See Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 210. 125. Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 210. 126. Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 210–211. 127. See Chōsen sōtoku, “Chōsen shisōhan yobō kōkin ryō” (February 12, 1941), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 84–87. For the Government-­General’s expla- nation for implementing Preventative Detention in the colony, see Chōsen sōtokufu, “Riyū to setsumei” (November 1940), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 87–89. On the Peace Preservation Law in war­time colonial ­Korea, see Mizuno Naoki, “Senjiki chōsen no chianiji taisei,” in Iwanami kōza: Ajia • Taiheiyō sensō 6: Shihai to bōryoku, ed. Kurosawa Aiko et al. (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2006), 95–122. 128. Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 700–701. 129. Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 701. See the draft proposal prepared by the Korean Government-­General: Chōsen sōtokufu, “Chōsen shisōhan yobō kōkin ryō nado no sōan” (fall 1940), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 76–84. 130. A Preventative Detention report cited in Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 723. 131. For an overview of recent research on the Mantetsu Research Bureau Incident, see Matsumura Takao, “Mantetsu chōsabu danatsu jiken (1942 • 43nen) sairon,” Mita 256 Notes to Chapter 5 gakkai zasshi 105, no. 4 (January 2013): 719–754. For a firsthand account of the Yoko- hama Incident, see Kuroda Hidetoshi, Yokohama jiken (Tokyo: Gakugei Shorin, 1975). See also Janice Matsumura, More Than a Momentary Nightmare: The Yokohama Incident and War­time Japan (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University East Asia Program, 1998); Ogino Fujio, Yokohama jiken to chianijihō (Tokyo: Kinohanasha, 2006). For a general overview of the application of the New Peace Preservation Law between 1941 and 1945, see Naka- zawa, Chianijihō, 181–200; and Uchida, Chianijihō no kyōkun, 459–497. 132. ­These numbers are derived from the graph in Nakazawa, Chianijihō, 183. Dif­fer­ent numbers are given in appendix 1, “Chianijihō ihan jiken nendo betsu shori jinin hyō,” in gss45, 646–649. 133. See the ­table “Chianijihō ihan jiken nendo betsu shori” in Hong Jong-­wook, Senjiki chōsen no tenkōsha-­tachi (Tokyo: Yūshisha, 2011), 63. 134. Chōsen sōtokufu, “Yobō kōkin shūyōsha no jōkyō” (December 1944), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 325. Ogino notes that in August 1944, ­there ­were 2,897 thought criminals in ­Korea in the Protection and Supervision system. See Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 687. 135. Matsumoto Kazumi, “Tokyo yobō kōkinsho no kaisō,” in Gokuchū no shōwashi: Toyotama keimusho, ed. Kazahaya Yasoji (Tokyo: Aoki Shoten, 1986), 167, cited in Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 723. For another account of life inside a Preventative Detention Center, see Tsuchiya Shukurō, Yobō kōkin sho (Tokyo: Banseisha, 1988). 136. In addition to Matsumoto, see Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 722. 137. Mitchell, Janus-Faced­ Justice, 142. Reports on Fukumoto’s ideological develop- ment, as well as his own thought reports, are collected in Shihōshō keijikyoku, ed., Shisō shiryō panfuretto tokushū 12: Tokuda Kyūichi, Shiga Yoshio, Fukumoto Kazuo ni kansuru yobōkōkin seikyū jiken kiroku (Tokyo: Shihōshō Keijikyoku, December 1942). 138. Matsumoto, “Tokyo yobō kōkinsho no kaisō,” 179. The following information comes from Matsumoto’s recollections. 139. Monbushō, ed., Kokutai no hongi (Tokyo: Monbushō, 1937). On the use of Kokutai no hongi in the Tokyo Center, see Matsumoto, “Tokyo yobō kōkinsho no kaisō,” 174–175. Matsumoto reports that a thought criminal who successfully demonstrated conversion and was released received a copy of the Kokutai no hongi as a gift (181). 140. Matsumoto, “Tokyo yobō kōkinsho no kaisō,” 177. 141. See Shihōshō, “Chianijihō ihan shūyōsha no tenkō bunrui ni kansuru ken tsūchō” (November 13, 1941), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 301. This definition applied to the Protection and Supervision System as well. See Moriyama Takeichirō, “Shihōshō hogo kyoku” (Order No. 16739, September 12, 1941), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 3, 357–358. 142. Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 685. 143. Interestingly, ­because of the ­later increase in tenkō cases in colonial ­Korea, Ogino reports that as late as 1944, ­there ­were 2,897 individuals ­under Protection and Supervision in ­Korea. Ogino, “Kaisetsu,” 687. 144. The second exhibition was less of a production than the 1938 exhibit, with fewer advertisements, a tour that included only two other locations (Osaka and Nagoya), and a simpler commemorative book published in a smaller quantity. On the 1940 Thought War Exhibition, see Naikaku Jōhōbu, ed., Shisōsenten: Dainimen (Tokyo: Naikaku Notes to Chapter 5 257 Jōhōbu, 1940). On the idea of holy war, see Walter Edwards, “Forging Tradition for a Holy War: The ‘Hakkō Ichiu’ Tower in Miyazaki and Japa­nese War­time Ideology,” Journal of Japa­nese Studies 29, no. 2 (summer 2003): 289–324. Public advertisements presented the 1940 Thought War Exhibition in Tokyo in the following manner: “The assault of the thought war, which attempts to break the unity of our spirit kokoro[ no danketsu], must be decisively crushed. To prepare the unshakable one million spirits is itself to serve as a soldier of the thought war.” Conversion was represented as merely a tactic in Japan’s intensifying holy war. See the advertisement on page 6 of the Febru- ary 9, 1940, Tokyo Asahi Shimbun, morning edition. 145. On the Metalworks Vocational Center, see Kobayashi, “Tenkōki” no hitobito, 225–230; on the Reformed Workers Production Factory, 233–236. Kobayashi reports that the factory manufactured parts in conjunction with the larger Japan Shipbuilding Machines Incorporated (Nihon zōsen kikai kabushiki gaisha).

Epilogue 1. ghq/scap, “Seijiteki, kōminteki oyobi shūkyōteki jiyū ni taisuru seigen jokyo no ken” (October 4, 1945), in Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, ed. Ogino Fujio (Tokyo: Shinnihon Shuppansha, 1996), 368–371. 2. For the repeal of the Peace Preservation Law, among other institutions, see Seifu, Order Nos. 542 (October 13), 575 (October 15), and 638 (November 20), in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 371–372. The 1900 Public Peace Police Law (Chian keisatsu hō) was repealed on November 21. 3. John Dower, Embracing Defeat: Japan in the Wake of World War II (New York: Norton, 1999), 69, 236. 4. Ogino Fujio, Shisō kenji (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2000), 186. 5. Ogino, Shisō kenji, 192–193. 6. The Home Ministry was reor­ga­nized soon afterward but demonstrates how the prewar police continued into the immediate postwar and beyond. See Ogino Fujio, “Kaisetsu: Chianijihō seiritsu • ‘kaisei’ shi,” in Ogino, Chianijihō kankei shiryōshū, vol. 4, 746. See also Ogino Fujio, Tokkō keisatsu (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2012), 222. 7. Ogino, Tokkō keisatsu, 224–225. 8. On the construction of the postwar security police, see Ogino Fujio, Sengo kōan taisei no kakuritsu (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1999). 9. Ogino, Shisō kenji, 185–191. 10. On the discrepancies between ghq’s dismantling of the Home and Justice Minis- try bureaus dealing with po­liti­cal crime, see Ogino, Shisō kenji, 188. In total, twenty-­five justice officials ­were dismissed, including the prominent procurator Ikeda Katsu, who was working in Nagoya at the time. However, ­after the Occupation ended in 1952, Ikeda was assigned to the Supreme Court in 1954 (iv–­v, 189–192). On the return of justice of- ficials that w­ ere dismissed earlier, see 200–201. On thought procurators, see 183. 11. See Ogino, Shisō kenji, 193–196. 12. On this law, see John M. Maki, “Japan’s Subversive Activities Prevention Law,” Western Po­liti­cal Quarterly 6, no. 3 (September 1953): 489–511; Cecil H. Uyehara, The Subversive Activities Prevention Law: Its Creation, 1951–1952 (Leiden: Brill, 2010). 258 Notes to Chapter 5 13. For an overview of the subjectivity debates, see Victor J. Koschmann, Revolution and Subjectivity in Postwar Japan (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996). 14. The two most infamous jcp tenkōsha, Sano Manabu and Nabeyama Sadachika, remained staunch critics of the jcp ­after the war. 15. See Honda Shūgo, Tenkō bungakuron (Tokyo: Miraisha, 1957). Honda himself was arrested in 1933 for his association with the proletarian writers’s movement. For a trans- lated collection of early essays from this debate, see Atsuko Ueda, Michael Bourdaghs, Richi Sakakibara, and Hirokazu Toeda, eds., The Politics and Lit­er­a­ture Debate in Postwar Japa­nese Criticism, 1945–1952 (Lanham, MD: Lexington, 2017). 16. Shisō No Kagaku Kenkyūkai, ed., Kyōdō kenkyū: Tenkō, 3 vols. (Tokyo: Heibonsha, 1959–1962). See also Takeuchi Yoshimi, “What Is Modernity? (The Case of Japan and China)” (1948), in What Is Modernity? Writings of Takeuchi Yoshimi, trans. Richard F. Calichman (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005), 53–81. 17. Adam Bronson, One Hundred Million Phi­los­o­phers: Science of Thought and the Culture of Democracy in Postwar Japan (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 2016), 161–195. 18. In Japa­nese scholarship, Ogino Fujio and ­others have suggested ­these legacies. See Ogino, Sengo chian taisei no kakuritsu; Uchida Hirofumi, Chianijihō to kyōbōzai (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 2017), 95–187; and Uchida Hirofumi, Keihō to sensō: Senji chian hōsei no tsukurikata (Misuzu Shobō, 2015), 97–101. 19. For the new 1947 Juvenile Offenders Law, see Uchida Hirofumi,Kōsei hogo no tenkai to kadai (Kyoto: Hōritsu Bunkasha, 2015), 129–140; Moriya Katsuhiko, Shōnen no hikō to kyōiku: Shōnen hōsei no rekishi to genjō (Tokyo: Keisōshobō, 1977), 152–195. For an extensive overview of this history, see chapter 7, “Sengo kōsei hogo no seiseiki naishi junbiki,” in Uchida, Kōsei hogo no tenkai to kadai, 99–239. 20. On ­these laws, see Kōsei Hogo Gojūnen Shi Henshū Iinkai, ed., Kōsei hogo gojūnen shi: Chiiki shakai to tomo ni ayumu kōsei hogo (Tokyo: Zenkoku Hogoshi Ren- mei, 2000), vol. 1, 8–9. For the original bill, explanation, and subsequent Diet debates over the Offenders Prevention and Rehabilitation Act, see Kōsei Hogo Gojūnen Shi Henshū Iinkai, Kōsei hogo gojūnen shi, vol. 2, 449–480. In the new postwar Judicial Protection system, probationary duties for both youths and adults w­ ere combined in 1952 into the office of probation officershogoshi ( ). And with the prohibition of prostitu- tion in 1958, the protection system came to oversee the reform of ­women arrested for prostitution as well. 21. On scap’s involvement in the emperor’s Declaration of Humanity, see Dower, Embracing Defeat, 308–314. 22. Glenn D. Hook and Gavan McCormack, Japan’s Contested Constitution: Docu- ments and Analy­sis (London: Routledge, 2001), 4. 23. See images of Emperor Hirohito attending the Tenth and Twentieth Anniversary Cele­brations of the Criminal Reform System (Kōsei hogo seido) in October 1959 in Hibiya Park and October 1969 in Nippon Budōkan arena, in Kōsei Hogo Gojūnen Shi Henshū Iinkai, Kōsei hogo gojūnen shi, 250 and 282 respectively. 24. See the report of the Fiftieth Anniversary (1999) of the (postwar) Criminal Re- form System in which Emperor Akihito and Empress Michiko attended, in Kōsei Hogo Gojūnen Shi Henshū Iinkai, Kōsei hogo gojūnen shi, frontmatter and 393–394. Notes to Epilogue 259 25. Jonathon E. Abel, Redacted: The Archives of Censorship in Transwar Japan (Berke- ley: University of California Press, 2012), 17–20. 26. For example, see the section “Kōsei hogo zenshi II,” in Kōsei Hogo Gojūnen Shi Henshū Iinkai, Kōsei hogo gojūnen shi, vol. 1, 164–195. 27. For example, see Ministry of Japan Rehabilitation Bureau, Non-institutional­ Treat- ment of Offenders in Japan (Tokyo: Hōmushō Hogokyoku, 1974), 1–5. 28. See Umemori Naoyuki, “Modernization through Colonial Mediations: The Establishment of the Police and Prison System in Meiji Japan” (PhD diss., University of Chicago, 2002). 29. I touch on this briefly in the preface. For recent­le gal critiques of ­these develop- ments, see Uchida, Keihō to sensō; Uchida, Chianijihō to kyōbōzai; Hōgaku Seminaa Henshūbu, ed., Kyōbōzai hihyō: Kaisei soshikiteki hanzai shobatsu hō no kentō (Tokyo: Nihon Hyōronsha, 2017); and Colin Jones, “­Will Japan’s New Conspiracy Law Lead to ‘Thought Crime’?”The Diplomat, July 17, 2017, https://­thediplomat​.com­ ​/­2017​/­07​/­will​ -­japans-​ new­ -​ conspiracy­ -​ ­law-​ ­lead-​ ­to-​ ­thought-​ crime­ ​/­.

260 Notes to Epilogue