Number and Individuation a Dissertation Submitted To

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Number and Individuation a Dissertation Submitted To NUMBER AND INDIVIDUATION A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS AND THE COMMITTEE ON GRADUATE STUDIES OF STANFORD UNIVERSITY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Scott Grimm August 2012 Abstract This dissertation investigates the semantic foundations of nominal countability. Standard accounts are typically concerned with a binary distinction between countable words (dog/ dogs) and non-countable words (water). This dissertation examines this issue from the perspective of languages with richer grammatical number systems. I develop a typological generalization that countability is a scalar phenomenon and propose new techniques to formally model these facets of nominal semantics by augmenting standard mereological accounts with topological relations. Languages such as Welsh or Maltese grammatically recognize what I call aggregate nouns—nouns which designate entities that habitually come together, such as insects (ants) or granular substances (sand). These nouns are grammatically distinct from both non- countable nouns and countable nouns with a singular/plural contrast, instead they display a collective/singulative contrast. These grammatical number systems vividly demonstrate how a binary countable/non-countable distinction oversimplifies the typological space. I argue from the data from Welsh and Maltese, and even more complex fieldwork data from the Gur language Dagaare, that countability is a scalar phenomenon. I propose that the morphosyntactic organization of grammatical number systems re- flects the semantic organization of noun types according to the degree of individuation of their referents. Nouns of different types are individuated to different degrees and can ac- cordingly be ordered along a scale of individuation: substances < granular aggregates < collectives < individual entities. Noun types which are less individuated are on the lower end of the scale and are cross-linguistically less likely to signal grammatical number, while the converse holds for highly individuated noun types. Understanding morphosyntactic number categories in light of a scale of individuation avoids the difficulties binary accounts iv face, since languages may divide up the scale of individuation into any number of classes and at different points. For instance, languages with a collective/singulative recognize a grammatical number category corresponding to the middle region of the scale. At the same time, the proposal provides a predictive framework for how grammatical number systems are organized: the contrasts being made are common across languages, and, as a corollary, the endpoints of the scale (substances and individual entities) are predicted to be stable across languages. I show that this view of countability also answers many of the standard criticisms of accounts where a noun’s meaning determines its grammatical behavior with respect to number marking. I explore the implications of this broader typological view for formal semantic treat- ments of countability. Standard mereological accounts turn out to be not sufficiently expres- sive to model the aggregate nouns nor the grammatical number systems which distinguish them. I enrich the standard mereology framework with topological connection relations, resulting in the more expressive “mereotopology”. Through using different connection re- lations, this framework is able to represent aggregate nouns and the ways in which entities may come together. Consequently, this framework is able to deliver analyses of particular grammatical number systems, such as Welsh. In addition, this more expressive framework resolves several recalcitrant problems noted for many treatments of countability, such as the “minimal parts” problem discussed in relation to nouns such as sand or furniture which, while non-countable, still have minimal pieces. v Acknowledgements This dissertation has benefitted from a large number of people who have advised me, pro- vided insights and criticisms, and who have generally helped me to develop as a linguist. First and foremost, I would like to thank my dissertation advisor Beth Levin. She has given me guidance in matters large and small throughout my time at Stanford—practically every aspect of my graduate career has benefitted from her advice. She has also been an ideal advisor for me. She has a rare ability to make the right suggestion at the right time, simul- taneously leaving much freedom in how to follow up on the suggestion. I have learned an enormous amount working with her. For this, and much more, I am grateful. The other members of my committee have had a similarly large influence on my de- velopment. Paul Kiparsky’s breadth and depth of knowledge has been a source of awe for me throughout my graduate career. Many of the most thrilling intellectual moments of my graduate studies occurred in his classes and in meetings with him. In the context of this dissertation, he has been particularly helpful in both drawing my attention to many portions of my thinking which needed clarity as well as to encouraging me to always re- late my proposals to the big questions. Chris Potts has provided me with extremely useful counsel during the course of this dissertation, and also advised me on projects concern- ing plurality that led up to the dissertation. I have consistently enjoyed being exposed to his infectious enthusiasm for innovative approaches in linguistics and have learned much about semantics, among many other things, through our interactions. I met Donka Farkas through various Bay Area semantics events and it has been a true privilege to have her as part of my committee. I am grateful to her for all the insights she has shared with me about plurals, markedness and semantic theory during our meetings on the idyllic UC Santa Cruz campus. I would also like to thank Tom Wasow for his participation in my dissertation vi defense and for much valuable advice throughout my time at Stanford. This dissertation grew out of my fascination with the Dagaare inverse number marking system. Arto Anttila and Adams Bodomo introduced me to the problem during my first year at Stanford and have provided encouragement for my work on it ever since. Thanks to Adams Bodomo, I got into contact with Mark Ali at the University of Education in Winneba, Ghana. Mark Ali devoted an enormous amount of time to working with me on Dagaare during two trips to Ghana—simply put, this dissertation would not have come into being without him. I can never thank him enough for his generosity, insight, and friendship. As my dissertation research progressed, I gained much from conversations with Dave Barner, Jade Comfort, Cleo Condoravdi, Hana Filip, Jeff Good, Peggy Li, John Lucy, Frank Seifart, and Henriette¨ de Swart. I would also like to thank the members of the “Mass- Count Collective”: David Clausen, Alex Djalali, Sven Lauer, and Tania Rojas-Esponda. Our weekly meetings during Spring Quarter of 2010 shaped many aspects of my thinking which became foundational for this dissertation. During the final phase, Nadine Borchardt, Dan Lassiter, Tania Rojas-Esponda, and Middy Tice provided proof-reading and many valuable comments. Part of the research for this dissertation was carried out during stays in Berlin, Germany. My first stay was as a guest researcher at Zentrum fur¨ Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft (ZAS). I would like to thank Manfred Krifka and Barbara Stiebels for arranging for that stay, as well as providing me with office space on a subsequent visit, as well as to thank my ZAS colleagues for such a stimulating environment. I also would like to thank Tom Guldemann¨ for supporting me during a second stay in Berlin as a Deutscher Akademis- cher Austauschdienst (DAAD) scholar at Humboldt University. During these stays, I had the pleasure of engaging with the vibrant linguistics community in Berlin. In particular, I would like to thank Laura Downing, Ines Fielder, Gudrun Miehe, Anne Schwarz, Ker- stin Schwabe, Stephanie Solt, Uli Sauerland, Frank Seifart, Tonjes Veenstra, and Malte Zimmermann. A large part of the richness of my graduate experience has been of course due to my fel- low students. I would like to thank my cohort with whom I have spent a most enjoyable six years: Matthew Adams, Uriel Cohen Priva, Marie-Catherine de Marneffe, Jason Grafmiller, and Tyler Schnoebelen. Marie-Catherine deserves special mention: office-mate, frequent vii co-author, and friend, she has also single-handedly prevented my French from falling into total ruin during the last six years. Merci! During my time at Stanford, I have over- lapped with many other students who have provided me with stimulating conversations about linguistics as well as good times. Inbal Arnon, Lucas Champollion, Liz Coppock, Alex Djalali, Itamar Francez, Roey Gafter, Lauren Hall-Lew, Philip Hofmeister, Andrew Koontz-Garboden, Tatiana Nikitina, Lis Norcliffe, Nola Stephens, and Hal Tily—thank you all. I gratefully acknowledge the financial support I have received for the research under- taken in this dissertation: a National Science Foundation Dissertation Improvement Grant (Grant No. 1023289, P.I. Beth Levin), a Stanford Center for African Studies Summer Fel- lowship, a Graduate Research Opportunity Grant from Stanford University and a Deutscher Akademischer Austauschdienst (DAAD) Visiting Scholar Grant. Finally, I would like to thank my family who has provided me with a constant source of love and all manners of support during the various stages of my life. I am especially grateful to my parents who
Recommended publications
  • Animacy and Alienability: a Reconsideration of English
    Running head: ANIMACY AND ALIENABILITY 1 Animacy and Alienability A Reconsideration of English Possession Jaimee Jones A Senior Thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation in the Honors Program Liberty University Spring 2016 ANIMACY AND ALIENABILITY 2 Acceptance of Senior Honors Thesis This Senior Honors Thesis is accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation from the Honors Program of Liberty University. ______________________________ Jaeshil Kim, Ph.D. Thesis Chair ______________________________ Paul Müller, Ph.D. Committee Member ______________________________ Jeffrey Ritchey, Ph.D. Committee Member ______________________________ Brenda Ayres, Ph.D. Honors Director ______________________________ Date ANIMACY AND ALIENABILITY 3 Abstract Current scholarship on English possessive constructions, the s-genitive and the of- construction, largely ignores the possessive relationships inherent in certain English compound nouns. Scholars agree that, in general, an animate possessor predicts the s- genitive while an inanimate possessor predicts the of-construction. However, the current literature rarely discusses noun compounds, such as the table leg, which also express possessive relationships. However, pragmatically and syntactically, a compound cannot be considered as a true possessive construction. Thus, this paper will examine why some compounds still display possessive semantics epiphenomenally. The noun compounds that imply possession seem to exhibit relationships prototypical of inalienable possession such as body part, part whole, and spatial relationships. Additionally, the juxtaposition of the possessor and possessum in the compound construction is reminiscent of inalienable possession in other languages. Therefore, this paper proposes that inalienability, a phenomenon not thought to be relevant in English, actually imbues noun compounds whose components exhibit an inalienable relationship with possessive semantics.
    [Show full text]
  • Verbal Agreement with Collective Nominal Constructions: Syntactic and Semantic Determinants
    ATLANTIS Journal of the Spanish Association of Anglo-American Studies 39.1 (June 2017): 33-54 issn 0210-6124 | e-issn 1989-6840 Verbal Agreement with Collective Nominal Constructions: Syntactic and Semantic Determinants Yolanda Fernández-Pena Universidade de Vigo [email protected] This corpus-based study investigates the patterns of verbal agreement of twenty-three singular collective nouns which take of-dependents (e.g., a group of boys, a set of points). The main goal is to explore the influence exerted by theof -PP on verb number. To this end, syntactic factors, such as the plural morphology of the oblique noun (i.e., the noun in the of- PP) and syntactic distance, as well as semantic issues, such as the animacy or humanness of the oblique noun within the of-PP, were analysed. The data show the strongly conditioning effect of plural of-dependents on the number of the verb: they favour a significant proportion of plural verbal forms. This preference for plural verbal patterns, however, diminishes considerably with increasing syntactic distance when the of-PP contains a non-overtly- marked plural noun such as people. The results for the semantic issues explored here indicate that animacy and humanness are also relevant factors as regards the high rate of plural agreement observed in these constructions. Keywords: agreement; collective; of-PP; distance; animacy; corpus . Concordancia verbal con construcciones nominales colectivas: sintaxis y semántica como factores determinantes Este estudio de corpus investiga los patrones de concordancia verbal de veintitrés nombres colectivos singulares que toman complementos seleccionados por la preposición of, como en los ejemplos a group of boys, a set of points.
    [Show full text]
  • Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: a Case Study from Koro
    Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: A Case Study from Koro By Jessica Cleary-Kemp A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Associate Professor Lev D. Michael, Chair Assistant Professor Peter S. Jenks Professor William F. Hanks Summer 2015 © Copyright by Jessica Cleary-Kemp All Rights Reserved Abstract Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: A Case Study from Koro by Jessica Cleary-Kemp Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics University of California, Berkeley Associate Professor Lev D. Michael, Chair In this dissertation a methodology for identifying and analyzing serial verb constructions (SVCs) is developed, and its application is exemplified through an analysis of SVCs in Koro, an Oceanic language of Papua New Guinea. SVCs involve two main verbs that form a single predicate and share at least one of their arguments. In addition, they have shared values for tense, aspect, and mood, and they denote a single event. The unique syntactic and semantic properties of SVCs present a number of theoretical challenges, and thus they have invited great interest from syntacticians and typologists alike. But characterizing the nature of SVCs and making generalizations about the typology of serializing languages has proven difficult. There is still debate about both the surface properties of SVCs and their underlying syntactic structure. The current work addresses some of these issues by approaching serialization from two angles: the typological and the language-specific. On the typological front, it refines the definition of ‘SVC’ and develops a principled set of cross-linguistically applicable diagnostics.
    [Show full text]
  • Names a Person, Place, Thing, Or an Idea. A. Common Noun – Names Any One of a Group of Persons, Places, Things, Or Ideas
    Name: __________________________________________ Block: ______ English II: Price 1. Noun – names a person, place, thing, or an idea. a. Common noun – names any one of a group of persons, places, things, or ideas. b. Proper noun – names a particular person, place, thing, or idea. c. Compound noun – consists of two or more words that together name a person, place, thing, or idea. d. Concrete noun – names a person, place, thing that can be perceived by one or more of the senses. e. Abstract noun – names an idea, a feeling, a quality, or a characteristic. f. Collective noun – names a group of people, animals, or things. 2. Pronoun – takes the place of one or more nouns or pronouns. a. Antecedent – the word or word group that a pronoun stands for. b. Personal pronouns – refers to the one(s) speaking (first person), the one(s) spoken to (second person), or the one(s) spoken about (third person). Singular Plural First person I, me, my, mine We, us, our, ours Second person You, your, yours You, your, yours Third person He, him, his, she, her, hers, it, its They, them, their, theirs c. Case Forms of Personal Pronouns – form that a pronoun takes to show its relationship to other words in a sentence. Case Forms of Personal Pronouns Nominative Case Objective Case Possessive Case Singular Plural Singular Plural Singular Plural First Person I We Me Us My, mine Our, ours Second Person You You You You Your, yours Your, yours Third Person He, she, it they Him her it them His, her, hers, its Their, theirs d.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Relation Between Grammatical Number and Cardinal Numbers in Development
    MINI REVIEW ARTICLE published: 09 October 2014 doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01132 On the relation between grammatical number and cardinal numbers in development Barbara W. Sarnecka * Department of Cognitive Sciences, University of California at Irvine, Irvine, CA, USA Edited by: This mini-review focuses on the question of how the grammatical number system of Ann Dowker, University of a child’s language may help the child learn the meanings of cardinal number words Oxford, UK (e.g., “one” and “two”). Evidence from young children learning English, Russian, Reviewed by: Emily Mather, University of Hull, UK Japanese, Mandarin, Slovenian, or Saudi Arabic suggests that trajectories of number-word Ruth Ford, Anglia Ruskin learning differ for children learning different languages. Children learning English, University, UK which distinguishes between singular and plural, seem to learn the meaning of the *Correspondence: cardinal number “one” earlier than children learning Japanese or Mandarin, which Barbara W. Sarnecka, Department have very little singular/plural marking. Similarly, children whose languages have a of Cognitive Sciences, University of California at Irvine, 3151 Social singular/dual/plural system (Slovenian and Saudi Arabic) learn the meaning of “two” earlier Sciences Plaza A, Irvine, CA than English-speaking children. This relation between grammatical and cardinal number 92697-5100, USA may shed light on how humans acquire cardinal-number concepts. There is an ongoing e-mail: [email protected] debate about whether mental symbols for small cardinalities (concepts for “oneness,” “twoness,” etc.) are innate or learned. Although an effect of grammatical number on number-word learning does not rule out nativist accounts, it seems more consistent with constructivist accounts, which portray the number-learning process as one that requires significant conceptual change.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Semantics
    HG2002 Semantics and Pragmatics Formal Semantics Francis Bond Division of Linguistics and Multilingual Studies http://www3.ntu.edu.sg/home/fcbond/ [email protected] Lecture 10 Location: HSS Auditorium Creative Commons Attribution License: you are free to share and adapt as long as you give appropriate credit and add no additional restrictions: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. HG2002 (2018) Overview ã Revision: Components ã Quantifiers and Higher Order Logic ã Modality ã (Dynamic Approaches to Discourse) ã Next Lecture: Chapter 11 — Cognitive Semantics HG2002 (2018) 1 Revision: Componential Analysis HG2002 (2018) 2 Break word meaning into its components ã components allow a compact description ã interact with morphology/syntax ã form part of our cognitive architecture ã For example: woman [female] [adult] [human] spinster [female] [adult] [human] [unmarried] bachelor [male] [adult] [human] [unmarried] wife [female] [adult] [human] [married] ã We can make things more economical (fewer components): woman [+female] [+adult] [+human] spinster [+female] [+adult] [+human] [–married] bachelor [–female] [+adult] [+human] [–married] wife [+female] [+adult] [+human] [+married] HG2002 (2018) 3 Defining Relations using Components ã hyponymy: P is a hyponym of Q if all the components of Q are also in P. spinster ⊂ woman; wife ⊂ woman ã incompatibility: P is incompatible with Q if they share some components but differ in one or more contrasting components spinster ̸≈ wife ã Redundancy Rules [+human] ! [+animate] [+animate] ! [+concrete] [+married]
    [Show full text]
  • Corpus Study of Tense, Aspect, and Modality in Diglossic Speech in Cairene Arabic
    CORPUS STUDY OF TENSE, ASPECT, AND MODALITY IN DIGLOSSIC SPEECH IN CAIRENE ARABIC BY OLA AHMED MOSHREF DISSERTATION Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics in the Graduate College of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2012 Urbana, Illinois Doctoral Committee: Professor Elabbas Benmamoun, Chair Professor Eyamba Bokamba Professor Rakesh M. Bhatt Assistant Professor Marina Terkourafi ABSTRACT Morpho-syntactic features of Modern Standard Arabic mix intricately with those of Egyptian Colloquial Arabic in ordinary speech. I study the lexical, phonological and syntactic features of verb phrase morphemes and constituents in different tenses, aspects, moods. A corpus of over 3000 phrases was collected from religious, political/economic and sports interviews on four Egyptian satellite TV channels. The computational analysis of the data shows that systematic and content morphemes from both varieties of Arabic combine in principled ways. Syntactic considerations play a critical role with regard to the frequency and direction of code-switching between the negative marker, subject, or complement on one hand and the verb on the other. Morph-syntactic constraints regulate different types of discourse but more formal topics may exhibit more mixing between Colloquial aspect or future markers and Standard verbs. ii To the One Arab Dream that will come true inshaa’ Allah! عربية أنا.. أميت دمها خري الدماء.. كما يقول أيب الشاعر العراقي: بدر شاكر السياب Arab I am.. My nation’s blood is the finest.. As my father says Iraqi Poet: Badr Shaker Elsayyab iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I’m sincerely thankful to my advisor Prof. Elabbas Benmamoun, who during the six years of my study at UIUC was always kind, caring and supportive on the personal and academic levels.
    [Show full text]
  • Collective Nouns Collective Nouns Are Names for a Collection Or a Number of People Or Things
    10/27/2018 What is a Collective Noun? Examples & Exercises | Ginger (//www.gingersoftware.com/) Grammar Rules << Back to Nouns (https://www.gingersoftware.com/content/grammar-rules/nouns/) Collective Nouns Collective nouns are names for a collection or a number of people or things. Words like group, herd, and array are collective noun examples. Here, we’ll take a closer look at collective nouns, and provide even more examples, placing them in context so you can gain a greater understanding of how they work. What is a Collective Noun You might not know it, but you encounter collective nouns in everyday speech. Collective nouns are words for single things that are made up of more than one person, animal, place, thing, or idea. You can’t have a team without individual members; even so, we discuss a team as a single entity. Collective Noun Examples Remember that nouns (http://www.gingersoftware.com/content/grammar-rules/nouns/) are words naming people, animals, places, and things. Collective nouns are in a class all their own. Once you’ve read these examples, you’ll find it much easier to recognize collective nouns when you see them. Our class took a field trip to the natural history museum. The herd of bison ran across the prairie, leaving a massive dust cloud in its wake. We waited anxiously for the jury to come to a verdict. This year’s basketball team includes three players who are over six feet tall. Napoleon’s army was finally defeated at Waterloo. The town council has approved plans to create a new park.
    [Show full text]
  • Number Systems in Grammar Position Paper
    1 Language and Culture Research Centre: 2018 Workshop Number systems in grammar - position paper Alexandra Y. Aikhenvald I Introduction I 2 The meanings of nominal number 2 3 Special number distinctions in personal pronouns 8 4 Number on verbs 9 5 The realisation of number 12 5.1 The forms 12 5.2 The loci: where number is shown 12 5.3 Optional and obligatory number marking 14 5.4 The limits of number 15 5.4.1 Number and the meanings of nouns 15 5.4.2 'Minor' numbers 16 5.4.3 The limits of number: nouns with defective number values 16 6 Number and noun categorisation 17 7 Markedness 18 8 Split, or mixed, number systems 19 9 Number and social deixis 19 10 Expressing number through other means 20 11 Number systems in language history 20 12 Summary 21 Further readings 22 Abbreviations 23 References 23 1 Introduction Every language has some means of distinguishing reference to one individual from reference to more than one. Number reference can be coded through lexical modifiers (including quantifiers of various sorts or number words etc.), or through a grammatical system. Number is a referential property of an argument of the predicate. A grammatical system of number can be shown either • Overtly, on a noun, a pronoun, a verb, etc., directly referring to how many people or things are involved; or • Covertly, through agreement or other means. Number may be marked: • within an NP • on the head of an NP • by agreement process on a modifier (adjective, article, demonstrative, etc.) • through agreement on verbs, or special suppletive or semi-suppletive verb forms which may code the number of one or more verbal arguments, or additional marker on the verb.
    [Show full text]
  • Full and Null Pronouns in Spanish: the Zero Pronoun Hypothesis
    Full and Null Pronouns in Spanish: the Zero Pronoun Hypothesis*. Luis Alonso-Ovalle & Francesco D’Introno University of Massachusetts at Amherst 1. The Puzzle Montalbetti (1984) points out certain semantic differences between phonetically full and phonetically empty pronouns (henceforth full and null pronouns) that challenge the traditional interpretive parallelism between empty and full categories (see Chomsky 1981, 1982). He shows that both in subject (1) and object position (2), while null pronouns can be interpreted as bound variables (as in (1a) and (2a) ), full pronouns cannot (as in (1c) and (2c)).1 (1) a. Nadiei sabe que proi vendrá. Nobody know:3S that pro come:3SFUT ‘Nobodyi knows that hei will come’. b. ~∃x ( person’ (x) & ( know’ (x) ( come’(x) ) )2 c. *Nadiei sabe que éli vendrá. Nobody know:3S that pro come3SFUT ‘Nobodyi knows that hej will come’. d. ~∃x ( person’ (x) & ( know’ (x) ( come’(y) ) ) (2) a. Nadiei sabe que el profesor lo vigila proi Nobody know:3S that the teacher HIM-CL watch-over:3S pro ‘Nobodyi knows that the teacher watches over himi’. b. ~∃x ( person’ (x) & know’ (x) (watch-over’ (p) (x) ) ) c. *Nadiei sabe que el profesor lo vigila a éli. Nobody know:3S that the teacher HIM-CL watch-over:3s him ‘Nobodyi knows that the teacher watches over himj’. d. ~∃x ( person’(x) & know’ (x) (watch-over’ (p) (y) ) ) Contrasts like those under (1) and (2) seem to suggest that a principle equivalent to (3) has to be taken to describe the strategy responsible for anaphora resolution in Spanish3. (3) Variable binding is restricted to null pronouns.
    [Show full text]
  • Serial Verb Constructions: Argument Structural Uniformity and Event Structural Diversity
    SERIAL VERB CONSTRUCTIONS: ARGUMENT STRUCTURAL UNIFORMITY AND EVENT STRUCTURAL DIVERSITY A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS AND THE COMMITTEE ON GRADUATE STUDIES OF STANFORD UNIVERSITY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Melanie Owens November 2011 © 2011 by Melanie Rachel Owens. All Rights Reserved. Re-distributed by Stanford University under license with the author. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- Noncommercial 3.0 United States License. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/us/ This dissertation is online at: http://purl.stanford.edu/db406jt2949 ii I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Beth Levin, Primary Adviser I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Joan Bresnan I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Vera Gribanov Approved for the Stanford University Committee on Graduate Studies. Patricia J. Gumport, Vice Provost Graduate Education This signature page was generated electronically upon submission of this dissertation in electronic format. An original signed hard copy of the signature page is on file in University Archives. iii Abstract Serial Verb Constructions (SVCs) are constructions which contain two or more verbs yet behave in every grammatical respect as if they contain only one.
    [Show full text]
  • 3 Types of Anaphors
    3 Types of anaphors Moving from the definition and characteristics of anaphors to the types of ana- phors, this chapter will detail the nomenclature of anaphor types established for this book. In general, anaphors can be categorised according to: their form; the type of relationship to their antecedent; the form of their antecedents; the position of anaphors and antecedents, i.e. intrasentential or intersentential; and other features (cf. Mitkov 2002: 8-17). The procedure adopted here is to catego- rise anaphors according to their form. It should be stressed that the types dis- tinguished in this book are not universal categories, so the proposed classifica- tion is not the only possible solution. For instance, personal, possessive and re- flexive pronouns can be seen as three types or as one type. With the latter, the three pronoun classes are subsumed under the term “central pronouns”, as it is adopted here. Linguistic classifications of anaphors can be found in two established gram- mar books, namely in Quirk et al.’s A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language (2012: 865) and in The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language (Stirling & Huddleston 2010: 1449-1564). Quirk et al. include a chapter of pro- forms and here distinguish between coreference and substitution. However, they do not take anaphors as their starting point of categorisation. Additionally, Stirling & Huddleston do not consider anaphors on their own but together with deixis. As a result, anaphoric noun phrases with a definite article, for example, are not included in both categorisations. Furthermore, Schubert (2012: 31-55) presents a text-linguistic view, of which anaphors are part, but his classification is similarly unsuitable because it does not focus on the anaphoric items specifi- cally.
    [Show full text]