Holmes and the Romantic Mind Anne Dailey University of Connecticut School of Law

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Holmes and the Romantic Mind Anne Dailey University of Connecticut School of Law University of Connecticut OpenCommons@UConn Faculty Articles and Papers School of Law 1998 Holmes and the Romantic Mind Anne Dailey University of Connecticut School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://opencommons.uconn.edu/law_papers Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Legal Biography Commons Recommended Citation Dailey, Anne, "Holmes and the Romantic Mind" (1998). Faculty Articles and Papers. 234. https://opencommons.uconn.edu/law_papers/234 +(,121/,1( Citation: 48 Duke L.J. 429 1998-1999 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Tue Aug 16 12:50:56 2016 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: https://www.copyright.com/ccc/basicSearch.do? &operation=go&searchType=0 &lastSearch=simple&all=on&titleOrStdNo=0012-7086 HOLMES AND THE ROMANTIC MIND ANNE C. DAILEYt ABSTRACr Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. is perhaps best known for his "tough- minded" jurisprudence based on objective standards of reasonable- ness. Scholars have traditionallyunderstood Holmes's jurisprudential outlook as fundamentally behavioristic. Professor Dailey challenges that understanding,revealing the importance of Romantic psychology in Holmes's major writings. His outlook, she argues, was shaped by his belief in unconscious motivations, imagination, irrationality and instinctual drives. Rather than simply characterize Holmes as a "Romantic," Professor Dailey draws out the conflict in his thought, illuminating his struggle to develop an empiricalapproach to law that could also accountfor the depth and complexity of human nature. TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction ............................................................................................430 I. The Psychology of Holmes's Jurisprudential Writings ..................438 A. Instincts and Evolution ................................................................439 B. Unconscious Ideas and Legal Rules ............................................447 II. Empirical Foundations and Their Limits .......................................457 A. German Physiological Psychology ..............................................461 B. British Associationist Psychology ...............................................472 C. American Functionalism ..............................................................480 III. Rom antic H orizons .........................................................................485 A. German and English Romantic Influences ................................486 B. Seeing Through the Heart and Will ............................................493 C. H eroism in the Law .......................................................................502 C onclusion ..............................................................................................508 t Professor of Law, University of Connecticut School of Law. I would like to thank Professors Peter Gay, Rick Kay, Tom Morawetz, Kent Neumeyer, Jeremy Paul, Nomi Stolzenberg, Chief Judge Richard Posner, and Dr. Ernst Prelinger for their helpful comments and criticisms. Special thanks go to Steven Ecker and Deborah Rothstein. 430 DUKE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 48:429 A keen, slender, stridulous vibration-almost too fine for the hearing, weaving in and out, and in the pauses of the music dividing the silence like a knife-pierces my heart with an ecstasy I cannot utter. A! what is it? Did I ever hear it? Is it a voice within, answer- ing to the others, but different from them-and like a singing flame not ceasing with that which made it vocal?' INTRODUCTION The jurisprudence of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. is not usually associated with the poetry of Wordsworth, Shelley and Coleridge, the novels of Goethe, or the philosophy of Fichte, Schelling, and Carlyle. In fact, eighteenth-century Romanticism' seems directly at odds with the scientific empiricism of Holmes's professional writings: the "bad man" view of lawyering;3 the positivist definition of law as prediction;4 the enthusiasm for the "master of economics" and 1. Letter from Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. to William James (Apr. 19, 1868), quoted it RALPH BARTON PERRY, THE THOUGHT AND CHARACTER OF WILLIAM JAMES 92-93 (Harvard Univ. Press, briefer version 1948) (1935). 2. The use of the term "Romanticism" in this Article is discussed in Part III.A. Briefly, the term "Romantic" is used here to denote the counter-Enlightenment ideas about human nature present in the work of a wide and varied group of writers, critics and philosophers across France, Germany and England during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. As explained below, Romantic psychology stressed the powers of intuition and imagination, subjective experience, psychic conflict, irrationality, nature and inner transcendence. See infra notes 283-95 and accompanying text. This Article assesses the place of Romantic ideas about human nature in Holmes's jurisprudential work. The focus here is on his early theoretical writings, speeches, and correspondence, and not on his later decisions as a Supreme Court Justice. Although it is my belief that Holmes's Romantic psychology played a role in his later decisions, including his post-World War I First Amendment opinions, I do not develop that thesis here. For an example of a Holmes opinion that uses language reflecting a Romantic view of the unconscious, see Chicago B. & Q. Ry. Co. v. Babcock, 204 U.S. 585, 598 (1907) (stating that the reasoning of an administrative body expresses "an intuition of experience which outruns analysis and sums up many unnamed and tangled impressions ... which may lie beneath consciousness without losing their worth"). 3. Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REv. 457, 459 (1897) [hereinafter The Path of the Law], reprintedin 3 THE COLLECTED WORKS OF JUsTICE HOLMES 391, 392 (Sheldon M. Novick ed., 1995) [hereinafter COLLECrED WORKS] ("You can see very plainly that a bad man has as much reason as a good one for wishing to avoid an encounter with the public force, and therefore you can see the practical importance of the distinction between morality and law."). 4. See, e.g., id. at 460-61 ("The prophecies of what the courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious, are what I mean by the law."). 1998] HOLMES AND THE ROMANTIC MIND 431 quantitative decisionmaking5 and the external standard of liability.6 Even the discovery of Holmes's romance with Lady Castletown7 has done little to alter the views of a legal world long accustomed to the idea of Holmes as a "tough-minded," unsentimental legal thinker.8 Yet as this Article explains, the central tenets of Romantic psychology occupied an important place in Holmes's jurisprudence. Taken together, Holmes's published writings, speeches and correspondence offer a view of human nature strongly reminiscent of eighteenth-century Romantic literature and philosophy. Like the Romantic writers he read most frequently-notably, Wordsworth, Coleridge, Carlyle and Goethe-Holmes asserted the existence of such fundamental and nonempirical psychological concepts as unconscious motivations, instinctual desires, inner conflict, irrationality, imagination and transcendent faith in "the infinite."9 His two most important jurisprudential works, The Common Law and The Path of the Law, incorporate a view of individuals as intuitive beings whose rational faculties can be overcome by deep-seated instincts and unconscious passions. His letters, speeches, journals and reading lists document his abiding interest in the idea of an active and creative mind endowed with native faculties and capable of intuitive insight. Alongside his celebrated enthusiasm for empirical science lay 5. See, e.g., id. at 469 ("For the rational study of the law the black-letter man may be the man of the present, but the man of the future is the man of statistics and the master of economics."). 6. See, e.g., OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES, JR., THE COMMON LAW 108 (Boston, Little, Brown & Co. 1881) [hereinafter THE COMMON LAW] ("The law considers, in other words, what would be blameworthy in the average man, the man of ordinary intelligence and prudence, and determines liability by that."). 7. In 1985, a trove of letters written by Holmes to Lady Clare Castietown, the wife of an Irish Baron, was discovered. Written over a three-year period from 1896 to 1899, the letters reveal Holmes, 55 years old and married at the time, to have been passionately and somewhat impulsively in love. See David J. Seipp, Holmes's Path, 77 B.U. L. REV. 515, 534-37 (1997) (excerpting several of the 103 letters from Hoimes to Lady Castletown that have been preserved). 8. The term "tough-minded" as applied to scientific empiricism comes from William James. See WILLIAM JAMES, PRAGMATISM: A NEW NAME FOR SOME OLD WAYS OF THINKING 262-63 (1907). In a letter to James written after receiving a copy of Pragmatism, Holmes conceded: "You would say that I am too hard or tough-minded." Letter from Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. to William James, quoted in David A. Hollinger, The "Tough-Minded" Justice Holmes, Jewish Intellectuals, and the Making of an American Icon, in THE LEGACY OF OLIVER WENDELLHOLMES, JR. 216,218 (Robert W. Gordon ed., 1992). 9. The Path of the Law, supra note 3, at 459, reprinted in 3 COLLECrED WORKS, supra note
Recommended publications
  • 'Introspectionism' and the Mythical Origins of Scientific Psychology
    Consciousness and Cognition Consciousness and Cognition 15 (2006) 634–654 www.elsevier.com/locate/concog ‘Introspectionism’ and the mythical origins of scientific psychology Alan Costall Department of Psychology, University of Portsmouth, Portsmouth, Hampshire PO1 2DY, UK Received 1 May 2006 Abstract According to the majority of the textbooks, the history of modern, scientific psychology can be tidily encapsulated in the following three stages. Scientific psychology began with a commitment to the study of mind, but based on the method of introspection. Watson rejected introspectionism as both unreliable and effete, and redefined psychology, instead, as the science of behaviour. The cognitive revolution, in turn, replaced the mind as the subject of study, and rejected both behaviourism and a reliance on introspection. This paper argues that all three stages of this history are largely mythical. Introspectionism was never a dominant movement within modern psychology, and the method of introspection never went away. Furthermore, this version of psychology’s history obscures some deep conceptual problems, not least surrounding the modern conception of ‘‘behaviour,’’ that continues to make the scientific study of consciousness seem so weird. Ó 2006 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Keywords: Introspection; Introspectionism; Behaviourism; Dualism; Watson; Wundt 1. Introduction Probably the most immediate result of the acceptance of the behaviorist’s view will be the elimination of self-observation and of the introspective reports resulting from such a method. (Watson, 1913b, p. 428). The problem of consciousness occupies an analogous position for cognitive psychology as the prob- lem of language behavior does for behaviorism, namely, an unsolved anomaly within the domain of an approach.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanislaw Piatkiewicz and the Beginnings of Mathematical Logic in Poland
    HISTORIA MATHEMATICA 23 (1996), 68±73 ARTICLE NO. 0005 Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz and the Beginnings of Mathematical Logic in Poland TADEUSZ BATO G AND ROMAN MURAWSKI View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Adam Mickiewicz University, ul. Matejki 48/49, 60-769 PoznanÂ, Poland provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector This paper presents information on the life and work of Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz (1849±?). His Algebra w logice (Algebra in Logic) of 1888 contains an exposition of the algebra of logic and its use in representing syllogisms. This was the ®rst original Polish publication on symbolic logic. It appeared 20 years before analogous works by èukasiewicz and Stamm. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. In dem Aufsatz werden Informationen zu Leben und Werk von Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz (1849±?) gegeben. Sein Algebra w logice (Algebra in der Logik) von 1888 enthaÈlt eine Darstel- lung der Algebra der Logik und ihre Anwendung auf die Syllogistik. PiaËtkiewicz' Schrift war die erste polnische Publikation uÈ ber symbolische Logik. Sie erschien 20 Jahre vor aÈhnlichen Arbeiten von èukasiewicz und Stamm. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. W pracy przedstawiono osobeË i dzieøo Stanisøawa PiaËtkiewicza (1849±?). W szczego lnosÂci analizuje sieË jego rozpraweË Algebra w logice z roku 1888, w kto rej zajmowaø sieË on nowymi no wczas ideami algebry logiki oraz ich zastosowaniami do sylogistyki. Praca ta jest pierwszaË oryginalnaË polskaË publikacjaË z zakresu logiki symbolicznej. Ukazaøa sieË 20 lat przed analog- icznymi pracami èukasiewicza i Stamma. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. MSC 1991 subject classi®cations: 03-03, 01A55.
    [Show full text]
  • Running Head: a REVIEW and EVALUATION of an OPEN 1
    Running Head: A REVIEW AND EVALUATION OF AN OPEN 1 A Review and Evaluation of an Open-Source Mood Assessment, the Brief Mood Introspection Scale Rachael M. Cavallaro University of New Hampshire Victoria Bryan University of New Hampshire John D. Mayer University of New Hampshire A REVIEW AND EVALUATION OF AN OPEN 2 Abstract The Brief Mood Introspection Scale (BMIS) is an open-source, 16-item assessment of current mood regularly used in psychological research. The scale has two sets of scales: one pair of scales assesses mood using Pleasant-Unpleasant and Arousal-Calm dimensions; the other (less used alternative) assesses mood using Positive and Negative Affect. However, since its publication in 1988, there have been no systematic reports of its usage pattern, norms or of evidence for its validity. The present meta-analysis aims to (1) identify the nature of the studies that employed the BMIS (i.e. research areas and design), (2) establish the norms for the BMIS the scale means, standard deviations, and reliabilities, and (3) evaluate for the BMIS’s validity. One hundred and fifty studies that utilized the BMIS over a five-year timespan (2016-2011) were identified, including 27 studies that reported information pertinent to the scale’s norms. Our findings indicated that BMIS was primarily used in experimental research, and that its norms were similar to those from the original report. We make recommendations for use of Likert response scales and scoring conventions. A more qualitative review suggested that the Pleasant- Unpleasant mood scale had considerable evidence for its validity from its relation to criteria.
    [Show full text]
  • Wilhelm Wundt & Herman Ebbinghaus Wilhelm Wundt & Herman
    1 2 Wilhelm Wundt & Herman Ebbinghaus Wilhelm Wundt & Herman Ebbinghaus 1. Wundt 2. Ebbinghaus A. Biographical details A. Biographical details B. Career history B. Career history C. Psychological theories C. Psychological theories D. Impact on Psychology D. Impact on Psychology Setting the Scene… 3 4 (After Darwin, Descartes (d. 1650) – psychologists William James (1890) – we consist of a preferred the study we are not automata; material body & of learning to that of consciousness selects immaterial soul consciousness) (Newton) Copernicus (1543): J.-O. la Mettrie (1748) Charles Darwin (1859) Wilhelm Wundt Sigmund Freud heliocentric theory of the L’Homme Machine – (On the Origin of Species) (1879) established (1899) – unconscious universe – Earth, and humans are just more – evolution by common first lab for study of more important than human race, are not the complex animals descent of all creatures human psychology consciousness centre of the universe Opposing views… 5 6 Humans are special. We’re not just smarter monkeys. Reflective self- consciousness (subjective experience) is unique to humans. It is too Wilhelm Wundt remarkable to have evolved for no reason. It permits selection. It creates (1832-1920) our experience of the world. It makes us care whether we live or die. William James Wilhelm Wundt Humans are not special – we are not the center of the universe. We’re just more complex animals on a little planet in an uncaring universe. Consciousness is not special (in any useful way) – it doesn’t produce our behavior; our behavior issues from unconscious processes shared with animals and generated by brains. Consciousness is an epiphenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • What Literature Knows: Forays Into Literary Knowledge Production
    Contributions to English 2 Contributions to English and American Literary Studies 2 and American Literary Studies 2 Antje Kley / Kai Merten (eds.) Antje Kley / Kai Merten (eds.) Kai Merten (eds.) Merten Kai / What Literature Knows This volume sheds light on the nexus between knowledge and literature. Arranged What Literature Knows historically, contributions address both popular and canonical English and Antje Kley US-American writing from the early modern period to the present. They focus on how historically specific texts engage with epistemological questions in relation to Forays into Literary Knowledge Production material and social forms as well as representation. The authors discuss literature as a culturally embedded form of knowledge production in its own right, which deploys narrative and poetic means of exploration to establish an independent and sometimes dissident archive. The worlds that imaginary texts project are shown to open up alternative perspectives to be reckoned with in the academic articulation and public discussion of issues in economics and the sciences, identity formation and wellbeing, legal rationale and political decision-making. What Literature Knows The Editors Antje Kley is professor of American Literary Studies at FAU Erlangen-Nürnberg, Germany. Her research interests focus on aesthetic forms and cultural functions of narrative, both autobiographical and fictional, in changing media environments between the eighteenth century and the present. Kai Merten is professor of British Literature at the University of Erfurt, Germany. His research focuses on contemporary poetry in English, Romantic culture in Britain as well as on questions of mediality in British literature and Postcolonial Studies. He is also the founder of the Erfurt Network on New Materialism.
    [Show full text]
  • Imagination Bound: a Theoretical Imperative
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy Philosophy 2016 Imagination Bound: A Theoretical Imperative Robert Michael Guerin University of Kentucky, [email protected] Digital Object Identifier: http://dx.doi.org/10.13023/ETD.2016.017 Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Guerin, Robert Michael, "Imagination Bound: A Theoretical Imperative" (2016). Theses and Dissertations-- Philosophy. 8. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/philosophy_etds/8 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STUDENT AGREEMENT: I represent that my thesis or dissertation and abstract are my original work. Proper attribution has been given to all outside sources. I understand that I am solely responsible for obtaining any needed copyright permissions. I have obtained needed written permission statement(s) from the owner(s) of each third-party copyrighted matter to be included in my work, allowing electronic distribution (if such use is not permitted by the fair use doctrine) which will be submitted to UKnowledge as Additional File. I hereby grant to The University of Kentucky and its agents the irrevocable, non-exclusive, and royalty-free license to archive and make accessible my work in whole or in part in all forms of media, now or hereafter known. I agree that the document mentioned above may be made available immediately for worldwide access unless an embargo applies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Nature of Learning and Memory
    Arlo Clark-Foos, Ph.D. 2 October 2017 1 • Life Without Memory (Clive Wearing) – Video Clive’s Diary “10:08 a.m.: Now I am superlatively awake. First time aware for years.” “10:13 a.m.: Now I am overwhelmingly awake.” “10:28 a.m.: Actually I am now the first time awake for years.” 10/2/2017 12:41 PM 2 • Genes determine the possible range. • Reflex actions, simple behaviors – Knee-jerk, swallow, suck, grip John B. Watson and Rosalie Rayner 2 October 2017 3 • Experience (and memory of it) determines our individual differences and allows us to improve upon initial behaviors and reflexes. 2 October 2017 4 • How well can you read these sentences? The quick brown fox jumps over the lazy dog. Pack my box with five dozen liquor jugs. 2 October 2017 5 • Context and Expectations Group 1 Group 2 2 October 2017 6 Bugelski & Alampay (1961) 2 October 2017 7 Jastrow (1899) 2 October 2017 8 Kremen (2010) 2 October 2017 9 2 October 2017 10 2 October 2017 11 • Introspection, Logic, & Philosophy • Plato’s Aviary metaphor 2 October 2017 12 “other animals (as well as man) have memory, but … none … except man, shares in the faculty of recollection” • Observation and Data Theories • Contiguity, Frequency, Similarity • All knowledge is innate, • Memory The Republic – Replication of sensory perception – Passive re-perception • Familiarity? • Intuition and Logic • Reminiscence – Replaying an entire experience – Temporal contiguity • Recollection? 2 October 2017 13 Mind Body Cogito ergo sum Stimulus, Response (reflex arc) (Descartes, 1637) Like a machine/clock Animal “Spirits” flow Knowledge is mostly innate 2 October 2017 14 • Absolute Power of the Monarchy – Isaac Newton’s Light and Robert Boyle’s chemicals • Associationism (Green, Bitter/Sour vs.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comprehension of Spinoza's God
    A Comprehension of Spinoza's God Through the Dichotomy of Labels Tania Norell LUNDS UNIVERSITET | CENTRUM FÖR TEOLOGI OCH RELIGIONSVETENSKAP TLVM77 Philosophy of Religion Master Thesis 30 credits Supervisor: Jayne Svenungsson, Professor of Systematic Theology Examiner: Jesper Svartvik, Professor of Theology of Religions Autumn term 2015 Lund University Sweden Lund University Tania Norell Abstract: The 17 th century philosopher Spinoza is known for his concept of God as One Substance, God or Nature and therefore considered as a monist and categorized as a naturalist. He has been labeled an atheist and God-intoxicated man, as well as a determinist and pantheist, which I perceive to be dichotomies. The problem, as I see it, is that Spinoza’s philosophy and concept of God has mainly been interpreted through a dualistic mind-set, traditional to philosophers and theologians of the West, but Spinoza has a monistic worldview, and this has consequences in regards to the comprehension of what Spinoza’s concept of God entails and what a relationship “with” God implies . The labels panentheist and necessitarianist are discussed and the label of theologian argued. The thesis methodology is constructive because the purpose is to provide a theoretical foundation that has the potential to be applied in dialogues about God between the vast varieties of believers and non-believers alike, as well as across boundaries of contradicting worldviews and academic disciplines, and this focus on functionalism is inspired by a theory that calls for the furthering of inter-disciplinary dialogue between the subject areas philosophy of religion and theology specifically. My personal worldview is that there might well be One Substance, God or Nature, but that does not necessarily mean that there is one truth that is valid, but rather that all truth claims may be of value.
    [Show full text]
  • The Positivist Repudiation of Wundt Kurt Danziger
    Jouml of the History ofthe Behuvioral Sciences 15 (1979): 205-230. THE POSITIVIST REPUDIATION OF WUNDT KURT DANZIGER Near the turn of the century, younger psychologists like KUlpe, Titchener, and Eb- binghaus began to base their definition of psychology on the positivist philosophy of science represented by Mach and Avenarius, a development that was strongly op- posed by Wundt. Psychology was redefined as a natural science concerned with phenomena in their dependence on a physical organism. Wundt’s central concepts of voluntarism, value, and psychic causality were rejected as metaphysical, For psy- chological theory this resulted in a turn away from Wundt’s emphasis on the dynamic and central nature of psychological processes toward sensationalism and processes anchored in the observable peripher of the organism. Behaviorism represents a logical development of this point orview. I. PSYCHOLOGYAS SCIENCE What makes the early years in the history of experimental psychology of more than antiquarian interest are the fundamental disagreements that quickly separated its prac- titioners. These disagreements frequently concerned issues that are not entirely dead even today because they involve basic commitments about the nature of the discipline which had to be repeated by successive generations, either explicitly, or, with increasing fre- quency, implicitly. In the long run it is those historical divisions which involve fundamental questions about the nature of psychology as a scientific discipline that are most likely to prove il- luminating. Such questions acquired great urgency during the last decade of the nineteenth and the first few years of the present century, for it was during this period that psychologists began to claim the status of a separate scientific discipline for their subject.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This Is a Story About Philosophy. Or About Science
    Chapter 1: An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This is a story about philosophy. Or about science. Or about philosophy transforming into science. Or about science and philosophy, and how they are related. Or were, in a particular time and place. At least, that is the general area that the following narrative will explore, I hope with sufficient subtlety. The matter is rendered non-transparent by the fact that that the conclusions one draws with regard to such questions are, in part, matters of discretionary perspective – as I will try to demonstrate. My specific historical focus will be on the propagation of a complex intellectual tradition concerned with human sensation, perception, and mental function in early nineteenth century Britain. Not only philosophical opinion, but all aspects of British intellectual – and practical – life, were in the process of significant transformation during this time. This cultural flux further confuses recovery of the situated significance of the intellectual tradition I am investigating. The study of the mind not only was influenced by a set of broad social shifts, but it also participated in them fully as both stimulus to and recipient of changing conditions. One indication of this is simply the variety of terms used to identify the ‘philosophy of mind’ as an intellectual enterprise in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.1 But the issue goes far deeper into the fluid constitutive features of the enterprise - including associated conceptual systems, methods, intentions of practitioners, and institutional affiliations. In order to understand philosophy of mind in its time, we must put all these factors into play.
    [Show full text]
  • 272 Bibliography Abbreviations for Frequently Cited Works Analysis = Mill [1829] E&W = Bain [1859] EAP = Reid[1788/1969]
    Bibliography Abbreviations for Frequently Cited Works Analysis = Mill [1829] E&W = Bain [1859] EAP = Reid[1788/1969] EIP = Reid [1785/1969] First Enquiry = “An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding” in Hume [1777/1975] Inquiry = Reid [1764/1997] Lectures = Brown [1828/1860] or Hamilton [1844/1877] (sense obvious in context) Observations, OM = Hartley [1749/1966] S&I = Bain [1855] Sketch = Brown [1820/1977] SSR = Kuhn [1962/1970] Treatise = Hume [1739-1740/1978] Section I: Primary Sources Allen, Grant, Physiological Aesthetics [Garland Publishing, 1877]. Bain, Alexander, The Senses and the Intellect [University Publications of America, 1855/1977]. Bain, Alexander, The Emotions and the Will [University Publications of America, 1859/1977]. Bain, Alexander, “The Early Life of James Mill” in Mind, 1(1), pp.97-116 [1876a]. Bain, Alexander, “The Life of James Mill” in Mind, 1(4), pp.509-531 [1876b]. Bain, Alexander, James Mill: A Biography [Augustus M. Kelley, 1882a/1967]. Bain, Alexander, John Stuart Mill: A Criticism with Personal Reflections [Longmans, Green and Co., 1882b]. Bain, Alexander, Autobiography [1904]. Barzellotti, Giacomo, “Philosophy in Italy” in Mind, 3(12), pp.505-538 [1878]. Berkeley, George, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Jonathan Dancy, ed. [Oxford University Press, 1710/1998] Brown, Thomas, Lectures on the Philosophy of the Human Mind [Hallowell Glazer and Co., 1828]. 272 Brown, Thomas, Lectures on the Philosophy of the Human Mind [William Tegg, 1828/1860 (20th Edition)]. Brown, Thomas, Sketch of a System of the Philosophy of the Human Mind [1820], reprinted in Significant Contributions to the History of Psychology, Series A: Orientations, Volume I, Daniel N.
    [Show full text]
  • Wundt's "New Psychology"
    Wundt's "New Psychology" Wilhelm Wundt(1832-1920) was the first professional to call himself a psychologist. He founded one of the first psychological laboratories in Leipzig, Germany, in 1879. Wundt believed the "only certain reality is immediate experience" (Blumenthal, 1975). If psychology were to be a science, then psychologists would have to collect data about experience. To do this, Wundt used procedures similar to those developed by the psychophysicists. He arranged controlled laboratory settings. He carefully administered stimulation such as sounds and sights. He gathered information about how quickly people responded to a stimulus (reaction time) and what they experienced. Wundt believed these experiments would lead to a consensus or agreement among scientists about the nature of experience. Wilhelm Wundt Wundt's approach was not unreasonable. It resembled the way most natural sciences developed in the 1800s. Science like botany and zoology began with careful observation and an effort to arrive at consensual validation (agreement among different observers). For example, biologists began with careful descriptions of plants and animals before trying to classify them. Wundt believed the same approach would work in psychology. Careful scientific observers could simply look inside themselves to see the mind in action, and they should be able to agree on the basic phenomena of psychology. After agreeing about basic observations, they could do a deeper analysis of what they had found. The technique of "looking inside" to gather data about the mind is called introspection . The problem with Wundt's program is fairly obvious to those of us in the modern world, where differences between people are taken for granted.
    [Show full text]