The Public Policy Doctrine in Choice of Law: a Reconsideration of Older Themes

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Public Policy Doctrine in Choice of Law: a Reconsideration of Older Themes Washington University Law Review Volume 1974 Issue 3 January 1974 The Public Policy Doctrine in Choice of Law: A Reconsideration of Older Themes Gary J. Simson Connecticut Bar Association Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_lawreview Part of the Conflict of Laws Commons, and the Jurisdiction Commons Recommended Citation Gary J. Simson, The Public Policy Doctrine in Choice of Law: A Reconsideration of Older Themes, 1974 WASH. U. L. Q. 391 (1974). Available at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_lawreview/vol1974/iss3/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington University Law Review by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY LAW QUARTERLY VOLUME 1974 NUMBER 3 THE PUBLIC POLICY DOCTRINE IN CHOICE OF LAW: A RECONSIDERATION OF OLDER THEMES GARY J.SIMSON* When presented with a cause of action not confined in its elements to the forum state, courts have on occasion announced that although the application of another jurisdiction's law is indicated in the instant case, they must decline to apply it because the law violates local public policy. In a classic formulation of the public policy doctrine, then- Judge Cardozo stated the test to be whether the foreign law can be said to "violate some fundamental principle of justice, some prevalent conception of good morals, some deep-rooted tradition of the common weal."1 The impact on the party against whom this doctrine is invoked may vary. A plaintiff whose complaint is dismissed on public policy grounds' will find no hospitable court for his action in the forum state. * Member of the Connecticut Bar. B.A., 1971, J.D., 1974, Yale University. 1. Loucks v. Standard Oil Co., 224 N.Y. 99, 111, 120 N.E. 198, 202 (1918). 2. Cases involving a dismissal on grounds of local policy regarding the allocation of judicial resources are not within the scope of this Article. See generally Hughes v. Fetter, 341 U.S. 609 (1951); Comment, Full Faith and Credit to Statutes of Sister States, 37 CORNELL L.Q. 441 (1952). Rather, the focus of this Article is the rejection of the application of foreign law on substantive grounds-i.e. because of the content of the specific law. Also distinguishable from the public policy doctrine is rejection of a cause of action because it calls for enforcement of foreign penal laws. For the special considerations raised by the penal doctrine, see Leflar, Extrastate Enforcement of Penal and Governmental Claims, 46 H~Av. L. Rav. 193 (1932). Washington University Open Scholarship 392 WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY LAW QUARTERLY [Vol. 1974:391 If the dismissal is made without prejudice, he may seek enforcement of his claim in another state. The latter possibility, however, may often prove illusory because of difficulties in obtaining personal jurisdiction over the defendant outside the state of the initial action.3 The fate of a defendant denied the opportunity to raise a defense for public policy reasons lacks any such ambiguities. Assuming no other ade- quate defense, he has lost on the merits, and a sister state is obliged under the full faith and credit clause to enforce the judgment against him. 4 The dissent to this doctrine long took the form of moral indignation. For one state to declare another's laws too abhorrent to enforce was for Beach "an intolerable affectation of superior virtue."5 Goodrich, in a similar vein, counseled "mutual tolerance for each other's little idiosyncracies"' and sought to persuade the doctrine's defenders that by applying foreign law in accordance with the mandate of basic choice of law rules, it [a state] does not, by such reference, flaunt its local policy with an implied recognition of the other state's as better; it does not make an appraisal one way or the other, but simply applies the foreign 7 rule as the appropriate one to determine this transaction. Nussbaum vehemently led the counterattack. He urged that "practic- ing liberalism becomes preposterous where it is exercised towards a foreign law which is plainly directed against the interests of the forum," and argued the consistency of the public policy doctrine with an inform- ing principle of American federalism-namely, "territorially limited experimentation."" Goodrich and others' seemed to get the better of the argument, at 3. See B. CURRIE, SELECTED ESSAYS ON THE CONFLICT OF LAws 212 n.88 (1963) (and sources cited) [hereinafter cited as CuamE]; cf. Pearson v. Northeast Airlines, Inc., 309 F.2d 553, 562 & n.17 (2d Cir. 1962). 4. See Fauntleroy v. Lum, 210 U.S. 230 (1908); Christmas v. Russell, 72 U.S. (5 Wall.) 290 (1866); Hampton v. M'Connel, 16 U.S. (3 Wheat.) 234 (1818); R. WEINTRAUB, COMMENTARY ON THE CONFLICT OF LAws 410-11 (1971). 5. Beach, Uniform Interstate Enforcement of Vested Rights, 27 YALE L.J. 656, 662 (1918). 6. Goodrich, Foreign Facts and Local Fancies,25 VA. L. REv.26, 35 (1938). 7. Id. at 33. But cf. CURIE 182. 8. Nussbaum, Public Policy and the Political Crisis in the Conflict of Laws, 49 YALE L.J. 1027, 1048-49, 1054 (1940). The impact on Nussbaum's position of the then-existing Fascist threat, it may be noted, is unmistakable. See also Kronstein, Crisis of "Conflict of Laws," 37 GEo. LI. 483 (1949). 9. See, e.g., Nutting, Suggested Limitations of the Public Policy Doctrine, 19 MINN. L. REv. 196 (1935). https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_lawreview/vol1974/iss3/1 Vol. 1974:391] PUBLIC POLICY DOCTRINE least in volume, with their indignant protests against parochialism. Some commentators, however, intimated that this umbrage might be fundamentally misguided. Courts invoke local public policy in choice of law, they argued, not so much out of dislike for the applicable foreign law but rather, in Cavers' terms, as a device to escape from the injustice or incongruity of applying the foreign law in a particular case.1" Because it provides an easy out from the result indicated by application of traditional rules, the public policy doctrine is objectionable as an escape from thoughtful articulation of better, more relevant conflict- of-law rules. With the development of Cavers' view in greater so- phistication and detail by Paulsen and Sovern," this conception of the doctrine appears to have relegated the more traditional criticisms of the public policy doctrine to the periphery, if not to total obscurity.12 Indeed, if the doctrine is only a guise-its invocation not really a state- ment on the content of the other jurisdiction's law at all-and its vice an invitation to unrigorous analysis, one would seem well advised to direct one's anger about parochialism elsewhere. The preemptive claim of the Paulsen-Sovem thesis, however, may not be as sound as is generally conceded. In this Article, I begin with the proposition that Professors Paulsen and Sovern have not wrested the field from the traditional critics. The parochialism argument against the public policy doctrine is one which can and should be made. It needs to be formulated, though, not in the metaphysical "right"- "wrong" terms in which Beach and his ideological brethren cast it, but instead contextually, in terms of the aggregate social consequences of the doctrine's employment. This Article attempts both to supplement and partly to supplant the Paulsen-Sovern contentions against the doc- trine by reinvigorating-or, perhaps more precisely, bringing to matur- ation-arguments directed at the doctrine's parochial tenor. I. THE LIMITATIONS OF THE PAULSEN-SOVERN PERSPECTIVE The contribution of the Paulsen-Sovern study to an understanding of 10. Cavers, A Critique of the Choice-of-Law Problem, 47 HARv. L. REv. 173, 180- 84 (1933). See also Note, The Public Policy Concept in the Conflict of Laws, 33 COLUM. L. REv. 508, 513 (1933). 11. Paulsen & Sovern, "Public Policy" in the Conflict of Laws, 56 CoLum. L. REv. 969 (1956) [hereinafter cited as Paulsen & Sovern]. 12. See E. CHnIAAM, E. GRiSWOLD, W. REESE & M. ROSENBERG, CONFLICT OF LAWS 403 (5th ed. 1964); R. CRAMToN & D. CURRIE, CONFLICT OF LAWS 146-47 (1968); CuiuuE 133 n.27, 181; Note, Illegality and Public Policy in the Conflict of Laws, 12 How. L.J. 331 (1966). Washington University Open Scholarship 394 WASMNGTON UNIVERSITY LAW QUARTERLY [Vol. 1974:391 the application of the public policy doctrine is of unquestionable sig- nificance. Writing in the best legal realist tradition,' 8 the authors pene- trated the courts' public explanations of their decision-making processes and set forth a view of the public policy doctrine attuned not to what courts say they are doing, but rather to what they are really doing: In short, "public policy" is one way to avoid the application of a choice of law rule which the forum wishes to avoid. The objection of the forum, thus, is not -to-the content of the law but to its own choice of law rule .... The overwhelming number of cases which have rejected foreign law on public policy grounds are cases with which the forum had some im- portant connection. It is apparent, then, that in most cases the choice of local rather than foreign law cannot be regarded simply as a matter of parochialism. 14 The attractiveness and basic plausibility of this thesis should not be allowed to obscure its limitations. For in two fundamental respects, one rooted in basic psychology and the other in the scope of the authors' focus on the social process, the, Paulsen-Sovern view fails to displace the "classical concept' 5 (as they disparagingly call it) of the public policy doctrine or to obviate the necessity for further development of the traditional criticisms.
Recommended publications
  • Application of the Theory of Dépeçage to Upstream Oil and Gas Contracts
    University of Calgary PRISM: University of Calgary's Digital Repository Graduate Studies The Vault: Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2018-03-29 Application of the Theory of Dépeçage to Upstream Oil and Gas Contracts Karimi, Sahar Karimi, S. (2018). Application of the Theory of Dépeçage to Upstream Oil and Gas Contracts (Unpublished master's thesis). University of Calgary, Calgary. AB. doi:10.11575/PRISM/31771 http://hdl.handle.net/1880/106483 master thesis University of Calgary graduate students retain copyright ownership and moral rights for their thesis. You may use this material in any way that is permitted by the Copyright Act or through licensing that has been assigned to the document. For uses that are not allowable under copyright legislation or licensing, you are required to seek permission. Downloaded from PRISM: https://prism.ucalgary.ca UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY Application of the Theory of Dépeçage to Upstream Oil and Gas Contracts by Sahar Karimi A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF LAWS GRADUATE PROGRAM IN LAW CALGARY, ALBERTA MARCH, 2018 © Sahar Karimi 2018 Abstract Determination of the applicable law in upstream oil and gas contracts plays an important role with regards to the parties’ rights and liabilities. There are various approaches regarding the choice of applicable law and different theories have been expressed relating to choice-of-law provisions. This research explores one of these theories called Dépeçage in private international law and conflict of law. The theory of Dépeçage is a concept in private international law that refers to the process of cutting a case into individual issues whereby each issue is constrained to a different applicable choice-of-law analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Lessons from the History of UK Science Policy
    Lessons from the History of UK Science Policy August 2019 2 Science Policy History Foreword The British Academy is the UK’s national body for the humanities and social sciences. Our purpose is to deepen understanding of people, societies and cultures, enabling everyone to learn, progress and prosper. The Academy inspires, supports and promotes outstanding achievement and global advances in the humanities and social sciences. We are a fellowship of over 1000 of the most outstanding academics, an international community of leading experts focused on people, culture and societies, and are the voice for the humanities and social sciences.1 The British Academy aims to use insights from the past and the present to help shape the future, by influencing policy and affecting change in the UK and overseas. Given this, the Academy is well-placed to bring humanities and social science insight from the past into policymaking for the present and the future. One way to do this is in using historical insights to inform policymaking – ‘looking back to look forward’. To support these efforts, the Academy’s public policy team in collaboration with the Department for Business, Energy and Industrial Strategy, has undertaken a new programme of work on policy histories. The policy histories series develop historical analyses for individual policy areas. These analyses are used to provide: • a structured, rigorous and objective account of the history of a given policy area and the significance of key milestones in context, • an informed basis for analysis and insights from the timelines as well as dialogue and discussion about what history can tell us about the future.
    [Show full text]
  • Science and Public Policy: What's Proof Got to Do With
    Environmental Science & Policy 7 (2004) 369–383 Science and public policy: what’s proof got to do with it? Naomi Oreskes Department of History and Science Studies Program, University of California, San Diego, 9500 Gilman Drive, La Jolla, CA 92093-0104, USA Abstract In recent years, it has become common for opponents of environmental action to argue that the scientific basis for purported harms is uncertain, unreliable, and fundamentally unproven. In response, many scientists believe that their job is to provide the “proof” that society needs. Both the complaint and the response are misguided. In all but the most trivial cases, science does not produce logically indisputable proofs about the natural world. At best it produces a robust consensus based on a process of inquiry that allows for continued scrutiny, re-examination, and revision. Within a scientific community, different individuals may weigh evidence differently and adhere to different standards of demonstration, and these differences are likely to be amplified when the results of inquiry have political, religious, or economic ramifications. In such cases, science can play a role by providing informed opinions about the possible consequences of our actions (or inactions), and by monitoring the effects of our choices. © 2004 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Keywords: Environmental policy; Science policy; Scientific proof; Uncertainty; Values; Politics; Lomborg 1. Introduction centive for manipulation and misrepresentation of informa- tion. This is particularly true in the domain of environmental The heart of Bjørn Lomborg’s recent critique of envi- policy. ronmentalism is that many assertions of the environmen- Lomborg assures us that everyone is for the environment— tal movement are unproven and therefore provide no good just as everyone is for world peace and against hunger—but grounds for sensible public policy.
    [Show full text]
  • Suggested Limitations of the Public Policy Doctrine Charles B
    University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Minnesota Law Review 1935 Suggested Limitations of the Public Policy Doctrine Charles B. Nutting Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Nutting, Charles B., "Suggested Limitations of the Public Policy Doctrine" (1935). Minnesota Law Review. 993. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr/993 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Minnesota Law Review collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MINNESOTA LAW REVIEW SUGGESTED LIMITATIONS OF THE PUBLIC POLICY DOCTRINE By CHARLES B. NUTTING* ECENT activity among writers in the field of the conflict of laws has revealed an awakened interest in the ever-vexing problem of determining the law applicable to situations in which the law of the forum differs from that of some other jurisdiction which may govern.' Apparently proceeding on the assumption that a court in such case is at liberty to select the law to be applied, varying suggestions have been made as to the criterion to be adopted. If the vested rights theory of conflicts is followed, much of this discussion becomes irrelevant, since under that theory there is, strictly speaking, no "choice" of law, one law and one alone being properly applicable in every case.- Whether this or some other theory embodies the true explanation of conflicts cases, we may leave to those who hurl thunderbolts about Olympus.' The writer, being sympathetically inclined toward the high church party in these matters, favors it for reasons which will appear hereafter.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Democratic Deliberation and Social Choice: a Review Christian List1
    1 Democratic Deliberation and Social Choice: A Review Christian List1 This version: June 2017 Forthcoming in the Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy 1. Introduction In normative political theory, it is widely accepted that democratic decision making cannot be reduced to voting alone, but that it requires reasoned and well-informed discussion by those involved in and/or subject to the decisions in question, under conditions of equality and respect. In short, democracy requires deliberation (e.g., Cohen 1989; Gutmann and Thompson 1996; Dryzek 2000; Fishkin 2009; Mansbridge et al. 2010). In formal political theory, by contrast, the study of democracy has focused less on deliberation, and more on the aggregation of individual preferences or opinions into collective decisions – social choices – typically through voting (e.g., Arrow 1951/1963; Riker 1982; Austen-Smith and Banks 2000, 2005; Mueller 2003). While the literature on deliberation has an optimistic flavour, the literature on social choice is more mixed. It is centred around several paradoxes and impossibility results showing that collective decision making cannot generally satisfy certain plausible desiderata. Any democratic aggregation rule that we use in practice seems, at best, a compromise. Initially, the two literatures were largely disconnected from each other. Since the 1990s, however, there has been a growing dialogue between them (e.g., Miller 1992; Knight and Johnson 1994; van Mill 1996; Dryzek and List 2003; Landa and Meirowitz 2009). This chapter reviews the connections between the two. Deliberative democratic theory is relevant to social choice theory in that deliberation can complement aggregation and open up an escape route from some of its negative results.
    [Show full text]
  • Electronic Democracy the World of Political Science— the Development of the Discipline
    Electronic Democracy The World of Political Science— The development of the discipline Book series edited by Michael Stein and John Trent Professors Michael B. Stein and John E. Trent are the co-editors of the book series “The World of Political Science”. The former is visiting professor of Political Science, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada and Emeritus Professor, McMaster University in Hamilton, Ontario, Canada. The latter is a Fellow in the Center of Governance of the University of Ottawa, in Ottawa, Ontario, Canada, and a former professor in its Department of Political Science. Norbert Kersting (ed.) Electronic Democracy Barbara Budrich Publishers Opladen • Berlin • Toronto 2012 An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libraries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high quality books Open Access for the public good. The Open Access ISBN for this book is 978-3-86649-546-3. More information about the initiative and links to the Open Access version can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org © 2012 This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0. (CC- BY-SA 4.0) It permits use, duplication, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you share under the same license, give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license and indicate if changes were made. To view a copy of this license, visit https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/ © 2012 Dieses Werk ist beim Verlag Barbara Budrich GmbH erschienen und steht unter der Creative Commons Lizenz Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International (CC BY-SA 4.0): https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/ Diese Lizenz erlaubt die Verbreitung, Speicherung, Vervielfältigung und Bearbeitung bei Verwendung der gleichen CC-BY-SA 4.0-Lizenz und unter Angabe der UrheberInnen, Rechte, Änderungen und verwendeten Lizenz.
    [Show full text]
  • Choice of Law in Complex Litigation
    CHOICE OF LAW IN COMPLEX LITIGATION LARRY KRAMER* Nearly all proceduralistsagree that all the claims in a complex case should be de. cided under a single substantive law or, at the very least, under a uniform choice-of- law rule In this paper, ProfessorKramer challenges the assumptions at the foun- dation of that consensus. In so doing, he confronts two myths of late-twentieth century procedure: that the sort of proceduralmaneuvers used to circumvent un- ambiguous Supreme Court precedents precluding federal courts from creating choice-of-law rules are legitimate;and that the unusualnature of complex litigation justifies such measures. ProfessorKramer exposes the fallacies underlying the first premisse then presents historicaland normative arguments against the second. He questions both the principle that the parties in complex litigationare similarly situ- ated with respect to the applicable law and the notion that adjudicatingsuch litiga- don under more than one law is unmanageable. Consensus is increasingly rare in today's legal world. Our profes- sion has grown so big and has such a wide assortment of groups repre- senting diverse interests that advocates are found on more than one side of almost any issue. This is especially true if the stakes are high, as in complex litigation. Few questions about how to handle these gigantic lawsuits are matters of general agreement. Choice of law is even worse, though not necessarily because the stakes are high. Con- flicts scholars just seem to like disagreement, and they have helped to confuse courts and make a mess of choice-of-law analysis. All things considered, then, it's surprising to find even partial consensus on choice of law in complex litigation.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy, Politics, and Economics
    Where Can PPE Take You? By facilitating a multidisciplinary approach to practical problems, the PPE major offers a liberal arts education that prepares students for leadership roles in a variety of fields. The major prepares students for careers in public policy and business. It is a good preparation for law school and for a variety of graduate programs in the humanities and social sciences. Moreover, it helps students become PHILOSOPHY, informed and engaged citizens. POLITICS, AND ECONOMICS For more information contact: Professor Frank Howland [email protected] wabash.edu About the Major Courses Offered Philosophy, Politics, and Economics (PPE) majors learn to Common PPE Requirements: Economics Courses: investigate the social phenomena that philosophy, political PPE-200: Introduction to PPE PPE-251: Law and Economics science, and economics address from different perspectives. (every spring) PPE-252: Public Policy Philosophy fosters clear and creative thinking, ethical PPE-400: Senior Seminar PPE-254: Environmental Economics reflection, and the capacity to interrogate received opinion. (every fall) Political science offers both theoretical and empirical PPE-255: Health Economics approaches to studying governing institutions and political relationships. PPE-256: The Global Economy Philosophy Courses: By studying economics, students learn to analyze the role of incentives, PPE-264: Development Economics PPE-213: Philosophy of Law markets, and governments in the allocation of scarce resources and PPE-265: History of Economic Thought distribution
    [Show full text]
  • Conflicts Basics: CHOICE of LAW and MULTISTATE JUSTICE by Friedrich K. Juenger
    Catholic University Law Review Volume 44 Issue 2 Winter 1995 Article 4 1995 Back to Conflicts Basics: CHOICE OF LAW AND MULTISTATE JUSTICE by Friedrich K. Juenger Stanley E. Cox Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.edu/lawreview Recommended Citation Stanley E. Cox, Back to Conflicts Basics: CHOICE OF LAW AND MULTISTATE JUSTICE by Friedrich K. Juenger, 44 Cath. U. L. Rev. 525 (1995). Available at: https://scholarship.law.edu/lawreview/vol44/iss2/4 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by CUA Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Catholic University Law Review by an authorized editor of CUA Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW Back to Conflicts Basics: CHOICE OF LAW AND MULTISTATE JUSTICE by Friedrich K. Juenger Reviewed by Stanley E. Cox* Chief Justice Stone is reported to have said that the study of conflict of laws is a good substitute for a more formal course on legal jurisprudence.' Conflicts theories, among other things, at their heart address issues of how "true" laws are, how much respect governments should give to other sovereigns or to private agreements, and what role the judiciary should play as lawmaker or law interpreter. Discussions about how to choose law are in essence discussions about what constitutes justice. A good book on conflicts should provoke foundational thinking about such issues and other basics of the conflicts discipline. Choice of Law and Multistate Justice2 does. I. A QUICK OVERVIEW Professor Juenger's thesis is that the only sensible choice-of-law theory is to apply the best substantive law to interstate and international dis- putes.3 Whether one agrees or disagrees with this thesis, it is refreshing to read a conflicts monograph that argues consistently at the foundational level and pursues its thesis from introduction to conclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Policy Priorities
    THE SOUTHERN EDUCATION FOUNDATION’S Public Policy Priorities www.SouthernEducation.org THE SOUTHERN EDUCATION FOUNDATION’S Public Policy Priorities ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The Southern Education Foundation (SEF) would like to thank Center for Community Organizing and Engagement at New York University, Communities for Just Schools, Education Counsel, the Learning Policy Institute, and SEF’s Racial Equity Leadership Network Fellows for offering thoughtful feedback and advice in preparation of this document. We appreciate your willingness to share your time and insights as we developed a comprehensive set of policy priorities for policymakers, community advocates, and families. This would not have been possible without your valuable input and feedback. Thank you once again. © 2019 Southern Education Foundation, Inc., Atlanta, Georgia. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America. Portions of this work may be reproduced without permission, provided that acknowledgement is fully given to the Southern Education Foundation. Limited permission is also granted for larger portions to be reproduced by nonprofit and public agencies and institutions only, solely for non-commercial purposes so long as full acknowledgement to the Southern Education Foundation as the source is prominently given. Reproduction or storage in any electronic form for any commercial purpose is prohibited without the express written permission of the Southern Education Foundation. SOUTHERN EDUCATION FOUNDATION 2 TABLE OF CONTENTS Foreword.…………………….............................…………………………….....................
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 8: Economics, Economists and Public Policy in Australia
    Economics, economists and public policy in Australia* The topic for the 2011 Symposium, ‘Does Australian public policy get the economics it deserves?’ has been partitioned into two questions. One asks ‘whether public policy gets the economics it needs?’ The other, no doubt inspired by Alexis de Tocqueville’s famous observation about people and their elected governments, is ‘whether Australian economics gets the public policy it deserves’. My answer to the first question came readily: in short, no — or at least not often. The answer to the de Tocquevillian one required reflection, however, not only about the state of public policy in Australia, but also about that of Australian economics. And my answer to that one is: I’m not sure! Much could be said from both perspectives. In setting the scene, I will confine myself to some observations about what might be called the ‘contextual’ influences on public policy and its use of economics (or information generally). My key message, which should not be surprising, is that systems determine outcomes. Public policy will only get the economics it needs, or indeed that society needs, if the processes, the institutions and the individuals responsible for developing it are receptive to good economics, and responsive to it. Equally, I’d argue that how ‘deserving’ Australian economics or economists might be — in other words, the health of the supply-side — is not independent of the incentives generated by the policy system — the demand side. What sort of ‘economics’? Now the term ‘needs’ might suggest that it is challenging to discover and apply this necessary economics.
    [Show full text]
  • DFID Policy Approach to Rule Of
    Rule of Law policy approach, final version: 12 July 2013 Policy Approach to Rule of Law What I call the building blocks of democracy (are) the independence of the judiciary and the rule of law, the rights of individuals, a free media, free association, a proper place in society for the army, strong political parties and a proper, rich civil society. These things together make up a golden thread that can be found woven through successful countries and sustainable economies all over the world (Prime Minister David Cameron, 2012) Contents Executive summary ..........................................................................................................................2 1. Introduction ...................................................................................................................................3 2. What is the rule of law? ...............................................................................................................4 3. Why is the rule of law important for poverty reduction? ...........................................................7 4. How are international partners supporting the rule of law? ......................................................9 5. How are HMG and DFID supporting the rule of law? ............................................................. 12 6. A renewed approach to the rule of law .................................................................................... 17 Annex 1: Country contexts and rule of law: examples of features, priorities and illustrative areas of
    [Show full text]