Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy the Elves, Rivendell, for Example)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy the Elves, Rivendell, for Example) pdf version of the entry Fictional Entities https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/fictional-entities/ Fictional Entities from the Fall 2018 Edition of the First published Thu Jul 26, 2018 Stanford Encyclopedia Philosophical issues surrounding fiction have attracted increasing attention from philosophers over the past few decades. What follows is a discussion of Philosophy of one familiar and quite fundamental topic in this area: fictional entities (both the issue of what such entities might be like and whether there really are such entities). A familiar characteristic of works of fiction is that they feature fictional characters: individuals whose exploits are written about in works of fiction Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen R. Lanier Anderson Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor and who make their first appearance in a work of fiction. Shakespeare’s Editorial Board Hamlet, for example, features the fictional character Hamlet, Doyle’s The https://plato.stanford.edu/board.html Hound of the Baskervilles features Sherlock Holmes, Tolstoy’s Anna Library of Congress Catalog Data Karenina features Anna Karenina, and so on. All of these works feature ISSN: 1095-5054 numerous other fictional characters, of course (Ophelia and Dr Watson, for example); indeed, some works of fiction are characterized by the sheer Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem- abundance of their characters (Russian novels are often said to have this bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized characteristic). Fictional characters belong to the class of entities variously distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the known as fictional entities or fictional objects or ficta, a class that includes SEP Society and obtain authorized PDF versions of SEP entries, not just animate objects of fiction (fictional persons, animals, monsters, please visit https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/ . and so on) but also inanimate objects of fiction such as fictional places (Anthony Trollope’s cathedral town of Barchester and Tolkien’s home of Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy the elves, Rivendell, for example). As stated, however, it doesn’t include Copyright c 2018 by the publisher The Metaphysics Research Lab entities located in the real world, although real entities do have an DRAFTCenter for the Study of Language and Information important role to play in works of fiction. Thus, neither London nor Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305 Napoleon are fictional entities, although the first is the quite essential Fictional Entities Copyright c 2018 by the authors backdrop to what goes on in the Holmes stories while the second plays an Fred Kroon and Alberto Voltolini important role in the events described in War and Peace. (While London All rights reserved. and Napoleon are not fictional entities, some have thought that the London Copyright policy: https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/info/copyright/ of the Holmes stories and the Napoleon of War and Peace should be 1 View metadata,citationandsimilarpapersatcore.ac.uk provided by Institutional ResearchInformationSystemUniversityofTurin brought toyouby CORE Fictional Entities Fred Kroon and Alberto Voltolini classed as special fictional entities. This view has recently gained some Academic Tools popularity: cf. Landini 1990, Bonomi 2008, Voltolini 2006, 2013, Other Internet Resources Motoarca 2014.) Related Entries The above characterization suggests that fictional entities constitute a special type of entity. Not surprisingly, then, one fundamental 1. The Metaphysics of Fictional Entities philosophical question we can ask about fictional entities is a question about their nature: what kind of thing is a fictional entity? This question is As Thomasson (1999: 5) puts it, the first question amounts to asking: what separate from what seems an even more fundamental question: why would fictional entities be, if there were any? To this question different suppose that there are any fictional entities in the first place? After all, our answers have been proposed. But however much they differ, they all try to world never contained a Sherlock Holmes or a Rivendell—these alleged accommodate in some way or other what seems to be an intuitive datum entities make their appearance in works of fiction, not works of fact. facing philosophers who theorize about fictional entities: these entities Following the division in Thomasson 1999, we shall call the first question lack existence, or at least existence as ordinary physical objects. the metaphysical question, and the second the ontological question. According to this datum—call it the nonexistence datum—paradigmatic objects of fiction like Hamlet and Holmes do not exist. In support of this 1. The Metaphysics of Fictional Entities datum, note that the layperson would almost certainly answer “No” to the 1.1 Possibilism question of whether such objects exist, although she might qualify this 1.2 Meinong and Neo-Meinongianism answer by adding “there is at least some sense in which they don’t.” We 1.2.1 Meinong’s theory of objects also appeal to nonexistence in this sense when we want to dispute the view 1.2.2 Orthodox and unorthodox neo-Meinongianism that some alleged individual is a genuine historical figure; we might say, 1.2.3 Two kinds of properties vs. two modes of predication for example, that King Arthur does not exist, thereby underlining our view 1.3 Creationism that a search for a historical King Arthur would be in vain. 2. The Ontology of Fictional Entities 2.1 Semantical Arguments for and Against Realism Those who do not believe that there are any fictional entities (fictional 2.1.1 Russell’s anti-realism antirealists, as we shall call them) will claim that the nonexistence datum 2.1.2 Metafictional sentences and “in the fiction” operators has an ontological reading only: to say that fictional entities do not exist 2.1.3 The descriptivist problem for theories of fictional amounts to saying that in the overall domain of what there is there are no names such things as fictional entities. As they see it, fictional realists (those who 2.1.4 Pretense Theory do believe that there are fictional entities) are the only ones to give the 2.1.5 Quantificational arguments for realism datum a certain metaphysical reading, namely that fictional entities have 2.2 Ontological Arguments for and Against Realism the property of not existing (in some sense or other). They might also Bibliography insist that fictional realists are the only ones to think that the nonexistence 2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2018 Edition 3 Fictional Entities Fred Kroon and Alberto Voltolini of fictional entities is determined by their nature as fictional entities. But 1.1 Possibilism this overstates the case. Because they hold that there are no such things as fictional entities, even antirealists are likely to admit that the fact that there One way to account for the nonexistence datum is the possibilist theory of is no such thing as some alleged entity X follows from the fact that X has fictional entities, which holds that fictional entities do not exist in the been shown to be fictional. That is what happened in the case of King actual world but only in some other possible worlds. In this respect, Arthur and many other legendary or mythological entities (fictional fictional entities are thought to be like other merely possible entities such entities in the broad sense). People originally supposed (cf. Geoffrey of as talking donkeys. According to standard versions of the possible worlds Monmouth’s Historia Regum Britanniae) that King Arthur was a real framework, some things not present at the actual world exist as talking person, a British leader who ruled England after the departure of the donkeys at some merely possible worlds. Similarly, the possibilist theory Romans, until it was discovered that King Arthur is merely a figure of holds that Sherlock Holmes does not exist in the actual world, although he legend, a fictional entity. It was this discovery that licensed the conclusion does exist at some merely possible worlds: worlds in which the Holmes that King Arthur doesn’t exist. So it seems that even antirealists have a stories are fact. stake in the answer to the metaphysical question “What would it take for Such a possibilist theory is faced with a problem of ontological something to be a fictional entity?” indeterminacy. For there is more than one possible world in which Conan One further comment about the nonexistence datum before we turn to Doyle’s Holmes stories are fact, and in which there is a witty, cocaine- various accounts of fictional objects and the ways in which such accounts addicted detective called “Holmes” who lives at 221B Baker St., has a cope with the datum. As we have already seen, it is natural when friend called “Watson”, and does the things recorded of him in the Holmes discussing the datum to use quantifiers such as “Some things are …” stories. Not all of these Holmes-candidates are the same; while they all (“There are things that are …”), and “Everything is…”, whose domain match each other in terms of what the stories say about Holmes, they may appears to include both existent and nonexistent objects. We do so when be very different in other crucial ways—they may have had very different we say, for example, that there are objects, such as fictional objects, that childhoods, including different parents, and so on. (Indeed, when don’t exist. Fictional antirealists will take such talk with a grain of salt, characters are underdescribed in a story, a single possible world may since they do not acknowledge a sense in which there really are any contain many individuals who fit exactly what the story says about the fictional objects.
Recommended publications
  • Existence As a Real Property
    Francesco Berto Existence as a Real Property The Ontology of Meinongianism For Graham Priest, Long-distance teacher Prologue: Much Ado About Nothing Some philosophers think that something’s having intuitive content is very inconclusive evidence in favor of it. I think it is very heavy evidence in favor of anything, myself. I really don’t know, in a way, what more conclusive evidence one can have about anything, ultimately speaking. –Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity 1 In an episode of The Today Show of some years ago, Gene Shalit – NBC’s film and book critic, famous for his wits – reviews several books sharing the feature of bearing entertaining titles. The highpoint of the monologue comes with Nonexistent Objects, by the UCLA philosopher Terence Parsons. Shalit wonders how one could write a whole book on things that do not exist!1 This whole book, too, is about things that do not exist. But if one stops to think, one may find that, in a sense, there is nothing special about this. There are, in fact, thousands of books speaking about unreal things. You have probably read quite a few of them: Sir Arthur Conan Doyle’s stories portrait the adventures of the detective Sherlock Holmes; The Lord of the Rings speaks at length of Gandalf the wizard. Doyle represents Sherlock Holmes as a detective living in London, Baker Street (precisely, at number 221b), describes his remarkable observational and deductive abilities, makes of him the arch-enemy of the criminal mastermind Moriarty. J.R.R. Tolkien characterizes Gandalf as a wizard with a pointy hat and a grey robe (a white one, from a certain point of the story onwards), a heavy pipe-herb 1 The anecdote is reported by Roy Sorensen [2003], p.
    [Show full text]
  • Truths Containing Empty Names Michael Mckinsey
    In Philosophical Approaches to Proper Names, P. Stalmaszczyk and L. Fernández Moreno (eds.).Peter Lang, 2016. Truths Containing Empty Names Michael McKinsey 1. A problem for direct reference. According to the thesis of Direct Reference (or the DR-thesis for short), the propositions expressed by sentences containing the proper names and indexical pronouns of natural language are a strict function of the semantic referents of the names and indexicals, as opposed to being a function of any Fregean descriptive senses or contents that the names and indexicals might be alleged to possess.1 Another way of expressing this idea is to say that the sole semantic contribution that a proper name or indexical can make to the propositions expressed by sentences containing the term is the term’s semantic referent. Bertrand Russell called terms of this sort ‘names in the logical sense’ (1918, 201). I will call them ‘genuine terms’. Following standard practice, I will call the propositions expressed by sentences containing genuine terms, ‘singular propositions’. Like many others, I endorse the DR-thesis. In my case, the primary reason for endorsing the thesis lies in the modal considerations first briefly introduced by John Searle (1958) and later clarified and forcefully applied by Saul Kripke (1972a), considerations which show that proper names do not have the meanings of contingent definite descriptions. David Kaplan (1989) raised related points to support the conclusion that indexical pronouns are also genuine terms. In recent work I have argued at some length that the DR-thesis entails both that (a) a sentence containing a non-referring name or indexical can express no proposition, and hence that (b) such sentences can have no truth value, that is, can be neither true or false.
    [Show full text]
  • Recovering What Is Said with Empty Names 239 Volume 40, Number 2, June 2010, Pp
    CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHYRecovering What Is Said With Empty Names 239 Volume 40, Number 2, June 2010, pp. 239-274 Recovering What Is Said With Empty Names1 GUALTIERO PICCININI University of Missouri – St. Louis St. Louis, MO 63132 USA and SAM SCOTT Toronto, ON M6K 3B2 CANADA I Introduction As our data will show, negative existential sentences containing so- called empty names evoke the same strong semantic intuitions in ordi- nary speakers and philosophers alike. 1 Many thanks to Fred Adams, Kent Bach, Anthony Everett, Mitchell Green, Thomas Hofweber, Stephen McLeod, Phillip Robbins, Rob Stainton, Nicole Wyatt, and sev- eral anonymous referees for comments on previous versions of this paper, to Brett Hyde and other members of the Semantics Reading Group at Washington Univer- sity in St. Louis, to the audience — especially Kit Fine — at the 2008 Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association, and to Jim Virtel for editorial assistance. Gualtiero Piccinini gratefully acknowledges support from the Center for International Studies at the University of Missouri – St Louis. 240 Gualtiero Piccinini and Sam Scott (1) (a) Santa Claus does not exist. (b) Superman does not exist. (c) Clark Kent does not exist. Uttering the sentences in (1) seems to say something truth-evaluable, to say something true, and to say something different for each sentence. A semantic theory ought to explain these semantic intuitions. The intuitions elicited by (1) are in apparent confl ict with the Mil- lian view of proper names. According to Millianism, the meaning (or ‘semantic value’) of a proper name is just its referent.
    [Show full text]
  • Sylvan's Bottle and Other Problems
    Australasian Journal of Logic Sylvan’s Bottle and other problems Diane Proudfoot University of Canterbury New Zealand Abstract According to Richard Routley, a comprehensive theory of fiction is impossible, since almost anything is in principle imaginable. In my view, Routley is right: for any purported logic of fiction, there will be actual or imaginable fictions that successfully counterexample the logic. Using the example of ‘impossible’ fictions, I test this claim against theories proposed by Routley’s Meinongian contemporaries and also by Routley himself (for what he called ‘esoteric’ works of fiction) and his 21st century heirs. I argue that the phenomenon of impossible fictions challenges even today’s modal Meinongians. 1 Routley’s rules for the semantics of fiction According to Richard Routley, ‘any properly comprehensive theory of objects ... is obliged to supply a theory of fictions’ (1980, p. 538). Nevertheless, fictions, he said, ‘provide a severe testing ground for logical and semantical theories’ and ‘have regularly revealed serious weaknesses in each new theory proposed’ (ibid., p. 537). The severity of the test is due to certain characteristics of fiction noted by Routley, which I shall formulate as a set of three rules: R1. ‘[T]he author of a work of fiction can try to set down whatever he imagines; and the free range of imagination is virtually unlimited.’ ‘[An author has the] freedom to create whatever he will within the bounds of his art’ (Routley 1979, pp. 6, 8) R2. ‘[T]here are fictional worlds in which any given logical truth (or theorem) fails to hold or is violated.’ (ibid., p.
    [Show full text]
  • Synthese Library
    Synthese Library Studies in Epistemology, Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science Volume 415 Editor-in-Chief Otávio Bueno, University of Miami, Department of Philosophy, USA Editors Berit Brogaard, University of Miami, USA Anjan Chakravartty, University of Notre Dame, USA Steven French, University of Leeds, UK Catarina Dutilh Novaes, VU Amsterdam, The Netherlands The aim of Synthese Library is to provide a forum for the best current work in the methodology and philosophy of science and in epistemology. A wide variety of different approaches have traditionally been represented in the Library, and every effort is made to maintain this variety, not for its own sake, but because we believe that there are many fruitful and illuminating approaches to the philosophy of science and related disciplines. Special attention is paid to methodological studies which illustrate the interplay of empirical and philosophical viewpoints and to contributions to the formal (logical, set-theoretical, mathematical, information-theoretical, decision-theoretical, etc.) methodology of empirical sciences. Likewise, the applications of logical methods to epistemology as well as philosophically and methodologically relevant studies in logic are strongly encouraged. The emphasis on logic will be tempered by interest in the psychological, historical, and sociological aspects of science. Besides monographs Synthese Library publishes thematically unified anthologies and edited volumes with a well-defined topical focus inside the aim and scope of the book series. The contributions in the volumes are expected to be focused and structurally organized in accordance with the central theme(s), and should be tied together by an extensive editorial introduction or set of introductions if the volume is divided into parts.
    [Show full text]
  • Impossible Worlds OUP.Pdf (1.475Mb)
    Impossible Worlds Impossible Worlds Francesco Berto and Mark Jago 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Francesco Berto and Mark Jago 2019 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2019 Impression: 1 Some rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, for commercial purposes, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. This is an open access publication, available online and distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution – Non Commercial – No Derivatives 4.0 International licence (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0), a copy of which is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of this licence should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2019936333 ISBN 978–0–19–881279–1 Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Mechanizing Principia Logico-Metaphysica in Functional Type Theory
    D. Kirchner, C. Benzmüller, and E. Zalta 2 system Isabelle/HOL. Initial experiments within this framework reveal a crucial but overlooked fact: a deeply-rooted and known paradox is reintroduced in AOT when the logic of complex terms is simply adjoined to AOT’s specially formulated comprehension Mechanizing Principia Logico-Metaphysica principle for relations. This result constitutes a new and impor- ∗ tant paradox, given how much expressive and analytic power is in Functional Type Theory contributed by having the two kinds of complex terms in the sys- tem. Its discovery is the highlight of our joint project and provides Daniel Kirchner strong evidence for a new kind of scientific practice in philosophy, Fachbereich Mathematik und Informatik namely, computational metaphysics. Our results were made technically possible by a suitable adap- Freie Universität Berlin tation of Benzmüller’s metalogical approach to universal reason- [email protected] ing by semantically embedding theories in classical higher-order logic. This approach enables one to reuse state-of-the-art higher- Christoph Benzmüller order proof assistants, such as Isabelle/HOL, for mechanizing and Fachbereich Mathematik und Informatik experimentally exploring challenging logics and theories such as Freie Universität Berlin AOT. Our results also provide a fresh perspective on the question [email protected] of whether relational type theory or functional type theory better serves as a foundation for logic and metaphysics. & Computer Science and Communications University of Luxembourg [email protected] 1 Abstract Summary Edward N. Zalta Principia Logico-Metaphysica (PLM) [16] is an online research monograph Center for the Study of Language and Information that contains a canonical presentation of Abstract Object Theory (AOT) arXiv:1711.06542v4 [cs.LO] 24 Jul 2019 Stanford University [17], [18], along with motivation for, and commentary on, the theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Existence, Noneism, and the Varieties of Worlds by Carolyn Garland B.A
    Existence, Noneism, and the varieties of worlds by Carolyn Garland B.A., University of Manitoba, 2012 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Philosophy © Carolyn Garland, 2014 University of Victoria All rights reserved. This thesis may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without the permission of the author. ii Supervisory Committee Existence, Noneism, and the varieties of worlds by Carolyn Garland B.A., University of Manitoba, 2012 Supervisory Committee Dr. Mike Raven (Department of Philosophy) Co-Supervisor Dr. Audrey Yap (Department of Philosophy) Co-Supervisor iii Abstract Supervisory Committee Dr. Mike Raven (Department of Philosophy) Co-Supervisor Dr. Audrey Yap (Department of Philosophy) Co-Supervisor Intentionality is a feature of mental states that are directed towards objects. One puzzle of intentionality is that mental states can be directed towards nonexistent objects. We may relate to fictional characters, or worry about events that never take place. However, if these objects do not exist, then it is difficult to make sense of how it is that we bear these relations towards them. In this thesis I outline Graham Priest’s world-based semantic and metaphysical theory of intentionality intended to accommodate these intentional relations born towards nonexistent objects. Priest supposes that this theory is compatible with any conception of worlds. I argue that this is not the case. Within Priest’s framework merely possible worlds should be understood as existent genuine worlds, and impossible worlds can be neither existent genuine worlds, nor should they be conceived of as nonexistent objects.
    [Show full text]
  • A Referential Analysis of Fictional Names
    A Referential Analysis of Fictional Names by Dylan Hurry A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario ©2016 Dylan Hurry Abstract Do fictional names refer to fictional characters? Realists argue they do, while anti-realists argue they do not. According to referentialism, a proper name contributes its referent to the singular proposition expressed by sentences of which the name is a constituent. Furthermore, referentialists argue that the mechanism via which a name means its bearer is best understood as a causal-historical chain of which subsequent uses of the name are parasitic on some initial use (or baptism). For the anti-realist, fictional names present a problem for referentialism as many sentences, such as “Peter Pan was created by J. M. Barrie," seem to refer and express true singular propositions. However, for realists, such sentences are congruent with a referential theory of naming. I will examine two realist accounts in detail, Meinongianism and artifactualism, and argue that artifactualism is the more likely candidate for a realist referential theory concerning fictional names. !ii Acknowledgements I would like to begin by thanking my thesis supervisor, Eros Corazza, for his useful comments on various drafts of this thesis. I would also like to thank him for his continued emphasis that the “devil is in the detail” when it comes to philosophizing. Furthermore, I wish to thank him for his engaging seminars on various problems in the philosophy of language. They have made me realize that the field is where I feel most at home philosophically.
    [Show full text]
  • 3.5 Priest's Dialetheism
    n Young, Gareth (2015) Revenge: dialetheism and its expressive limitations. PhD thesis. http://theses.gla.ac.uk/6415/ Copyright and moral rights for this thesis are retained by the author A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the Author The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the Author When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given Glasgow Theses Service http://theses.gla.ac.uk/ [email protected] Revenge: Dialetheism and its Expressive Limitations Gareth Young MA, Mlitt Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Ph.D. Philosophy School of Humanities University of Glasgow September 2014 2 3 Abstract This thesis is about dialetheism and the problem of revenge. More broadly, it is about truth and what the logical paradoxes tell us about the logical behaviour of truth. One of the driving forces behind the contemporary study of truth and paradox is the problem of revenge: that many, perhaps all, available theories of truth, give rise to further paradoxes, invoking central notions of those theories, which demonstrate that the theory cannot express those notions. This sort of expressive limitation, especially if it involves the very notion invoked to diagnose what goes wrong in paradoxical sentences, would normally be thought a decisive point against a given theory of the paradoxes, were it not for the fact that the problem is so pervasive that every currently available theory has, at some point, been argued to suffer from it.
    [Show full text]
  • DIRECT REFERENCE and EMPTY NAMES By
    DIRECT REFERENCE AND EMPTY NAMES by BENJAMIN K. COOK A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Honors in the Major Program in Philosophy in the College of Humanities and in the Burnett Honors College at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Summer Term 2013 Thesis Chair: Donald Jones ABSTRACT: The purpose of my thesis is to explore and assess recent efforts by Direct Reference Theorists to explain the phenomenon of empty names. Direct Reference theory is, roughly, the theory that the meaning of a singular term (proper name, demonstrative, etc.) is simply its referent. Certain sentences, such as negative existentials (“Santa does not exist”), and sentences in contexts of fiction (“Holmes lived on Baker Street”), present the following challenge to DR Theory: Given that the semantic value of a name is simply its referent, how are we to explain the significance and truth-evaluability of such sentences? There have been various approaches DR Theorists have taken to address this problem, including the Pragmatic Strategy, Pretense Theory, Abstract Object Theory, and the Metalinguistic Strategy. All of these views are analyzed and assessed according to their various strengths and weaknesses. It is concluded that, overall, a Metalinguistic Strategy, supplemented by the notion of pretense, best deals with negative existentials and normal-subject predicate occurrences of empty names, Abstract Object Theory best deals with empty names in meta-fictional contexts, and Pretense Theory best deals with empty names in object-fictional contexts. i For my Bapa ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I’d like to first acknowledge and thank all my philosophical and intellectual peers at UCF.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reference and Content of Proper Names: a Social and Pragmatic Approach
    THE REFERENCE AND CONTENT OF PROPER NAMES: A SOCIAL AND PRAGMATIC APPROACH DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Yimin Kui, M.A. The Ohio State University 2005 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Joseph Levine, Adviser Professor Louise Antony Professor Robert Kraut ____________________________ Adviser Graduate Program in Philosophy ABSTRACT The goal of my dissertation is to propose and defend a unified account of the semantic content of proper names that can address all the following six problems facing various theories of proper names: The Modal Argument, the Epistemic Argument, the Semantic Argument, Frege’s Puzzle, Belief Puzzles, and Empty Names. I first defend a theory of reference concerning proper names. I argue that for every proper name, there is a structured web of community uses associated with it. Among the objects involved in the Kripkean causal network of the name, the object that stands out as the dominant bearer of the web of community uses is the referent of the name. Roughly, an object becomes the dominant bearer of the web of uses, if it either satisfies or causes the weighted most of the properties/uses in the web. Secondly, I examine Nathan Salmon’s and Scott Soames’s defenses of the direct reference theory. For their strategies to succeed, they need the assumption that all the properties/beliefs (or at least the specific ones) in the web of community uses of a name are pragmatically imparted information and thus semantically irrelevant information.
    [Show full text]