Table of Contents

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Table of Contents TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter Page Chapter 1 – Legal Theories 2 Chapter 2 – Aboriginals 13 Chapter 3 – Bijuralism & International law 48 Chapter 4 – Rule of Law, Parliamentary 64 Privilege and Constitutional Supremacy Chapter 5 – Parliament and its Components 76 Chapter 6 – Functions of Parliament 77 Chapter 7 – The Executive and its Functions 79 Chapter 8 – Hierarchy of Courts 90 Chapter 9 – Statutory Interpretations 103 Chapter 10 – Judicial Review & its Limitation 111 in Democratic Society 1 CHAPTER ONE Positive Law • Positivism Law is nothing more than the rules and principles that actually govern or regulate society (laws are made by human beings’ vs created via nature). Legal positivism and its conception of law as nothing more than the rules and principles (or social facts) that actually regulate a society • Insists on the separation of law and morality focuses on describing laws without reference to justness or legitimacy. Concerned with what is legally valid, not morally valid. Morality can be relative. (a) Legal Positivism What the law is Re Noble and Wolf Restrictive covenant held valid. Facts: Individual cottage lots contained similar Judge said that he would rather stick to law, written statues, covenants relating to coloured and jews. unwritten or common law decisions, or text etc.; not Tried to rely on the above case to invalidate. speculations Leave the public policy to the politicians. Judge job is to interpret the law and not to create the law based on Held- Disagrees with Drummond Case. The individual belief of what the law ought to be. judge said that leave the concept of public policy for the politicians. Re Drummond case was based on shelter, whereas in this case it was for creation purposes rather than shelter. Natural Law; Natural law theory: • Laws are those that adhere to certain moral truths, most often of a universal and immutable nature; i.e. law’s legal authority depends upon an external moral standard that holds across all societies. • It views law as existing independently of positive law and constituted by immutable moral truths. 2 (a) Natural law What laws are? (but with reference to normative criteria [touches on what law ought to be]) Re Drummond Wren A covenant for restriction to sell is void, - Facts: Held-The judge decides the case on morality and justice WEA bought a lot with the intention to build it and by extending his views beyond the statute and gives way then sell it in order to raise funds. There was a to public policy.. Since Canada is a country of minorities covenant that the land cannot be used or sold to therefore, it is his duty to aid unity. Jews or objectionable nationality. WEA (purchaser) applied to have this covenant invalid Inclusive positivists advocate that it is conceptually plausible, but not mandatory, that the legal validity or truth of a norm should be dependent on its consistency with moral values or principles. Exclusive positivists hold the opposite. They believe that it is not possible for the legal validity of a norm to even be a function of its consistency with moral values or principles. Critical Legal Theory: • Realists maintained that all legal rules were indeterminate in the sense that any articulation of a rule was subject to multiple interpretations…. the result would reflect the unstated public policy preferences of the judge. There could reasonable apprehension bias. CLS poses a deep challenge to the liberal belief that law should be certain and neutral R v R.D.S: Cory J implicitly affirms the insights of CLS scholarship to find that a judge who considered social context in making a decision was not violating the requirement for neutrality. Judge made statement saying that Police have been known to mislead the courts. Crown said this raised reasonable apprehension of bias. Crown appealed to Appeal Court, new trial ordered b/c agreed reasonable apprehension bias Law and Economic Theory: • Law and economics theories look at law differently, less grounded in moral theory and more in ideas about efficiency (as opposed to feminism, which deals with producing equality); • Efficiency tends to be defined in terms of an ideal where the welfare of each of the relevant parties 3 can no longer be maximized except at the expense of other parties, referred to as a state of “Pareto optimality.” • This form of analysis was first applied on common law rules developed in private law areas such as torts and contracts. Feminist Theory: • Feminist legal theory, also known as feminist jurisprudence, is based on the belief that the law has been fundamental in women's historical subordination. The project of feminist legal theory is twofold. First, feminist jurisprudence seeks to explain ways in which the law played a role in women's former subordinate status. Second, feminist legal theory is dedicated to changing women's status through a rework of the law and its approach to gender (i) Early formalist feminism – the “Persons” case Early feminism – concerned with seeking women’s formal equality to men. Edwards v. AG Canada [1930] AC 124, 1 DLR 98 (PC) LORD SANKEY LC: Question: whether the words “qualified persons” in that section include a woman, and consequently whether or women are eligible to be summoned to and become members of the Senate of Canada. ii) Contemporary Feminism Case of abortion one of most continuous areas of public debate and good start to examine feminist theory in practice. Three doctors, charged with the offence of procuring a miscarriage contrary to s. 251(1) [criminalizing the procurement of an abortion unless properly authorized by a physician]. The majority of the court found the provision to offend the Charter. Justice Bertha Wilson, who agreed with the majority in the end result, rendered a separate opinion. Her decision is an example of a modern feminist approach to a public law concern—note how her opinion takes a woman’s point of view, in finding that a woman should not be required to carry a baby to term if she does not wish to. Required Readings: Article 1: 4 Green, Leslie. “Legal Positivism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. • “The existence and content of law depends on social facts and not on its merits” • This article is a general but succinct overview of the history and development of positivism since its inception., an issue which has moved to the and forefront of debate among positivists and legal theorists more generally History, Development and Influence: • Leslie discusses John Austin, author of “Legal Positivism”. Jeremy Bentham is the originator of the positivism theory. The most important architects of this revised positivism are the Austrian jurist Hans Kelsen (1881-1973) and the two dominating figures in the analytic philosophy of law, H.L.A. Hart (1907- 92) and Joseph Raz among whom there are clear lines of influence, but also important contrasts. For Hart, the legal system is norms all the way down, but at its root is a social norm that has the kind of normative force that customs have. Sources of LAW • What survives of their outlook is the idea that legal theory must ultimately be rooted in some account of the political system, an insight that came to be shared by all major positivists except Kelsen. For others, legal obligations when there is no probability of sanctions being applied and when there is no provision for sanctions (as in the duty of the highest courts to apply the law). Moreover, we take the existence of legal obligations to be a reason for imposing sanctions, not merely a consequence of it. • Hans Kelsen retains the imperativalists' monism, where to apply sanctions if a certain behavior (the “delict”) is performed. On this view, law is an indirect system of guidance: it does not tell subjects what to do; it tells officials what to do to its subjects under certain conditions. Therefore as imperatival , the legal system is founded upon rules, which if not followed, there is apenalty. The rules are created by the commanding sovereign, who is not questioned as to their morality to rule • For Hart, the authority of law is social. The ultimate criterion of validity in a legal system is neither a legal norm nor a presupposed norm, but a social rule that exists only because it is actually practiced. Law ultimately rests on custom: customs about who shall have the authority to decide disputes, what they shall treat as binding reasons for decision, i.e. as sources of law, and how customs may be changed. Of these three “secondary rules,” as Hart calls them, the source-determining rule of recognition is most important 5 Moral Principles and the Boundaries of Law • The most influential criticisms of legal positivism all flow, in one way or another, from the suspicion that it fails to give morality its due. • Accordingly, positivism's critics maintain that the most important features of law are not to be found in its source-based character, but in law's capacity to advance the common good, to secure human rights, or to govern with integrity. (It is a curious fact about anti-positivist theories that, while they all insist on the moral nature of law, without exception they take its moral nature to be something good. The idea that law might of its very nature be morally problematic does not seem to have occurred to them.) • As Finnis says, the reasons we have for establishing, maintaining or reforming law include moral reasons, and these reasons therefore shape our legal concepts . Dwarkin talks about - Who gives them power to make the law - Which law sovereign abide to - Allow the law to have this course, the law is not good if it is forced 4.
Recommended publications
  • Western Weekly Reports
    WESTERN WEEKLY REPORTS Reports of Cases Decided in the Courts of Western Canada and Certain Decisions of the Supreme Court of Canada 2013-VOLUME 12 (Cited [2013] 12 W.W.R.) All cases of value from the courts of Western Canada and appeals therefrom to the Supreme Court of Canada SELECTION EDITOR Walter J. Watson, B.A., LL.B. ASSOCIATE EDITORS (Alberta) E. Mirth, Q.C. (British Columbia) Darrell E. Burns, LL.B., LL.M. (Manitoba) E. Arthur Braid, Q.C. (Saskatchewan) G.L. Gerrand, Q.C. CARSWELL EDITORIAL STAFF Cheryl L. McPherson, B.A.(HONS.) Director, Primary Content Operations Audrey Wineberg, B.A.(HONS.), LL.B. Product Development Manager Nicole Ross, B.A., LL.B. Supervisor, Legal Writing Andrea Andrulis, B.A., LL.B., LL.M. (Acting) Supervisor, Legal Writing Andrew Pignataro, B.A.(HONS.) Content Editor WESTERN WEEKLY REPORTS is published 48 times per year. Subscrip- Western Weekly Reports est publi´e 48 fois par ann´ee. L’abonnement est de tion rate $409.00 per bound volume including parts. Indexed: Carswell’s In- 409 $ par volume reli´e incluant les fascicules. Indexation: Index a` la docu- dex to Canadian Legal Literature. mentation juridique au Canada de Carswell. Editorial Offices are also located at the following address: 430 rue St. Pierre, Le bureau de la r´edaction est situ´e a` Montr´eal — 430, rue St. Pierre, Mon- Montr´eal, Qu´ebec, H2Y 2M5. tr´eal, Qu´ebec, H2Y 2M5. ________ ________ © 2013 Thomson Reuters Canada Limited © 2013 Thomson Reuters Canada Limit´ee NOTICE AND DISCLAIMER: All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • 11488911.PDF (4.052Mb)
    Faculté de Droit Direction des bibliothèques AVIS NOTICE L’auteur a autorisé l’Université The author has given the de Montréal à reproduire et Université de Montréal diffuser, en totalité ou en partie, permission to partially or par quelque moyen que ce soit completely reproduce and et sur quelque support que ce diffuse copies of this report or soit, et exclusivement à des fins thesis in any form or by any non lucratives d’enseignement means whatsoever for strictly et de recherche, des copies de non profit educational and ce mémoire ou de cette thèse. purposes. L’auteur et les coauteurs le cas The author and the co-authors, échéant, conservent néan- if applicable, nevertheless keep moins la liberté reconnue au the acknowledged rights of a titulaire du droit d’auteur de copyright holder to com- diffuser, éditer et utiliser mercially diffuse, edit and use commercialement ou non ce this work if they choose. Long travail. Les extraits substantiels excerpts from this work may not de celui-ci ne peuvent être be printed or reproduced in imprimés ou autrement another form without reproduits sans autorisation de permission from the author. l’auteur. L’Université ne sera The University is not aucunement responsable d’une responsible for commercial, utilisation commerciale, indus- industrial or other use of this trielle ou autre du mémoire ou report or thesis by a third party, de la thèse par un tiers, y including by professors. compris les professeurs. Université rU, de Montréal Université de Montréal Pour une constitutionnalisation du droit à
    [Show full text]
  • Froduard Munyangabe Legal Meaning in The
    Institute of Advanced Legal Studies School of Advanced Study University of London Froduard Munyangabe Legal meaning in the interpretation of multilingual legislations: Comparative analysis of Rwanda, Canada and Ireland LLM 2010-2011 LLM in Advanced Legislative Studies (ALS) S2006 1 Legal meaning in the interpretation of multilingual legislations: Comparative analysis of Rwanda, Canada and Ireland Table of Contents Acknowledgements .................................................................................................................. 2 Dedication ................................................................................................................................. 2 1.0 Introduction ........................................................................................................................ 3 1.1 Methodology ........................................................................................................................ 4 1.3 Justification .......................................................................................................................... 5 1.4 Structure ............................................................................................................................... 6 2.0 Preliminary considerations ............................................................................................... 7 2.1 Concepts ............................................................................................................................... 7 2.1.1 Interpretation of Laws......................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Translating the Constitution Act, 1867
    TRANSLATING THE CONSTITUTION ACT, 1867 A Legal-Historical Perspective by HUGO YVON DENIS CHOQUETTE A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Law in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Laws Queen’s University Kingston, Ontario, Canada September 2009 Copyright © Hugo Yvon Denis Choquette, 2009 Abstract Twenty-seven years after the adoption of the Constitution Act, 1982, the Constitution of Canada is still not officially bilingual in its entirety. A new translation of the unilingual Eng- lish texts was presented to the federal government by the Minister of Justice nearly twenty years ago, in 1990. These new French versions are the fruits of the labour of the French Constitutional Drafting Committee, which had been entrusted by the Minister with the translation of the texts listed in the Schedule to the Constitution Act, 1982 which are official in English only. These versions were never formally adopted. Among these new translations is that of the founding text of the Canadian federation, the Constitution Act, 1867. A look at this translation shows that the Committee chose to de- part from the textual tradition represented by the previous French versions of this text. In- deed, the Committee largely privileged the drafting of a text with a modern, clear, and con- cise style over faithfulness to the previous translations or even to the source text. This translation choice has important consequences. The text produced by the Commit- tee is open to two criticisms which a greater respect for the prior versions could have avoided. First, the new French text cannot claim the historical legitimacy of the English text, given their all-too-dissimilar origins.
    [Show full text]
  • OFFICIAL LANGUAGES and PARLIAMENT Publication No
    OFFICIAL LANGUAGES AND PARLIAMENT Publication No. 2015-131-E 10 December 2015 Revised 19 May 2020 Chloé Forget Marie-Ève Hudon Élise Hurtubise-Loranger Legal and Social Affairs Division Revised by Marie-Ève Hudon Parliamentary Information and Research Service Library of Parliament Background Papers provide in-depth studies of policy issues. They feature historical background, current information and references, and many anticipate the emergence of the issues they examine. They are prepared by the Parliamentary Information and Research Service, which carries out research for and provides information and analysis to parliamentarians and Senate and House of Commons committees and parliamentary associations in an objective, impartial manner. This publication was prepared as part of the Library of Parliament’s research publications program, which includes a set of publications, introduced in March 2020, addressing the COVID-19 pandemic. Please note that, because of the pandemic, all Library of Parliament publications will be released as time and resources permit. © Library of Parliament, Ottawa, Canada, 2020 Official Languages and Parliament (Background Paper) Publication No. 2015-131-E Ce document est également publié en français. CONTENTS EXECUTIVE SUMMARY 1 INTRODUCTION ...............................................................................................................1 2 CONSTITUTIONAL PROVISIONS .....................................................................................1 2.1 Constitution Act, 1867 ........................................................................................................1
    [Show full text]
  • Bijuralism: a Supreme Court of Canada Justice's Perspective
    Louisiana Law Review Volume 62 Number 2 Winter 2002 Article 3 2-1-2002 Bijuralism: A Supreme Court of Canada Justice's Perspective Claire L'Heureux-Dubé Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.lsu.edu/lalrev Part of the Law Commons Repository Citation Claire L'Heureux-Dubé, Bijuralism: A Supreme Court of Canada Justice's Perspective, 62 La. L. Rev. (2002) Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.lsu.edu/lalrev/vol62/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at LSU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Louisiana Law Review by an authorized editor of LSU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Bijuralism: A Supreme Court of Canada Justice's Perspective The Honourable ClaireL 'Heureux-Dubg* I consider it an honour to have been invited to deliver the Rubin Lecture at the Louisiana State University Law Center. I had the privilege and good fortune to know Judge Alvin Rubin. I am delighted to have an opportunity to pay tribute to this great jurist whose "intellect, scholarship and judicial leadership," in the words of one of his colleagues, "place him in a select group" including Holmes, Brandeis, Cardozo, Learned Hand, and Henry Friendly, all judicial icons.' Alvin Rubin was a giant among jurists and, most importantly, one with a pronounced social conscience. The family tradition of excellence is shared by his wife Janice, his sons Michael and David, and his grandchildren. Life sometimes gives you presents. For me, my initial encounter with Janice and Alvin was a precious gift.
    [Show full text]
  • Appellant The-Information-Commissioner-Of
    File Nos. 33300, 33296, 33297, 33299 SUPREME COURT OF CANADA (ON APPEAL FROM A JUDGMENT OF THE FEDERAL COURT OF APPEAL) File No. 33300 BETWEEN: THE INFORMATION COMMISSIONER OF CANADA APPELLANT (Appellant) - and - THE MINISTER OF NATIONAL DEFENCE RESPONDENT (Respondent) ---------------------------------------------------- File No. 33296 BETWEEN: THE INFORMATION COMMISSIONER OF CANADA APPELLANT (Appellant) - and - THE MINISTER OF TRANSPORT CANADA RESPONDENT (Respondent) (Style of cause continues inside cover) APPELLANT’S FACTUM - 2 - File No. 33297 BETWEEN: THE INFORMATION COMMISSIONER OF CANADA APPELLANT (Respondent) - and - THE COMMISSIONER OF THE ROYAL CANADIAN MOUNTED POLICE RESPONDENT (Appellant) ---------------------------------------------------- File No. 33299 AND BETWEEN: THE INFORMATION COMMISSIONER OF CANADA APPELLANT (Appellant / Respondent on Cross-Appeal) - and - THE PRIME MINISTER OF CANADA RESPONDENT (Respondent / Appellant on Cross-Appeal) - 3 - Mr. Laurence Kearley Ms. Diane Therrien Information Commissioner of Canada 7th Floor – Tower B 112 Kent Street Ottawa, Ontario K1A 1H3 Tel.: 613 943-2577 Tel.: 613 996-3234 Fax: 613 947-5252 [email protected] [email protected] Ms. Marlys A. Edwardh Ms. Jessica R. Orkin Marlys Edwardh Barristers Professional Corporation Suite 1100 20 Dundas Street West Toronto, Ontario M5G 2G8 Tel.: 416 597-2801 Tel.: 416 597-6573 Fax: 416 597-0070 [email protected] [email protected] Counsel for the Appellant Mr. Christopher M. Rupar Attorney General of Canada
    [Show full text]
  • Subordinate Legislation! 34
    LAW, LEGISLATION & POLICY SECTION 2 - M. DEHKA FINAL OUTLINE - DEC 2011 JAMIE MYRAH ! Branches of Government! 3 Principles! 4 Legislative Process! 6 Stage 1 - Creation of Legislative Policy! 6 Stage 2 - Drafting the Legislation! 6 Stage 3 - Enactment of a Law! 7 Problem of Meaning! 9 Statutory Interpretation! 10 Overview of SI Approaches! 10 Overview of Interpretation “Rules”! 10 Sullivan’s Critique! 13 Statutory & Common Law Principles & Presumptions! 18 Approaches to Defining Words! 18 Interpretation Acts: Purpose & Provisions! 18 Components of a Statute! 20 Contextual Analysis! 22 Previous Statutory Interpretations! 25 Common Law Principles of Interpretation & Presumptions! 25 Temporal Issues in the Operation & Application of Statutes! 29 Coming Into Force! 29 Subsequent Changes to Legislation/Transitional Rules! 29 Temporal Operation & Application of Legislation! 31 Subordinate Legislation! 34 History & Types of Subordinate Legislation! 34 Authority to Enact Subordinate Legislation! 36 Regulation-Making Process & Procedures! 37 Judicial Oversight of Subordinate Legislation! 40 Summary of Concepts & Process! 42 Key Principles of a Contextual Analysis! 42 Application of Principles to Case Law! 42 Page 2 Branches of Government LEGISLATIVE EXECUTIVE JUDICIAL Role & Make laws Implement/ Interpret/apply laws Function: (statutes) administer laws Make laws Drafts, debates & Make laws (primarily (common law - case votes sub-ordinate/ law/jurisprudence) regulatory) Structure & Monarch - G.G. Monarch - G.G./L.G. Monarch Positions: (Royal Assent) I (appointments) I P.M. / Premier Parliament I *Cabinet *Court Systems: Note: Privy I Ministers Council - all Senate I Supreme Court of members of (unelected) Committees Canada past/present I I I cabinets - the House of Commons I Federal / Provincial “Crown’s (elected) I Courts advisors” - --------------------------- I power Monarch - L.G.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Problems with the Shared Meaning Rule As Formulated in R V Daoust and the Law of Bilingual Interpretation
    71 Some Problems with the Shared Meaning Rule as Formulated in R v Daoust and The Law of Bilingual Interpretation RUTH SULLIVAN* This article offers a critical analysis of the account of the Cet article pr6sente une analyse critique du principe shared meaning rule adopted by the Supreme Court du sens commun, adopt6 par la Cour supreme du of Canada in R v Daoust and subsequently defended Canada dans l'arr~t R c Daoust, que les auteurs de Le by the authors of The Law of Bilingual Interpretation, droit de l'interprtationbilingue ont par la suite d~fendu, including retired Justice Michel Bastarache who wrote notamment le juge 1 la retraite Michel Bastarache, qui the unanimous judgment of the Court in Daoust. The a r&digh la d6cision unanime de la Cour dans Daoust. author argues that, contrary to the position taken in L'auteure soutient que, contrairement i la position Daoust, the presumption of shared meaning should not adopthe dans Daoust, la prbsomption du sens commun arise when one language version of a legislative text ne devrait pas &tre invoqube lorsque la version dans is clear but broad while the other is clear but narrow. une langue d'un texte Iagislatif est claire mais large She suggests that relying on the presumption in these alors que la version dans l'autre langue est claire mais circumstances focuses too narrowly on the norms plus restreinte. Elle est d'avis que si l'on se fie i la of linguistic equality and the protection of minority pr6somption dans ces circonstances, on se concentre language rights while inappropriately neglecting the trop sur les normes rbgissant l'6galite linguistique et norms of rule of law and linguistic security.
    [Show full text]
  • Harmonization and Dissonance in Canadian Charity Law
    canadian tax journal / revue fiscale canadienne (2007) vol. 55, no 3, 481 - 556 Taxing Charities/Imposer les Organismes de Bienfaisance: Harmonization and Dissonance in Canadian Charity Law Kathryn Chan* P r é c i s Pendant de nombreuses années, la détermination de l’admissibilité des organismes aux importants avantages fiscaux accordés aux organismes de bienfaisance enregistrés (« registered charities ») en vertu de la Loi de l’impôt sur le revenu (Lir) reposait, dans toutes les provinces, sur la notion de bienfaisance (« charity ») élaborée dans la common law britannique des fiducies de bienfaisance. Au Canada, cependant, la notion de bienfaisance (« charity ») tire également sa signification d’autres sources, incluant celles de l’ancien droit civil qui font toujours partie du droit fondamental au Québec. Ces diverses sources du droit posent un défi aux organismes de bienfaisance enregistrés et au projet continu d’assurer l’accessibilité des lois fédérales aux nombreux auditoires juridiques et linguistiques au Canada. Cet article conteste la position générale selon laquelle il n’existe qu’une seule source d’interprétation pour les dispositions sur les organismes de bienfaisance enregistrés. L’auteur formule un certain nombre d’assertions qui contredisent l’approche unijuridique de longue date. Premièrement, l’interprétation actuelle de ces dispositions, en particulier la position selon laquelle la notion de bienfaisance retenue dans la Lir est une notion de droit fédérale uniforme, contredit les principes constitutionnels et réglementaires
    [Show full text]
  • A Transsystemic Approach to the Study of Law Between Law and Language
    591 Concepts and Words : A Transsystemic Approach to the Study of Law between Law and Language Yaëll Emerich* ** De concepts et de mots : approche transsystémique de l’étude du droit entre droit et langue Conceptos y palabras : un enfoque transistémico para el estudio del derecho entre derecho y lenguaje Conceitos e Palavras : uma Abordagem Transistêmica ao Estudo do Direito entre Lei e Linguagem 概念与词汇:法律与语言之间法学研究的跨系统进路 Résumé Abstract Le transsystémisme peut être décrit Transsystemia can be described as a comme une approche juridique centrée legal approach centered on a dialogue be- sur un dialogue entre des traditions juri- tween legal traditions, anchored in a plu- diques et ancrée dans une méthodologie ralist and interdisciplinary methodology, pluraliste et interdisciplinaire qui célèbre which celebrates the irreducible differ- les différences et les similitudes irréduc- ences and similarities between various le- tibles entre diverses traditions juridiques. gal traditions. This paper argues that * Associate professor at the Faculty of Law at McGill University. ** This paper was first presented at Pablo de Olavide University in Seville, at a conference entitled “From Legal Translation to Jurilinguistics : Interdisciplinary Approaches to the Study of Language and Law”, on October 27-28, 2016. The author wishes to thank Jesse Hartery, Audrée Sirois, Agatha Wong and Christian Laliberté for their help with this project. The author wishes to thank Robert Leckey and Nicholas Kasirer for their input on a previous version of the text. The project has received financial support from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. 592 (2017) 51 RJTUM 591 Cet article soutient que la jurilinguistique jurilinguistics could be used as a tool to pourrait être utilisée comme outil pour enhance the dialogue between languages améliorer le dialogue entre les langues et and traditions that speak to the core of les traditions, dialogue qui est au cœur du transsystemia.
    [Show full text]
  • The Challenges of Interpreting Multilingual, Multijural Legislation, 29 Brook
    Brooklyn Journal of International Law Volume 29 Issue 3 SYMPOSIUM: Article 2 Creating and Interpreting Law in a Multilingual Environmnent 2004 The hC allenges of Interpreting Multilingual, Multijural Legislation Ruth Sullivan Follow this and additional works at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/bjil Recommended Citation Ruth Sullivan, The Challenges of Interpreting Multilingual, Multijural Legislation, 29 Brook. J. Int'l L. (2004). Available at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/bjil/vol29/iss3/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at BrooklynWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Brooklyn Journal of International Law by an authorized editor of BrooklynWorks. File: Sullivan4.23.04macro.doc Created on: 4/23/2004 4:30 PM Last Printed: 6/25/2004 12:37 PM THE CHALLENGES OF INTERPRETING MULTILINGUAL, MULTIJURAL LEGISLATION Ruth Sullivan* I. INTRODUCTION....................................................................... 986 II. THE REFORM OF CANADA’S STATUTE BOOK ........................ 998 III. INTERPRETING MULTILINGUAL LEGISLATION.................. 1005 A. Legal Status ................................................................ 1005 B. Implications of Equal Authenticity............................ 1007 C. The Shared Meaning Rule.......................................... 1012 D. Applications of the Shared Meaning Rule ................. 1018 E. What Bilingual Legislation Reveals About Law ....... 1021 IV. INTERPRETING MULTIJURAL LEGISLATION ...................... 1022 A. New Scholarship........................................................
    [Show full text]