Serial Verb Constructions: Argument Structural Uniformity and Event Structural Diversity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Serial Verb Constructions: Argument Structural Uniformity and Event Structural Diversity SERIAL VERB CONSTRUCTIONS: ARGUMENT STRUCTURAL UNIFORMITY AND EVENT STRUCTURAL DIVERSITY A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS AND THE COMMITTEE ON GRADUATE STUDIES OF STANFORD UNIVERSITY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Melanie Owens November 2011 © 2011 by Melanie Rachel Owens. All Rights Reserved. Re-distributed by Stanford University under license with the author. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- Noncommercial 3.0 United States License. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/us/ This dissertation is online at: http://purl.stanford.edu/db406jt2949 ii I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Beth Levin, Primary Adviser I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Joan Bresnan I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Vera Gribanov Approved for the Stanford University Committee on Graduate Studies. Patricia J. Gumport, Vice Provost Graduate Education This signature page was generated electronically upon submission of this dissertation in electronic format. An original signed hard copy of the signature page is on file in University Archives. iii Abstract Serial Verb Constructions (SVCs) are constructions which contain two or more verbs yet behave in every grammatical respect as if they contain only one. This observation guides my approach to SVCs in this dissertation, in accord with which SVCs are de- fined through displaying (i) no markers of subordination or coordination, (ii) uniform tense, aspect and/or mood values, (iii) the phonological properties of a clause headed by a single verb, and (iv) any other properties that signify monoclausal status in the language concerned. But while (i)-(iv) are standard defining properties for SVCs, I propose a further new defining property: the Theta Structure Property for SVCs, which requires that a SVC display monoclausal argument structure. The Theta Structure Property – so called because it holds at the argument struc- ture level of Theta Structure in Lexical Decompositional Grammar (LDG) – requires that a SVC display the same number of structural arguments and the same list of configurationally-defined non-structural (oblique) arguments as some clause headed by a single verb (in some language). But while some SVCs, called ‘Possible Verb’ SVCs, satisfy this property straightforwardly by virtue of the fact that they have ex- actly the semantic content of a clause headed by a single verb, there is an additional, non-core class of ‘Impossible Verb’ SVCs for whom satisfaction of the Theta Structure Property is more complex. The basis for the Possible Verb-Impossible Verb distinction are LDG’s Possible Verbs constraints, which determine the semantic content of what can be expressed in a clause headed by a single verb. Possible Verb SVCs satisfy these constraints, but Impossible Verb SVCs, in not satisfying these constraints, have more complex semantic contents and argument structures. Special predicate combining operations iv (mainly consisting of argument coidentification operations) must apply in order for an Impossible Verb SVC to satisfy the Theta Structure Property for SVCs; these op- erations deliver (monoclausal) argument structural uniformity across SVCs, although SVCs still display considerable event structural diversity. Event structural analysis features prominently in this dissertation, primarily for the purpose of demarcating the boundaries of Possible Verb and Impossible Verb SVCs. In some instances these two types of SVC can be difficult to distinguish, as the case studies of instrumental and motion SVCs of Chapters 4 and 5 demonstrate. But if certain instrumental and motion SVCs present some rather subtle cases of Impossible Verb serialization, there are Impossible Verb SVCs outside these domains, such as (A), which more blatantly lack the semantic content or event structure of a clause headed by a single verb: ` (A) Oz´o kp`e´e `em`a d´e. Ozo beat drum buy ‘Ozo beat the drum (and then) bought it.’ (Edo; Stewart 2001, 49) Why are SVCs like (A), whose content could never be expressed in a clause headed by a single verb, behaving as if they contain only one verb? One of the most interest- ing answers to this question is that multi-event concepts are expressed in SVC form in those instances where they describe ‘recognizable event types’ – a combination of actions that cooccur so often as to be conceptualized as a single event. However, Stewart (2001) gives no indication that (A) expresses a recognizable event type. Are SVCs always constrained by some conceptualization of eventhood (recognizable event type or otherwise)? Are SVCs in some languages completely event structurally uncon- strained? And does (A) really behave in every grammatical respect as if it contains only one verb? These questions are addressed in the concluding chapter, drawing on the cross-linguistically expanded survey of SVCs built up in the preceding chapters. v Acknowledgements Although I don’t think I’ve broken any records, my dissertation completion timeline has definitely been of the extended variety, and so I’d like to thank my advisor Beth Levin for never giving up hope that I’d finish, and for her helpful advice and input right up until the very end. Beth is extremely dedicated to all her students, and in my case one manifestation of this was her effort to meet up with me several times in England, after I’d moved away from Stanford in 2005. I also thank Joan Bresnan for unquestioningly turning up at my dissertation defense in June, as if five years had never elapsed, and for her positive, encouraging and often funny outlook on linguistics and life in general. The other key faculty member who made the completion of my PhD possible this year was Vera Gribanova, who I’m so grateful to for joining my committee for the defense this summer, and for moreover engaging with what I’d written and asking helpful and thought-provoking questions. Many thanks also to Noah Goodman as the committee chair, to Tom Wasow for stepping in as the fourth reader, and to Arnold Zwicky for his help and insight in the early stages of my dissertation. Unfortunately it feels like years since I’ve been anywhere near Indonesia or things Indonesian, but I certainly owe a lot to my Bima friends who helped with the Bima components of my dissertation. First and foremost there is Yanti in New Zealand, who ignited my interest in her native language, and I also thank Mike Dukes for finding Yanti in the first place, and running a great field methods class around her at University of Canterbury. Many thanks also to all my Bima friends in Bima and Mataram who looked after me so well when I was there. When I think of my time at Stanford, what made it so enjoyable was of course vi the company of my fellow students, and for that I especially thank John, Itamar and Na’ama, Ela, Ivan, Andrew and Melissa, Judith, Lev, Philip, Lis, Jeanette, and Susanne. A huge thanks also to Dave SC, for being a kind of honorary linguistics student, but more importantly a great friend, and someone who put me up every time I came back to the Bay area. My final and most heartfelt thanks are naturally reserved for my family; for Mum, Dad, Sam and Jackie in New Zealand, for Philip and Ruth, who were instrumental in helping me complete the dissertation by way of providing childcare and support, and for Paddy, Ele, Alison, and Dorothy. Special thanks also to Lawrence, for being such a good little boy, and to Meredith for being a very good baby since her arrival seven weeks ago. But more than anyone else I want to thank my wonderful husband David, who has supported me, and my dissertation, in every way possible over the last few years. Over the last few weeks he has taken charge of my disastrously incomplete bibliography, which, although a major undertaking in itself, only forms a small part of everything he has done for me. vii Contents Abstract iv Acknowledgements vi 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Introduction................................ 1 1.2 PreviousworkonSVCs.......................... 8 1.2.1 DefinitionsofSVCs. .. .. 11 1.2.2 ArgumentstructureofSVCs. 16 1.2.3 SyntaxofSVCs .......................... 22 1.2.4 EventstructureofSVCs . 26 1.2.5 Conclusion............................. 38 1.3 Prospectus................................. 39 1.3.1 The Theta Structure Property for SVCs . 39 1.3.2 The Possible Verb-Impossible Verb distinction in SVCs.... 43 1.3.3 In search of Impossible Verb SVCs, and their limits . ... 46 2 The Theta Structure Property for SVCs 51 2.1 Introduction................................ 51 2.2 LexicalDecompositionGrammar . 53 2.3 TheThetaStructurePropertyforSVCs . 66 2.3.1 TheProperty ........................... 66 2.3.2 Structural arguments and the Theta Structure Property for SVCs 68 viii 2.3.3 Non-structural arguments and the Theta Structure Pro-perty forSVCs.............................. 71 2.4 Projecting the arguments of contiguous and non-contiguous SVCs . 77 2.4.1 Non-contiguousSVCs. 80 2.4.2 ContiguousSVCs ......................... 93 2.4.3 Conclusion............................. 100 2.5 Conclusion................................. 103 3 Possible Verb and Impossible Verb SVCs 109 3.1 Introduction................................ 109 3.2 PossibleVerbSVCs............................ 111 3.2.1 Satisfying the Possible Verbs constraints . ... 111 3.2.2 Serialization lexical rules and Possible Verb SVCs . ..... 115 3.2.3 Event structures for Possible Verb SVCs . 124 3.2.4 Conclusion............................. 130 3.3 ImpossibleVerbSVCs . .. .. 131 3.3.1 Event structures for Impossible Verb SVCs .
Recommended publications
  • Long and Short Adjunct Fronting in HPSG
    Long and Short Adjunct Fronting in HPSG Takafumi Maekawa Department of Language and Linguistics University of Essex Proceedings of the 13th International Conference on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar Linguistic Modelling Laboratory, Institute for Parallel Processing, Bulgarian Academy of Sciences, Sofia, Held in Varna Stefan Muller¨ (Editor) 2006 CSLI Publications pages 212–227 http://csli-publications.stanford.edu/HPSG/2006 Maekawa, Takafumi. 2006. Long and Short Adjunct Fronting in HPSG. In Muller,¨ Stefan (Ed.), Proceedings of the 13th International Conference on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar, Varna, 212–227. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications. Abstract The purpose of this paper is to consider the proper treatment of short- and long-fronted adjuncts within HPSG. In the earlier HPSG analyses, a rigid link between linear order and constituent structure determines the linear position of such adjuncts in the sentence-initial position. This paper argues that there is a body of data which suggests that ad- junct fronting does not work as these approaches predict. It is then shown that linearisation-based HPSG can provide a fairly straightfor- ward account of the facts. 1 Introduction The purpose of this paper is to consider the proper treatment of short- and long-fronted adjuncts within HPSG. ∗ The following sentences are typical examples. (1) a. On Saturday , will Dana go to Spain? (Short-fronted adjunct) b. Yesterday I believe Kim left. (Long-fronted adjunct) In earlier HPSG analyses, a rigid link between linear order and constituent structure determines the linear position of such adverbials in the sen- tence-initial position. I will argue that there is a body of data which sug- gests that adjunct fronting does not work as these approaches predict.
    [Show full text]
  • Representation of Inflected Nouns in the Internal Lexicon
    Memory & Cognition 1980, Vol. 8 (5), 415423 Represeritation of inflected nouns in the internal lexicon G. LUKATELA, B. GLIGORIJEVIC, and A. KOSTIC University ofBelgrade, Belgrade, Yugoslavia and M.T.TURVEY University ofConnecticut, Storrs, Connecticut 06268 and Haskins Laboratories, New Haven, Connecticut 06510 The lexical representation of Serbo-Croatian nouns was investigated in a lexical decision task. Because Serbo-Croatian nouns are declined, a noun may appear in one of several gram­ matical cases distinguished by the inflectional morpheme affixed to the base form. The gram­ matical cases occur with different frequencies, although some are visually and phonetically identical. When the frequencies of identical forms are compounded, the ordering of frequencies is not the same for masculine and feminine genders. These two genders are distinguished further by the fact that the base form for masculine nouns is an actual grammatical case, the nominative singular, whereas the base form for feminine nouns is an abstraction in that it cannot stand alone as an independent word. Exploiting these characteristics of the Serbo­ Croatian language, we contrasted three views of how a noun is represented: (1) the independent­ entries hypothesis, which assumes an independent representation for each grammatical case, reflecting its frequency of occurrence; (2) the derivational hypothesis, which assumes that only the base morpheme is stored, with the individual cases derived from separately stored inflec­ tional morphemes and rules for combination; and (3) the satellite-entries hypothesis, which assumes that all cases are individually represented, with the nominative singular functioning as the nucleus and the embodiment of the noun's frequency and around which the other cases cluster uniformly.
    [Show full text]
  • Animacy and Alienability: a Reconsideration of English
    Running head: ANIMACY AND ALIENABILITY 1 Animacy and Alienability A Reconsideration of English Possession Jaimee Jones A Senior Thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation in the Honors Program Liberty University Spring 2016 ANIMACY AND ALIENABILITY 2 Acceptance of Senior Honors Thesis This Senior Honors Thesis is accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation from the Honors Program of Liberty University. ______________________________ Jaeshil Kim, Ph.D. Thesis Chair ______________________________ Paul Müller, Ph.D. Committee Member ______________________________ Jeffrey Ritchey, Ph.D. Committee Member ______________________________ Brenda Ayres, Ph.D. Honors Director ______________________________ Date ANIMACY AND ALIENABILITY 3 Abstract Current scholarship on English possessive constructions, the s-genitive and the of- construction, largely ignores the possessive relationships inherent in certain English compound nouns. Scholars agree that, in general, an animate possessor predicts the s- genitive while an inanimate possessor predicts the of-construction. However, the current literature rarely discusses noun compounds, such as the table leg, which also express possessive relationships. However, pragmatically and syntactically, a compound cannot be considered as a true possessive construction. Thus, this paper will examine why some compounds still display possessive semantics epiphenomenally. The noun compounds that imply possession seem to exhibit relationships prototypical of inalienable possession such as body part, part whole, and spatial relationships. Additionally, the juxtaposition of the possessor and possessum in the compound construction is reminiscent of inalienable possession in other languages. Therefore, this paper proposes that inalienability, a phenomenon not thought to be relevant in English, actually imbues noun compounds whose components exhibit an inalienable relationship with possessive semantics.
    [Show full text]
  • On Binding Asymmetries in Dative Alternation Constructions in L2 Spanish
    On Binding Asymmetries in Dative Alternation Constructions in L2 Spanish Silvia Perpiñán and Silvina Montrul University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign 1. Introduction Ditransitive verbs can take a direct object and an indirect object. In English and many other languages, the order of these objects can be altered, giving as a result the Dative Construction on the one hand (I sent a package to my parents) and the Double Object Construction, (I sent my parents a package, hereafter DOC), on the other. However, not all ditransitive verbs can participate in this alternation. The study of the English dative alternation has been a recurrent topic in the language acquisition literature. This argument-structure alternation is widely recognized as an exemplar of the poverty of stimulus problem: from a limited set of data in the input, the language acquirer must somehow determine which verbs allow the alternating syntactic forms and which ones do not: you can give money to someone and donate money to someone; you can also give someone money but you definitely cannot *donate someone money. Since Spanish, apparently, does not allow DOC (give someone money), L2 learners of Spanish whose mother tongue is English have to become aware of this restriction in Spanish, without negative evidence. However, it has been noticed by Demonte (1995) and Cuervo (2001) that Spanish has a DOC, which is not identical, but which shares syntactic and, crucially, interpretive restrictions with the English counterpart. Moreover, within the Spanish Dative Construction, the order of the objects can also be inverted without superficial morpho-syntactic differences, (Pablo mandó una carta a la niña ‘Pablo sent a letter to the girl’ vs.
    [Show full text]
  • 2008. Pruning Some Branches from 'Branching Spacetimes'
    CHAPTER 10 Pruning Some Branches from “Branching Spacetimes” John Earman* Abstract Discussions of branching time and branching spacetime have become com- mon in the philosophical literature. If properly understood, these concep- tions can be harmless. But they are sometimes used in the service of debat- able and even downright pernicious doctrines. The purpose of this chapter is to identify the pernicious branching and prune it back. 1. INTRODUCTION Talk of “branching time” and “branching spacetime” is wide spread in the philo- sophical literature. Such expressions, if properly understood, can be innocuous. But they are sometimes used in the service of debatable and even downright per- nicious doctrines. The purpose of this paper is to identify the pernicious branching and prune it back. Section 2 distinguishes three types of spacetime branching: individual branch- ing, ensemble branching, and Belnap branching. Individual branching, as the name indicates, involves a branching structure in individual spacetime models. It is argued that such branching is neither necessary nor sufficient for indeterminism, which is explicated in terms of the branching in the ensemble of spacetime mod- els satisfying the laws of physics. Belnap branching refers to the sort of branching used by the Belnap school of branching spacetimes. An attempt is made to sit- uate this sort of branching with respect to ensemble branching and individual branching. Section 3 is a sustained critique of various ways of trying to imple- ment individual branching for relativistic spacetimes. Conclusions are given in Section 4. * Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, USA The Ontology of Spacetime II © Elsevier BV ISSN 1871-1774, DOI: 10.1016/S1871-1774(08)00010-7 All rights reserved 187 188 Pruning Some Branches from “Branching Spacetimes” 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Layers and Operators in Lakota1 Avelino Corral Esteban Universidad Autónoma De Madrid
    Kansas Working Papers in Linguistics, Vol. 36 (2015), 1-33 Layers and operators in Lakota1 Avelino Corral Esteban Universidad Autónoma de Madrid Abstract Categories covering the expression of grammatical information such as aspect, negation, tense, mood, modality, etc., are crucial to the study of language universals. In this study, I will present an analysis of the syntax and semantics of these grammatical categories in Lakota within the Role and Reference Grammar framework (hereafter RRG) (Van Valin 1993, 2005; Van Valin and LaPolla 1997), a functional approach in which elements with a purely grammatical function are treated as ´operators`. Many languages mark Aspect-Tense- Mood/Modality information (henceforth ATM) either morphologically or syntactically. Unlike most Native American languages, which exhibit an extremely complex verbal morphological system indicating this grammatical information, Lakota, a Siouan language with a mildly synthetic / partially agglutinative morphology, expresses information relating to ATM through enclitics, auxiliary verbs and adverbs, rather than by coding it through verbal affixes. 1. Introduction The organisation of this paper is as follows: after a brief account of the most relevant morpho- syntactic features exhibited by Lakota, Section 2 attempts to shed light on the distinction between lexical words, enclitics and affixes through evidence obtained in the study of this language. Section 3 introduces the notion of ´operator` and explores the ATM system in Lakota using RRG´s theory of operator system. After a description of each grammatical category, an analysis of the linear order exhibited by the Lakota operators with respect to the nucleus of the clause are analysed in Section 4, showing that this ordering reflects the scope relations between the grammatical categories conveyed by these operators.
    [Show full text]
  • Serial Verb Constructions in English and Chinese
    SERIAL VERB CONSTRUCTIONS IN ENGLISH AND CHINESE Hui Yin University of Alberta Traditionally, the term serial verb construction refers to a sequence of verbs or verb phrases in a sentence in which there is no intervening conjunction. The English expression go eat, for example, might be considered as a kind of serial verb construction since there is no infinitive or other morphosyntactic marker present to indicate a coordinating or subordinating relationship between the two verbs go and eat. English is traditionally termed as a non-serial language; however, this does not suggest that in English there is no serial verb construction (SVC). Chinese is classified as a serial language; however, according to the results obtained from the Lancaster Corpus of Mandarin Chinese only one out of five sentences contains serial verbs though Chinese is thought to have high frequency in serial verbs. In fact, the issue of serial or non-serial language is basically a matter of frequency. 1. Common Types of VV Sequence in English and Chinese Although Chinese and English is different in the total number of SVC types the following three types of VV sequence are found to be common across English and Chinese: (1) purposive SVCs a. go eat (English) b. qu chifan (Chinese) ‘go eat’ (2) causative SVCs a. I made him laugh. (English) b. Wo shi ta xiao. (Chinese) I make him laugh ‘I made him laugh.’ (3) perceptive SVCs a. I saw him laugh. (English) b. Wo kan ta youyong. (Chinese) I see he swim ‘I saw him swim’ However, it has been noticed that not any VV sequence or multi-verb structure can be regarded as an SVC.
    [Show full text]
  • The Term Declension, the Three Basic Qualities of Latin Nouns, That
    Chapter 2: First Declension Chapter 2 covers the following: the term declension, the three basic qualities of Latin nouns, that is, case, number and gender, basic sentence structure, subject, verb, direct object and so on, the six cases of Latin nouns and the uses of those cases, the formation of the different cases in Latin, and the way adjectives agree with nouns. At the end of this lesson we’ll review the vocabulary you should memorize in this chapter. Declension. As with conjugation, the term declension has two meanings in Latin. It means, first, the process of joining a case ending onto a noun base. Second, it is a term used to refer to one of the five categories of nouns distinguished by the sound ending the noun base: /a/, /ŏ/ or /ŭ/, a consonant or /ĭ/, /ū/, /ē/. First, let’s look at the three basic characteristics of every Latin noun: case, number and gender. All Latin nouns and adjectives have these three grammatical qualities. First, case: how the noun functions in a sentence, that is, is it the subject, the direct object, the object of a preposition or any of many other uses? Second, number: singular or plural. And third, gender: masculine, feminine or neuter. Every noun in Latin will have one case, one number and one gender, and only one of each of these qualities. In other words, a noun in a sentence cannot be both singular and plural, or masculine and feminine. Whenever asked ─ and I will ask ─ you should be able to give the correct answer for all three qualities.
    [Show full text]
  • LINGUISTICS 221 Lecture #3 DISTINCTIVE FEATURES Part 1. an Utterance Is Composed of a Sequence of Discrete Segments. Is the Segm
    LINGUISTICS 221 Lecture #3 DISTINCTIVE FEATURES Part 1. An utterance is composed of a sequence of discrete segments. Is the segment indivisible? Is the segment the smallest unit of phonological analysis? If it is, segments ought to differ randomly from one another. Yet this is not true: pt k prs What is the relationship between members of the two groups? p t k - the members of this set have an internal relationship: they are all voiceles stops. p r s - no such relationship exists p b d s bilabial bilabial alveolar alveolar stop stop stop fricative voiceless voiced voiced voiceless SIMILARITIES AND DIFFERENCES! Segments may be viewed as composed of sets of properties rather than indivisible entities. We can show the relationship by listing the properties of each segment. DISTINCTIVE FEATURES • enable us to describe the segments in the world’s languages: all segments in any language can be characterized in some unique combination of features • identifies groups of segments → natural segment classes: they play a role in phonological processes and constraints • distinctive features must be referred to in terms of phonetic -- articulatory or acoustic -- characteristics. 1 Requirements on distinctive feature systems (p. 66): • they must be capable of characterizing natural segment classes • they must be capable of describing all segmental contrasts in all languages • they should be definable in phonetic terms The features fulfill three functions: a. They are capable of describing the segment: a phonetic function b. They serve to differentiate lexical items: a phonological function c. They define natural segment classes: i.e. those segments which as a group undergo similar phonological processes.
    [Show full text]
  • Definiteness and Determinacy
    Linguistics and Philosophy manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Definiteness and Determinacy Elizabeth Coppock · David Beaver the date of receipt and acceptance should be inserted later Abstract This paper distinguishes between definiteness and determinacy. Defi- niteness is seen as a morphological category which, in English, marks a (weak) uniqueness presupposition, while determinacy consists in denoting an individual. Definite descriptions are argued to be fundamentally predicative, presupposing uniqueness but not existence, and to acquire existential import through general type-shifting operations that apply not only to definites, but also indefinites and possessives. Through these shifts, argumental definite descriptions may become either determinate (and thus denote an individual) or indeterminate (functioning as an existential quantifier). The latter option is observed in examples like `Anna didn't give the only invited talk at the conference', which, on its indeterminate reading, implies that there is nothing in the extension of `only invited talk at the conference'. The paper also offers a resolution of the issue of whether posses- sives are inherently indefinite or definite, suggesting that, like indefinites, they do not mark definiteness lexically, but like definites, they typically yield determinate readings due to a general preference for the shifting operation that produces them. Keywords definiteness · descriptions · possessives · predicates · type-shifting We thank Dag Haug, Reinhard Muskens, Luca Crniˇc,Cleo Condoravdi, Lucas
    [Show full text]
  • Verbal Case and the Nature of Polysynthetic Inflection
    Verbal case and the nature of polysynthetic inflection Colin Phillips MIT Abstract This paper tries to resolve a conflict in the literature on the connection between ‘rich’ agreement and argument-drop. Jelinek (1984) claims that inflectional affixes in polysynthetic languages are theta-role bearing arguments; Baker (1991) argues that such affixes are agreement, bearing Case but no theta-role. Evidence from Yimas shows that both of these views can be correct, within a single language. Explanation of what kind of inflection is used where also provides us with an account of the unusual split ergative agreement system of Yimas, and suggests a novel explanation for the ban on subject incorporation, and some exceptions to the ban. 1. Two types of inflection My main aim in this paper is to demonstrate that inflectional affixes can be very different kinds of syntactic objects, even within a single language. I illustrate this point with evidence from Yimas, a Papuan language of New Guinea (Foley 1991). Understanding of the nature of the different inflectional affixes of Yimas provides an explanation for its remarkably elaborate agreement system, which follows a basic split-ergative scheme, but with a number of added complications. Anticipating my conclusions, the structure in (1c) shows what I assume the four principal case affixes on a Yimas verb to be. What I refer to as Nominative and Accusative affixes are pronominal arguments: these inflections, which are restricted to 1st and 2nd person arguments in Yimas, begin as specifiers and complements of the verb, and incorporate into the verb by S- structure. On the other hand, what I refer to as Ergative and Absolutive inflection are genuine agreement - they are the spell-out of functional heads, above VP, which agree with an argument in their specifier.
    [Show full text]
  • Serial Verb Constructions in Pitjantjatjara and Yankunytjatjara
    The ITB Journal Volume 14 Issue 1 Article 3 2013 Serial Verb Constructions in Pitjantjatjara and Yankunytjatjara Conor Pyle Trinity College Dublin Follow this and additional works at: https://arrow.tudublin.ie/itbj Part of the Anthropological Linguistics and Sociolinguistics Commons Recommended Citation Pyle, Conor (2013) "Serial Verb Constructions in Pitjantjatjara and Yankunytjatjara," The ITB Journal: Vol. 14: Iss. 1, Article 3. doi:10.21427/D7SM9Z Available at: https://arrow.tudublin.ie/itbj/vol14/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Ceased publication at ARROW@TU Dublin. It has been accepted for inclusion in The ITB Journal by an authorized administrator of ARROW@TU Dublin. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 4.0 License Serial Verb Constructions in Pitjantjatjara and Yankunytjatjara Conor Pyle Trinity College Dublin ABSTRACT This study looks at serial verb constructions in two dialects of the Western Desert language of Australia, Pitjantjatjara and Yankunytjatjara. With a Role and Reference Grammar analysis, the paradigm allows us to look at the constituents for logical structure, and marking of macroroles. We find that core and peripheral argument phrases are marked by case with ergative nominal marking and accusative pronoun marking. Dependent marking is on the phrase level and there is no verb agreement for number, gender or person marking on the verb. Simple verbs use endings for tense, aspect, mood and status. The operator projection shows the nature of linkage between the verbs involved in multi verb structures.
    [Show full text]