Jessica Pepp Dissertation Final Draft

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Jessica Pepp Dissertation Final Draft UCLA UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Locating Semantic Reference Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3z15t80z Author Pepp, Jessica Alden Publication Date 2012 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Locating Semantic Reference A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Jessica Pepp 2012 ⓒ Copyright by Jessica Pepp 2012 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Locating Semantic Reference by Jessica Pepp Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Los Angeles, 2012 Professor Joseph Almog, Chair The dissertation studies a question of longstanding interest in the philosophy of language, which I call the “Reference Determination Question.” The question is: what determines that a linguistic expression (such as a name, indexical, demonstrative, or description) refers to a particular thing? In one way or another, the question seeks a reduction of reference in terms of other features of speakers, words, and the things to which they refer. Until the work of Saul Kripke and Keith Donnellan in the 1960s and 1970s, such a reduction seemed available. According to what I call the “Condition View,” the reference of a linguistic expression is whatever, if anything, uniquely satisfies the conditions that the user of the expression associates with it. I show how this view fits within a broader picture of language, which I call the “Capture Picture.” The Capture Picture envisions linguistic reference as a speaker’s reaching out from her interior experience to capture a particular thing in the world outside that experience. Kripke’s and Donnellan’s criticisms of the Condition View led to its widespread rejection, but not, I argue, to radical revision of the Capture Picture. I press the same form of argument that they ii employed against the Condition View against replacements for it that remain within the Capture Picture. I suggest that this expansion of the Kripke-Donnellan critique has not been pursued because of Kripke’s influential distinction between “speaker’s reference” and “semantic reference,” and I explain why this distinction does not in fact track a substantive difference, and does not block my arguments. My criticism of alternative views within the Capture Picture reveals a parallel between linguistic reference and sensory perception: both are ways of experiencing things that are present in one’s sensory or cognitive environment. I defend this parallel, and show how it makes available a replacement for the Capture Picture that I call “Referential Direct Realism.” Referential Direct Realism is the counterpart, for referential experience, of the position usually called “Direct Realism” or “Naïve Realism” about perceptual experience. It holds that linguistic referring experience is direct cognitive contact with the objects to which one refers. On this view of linguistic referring experience, the Reference Determination Question does not arise. For there is no gulf to be bridged between what is inside the speaker’s experience (the linguistic expression) and what is outside (the object). I argue for Referential Direct Realism and show how it points the philosophical study of linguistic reference, and language in general, in a different direction from those that traditionally have been followed. iii The dissertation of Jessica Pepp is approved. David B. Kaplan Donald A. Martin Howard Wettstein Edward L. Keenan Joseph Almog, Committee Chair University of California, Los Angeles 2012 iv Dedicated to the memories of my grandmothers, Bertha Pepp and Rose Alden. v TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ix VITA x INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER ONE: PICTURING THE REFERENCE OF PROPER NAMES 11 1.1 Introduction 11 1.2 The Reference Determination Question 12 1.3 Levels of inquiry: theory versus picture 15 1.4 The Capture Picture 20 1.5 The Condition View 21 1.6 Empirical counterexamples to the Condition View 25 1.7 Hard cases, bad law? 27 1.8 Challenging the Capture Picture 31 1.9 An alternative picture? 33 1.9.1 The Capture-and-Save Picture: a conservative revision 34 1.9.2 A more radical revision? 38 CHAPTER TWO: TOWARD A MORE RADICAL REVISION OF THE PICTURE OF PROPER NAME REFERENCE 43 2.1 Introduction 43 2.2 Pictures and views 44 2.3 A pattern of argument 48 2.4 Counterexamples to the Baptism View and the File View 50 2.5 Speaker’s reference and semantic reference 55 2.6 Donnellan’s referential-attributive distinction 58 2.7 Fitting Donnellan’s argument into the pattern 64 2.8 Kripke’s response to Donnellan questioned 68 vi 2.9 Inadequacy of the Save Picture 71 Conclusion 74 CHAPTER THREE: WHAT TO MAKE OF THE REFERENCE DETERMINATION QUESTION? 76 3.1 Introduction 76 3.2 The aim of the Reference Determination Question 78 3.3 A parallel with perception 82 3.4 A stronger parallel between reference and perception 88 3.5 Defending the parallel between reference and perception 89 3.6 Referring is experiencing 98 Conclusion 105 CHAPTER FOUR: REFERENTIAL DIRECT REALISM AND THE FOCUS PICTURE OF LINGUISTIC REFERENCE 107 4.1 Introduction 107 4.2 Motivating Referential Direct Realism 108 4.3 The Picture 116 4.3.1 Picture vs. theory, again 116 4.3.2 Review of views 117 4.3.3 The Focus Picture 119 4.4 Three levels of the analogy with perception 121 4.4.1 Perception and having in mind 121 4.4.2 Vision (as an example) and language 123 4.4.3 Lenses and names 129 4.5 Communication of reference 135 4.5.1 Communicative experience: the transmission of having-in-mind 136 4.5.2 Transmission and names 140 Conclusion 149 vii CHAPTER FIVE: PROBLEMS OF REFERRING EXPERIENCE 150 5.1 Introduction 150 5.2 Reference failure and information loss 151 5.3 The problem of perceptual experience 158 5.4 The problem of referential experience 166 5.5 Referential Direct Realism, direct reference, and reference puzzles 168 5.5.1 Frege’s puzzle of informative identity statements 170 5.5.2 Significant statements involving reference failure 173 Conclusion 175 CONCLUSION 176 BIBLIOGRAPHY 182 viii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This dissertation has benefited from the insight and diligence of many teachers and colleagues. I wish to thank the members of my dissertation committee for their support and for comments and advice that have deepened and improved this work. It has been a great privilege to learn from David Kaplan, without whom the entire field in which my own work is situated would not exist in its present form. I am grateful to Howard Wettstein for his open-mindedness in pursuing and helping to develop ideas that are far from his sympathies. Tony Martin taught me the logic that got me interested in the philosophy of language in the first place, and his perspicuous comments have guided my thinking at critical junctures. I thank Ed Keenan for research suggestions early on that helped me find my way in this project. A special debt of gratitude is due to the Chair of my committee, Joseph Almog, who challenged me to eschew intellectual safety and to think for myself. While I owe him much for specific suggestions and conversations, I owe him more for this challenge, which has been central to the completion of this dissertation. In addition to my committee, many other faculty members and graduate students in the UCLA Philosophy Department and in other departments have helped me to develop this work. I wish to thank them all, but especially Antonio Capuano, John Carriero, Louis deRosset, Brendan Gillon, and Eliot Michaelson for extensive comments or conversations over the years. The sound advice of Barbara Herman has been indispensable. The Department of Philosophy at University College London gave me my start in academic philosophy by accepting me to read for my M.Phil. without prior philosophical education. I am grateful to them for this opportunity, and especially to Tim Crane, whose ideas continue to influence my own. I could not have navigated the administrative side of the doctoral process without the unfailingly competent guidance of Kristin Olson, who has my deep appreciation. Finally, I thank my partner, Andrew Reisner, for collegial and personal support well beyond the call of duty. ix VITA 1997 A.B., Government Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts 1997-1999 Corporate Banking Associate Brown Brothers Harriman & Co. New York, New York 1999-2001 Venture Strategy Associate Spencer Trask and Co. New York, New York 2003 M.Phil. in Philosophy University College London London, United Kingdom Thesis: “A Dissolution of the Problem of the Explanatory Gap.” Supervised by Tim Crane. 2005 M.A. in Philosophy University of California, Los Angeles 2007 C.Phil. in Philosophy University of California, Los Angeles 2010-2011 Faculty Lecturer McGill University Montreal, Canada Publications “Reference and Referring: A Framework,” in W. Kabasenche, M. O’Rourke, and M. Slater, eds., Reference and Referring. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2012. “Semantic Reference Not By Convention?” Abstracta – Linguagem, Mente e Ação. Volume 5 Number 2, 2009. “Two Conceptions of Semantic Reference,” Proceedings of ILCLI International Workshop on Semantics, Pragmatics, and Rhetoric, The University of the Basque Country Press (EHU Press), 2009. x Presentations “Reference, Semantic Reference, and Determination” Northwest Philosophy Conference, Salem, Oregon, October 2010. “Reference: by truth or by cognition?” Inland Northwest Philosophy Conference: Reference and Referring, Moscow, ID and Pullman, WA, April 2010. “Two Conceptions of Semantic Reference” · ILCLI International Workshop on Semantics, Pragmatics, and Rhetoric, Donostia (San Sebastian), Spain, May 2009. · University of Iowa, Graduate Philosophical Society, Spring Conference, Iowa City, IA, April 2009. · Second European Graduate School: Philosophy of Language, Mind and Science, Bochum, Germany, March 2009. “Reference and Convention” Language Workshop, University of California, Los Angeles, February 2009.
Recommended publications
  • Semantical Paradox* Tyler Burge
    4 Semantical Paradox* Tyler Burge Frege remarked that the goal of all sciences is truth, but that it falls to logic to discern the laws of truth. Perceiving that the task of determining these laws went beyond Frege’s conception of it, Tarski enlarged the jurisdiction of logic, establishing semantics as truth’s lawyer.1 At the core of Tarski’s theory of truth and validity was a diagnosis of the Liar paradox according to which natural language was hopelessly infected with contradiction. Tarski construed himself as treating the disease by replacing ordinary discourse with a sanitized, artificial construction. But those interested in natural language have been dissatisfied with this medication. The best ground for dis­ satisfaction is that the notion of a natural language’s harboring contradictions is based on an illegitimate assimilation of natural language to a semantical system. According to that assimilation, part of the nature of a “language” is a set of postulates that purport to be true by virtue of their meaning or are at least partially constitutive of that “language”. Tarski thought that he had identified just such postulates in natural language as spawning inconsistency. But postulates are contained in theories that are promoted by people. Natural languages per se do not postulate or Tyler Burge, “Semantical Paradox", reprinted from The Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979), 169-98. Copyright © 1979 The Journal of Philosophy. Reprinted by permission of the Editor of The Journal of Philosophy and the author. * I am grateful to Robert L. Martin for several helpful discussions; to Herbert Enderton for proving the consistency (relative to that of arithmetic) of an extension of Construction C3; to Charles Parsons for stimulating exchanges back in 1973 and 1974; and to the John Simon Guggenheim Foundation for its support.
    [Show full text]
  • Putnam's Theory of Natural Kinds and Their Names Is Not The
    PUTNAM’S THEORY OF NATURAL KINDS AND THEIR NAMES IS NOT THE SAME AS KRIPKE’S IAN HACKING Collège de France Abstract Philosophers have been referring to the “Kripke–Putnam” theory of natural- kind terms for over 30 years. Although there is one common starting point, the two philosophers began with different motivations and presuppositions, and developed in different ways. Putnam’s publications on the topic evolved over the decades, certainly clarifying and probably modifying his analysis, while Kripke published nothing after 1980. The result is two very different theories about natural kinds and their names. Both accept that the meaning of a natural- kind term is not given by a description or defining properties, but is specified by its referents. From then on, Putnam rejected even the label, causal theory of reference, preferring to say historical, or collective. He called his own approach indexical. His account of substance identity stops short a number of objections that were later raised, such as what is called the qua problem. He came to reject the thought that water is necessarily H2O, and to denounce the idea of metaphysical necessity that goes beyond physical necessity. Essences never had a role in his analysis; there is no sense in which he was an essentialist. He thought of hidden structures as the usual determinant of natural kinds, but always insisted that what counts as a natural kind is relative to interests. “Natural kind” itself is itself an importantly theoretical concept, he argued. The paper also notes that Putnam says a great deal about what natural kinds are, while Kripke did not.
    [Show full text]
  • Canadian Journal of Philosophy a Defense Of
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy A Defense of Derangement Author(s): Paul M. Pietroski Source: Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 24, No. 1 (Mar., 1994), pp. 95-117 Published by: Canadian Journal of Philosophy Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40231855 Accessed: 07-03-2019 17:45 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Canadian Journal of Philosophy is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Canadian Journal of Philosophy This content downloaded from 165.230.225.90 on Thu, 07 Mar 2019 17:45:29 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY 95 Volume 24, Number 1, March 1994, pp. 95 - 118 A Defense of Derangement PAULM.PIETROSKI McGill University Montreal, QC H3A2T7 Canada In a recent paper, Bar-On and Risjord (henceforth, 'B&R') contend that Davidson provides no good argument for his (in)famous claim that 'there is no such thing as a language/1 And according to B&R, if David- son had established his 'no language' thesis, he would thereby have provided a decisive reason for abandoning the project he has long advocated - viz., that of trying to provide theories of meaning for natural languages by providing recursive theories of truth for such languages.
    [Show full text]
  • The Case for Contextualism: Knowledge, Skepticism, and Context, Vol
    The Case for Contextualism: Knowledge, Skepticism, and Context, Vol. 1 Draft of 10/18/08 Keith DeRose [email protected] Chapter 1: Contextualism, Invariantism, Skepticism, and 1 What Goes On in Ordinary Conversation Chapter 2: The Ordinary Language Basis for Contextualism 50 Chapter 3: Assertion, Knowledge, and Context 87 Chapter 4: Single Scoreboard Semantics 138 Chapter 5: “Bamboozled by Our Own Words”: Semantic 165 Blindness and Some Objections to Contextualism Chapter 6: Now You Know It, Now You Don’t: 201 Intellectualism, Contextualism, and Subject-Sensitive Invariantism Chapter 7: Knowledge, Assertion and Action: Contextualism 246 vs. Subject-Sensitive Invariantism References 302 Acknowledgements vii Chapter 1: Contextualism, Invariantism, Skepticism, and 1 What Goes On in Ordinary Conversation 1. Contextualism and the Old Bank Cases 1 2. Cases Involving Speakers in Different Conversations Talking About the Same 4 Subject 3. Contextualism and Invariantism 7 4. “Strength of Epistemic Position,” Comparative Conditionals, and Generic 8 Contextualism 5. Semantic Mechanism? 10 6. Which Claims to Take Seriously and the “Floor” of “Know(s)” 15 7. Is This Epistemology or Philosophy of Language? 20 8. Contextualism Regarding Other Epistemic Terms 22 9. Contextualism is Not a Thesis about the Structure of Knowledge or of Justification 23 10. “Subject” Vs. “Attributor” Contextualism 24 11. Intellectualism and the Distinction between “Classical” and “Subject-Sensitive” 26 Invariantism 12. A Brief History of Contextualism 28 13. Contextualism, Invariantism, and Relevant Alternatives 32 14. Against Contextualist Versions of RA That Tie the Content of Knowledge 37 Attributing Claim Directly to What the Range of Relevant Alternatives Is 15. Against Contrastivism 41 16.
    [Show full text]
  • Intellectual Norms and Foundations of Mind Author(S): Tyler Burge Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Intellectual Norms and Foundations of Mind Author(s): Tyler Burge Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 12 (Dec., 1986), pp. 697-720 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026694 Accessed: 11-04-2017 02:21 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy This content downloaded from 128.97.244.236 on Tue, 11 Apr 2017 02:21:34 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY VOLUME LXXXIII, NO. 12, DECEMBER 1986 -1-- 0 -4- INTELLECTUAL NORMS AND FOUNDATIONS OF MIND* T WO paramount tasks for philosophy are articulating the na- ture of propositional attitudes and articulating the nature of the intellectual norms that govern thinking about objective matters. The first task is fundamental to explicating the notion of mind. The second is fundamental to saying what is significant and distinctive about being human. With respect to the first task, I have previously argued that prop- ositional mental-state and event kinds are nonindividualistically individuated.
    [Show full text]
  • Definite Descriptions Are Ambiguous FELIPE S
    (Forthcoming in Analysis 68: 4) Definite descriptions are ambiguous FELIPE S. AMARAL 1. The problem Keith Donnellan (1966) contrasted two uses of definite descriptions, the referential and the attributive. In using a definite description referentially the speaker communicates content about a particular object in mind,1 whereas in using the same description attributively the speaker communicates content about whatever object uniquely satisfies the description. Assuming that definite descriptions have a quantificational attributive meaning, the main problem raised by Donnellan’s contrast between uses is whether descriptions also have a referential meaning.2 If they do, it is plausible to think that the definite article is ambiguous between a referential and an attributive meaning. In what follows, I will call this thesis `Ambiguity’. For ease of exposition, I will take it as a thesis about English. The most influential arguments against Ambiguity invoke the independently motivated Gricean distinction between what a speaker means and what he or she says (Grice 1989). According to these arguments, we do not need to postulate a referential meaning for definite descriptions to account for referential uses. We can account for such uses in terms of what a speaker means but does not literally say. Thus, in using a definite description referentially the speaker means or communicates content about a particular object in mind, but what the speaker literally says is determined by the description’s quantificational attributive meaning. We are then told that on the grounds of parsimony this account of referential uses is superior to Ambiguity (see Grice 1969; Kripke 1977; Bach 1981; Neale 1990).
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL-36 - Philosophy of Language Amherst College Spring 2009 – Visiting Prof
    PHIL-36 - Philosophy of Language Amherst College Spring 2009 – Visiting Prof. Kevin C. Klement (UMass faculty member) Mondays and Wednesdays 12:30pm-1:50pm in Cooper House 201. Course description: “Caesar was stabbed.” With those words, I can make a claim about someone who lived in the distant past. How is that possible? How do our words succeed in picking out particular portions of reality, even ones with which we have had no contact? How does language enable us to convey thoughts about everything from Amherst College, to the hopes of a friend, to the stars beyond our galaxy? What are the thoughts, or the meanings, that our words carry? And whatever they turn out to be, how do they come to be associated with our words: through some mental activity on our part, or instead through our shared use of language? This course covers selected topics in 20th century analytic philosophy of language, including meaning, reference, naming, truth, speech acts, propositional attitudes, translation, and the nature of linguistic representation. Contact info: You may e-mail me at [email protected], which is often the best way to reach me. I have a mailbox in the Amherst College philosophy department office (208 Cooper House). My office at UMass is 353 Bartlett Hall, and I also have access to Prof. Alexander George’s Office (307 Cooper House) for meetings at Amherst College. My UMass office phone is 545-5784. My office hours there are Tuesdays 2:30-3:30pm, Thursdays 11am-12pm and other times by appointment. I am also happy to make an appointment to meet with you at AC instead.
    [Show full text]
  • Vindicating a Critique
    Aporia vol. 17 no. 2—2007 Vindicating a Critique JASON A. HILLS N “Reference and Definite Descriptions,” Keith Donnellan distinguishes Ibetween attributive and referential uses of definite descriptions. He uses this distinction to show that Bertrand Russell’s theory of definite descrip- tions fails to account for the referential use. Saul Kripke, in “Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference,” claims that to successfully provide a counterexample to Russell’s theory, Donnellan’s distinction should be semantic rather than pragmatic. Kripke then argues that Donnellan’s refer- ential use is actually pragmatic—not sematic—and therefore does not refute Russell’s theory. A significant part of this debate concerns truth-values. Kripke argues that Donnellan’s assignment of truth-value to sentences such as “Her hus- band is kind to her,” where “her husband” is used referentially, does not differ from the assignment given by Russell’s theory. I will consider this claim; using the concept of analysis I will argue that the two theories do of- fer different accounts of truth-value. I will also argue that even a pragmatic ambiguity, as given by Donnellan, is sufficient to prove that Russell does not offer a complete account of reference. Russell’s Theory, In Brief Without going into detail nor considering his argumentation in fa- vor of it, I will briefly outline Russell’s theory. In his essay “On Denoting,” Russell presents a method of translating English sentences into a format where the logical proposition contained in a sentence is not hidden by the grammar of normal English sentences (213–14).
    [Show full text]
  • 4210F: Survey of Philosophy of Language
    THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Course Outline Philosophy 4210F/9xxx and Ling 9453L: Survey of Philosophy of Language Summer Term 2020 Instructor: R. Stainton Intersession May 11- Jun 26 StH Room 3126 Day and Time: Wed, Fri 12:30-3:30 Office Hours: TBA Classroom: STVH 1145 E-mail: [email protected] PREREQUISITE Philosophy 2260F/G DESCRIPTION A survey of foundational and highly influential texts from 20th Century Analytic Philosophy of Language. Emphasis will be on twin topics of special interest to contemporary linguistic theorizing: 1) contrasting conceptions of linguistic meaning, including Frege-Russell-Davidson style truth-conditional approaches; Ordinary Language Philosophy’s use-oriented approaches; and the mentalist semantics familiar from Grice and generative grammar. 2) The contrast between semantics vs. pragmatics and attempts to trace a boundary between them. This latter section will conclude with a detailed case study on definite descriptions, indexicals and singular reference. Authors include: Austin, Davidson, Donnellan, Fodor, Frege, Grice, Kaplan, Kripke, Russell, Searle, Strawson and Wittgenstein. TEXTS Robert J. Stainton (2000). Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. Peterborough: Broadview. Paul Elbourne (2011). Meaning: A Slim Guide to Semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. • Note: Kripke’s “Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference” and Kaplan’s “Demonstratives” will be made available online OBJECTIVES - To overview key issues in contemporary philosophy of language and semantics/pragmatics. - To fine-tune students’ ability to read, think and write at the most sophisticated level. READINGS I. The Formalist Tradition • Gottlob Frege (1892), “On Sense and Reference” • Bertrand Russell (1919), “Descriptions” • Donald Davidson (1967), “Truth and Meaning” • Saul Kripke (1971), “Identity and Necessity” II.
    [Show full text]
  • Uhm Phd 8003287 R.Pdf
    INFORMAnON TO USERS This was produced from a copy of a document sent to us for microfilming. While the most advanced technological means to photograph and reproduce this document have been used, the quality is heavily dependent upon the quality of the material submitted. The following explanation of techniques is provided to help you understand markings or notations which may appear on this reproduction. 1. The sign or "target" for pages apparently lacking from the document photographed is "Missing Pagers)", If it was possible to obtain the missing page(s) or section, they are spliced into the film along with adjacent pages. This may have necessitated cutting through an image and duplicating adjacent pages to assure you of complete continuity. 2. When an image on the film is obliterated with a round black mark it is an indication that the film inspector noticed either blurred copy because of movement during exposure, or duplicate copy. Unless we meant to delete copyrighted materials that should not have been filmed, you will find a good image of the page in the adjacent frame. 3. When a map, drawing or chart, etc., is part of the material being photo­ graphed the photographer has followed a definite method in "sectioning" the material. It is customary to begin filming at the upper left hand comer of a large sheet and to continue from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps. If necessary, sectioning is continued again-beginning below the first row and continuing on until complete. 4. For any illustrations that cannot be reproduced satisfactorily by xerography, photographic prints can be purchased at additional cost and tipped into your xerographic copy.
    [Show full text]
  • Donnellan's Misdescriptions and Loose Talk
    Forthcoming in Kepa Korta & Maria de Ponte (eds.), Reference and Representation in Language and Thought,Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017 – last preprint. Donnellan’s misdescriptions and loose talk Carlo Penco Literal talk, metaphorical talk and loose talk are different not in kind, but in degree of looseness. [Sperber and Wilson 1986: 153] Keith Donnellan wrote his paper on definite descriptions in 1966 at Cornell University, an environment where nearly everybody was discussing Wittgenstein’s ideas of meaning as use. However, his idea of different uses of definite descriptions became one of the fundamental tenets against descriptivism, which was considered one of the main legacies of the Frege–Russell– Wittgenstein view; and I wonder whether a more Wittgensteinian interpretation of Donnellan’s work is possible. Donnellan distinguishes attributive uses of definite descriptions (using “the F” we talk of the individual object, whatever it is, that uniquely fits the description) and referential uses (using “the F” we refer to an individual object that we have in mind through direct access, even if the individual does not properly fit the description). In this chapter I will discuss a well- known example, proposed by Leonard Linsky (1963) and analyzed by Donnellan, which can be summarized as follows: If, attending a scene with a man and a woman (whom I don’t know is a spinster), I say “her husband is kind to her” intending to refer to the individual who is actually her lover, I refer to him and I say something true, revealing a kind of
    [Show full text]