10. According to Popper, a Research Enterprise Starts from a Problem (Pi in Fig

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

10. According to Popper, a Research Enterprise Starts from a Problem (Pi in Fig The Popperian Image of Science Gerard RADNITZKY Ruhr-Universitat Bochum, West-Germany 1. Skeleton outline of the methodology 10. According to Popper, a research enterprise starts from a problem (Pi in fig. 1). Wheredoes the problemcome from? Popper focusseson the type of research situation in which progress of a dramatic order may occur rather than on the "piecemeal" mode production of new knowledge characteristic of research enter prises approximating the Kuhnian ideal type of Normal Science. In the typical situation of this type a "veteran" theory has run into diffculty, "clashed" with some experimental results. The "clash" may be more or less manifest, and more or less serious, with logical contradiction as a limit case. It may be latent, in particular in a type of research situation where pieces of knowledgeproduced in an "empirical" manner cannot be explained by the pertinent veteran theory. The residual may grow but resist explanation, as e.g., spectroscopicknowledge did before 1913. Such a residual-knowledgewhich cannot be explained by the veteran theory is practically always in evidence; however, when it accumulates or manifestly con flicts with the veteran theory, it constitutes a challenge which can no longer be ignored. The afore-mentioned type of situation of manifest conflict typically arises when attempts are being made to apply a theory to a new territory. Indeed it must occur, sooner or later, since the kernel of the theory is a conceptual model of a real (physical, biological,...) system, and because it is in the natur eof a model that it also has negative analogy. Thus a theory, once created, will sooneror later give rise to an objectiveproblem situation of that sort: a problem which confronts us or which we literally have to dis-cover. In particular, in case of a "clash", it is not just a question, but a problem in the etymological sense of the word 'problema': situation in which one cannot remain. The case under discussionis just one example of the phenomenon that objective problems arise whether the researcher wishes it or not, which phenomenon serves as part of Popper's "argument from independence" for giving ontological status to World-3.1 11. Where does the theory came from? Figure 1 sketches only two possibilities: the theory being one of the theories which, at the time, are accepted 1. E .g. OK pp. 160, 118 f., 147. -3- 4 G. RADNITZKY Vol. 5 in the discipline concerned; and the situation where an Ansatz towards a theory has just been made on the basis of the background knowledge, in particular on the basis of preconceptions about the general nature of the new "territory" (new sort of real system) which are derived from "world-picture" hypotheses. In the creation of theories about a hitherto unexplored realm "metaphysics" is structurally indispensible, and not merely indispensible as a part of psychological heuristics (world-2).2 normative (praxiological) model of the "game of science" legend: _??_•« " mapping" _??_ steering _??_ processes T theories/hypotheses X subject matter/territory •› results/store P problems Y other territories •Þ selector HG hypothesis generation ISF "internal steering factors" _??_ decision process HC hypothesis control Fig. 1 (artwork, text, legend) Preconceptions about the general nature of the subject matter at the level of world-picture hypotheses ("cosmological"hypotheses) also play an important role in the first-mentioned type of case, even if they remain implicit. They constitute the kernel of a system of factors -preconceptions, evaluations,... -which may 2. Cf . LSCD pp. 38, 277 f. -4- No. 1 The Popperian Image of Science 5 be called 'Internal Steering Factors' (ISF in fig. 1).3 Partially based upon the preconceptions is a programmatic conception about the discipline to which the theory belongs: evaluative statments about what the discipline (the "X-ology" in question, 9 in figs. 1 and 2) should be like, which may include an "ideal of science." According to the methodology under discussion a research enterprise that is properly conducted is governed by the rules4 derived from Critical Rationalism (right column of fig. 1); and thus the models presented by figs. 1 and 2 consist of the gambits and moves resulting from the application of these general rules to the various moments of research. The rules also specify the concept of "scientific progress" or the comparative concept of scientificquality, and the methodology of appraisal is spelled out in figure 2 as the operational characteristics of the "Hypotheses-Checking/Control Station" HC. These methodological gambits and moves apply to all research enterprises worthy that name. In "Normal Science" a certain substantive system of ISF, in particular a certain set of pre concepstions (cosmological hypotheses), steers the concrete procedures of a certain ensemble of concrete research enterprises in more detail; it provides sub stantive criteria for the appraisal of products and gives these research enterprises a certain unity and direction: gathers them together in a research "direction", "tradition" , "school", "style",...5 3. Preconceptions at the level of world-picture hypotheses do not belong to the theories themselves. E.g. among the preconceptions characteristic for the ISF of "Newtonian" type of theory would be the ontological posit that the world (that world with which physics is concerned) consists of matter spread out in empty space; in such a world, for two bodies not in contact with each other (not even through intermediation of other bodies travelling from one to the other) to interact causally, the simplest thing to assume is "simultaneous action at a distance" as a causal connector, (cf., e.g., (Radnitzky, 1974b) p. 33) etc. For a discussion of the concept of "preconcep tions" cf., e.g., (Radnitzky, 1974a) •˜ 212, Radnitzky, 1972) pp. 141-147; on the role of preconceptions in research cf. (Radnitzky, (1974b) with that title, esp. pp. 27 ff. and for examples from the "distilled history of science" pp. 32-43. Imre Lakatos confirmed to me in personal conversation that the "hard core" of an RP basically consists of such preconceptions; but there are passages in his writing which suggest that the hard core is made up mainly to the central components of the theory, which, over its history, constitutes the RP. Of course, the concept of the ISF is close to one of the many meanings of the Kuhnian "paradigm". Such as the "master-rule" mentioned in fig. l. 5. Cf., e.g., (Radnitzky, 1974b) pp. 7f. The claim that the rules apply to all research should not be taken to imply any form of "unity of science" thesis. We only wish to imply that the sciences humaines a very heterogenous group too contain certain moments (which Apel calls 'quasi-naturalistic' or 'explanatory' moments) to which the model of figs. I and 2 may be adapted. Again, to claim this is not to deny that the typical sciences humaines, the Geisteswissenschaftenhave additional methodological problems of their own, which this model does not touch upon. Some of them very likely cannot be tackeld without taking into consideration "knowledge-constitutive interests": there is a great difference between the task of "giving an explanation of understanding" (Erklaren des Verstehens) and the task of "understanding explanation" (Verstehen des Erkldrens). -5- 4 6 G. RADNITZKY Vol. 5 12. The proposed solution to the problem (Pi in fig. 1) is a tentative theory (Ti+1 in fig. 1). Where does Ti+1 comefrom? In figure 1 the box "Hypothesis Generation", HG, marks the "station" producing the tentative theory. Following Popper's usage, in figure 1 'theory' and 'hypothesis' are used interchangeably. Among the general rules (applying to all research) the one particularly important for the operation of HG is that labelled "preference rule": "Prefer theories (hypotheses)with high informationcontent (and hence more "falsifie-able" i.e. involv ing greater risks of being wrong, allowingmore severetests, theories whose absolute logical probability is as low as possible) to hypotheses with a lesser amount of information!" (Roughly: Nothing risked, nothing gained: the more "daring" the theory, the greater its potential for corroboration by tests.) (This rule of course follows from striving for severe tests.) However this rule gives only a very broad "policy" direction. In a concrete research situation the operation characteristics of HG are governed, in more detail, by the ISF, especially the (substantive) preconceptions ("cosmological" hypotheses). The ISF also steer the operation of the selector (marked in the way customary in cybernetic charts, by a "standing" triangle), i.e. they guide the decision concerning which part of the background knowledgeavailable at t is made use of. Of course all the input into HG are world-3 entities. Within the scope of the operation characteristics of this type of "Hypotheses - Generator", a logical move may be accomodated which, if used as a move of appraisal, would be highly objectionable (because then appraisal and generation, HG and HC, would have been conflated): a logical move which is often called "inductive" and which might more properly be labelled "observationist inductivist": from a set of data sentences to a generalizationof the same kind. If the data are taken as basic only in the sense of not being problematized in the particular research context at hand, then, although the logical move is not governed by precise formal rules, the procedure may nonetheless lead to a probabilistic conjecture. This move is certainly made use of in experimental work. But it must not be forgotten that not even this procedure is purely "empirical" (as one objectionable branch of "inductivism" would have it) since it is guided by the ISF all the way, even if this guidance may not be prima facie recognizable. In the type of research situation Popper focusseson (situation with chances for a "big step forward", other than "normal science"), in situations where the essential output of the HG is a theory rather than a law hypothesis, the the essential input will come from the preconceptions, from the "cosmological" hypotheses.
Recommended publications
  • The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes Philosophical Papers Volume I
    The methodology of scientific research programmes Philosophical Papers Volume i IMRE LAKATOS EDITED BY JOHN WORRALL AND GREGORY CURRIE CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. UB der LMU München, on 13 Apr 2020 at 02:49:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511621123 cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo, Delhi, Dubai, Tokyo, Mexico City Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521280310 © Imre Lakatos Memorial Appeal fund and the Estate of Imre Lakatos 1978 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1978 First paperback edition 1980 Reprinted 1984, 1986, 1989, 1992, 1994, 1995, 1999 A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library isbn 978-0-521-21644-9 Hardback isbn 978-0-521-28031-0 Paperback Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication, and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate. Information regarding prices, travel timetables, and other factual information given in this work is correct at the time of first printing but Cambridge University Press does not guarantee the accuracy of such information thereafter.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoclassical Economics As a Method of Scientific Research Program
    Munich Personal RePEc Archive Neoclassical Economics as a Method of Scientific Research Program : A review of existing literature Brahmachari, Deborshi IGNOU, India January 2016 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/75341/ MPRA Paper No. 75341, posted 04 Dec 2016 06:02 UTC Neoclassical Economics as a Method of Scientific Research Program Deborshi Brahmachari1 Abstract This paper aims at a commentary on the Neoclassical Economics as a Method of Scientific Research Program which argues that many theories in Neo-Classical Economics when tested using Lakatos’ Methodology of Scientific Research Program, were not categorised as 'progressive research program'. However, some endogenous growth theories have now been tested by few researcher as progressive in terms of Lakatos’ Scientific Research Program. 1 The author is a Ph D scholar in IGNOU, New Delhi 1 Neoclassical Economics as a Method of Scientific Research Program 1. Philosophy of Science and Neoclassical Economics: A brief summary Neoclassical economics and physical sciences have many things in common. Both economists and physicists, formulate laws based on their observations. Like physicists, economists rely on mathematics to formalize theories that are often not constrained by experimental evidence. Like physicists, economists reduce complex phenomena to basic units, such as the utility of the rational individual, and then explain the complex phenomena in terms of the interaction and aggregation of the basic units. However, one of the most important similarities is that neoclassical economists frequently justify their discipline, particularly their methods, using theories of scientific method devised by philosophers of science, especially by philosophers of physics. Traditionally, philosophy of science has been closely identified with the philosophy of physics, especially the ontological and epistemological issues in the physical sciences2.
    [Show full text]
  • AFRREV STECH, Vol. 2 (1) January, 2013
    AFRREV STECH, Vol. 2 (1) January, 2013 AFRREV STECH An International Journal of Science and Technology Bahir Dar, Ethiopia Vol. 2 (1) January, 2013:94-112 ISSN 2225-8612 (Print) ISSN 2227-5444 (Online) Inductivism and Science: An Appraisal of Scientific Methodology Obi, Chidiebere Cyriacus Department of Philosophy, Nnamdi Azikiwe University, Awka Anambra State, Nigeria E-mail: [email protected] Phone Number: +2348034946931 Abstract Inductivism is the claim that induction is the basis of proper scientific inquiry. Induction holds that we can infer that what we know to be true in a particular case or cases will be true in all cases, which resemble the former in certain assignable respects. Sequel to this, proponents of inductivism such as John Stuart Mill, Francis Bacon etc rejected every rationalistic or idealistic approach to scientific knowledge; instead, they suggested experience as the basis for any knowledge that is worthwhile. The history of philosophy has been characterized by arguments and counter arguments on what should constitute the nature of scientific methodology and this has led to absolutism in science that is, the belief that scientists must adhere to some stipulated method (s). This work employs critical method, functional analysis and hermeneutical method to appraise the above stated claim by first of all establishing the roles played by the human reason and a priori ideas in the scientific enterprise. After this, we will also examine issues surrounding the Copyright © IAARR 2012: www.afrrevjo.net/stech 94 Indexed African Researches Reviews online: www.arronet.info AFRREV STECH, Vol. 2 (1) January, 2013 methodology of science as raised by philosophers of science like Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos, and Feyerabend etc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes I
    The methodology of scientific research progralllllles Philosophical Papers Volume I IMRE LAKATOS EDITED BY JOHN WORRALL AND GREGORY CURRIE The Tight of the Umvers,fJ of Camh"clg(' 10 print and 5('// all manner of boo/.. s It a~ Krunted by Henry VIII In /534 The Umverslly htJ\ pflnlt'd and pubhsht'd continuous!)' since /584 CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS CAMBRIDGE NEW YORK PORT CHESTER MELBOURNE SYDNEY Published by the Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 IRP 32 East 57th Street, New York, NY 10022, USA 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia © Imre Lakatos Memorial Appeal fund and the Estate of Imre Lakatos 1978 First published 1978 First paperback edition 198o Reprinted 1984, 1986, 1989 Printed in the United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Lakatos, Imre Philosophical papers. Vol I: The methodology of scientific research programmes I. Science - Philosophy 2. Mathematics - Philosophy I. Title II. Worrall, John III. Currie, Gregory IV. Methodology of scientific research programmes 5°7'·2 Q175·3 77-71415 ISBN 0-521-28°31 -1 paperback Contents Editors' introduction v Introduction: Science and pseudoscience Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes 8 Science: reason or religion? 8 2 Fallibilism versus falsification ism 10 a Dogmatic (or naturalistic) falsificationism. The empirical basis 12 b Methodological falsificationism. The' empirical basis' 20 C Sophisticated versus naive methodological falsificationism.
    [Show full text]
  • Criticism of Falsifiability
    Criticism of Falsifiability Nicolae Sfetcu February 22, 2019 Sfetcu, Nicolae, "Criticism of Falsifiability", SetThings (February 22, 2019), MultiMedia Publishing (ed.), URL = Email: [email protected] This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NoDerivatives 4.0 International. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nd/4.0/. This is a partial translation of: Sfetcu, Nicolae, "Distincția dintre falsificare și respingere în problema demarcației la Karl Popper", SetThings (3 iunie 2018), MultiMedia Publishing (ed.), DOI: 10.13140/RG.2.2.10444.72329, ISBN 978-606-033-139-1, URL = https://www.telework.ro/ro/e- books/distinctia-dintre-falsificare-si-respingere-in-problema-demarcatiei-la-karl-popper/ Criticism of Falsifiability Thomas Kuhn criticized falsifiability because it characterized "the entire scientific enterprise in terms that apply only to its occasional revolutionary parts," (Kuhn 1970) and it cannot be generalized. In Kuhn's view, a delimitation criterion must refer to the functioning of normal science. (Kuhn 1970, 802) But Kuhn ignored Popper's sophisticated falsification and his extended theory. Kuhn objects to Popper's entire theory and excludes any possibility of rational reconstruction of the development of science. In Kuhn's view, "there can be no logic, but only psychology of discovery". (Lakatos 1978, 90) In a brief comparison of Hume, Carnap and Popper, Watkins points out that the development of science is inductive and irrational according to Hume, inductive and rational according to Carnap, non-inductive and rational according to Popper. (Watkins 1968) Extending this comparison, it can be added that the development of science is non-inductive and irrational, according to Kuhn.
    [Show full text]