Lecture 10.2: Stoics and the Hellenistic World Rorty UCSC I

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Lecture 10.2: Stoics and the Hellenistic World Rorty UCSC I Lecture 10.2: Stoics and the Hellenistic World Rorty UCSC I: The School They talk about the school in two stages: the Early Stoa, and the Late Stoa. Three names associated with the original ‘school’: Zeno of Citium, a Cypriot (244-262 BC) Cleanthes, from Asia Minor (died c. 232 BC) Chrysippus (died c. 206 BC) The texts of the Early Stoa are as scattered and fragmentary as those of the pre-socratics—but the doxography is much better. Many of the same people who are the sources of the fragments of the Presocratics are also responsible for the reports of the doctrines attributed to the early stoa. The doctrines of the school are considered to have been solidified pretty much by Chrysippus. The only complete works of the stoics we have are from the Latin stoics: primarily Seneca (4 BC-65 AD) Epictetus (55-135 AD) Marcus Aurelius (121-180 AD) Epictetus was a Turkish slave; Marcus Aurelius was a Roman emperor. It was a very cosmopolitan school; the people who figure in its history came from all over Alexander’s empire, and were associated by doctrines rather than common background. The same conditions that lead us to our current concern with multiculturalism were the conditions that obtained in the Hellenistic period. Alexander conquered the known world; his empire extended north to Germany, east through Asia minor to Egypt, west through Spain… One empire means lax borders; heavy trade (in ideas as well as objects); a lingua franca , a common language (not French, as it was at one time in Europe and Africa, nor English, as it is now coming to be the case in this century)—but the common language of greek, and later, as the center of empire moved to Rome, Latin. It means free movement across what used to be borders: we are all equally citizens of Alexander’s empire, and later, of the Roman empire. And—we are all, by this point in the Mediterranean, literate cultures. I’m not saying that there was universal literacy; but there were throughout the empire, everywhere, people who read; and they all read the works of all the sages, the philosophers, the schools. The writings of a sage were (as Sloterdjik says of all the classical texts, well into modernity) “letters to unknown friends,” inviting them to join a community of like-minded people; catching hold of common needs and experiences, offering a way of looking at the world which could catch the imagination of someone hundreds of miles away, raised in a different language or time…1 They did have a place, though, for a while: the Stoa, the porch—an architectural feature of the main marketplace of Athens, where the Cypriot Zeno established his school. I imagine the Athenian agora to be the equivalent of Hyde Park in London, or the Plaza up at UC Berkeley—a place where people hung out to harangue each other. Zeno sort of took over that corner of the public space, and the name of the school traces back to that formative location, however far it later spread. And it was a school, in the sense of a school of thought. People who considered themselves stoics were united by a body of doctrine in three divisions: physics, logic and ethics. The Later Stoics were mainly interested in the ethics (which is what makes them such fun to read); so information about the physics is sort of scanty. II: The Doctrines As the Epicureans stood to Democritus, so stood the Stoics to Heraclitus. Now as you know, I LOVE Heraclitus. I like his images: the universality of booming, throbbing life saturating all; his paradoxes of identity—that you can’t step into the same river twice; that ‘into the 1 For Sloterdjik on the subject of humanistic education (and its decline) see “Sloterdijk: Elmauer Rede” on my website, main page, under “papers.” (“For Love of the Game” at the same location is a comment on that paper. 1 same river we both step and do not step, we are and are not’; his quotable quotes: “this world is and ever will be an ever-living fire, kindling in measures and going out in measures…” Can’t beat it. But the Stoics remind me of the dangers of reading too much Heraclitus; or at least, of taking him too literally. Their understanding of the nature of the world is a Heraclitean monism. 1. They are materialists (of a heraclitean, not a democritean, sort) --and the material is itself, of itself, dynamic. I think when we were talking about Heraclitus I introduced the term “ hylozoism ”—animate matter. The ultimate material of the universe is not inert, as Aristotle (or modern mechanics) might have it—but something which is to be understood as an integrated unity of concrete energy. Heraclitus calls it ‘fire’; the Stoics understand it as pneuma , ‘fiery breath.’ (see my p. 483) (In this reading of the stoics as hylozoistic monists, by the way, I am disagreeing with the editors of our text on my p.474: they describe the stoics as having two principles, pneuma and matter. Some of the other commentators take this tack too, so consider this one of the many places this quarter where your Talking Head has imposed her own interpretation upon you.) The universe is of one stuff throughout, although it takes various forms, or modes, or currents – the 4 elements, and through them, the various bodies and things that occupy the world. Force is coextensive with ‘matter’ in this sense, and it is not passive . What the stoics call ‘tension’ is the essential attribute of body. [Personally, I think that is darned clever. As I may have said in other connections, once you separate things out, you have the devil of a time putting them back together again; and the hylozoism of the presocratics keeps matter and energy interconnected in a way that modern physics seems to me to find sympathetic. If the Epicureans were corpuscularian materialists, the Stoics were something closer to modern atomic theory.] 2. Their monism is a pantheism. As you may remember, for Heraclitus, logos=fire=god. The same thing is true for the Stoics. God is as much material as the world itself is (namely, one manifestation of pneuma ); and saturates the world throughout; and the soul has the same relation to the body (=microcosmic/macrocosmic analogy). AND, furthermore—the nature of that soul is identical with the nature of god—providing the basis for a soterical claim that the soul after death can be reunited with the divine. God is logos, nomos and hegemenon: reason, mind and ruling principle; and so is the soul, with respect to our body. 3. The universe is strictly deterministic. Since god is reason, it follows that the world is governed by reason; and this means two things. First, it means that there is purpose in the world, and therefore order, harmony, beauty and design. Secondly, since reason is the law of nature, it means that the universe is subject to the absolute sway of law, is governed by the rigorous necessity of cause and effect. The stoic lives in a deterministic, and determined, world. (It may, indeed, it must, be the best possible world, too, since by the logic we’ve been pursuing it is the only possible world.) One of the stoic stories that sticks in my mind is a definition of freedom. The image is of a dog tied on a short leash behind a cart. The cart is being driven down the road. But the dog is absolutely free: he can choose to assent, or to refuse to assent. He can choose whether to run after the cart—or be dragged. 2 Furthermore, that world is subject to eternal recurrence. There is a cycle to our cosmos; it will be consumed by a conflagration, and will in endless cycles re-emerge and repeat itself. 4. Psychology This pantheism/panpsychism has implications for the stoic doctrines about the operations of the soul, both for perception, and for action. a--perception The soul is not tripartite, or in any other way divided or divisible. It is the one rational soul that has sensations; assents to judgments; is impelled (or not) toward objects of desire; just as much as 2 --A philosopher’s joke: What’s the difference between a stoic and an existentialist? For the stoic, freedom is choosing to run after cart. For the existentialist, freedom is to be dragged. 2 it thinks or reasons. The difference between thinking and perceiving is that one is in the absence of its object, the other in its presence. So perception for the stoics, as for the Epicureans, is of what exists and is veridical. The world appears to us as it is; the role of reason is to assent to our judgments about it, or not. The workings of the mind on the world don’t differ in kind, but only in degree.. First, we apprehend something through the senses. If it’s vivid and stable and plausible, we assent to it. (We can ‘assent’ prematurely or inappropriately, in which case we have opinion, which can be false.) Isolated apprehensions don’t constitute knowledge; we have to combine and synthesize our apprehensions, integrate them, through the force of reason, into a consistent and coherent whole. Zeno is said to have represented this process with first, a flat, outstretched hand (=sensation); bending the fingers was assent; a clenched fist represented “simple apprehension,” mental grasp of an object. Knowledge, integrated assents, is the clenched fist held tightly in the other hand.
Recommended publications
  • Ghost of Isaac Newton Vandalizes Rival's Wikipedia
    HARVARD SATYRICAL PRESS ISSUE 17 - SPRING 2009 SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY Ghost of Isaac Newton Vandalizes Rival’s Wikipedia Article THE INTERNETS — One of the greatest academic rivalries of Additional text edits made to both the English and Latin all time, long thought ended, has been reignited as the ghost Wikipedia articles on Leibniz by TrinityLad43 include: of British natural philosopher Sir Isaac Newton (1643-1727) has somehow gained access to the internet and made several 1. Replacing all mentions of the title of Leibniz’s book unfavorable edits to the Wikipedia entry of his German “Theodicy” with “The Idiocy”. contemporary Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716). 2. Adding “[citationem necitatae]” after almost every According to the Wikipedia archive dated 7 sentence related to Leibniz’s March, while they were alive, Newton and work on calculus. Leibniz disputed over scientific matters 3. Changing “List of Publications” to like whether Leibniz’s calculus was “List of Plagiarizations”. discovered independently of Newton’s, the meaning of the theory of universal 4. Replacing “mathematician” with gravitation, and the philosophical tenet “imbecilic wretch” and “philosopher” of hylozoism. According to the Wikipedia with “addle-pated bvffoon”. archive dated 16 March, their dispute centered largely around Leibniz’s body 5. Adding an entire section on lewd odor, his sexual impotence, and whether jokes about Leibniz’s mother, he would have been better described supposedly popular during the 1710s. as a “pompous horfe’s ass” or a “right pompous horfe’s ass”. TrinityLad43’s only other edits have involved augmenting the article The distinctive changes were not noticed “Isaac Newton in Popular Culture”, until after they had been copied and and adding details on the care and pasted into 2,783 high school physics grooming of Powdered Wigs, essays throughout the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Readingsample
    Studies on Ancient Moral and Political Philosophy 1 What is Up to Us? Studies on Agency and Responsibility in Ancient Philosophy von Edited by Pierre Destrée, Ricardo Salles 1. Academia Verlag St. Augustin bei Bonn 2014 Verlag C.H. Beck im Internet: www.beck.de ISBN 978 3 89665 634 6 Zu Inhaltsverzeichnis schnell und portofrei erhältlich bei beck-shop.de DIE FACHBUCHHANDLUNG Pierre Destrée, Ricardo Salles and Marco Zingano 1 Introduction Pierre Destrée, Ricardo Salles and Marco Zingano The present volume brings together twenty contributions whose aim is to study the problem of moral responsibility as it arises in Antiquity in connection with the concept of what depends on us, or is up to us, through the expression eph’ hêmin and its Latin synonyms in nostra potestate and in nobis. The notion of what is up to us begins its philosophical lifetime with Aristotle. However, as the chapters by Monte Johnson and Pierre Destrée point out, it is already present in earlier authors such as Democritus and Plato, who clearly raise some of the issues that were linked to this notion in the later tradition. In Aristotle, the expression eph’ hêmin is frequently used in the plural to denote the things that are up to us in the sense that they are in our power to do or not to do. It plays a central role in his action theory insofar as the scope of deliberate choice is specifi- cally the set of these things (we deliberate about how to bring about things that it is up to us to achieve).
    [Show full text]
  • The Death of Heraclitus Fairweather, Janet Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Fall 1973; 14, 3; Proquest Pg
    The Death of Heraclitus Fairweather, Janet Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Fall 1973; 14, 3; ProQuest pg. 233 The Death of Heraclitus Janet Fairweather ECENTLY there has been a revival of interest in a theory, Roriginally put forward by A. Gladisch,l about one ancient ac­ count of the death of Heraclitus. According to Neanthes of Cyzicus 2 Heraclitus, suffering from dropsy, attempted to cure him­ self by covering his body with manure and lying out in the sun to dry, but he was made unrecognizable by the dung covering and was finally eaten by dogs. Gladisch and others have seen in this anecdote a veiled allusion to a certain Zoroastrian ritual, described in the Videvdat (8.37f), in which a man who has come into contact with a corpse which has not been devoured by scavengers is supposed to rid himself of the polluting demon, Nasu the Druj, by lying on the ground, covering himself with bull's urine, and having some dogs brought to the scene. The fact that we find both in Neanthes' tale and in this ritual the use of bovine excreta, exposure of a man's body in the sun, and the inter­ vention of dogs has seemed to some scholars too remarkable to be coincidental. Gladisch and, following him, F. M. Cleve3 have seen in Neanthes' anecdote an indication that Heraclitus might have ordered a Zoroastrian funeral for himself. M. L. West,4 more cautiously and subtly, has suggested that the story of the manure treatment and the dogs could have originated as an inference from some allusion Hera­ clitus may have made to the purification ritual in a part of his work now lost, perhaps in connection with his sneer (fr.86 Marcovich=B 5 D/K) at people who attempt to rid themselves of blood pollution by spilling more blood.
    [Show full text]
  • The Heraclitus Anecdote: De Partibus Animalium I 5.645A17-23
    Ancient Philosophy 21 (2001) ©Mathesis Publications 1 The Heraclitus Anecdote: De Partibus Animalium i 5.645a17-23 Pavel Gregoric Chapter 5 of the first book of Aristotle’s De Partibus Animalium contains a short self-contained treatise (644b22-645a36) which has been characterised as a ‘protreptic to the study of animals’ (Peck in Aristotle 1937, 97). Such a charac- terisation of the treatise may be misleading, because Aristotle does not seem to have composed it in order to motivate his audience to go out in the field and study animals, but rather to kindle their interest in the scientific account of ani- mals which he is about to provide. It is reasonable to suppose that Aristotle’s audience, eager to learn something valuable and dignified, needed an explanation of why they should like to hear, amongst other animals, about sponges, snails, grubs, and other humble creatures which are displeasing even to look at, not to mention witnessing the dissections that might have accompanied Aristotle’s lec- tures on animals (cf. Bonitz 1870, 104a4-17; Lloyd 1978). Aristotle explains why such ignoble animals deserve a place in a scientific account of animals and he illustrates that with an anecdote about Heraclitus. So one must not be childishly repelled by the examination of the humbler animals. For in all things of nature there is some- thing wonderful. And just as Heraclitus is said to have spoken to the visitors who wanted to meet him and who stopped as they were approaching when they saw him warming himself by the oven (e‰don aÈtÚn yerÒmenon prÚw t“ fipn“)—he urged them to come in without fear (§k°leue går aÈtoÁw efisi°nai yarroËntaw), for there were gods there too (e‰nai går ka‹ §ntaËya yeoÊw)—so one must approach the inquiry about each animal without aversion, since in all of them there is something natural and beautiful.
    [Show full text]
  • WISDOM (Tlwma) and Pffllosophy (FALSAFA)
    WISDOM (tLWMA) AND PfflLOSOPHY (FALSAFA) IN ISLAMIC THOUGHT (as a framework for inquiry) By: Mehmet ONAL This thcsis is submitted ror the Doctor of Philosophy at the University of Wales - Lampeter 1998 b"9tr In this study the following two hypothesisare researched: 1. "WisdotW' is the fundamental aspect of Islamic thought on which Islamic civilisation was established through Islamic law (,Sharfa), theology (Ldi-M), philosophy (falsafq) and mysticism (Surism). 2. "Due to the first hypothesis Islamic philosophy is not only a commentary on the Greek philosophy or a new form of Ncoplatonism but a native Islamic wisdom understandingon the form of theoretical study". The present thesis consists of ten chaptersdealing with the concept of practical wisdom (Pikmq) and theoretical wisdom (philosophy or falsafa). At the end there arc a gcncral conclusion,glossary and bibliography. In the introduction (Chapter One) the definition of wisdom and philosophy is establishedas a conceptualground for the above two hypothesis. In the following chapter (Chapter Two) I focused on the historical background of these two concepts by giving a brief history of ancient wisdom and Greek philosophy as sourcesof Islamic thought. In the following two chapters (Chapter Three and Four) I tried to bring out a possibledefinition of Islamic wisdom in the Qur'5n and Sunna on which Islamic jurisprudence (fiqh), theology (A-alim), philosophy (falsafq) and mysticism (Sufism) consistedof. As a result of the above conceptual approaching,I tried to reach a new definition for wisdom (PiLma) as a method that helps in the establishmentof a new Islamic way of life and civilisation for our life.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucan's Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulf
    Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2014 Reading Committee: Catherine Connors, Chair Alain Gowing Stephen Hinds Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics © Copyright 2014 Laura Zientek University of Washington Abstract Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek Chair of the Supervisory Committee: Professor Catherine Connors Department of Classics This dissertation is an analysis of the role of landscape and the natural world in Lucan’s Bellum Civile. I investigate digressions and excurses on mountains, rivers, and certain myths associated aetiologically with the land, and demonstrate how Stoic physics and cosmology – in particular the concepts of cosmic (dis)order, collapse, and conflagration – play a role in the way Lucan writes about the landscape in the context of a civil war poem. Building on previous analyses of the Bellum Civile that provide background on its literary context (Ahl, 1976), on Lucan’s poetic technique (Masters, 1992), and on landscape in Roman literature (Spencer, 2010), I approach Lucan’s depiction of the natural world by focusing on the mutual effect of humanity and landscape on each other. Thus, hardships posed by the land against characters like Caesar and Cato, gloomy and threatening atmospheres, and dangerous or unusual weather phenomena all have places in my study. I also explore how Lucan’s landscapes engage with the tropes of the locus amoenus or horridus (Schiesaro, 2006) and elements of the sublime (Day, 2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 5. Zeno's Four Paradoxes of Motion
    Lecture 5. Zeno's Four Paradoxes of Motion Science of infinity In Lecture 4, we mentioned that a conflict arose from the discovery of irrationals. The Greeks' rejection of irrational numbers was essentially part of a general rejection of the infinite process. In fact, until the late 19th century most mathematicians were reluctant to accept infinity. In his last observations on mathematics1, Hermann Weyl wrote: \Mathematics has been called the science of the infinite. Indeed, the mathematician invents finite constructions by which questions are decided that by their very nature refer to the infinite. That is his glory." Besides the conflict of irrational numbers, there were other conflicts about the infinite process, namely, Zeno's famous paradoxes of motion from around 450 B.C. Figure 5.1 Zeno of Citium Zeno's Paradoxes of motion Zeno (490 B.C. - 430 B.C.) was a Greek philosopher of southern Italy and a member of the Eleatic School founded by Parmenides2. We know little 1Axiomatic versus constructive procedures in mathematics, The Mathematical Intelligencer 7 (4) (1985), 10-17. 2Parmenides of Elea, early 5th century B.C., was an ancient Greek philosopher born in Elea, a Greek city on the southern coast of Italy. He was the founder of the Eleatic school of philosophy. For his picture, see Figure 2.3. 32 about Zeno other than Plato's assertion that he went to Athens to meet with Socrates when he was nearly 40 years old. Zeno was a Pythegorean. By a legend, he was killed by a tyrant of Elea whom he had plotted to depose.
    [Show full text]
  • The Natural Philosophers
    The Natural Philosophers For us, the most interesting part is actually not what solutions these earliest philosophers arrived at, but The earliest Greek philosophers are sometimes which questions they asked and what type of answer called natural philosophers because they were mainly they were looking for. We are more interested in how concerned with the natural world and its processes. they thought than in exactly what they thought. We have already asked ourselves where everything We know that they posed questions relating to the comes from. Nowadays a lot of people imagine that at transformations they could observe in the physical some time something must have come from nothing. This world. They were looking for the underlying laws of idea was not so widespread among the Greeks. For one nature. They wanted to understand what was happening reason or another, they assumed that “something” had around them without having to turn to the ancient always existed. myths. And most important, they wanted to understand How everything could come from nothing was the actual processes by studying nature itself. This was therefore not the all-important question. On the other quite different from explaining thunder and lightning or hand the Greeks marveled at how live fish could come winter and spring by telling stories about the gods. from water, and huge trees and brilliantly colored So philosophy gradually liberated itself from flowers could come from the dead earth. Not to mention religion. We could say that the natural philosophers took how a baby could come from its mother’s womb! the first step in the direction of scientific reasoning, The philosophers observed with their own eyes thereby becoming the precursors of what was to become that nature was in a constant state of transformation.
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), Pp
    Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), pp. 187-215. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-1753%28198106%2972%3A2%3C187%3AOGAKNP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-C Isis is currently published by The University of Chicago Press. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ucpress.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Mon Aug 20 10:29:37 2007 Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes By Steven Shapin* FTER TWO AND A HALF CENTURIES the Newton-Leibniz disputes A continue to inflame the passions.
    [Show full text]
  • MATERIALISM: a HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL INTRODUCTION Charles Wolfe
    MATERIALISM: A HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL INTRODUCTION Charles Wolfe To cite this version: Charles Wolfe. MATERIALISM: A HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL INTRODUCTION. MATERI- ALISM: A HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL, Springer International Publishing, 2016, Springer Briefs, 978-3-319-24818-9. 10.1007/978-3-319-24820-2. hal-01233178 HAL Id: hal-01233178 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01233178 Submitted on 24 Nov 2015 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. MATERIALISM: A HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL INTRODUCTION Forthcoming in the Springer Briefs series, December 2015 Charles T. Wolfe Centre for History of Science Department of Philosophy and Moral Sciences Ghent University [email protected] TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter 1 (Introduction): materialism, opprobrium and the history of philosophy Chapter 2. To be is to be for the sake of something: Aristotle’s arguments with materialism Chapter 3. Chance, necessity and transformism: brief considerations Chapter 4. Early modern materialism and the flesh or, forms of materialist embodiment Chapter 5. Vital materialism and the problem of ethics in the Radical Enlightenment Chapter 6. Naturalization, localization: a remark on brains and the posterity of the Enlightenment Chapter 7. Materialism in Australia: The Identity Theory in retrospect Chapter 8.
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonism and Cartesianism – Episode: External World and Aliens
    Philosophy department, CEU Budapest, Hungary Table of Contents Table of Contents ....................................................................................................................... 1 Table of Contents ....................................................................................................................... Pyrrhonism and 2 List of Abbreviations .................................................................................................................. 3 IntroductionCartesianism: ................................................................................................................................ external 4 1.Methodological and practical skepticism: theory and a way of life ........................................ 6 2.Hypothetical doubt,world practical concerns and and the existence aliens of the external world .................. 13 2.1. An explanation for Pyrrhonists not questioning the existence of the external world .... 18 In partial2.2. An analysisfulfillment of whether ofPyrrhonists the requirements could expand the scope for of theirthe skepticism to include the external world .................................................................................................... 21 3.Pyrrhonism, Cartesianism and degreesome epistemologically of Masters interesting of Artsquestions ..................... 27 Conclusion ................................................................................................................................ by Tamara Rendulic 37 References ...............................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]