Thought and the Eucharist Philosophical Models and Their Theological Appropriation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Thought and the Eucharist Philosophical Models and Their Theological Appropriation Ephemerides Theologicae Lovanienses 86/1 (2010) 83-106. doi: 10.2143/ETL.86.1.2051611 © 2010 by Ephemerides Theologicae Lovanienses. All rights reserved. Thought and the Eucharist Philosophical Models and Their Theological Appropriation Joris GELDHOF K.U.Leuven The history of the relationship between Thought and the Eucharist is long and complex. Theology, resorting to concepts and the formation of philosophical thought, has never ceased to attempt an understanding of the mystery of the Eucharist. Theologians have certainly reflected on “the sacrament of sacraments”, lyrically described by Vatican II as “a sacra- ment of love, a sign of unity, a bond of charity, a Pascal banquet”1 inas- much as it is “the fount and apex of the whole Christian life”2. But philosophers themselves have thematized and examined the Eucharist, too, not only as a social ritual or a religious practice but also as a constitu- tive element of Christian faith. Xavier Tilliette demonstrates this in his recent volume on “Eucharistic philosophies”3. This fundamental observa- tion invites theologians to meticulously study what the philosophers have written, and then to make a critical and constructive assessment. In the current context, the task of dedicating the necessary energy to the deepen- ing of relationships between thought and the Eucharist has become of utmost importance. How is it possible to contemplate the Eucharist with- out being absorbed in a strictly scientific and rationalistic discourse on the one hand, or on the other hand, without spiritualizing it – which would finally and inevitably end up in a refutation of theology itself? This article presents an authentic exercise of theological thought which confronts each of these two positions. In order to establish a synthesis of Eucharistic thinking, I will refer to the monumental work of Jean Greisch, and in particular to the philosophical models which he highlights in his historical-systematic reconstruction of the philosophy of religion in the 1. Sacrosanctum Concilium, nr. 47 (cf. also Lumen Gentium, nr. 26), to which the recent apostolic exhortation Sacramentum Caritatis by Benedict XVI probably makes ref- erence. The idea of considering the Eucharist as the sacrament of charity is in any case an idea from Saint Augustine, taken up again by Saint Thomas Aquinas (Summa Theologiae III, q. 73, a. 3), reaffirmed by the Council and reminded by the exhortation. 2. Lumen Gentium, nr. 11. 3. Xavier TILLIETTE, Philosophies eucharistiques de Descartes à Blondel (Philosophie et théologie), Paris, Cerf, 2006. This book is based on a work written by the same author which is entitled Eucharistie et philosophie, Paris, Institut Catholique de Paris, 1983. All subsequent translations of this work are mine. 993364_ETL_2010_1_03_Geldhof.indd3364_ETL_2010_1_03_Geldhof.indd 8833 229-06-20109-06-2010 112:35:232:35:23 84 J. GELDHOF wake of Kantian philosophy4. This method permits the analysis of diverse philosophical and theological approaches to the Eucharist5. The thread which I will follow will thus be based on the following question: Which model is the most appropriate to contemplate the Eucharist in the contem- porary context? I. GREISCH’S PHILOSOPHICAL MODELS: AN OUTLINE IN VIEW OF THEOLOGICAL PURPOSES Before applying Greisch’s models to our theme of the Eucharist, it is fitting to describe them briefly. The first model is called speculative according to historical motifs; this model contains close links to German idealism6. Here, Greisch discusses three founding intellectuals (Schleier- macher, Hegel and Schelling) before he then turns toward two 20th cen- tury representative figures, Franz Rosenzweig and Karl Rahner. The sec- ond paradigm or model is that of criticism. Greisch draws attention to two different philosophical axes. Firstly he deals with Kant and Neokantians7, who wanted to reflect on transcendental questions and fundamental con- ditions of knowledge. Secondly, he deals with the atheistic and reduction- ist approaches of Ludwig Feuerbach and Friedrich Nietzsche. The third model, phenomenology, is equally subdivided in two major fields of inter- est. First, there is a more or less scientific phenomenology marked by the emergence of religious sciences which were equally represented by Rudolph Otto, Gerardus van der Leeuw, and Mircea Eliade. Next Greisch distinguishes a philosophical phenomenology in a more technical sense of the term, which was profoundly inspired by the example of Edmund Hus- serl, who, as is generally known, had a significant reception in France8. 4. Jean GREISCH, Le Buisson ardent et les Lumières de la raison: L’invention de la philosophie de la religion. Volume I: Héritages et héritiers du XIXe siècle. Volume II: Les approches phénoménologiques et analytiques. Volume III: Vers un paradigme herméneu- tique (Philosophie et théologie), Paris, Cerf, 2002-2004. All translations from this hitherto untranslated work are mine. 5. It would be appropriate here to refer to the interesting book by Kevin W. IRWIN, Mod- els of the Eucharist, Mahwah NJ, Paulist Press, 2005. In utilizing the methodology of “mod- els” as Avery Dulles has done for that which concerns the Church and revelation, Irwin analyzes different theological models in order to interpret the Eucharist. Differently from Irwin, I will follow models of a philosophical origin in view of a theological appropriation and evaluation. This will not prevent us from being able to adhere to Irwin’s conclusions. 6. GREISCH, Le Buisson ardent (n. 4), I, p. 63. 7. Strangely, GREISCH (ibid., I, p. 385 – cf. ibid., I, p. 416), included two Protestant theologians in his discussion of Neokantianism: Ernst Troeltsch and Paul Tillich. He was motivated to do so because they are “two thinkers who belong to the Neo-Kantian school of Baden, [which] inclined more towards the philosophy of values and culture than towards epistemology”. 8. Cf. the “theological turn” of (French) phenomenology (GREISCH, Le Buisson ardent [n. 4], I, p. 67). This term is borrowed from Dominique Janicaud. 993364_ETL_2010_1_03_Geldhof.indd3364_ETL_2010_1_03_Geldhof.indd 8844 229-06-20109-06-2010 112:35:232:35:23 THOUGHT AND THE EUCHARIST 85 The fourth model is attributed to Ludwig Wittgenstein and his philosophy of language. Greisch calls it analytic and associates it preponderantly with the Anglo-Saxon philosophical world9. Finally, the fifth model is characterized as hermeneutics and it is this last model which Jean Greisch undoubtedly favors. According to him, it is this paradigm which, from now on, will be capable of engaging in the fundamental task of the philosophy of religion, more so than the other models. This task involves being aware of all the aspects which constitute the religious phenomenon: the content of beliefs, the meaning of rituals, the customs of believers, the histories of the great religions as well as their power and current impact, mentalities and spirituality, moral behav- ior and sets of rules, etc. Greisch estimates that an “explicitly” herme- neutic paradigm10 is the most promising to be able to account for all of these perspectives, without trying to unite them in an inclusive amalgam which would neglect the real tensions between them. Still according to Greisch, the great advantage of a hermeneutic approach is that it is pos- sible to penetrate the object which is being examined without destroying, reducing, or alienating it from itself. In a mutually dynamic process, the interpreting allows the interpreted to be reconfigured. In the following reflections, I will not hold to Greisch’s “ideal-typical” order of presentation11, nor will I focus on the evaluation of his own pref- erences and points of view, although I am fully aware of the many good motifs that give life to Greisch’s philosophy of religion. The reason why I deviate from Greischian concepts not only involves the consciousness that the calling of a theology of the Eucharist differs from that of the phi- losophy of religion; I also believe that the option for a hermeneutical approach, even if it is well-founded and justified, could and should be enriched by other approaches, much more so than Greisch wants to admit. I have in mind one of these approaches in particular, namely the specula- tive one. I will argue that a contemporary theology of the Eucharist is developed best not as a reaction against speculative reflection but instead as a speculative endeavor in itself. This said, one must reiterate that the most important objective of this contribution is not a critical assessment of Greisch’s work12, but a genuine 9. In what follows I will leave this model unattended. Apart from a few thinkers who have dealt with aspects of Eucharistic doctrines from a logical-analytical point of view (like e.g. Alexander Pruss), there seems to be too little correspondence with the continental tradition to render the insights of analytic philosophers relevant for the purposes of this article. A due discussion of this philosophical current would require a separate study. 10. GREISCH, Le Buisson ardent (n. 4), III, p. 16; I, p. 69. 11. Ibid., I, pp. 7.60. 12. With this aim in view we shall consult the article by Paul GILBERT, L’invention de la “philosophie de la religion” selon Jean Greisch, in NRT 128 (2006) 67-74; cf. also my review of the third volume of GREISCH, Le Buisson ardent (n. 4), in ETL 81 (2005) 554- 556. 993364_ETL_2010_1_03_Geldhof.indd3364_ETL_2010_1_03_Geldhof.indd 8855 229-06-20109-06-2010 112:35:232:35:23 86 J. GELDHOF reflection on the relationship between thought and the Eucharist. Let us therefore look now at how this relationship can be revealed with the help of Greisch’s paradigms. It must be mentioned straightaway that the order of chosen models reveals a certain logic taken up in the conclusion. More- over, at each step, I will try to combine a Greischian model with aspects which correspond to Tilliette’s perspective. This should therefore be mutu- ally fruitful for philosophy, theology, and the history of ideas in order to produce an appropriate Eucharistic theology for today and tomorrow.
Recommended publications
  • 190 Dale M. Schlitt Two Centuries Ago in Berlin Classrooms, Some
    190 Book Reviews Dale M. Schlitt German Idealism’s Trinitarian Legacy. Albany, ny: State University of New York Press, 2016. Pp. x + 445. Hb, $95. Two centuries ago in Berlin classrooms, some now famous philosophers of re- ligion prosecuted contending systematic treatments of the Trinity that, for cer- tain, challenged their students. Today these philosophies are still taught and prove as daunting as ever for students and teachers alike. With Dale Schlitt’s new book on German Idealism’s Trinitarian legacy, we have an expert teacher to guide us all. This multifariously praiseworthy text’s chief merit lies in its pedagogical sensibility. Schlitt’s introduction concisely lays out how the book resulted from decades of teaching at St. Paul University in Ottawa and Oblate School of The- ology in San Antonio. Even better, the introduction presents a lucid, welcom- ing justification for the reader for the slate of ten thinkers to be treated later, and an equally clear statement on method. Then with an eye to future scholars’ potential contributions, Schlitt states that he offers this text as a celebration of the Idealist legacy, which should impel continuation of the Idealist Trinitarian adventure (see the detailed suggestions for further study in the book’s conclu- sion). Schlitt’s pedagogical sensibility manifests itself in each chapter with his judicious selection of examples and representative texts. Given the subject’s difficulty, this is absolutely worth lauding. The book has four parts. The first recounts the beginning of the Trinitarian adventure with Johann G. Fichte, Georg W.F. Hegel, and Friedrich W.J.
    [Show full text]
  • Schelling's Narrative Philosophy and Ankersmit's Narrative Logic
    Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 2021; 2(2): 237–257 Katarzyna Filutowska* Schelling’s Narrative Philosophy and Ankersmit’s Narrative Logic – Is There Any Philosophy to Narrative? https://doi.org/10.1515/jtph-2021-0013 Published online June 4, 2021 Abstract: This paper considers the problem of a narrative philosophy according to F. W. J. Schelling and narrative logic according to Franklin Ankersmit. Referring to these examples, I ask whether there is any philosophy to narrative at all. First, I discuss Schelling’s views from his unfinished work “The Ages of the World,” as well as his later dialectics of mythology of revelation from the system of the ages of the world. I focus on a dialectics of figurative and speculative order, which is at the core of Schelling’s project to tell philosophy in the form of poetry and demonstrate the origins of Schelling’s narrative philosophy in his early, transcendental thought. Next, I juxtapose my findings with Ankersmit’s analysis of historians’ language. I also consider whether, and how, some of these ideas can be applied in contemporary narrative research. Keywords: narrative philosophy, F.W.J. Schelling, German idealism, Franklin Ankersmit, narrative logic 1 Introduction Although Schelling, along with Kant and Fichte, is considered one of the most prominent representatives of transcendentalism, his philosophy is in fact irre- ducible to the typically systematic, negative thought that is characteristic of thinkers in this school. In his second, positive period, which began in 1809 with the famous treatise devoted to human freedom, he passed into the position of a so- called living system.
    [Show full text]
  • Losing Touch: Rethinking Contingency As Common Tangency in Continental Thought
    Losing Touch: Rethinking Contingency as Common Tangency in Continental Thought Liane Francesca Carlson Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2015 © 2015 Liane Francesca Carlson All rights reserved ABSTRACT Losing Touch: Rethinking Contingency as Common Tangency in Continental Thought Liane F. Carlson This dissertation grows out of the collapse of traditional Christian justifications for evil in the wake of Enlightenment critiques of religion and the atrocities of the twentieth century. Skeptical of teleological narratives that sought to domesticate suffering as part of a necessary plan - whether God’s plan, or some more secularized ideal of progress - a generation of Critical Theorists adopted the concept of contingency as their central tool for political critique. Defined as the realm of chance, change, and the unnecessary, contingency serves for most contemporary thinkers to remind us that even seemingly natural categories, such as sex, race, and religion could have been otherwise. Yet in using contingency to make sweeping statements about the nature of history, scholars often overlook how contingency is understood on the ground by those who feel their bodies and identities abruptly made unstable. This project seeks to reground contingency in the specificity of human experience by returning to a neglected Christian tradition that understood contingency as a state of finitude, defined in contrast to the necessary, impassive God. For such thinkers, contingency was experienced most acutely in the sense of touch as it renders the body vulnerable to the external world and the passions as they ambush the soul.
    [Show full text]
  • The Self and Death: an Existential Dialectic
    The Linacre Quarterly Volume 50 | Number 3 Article 16 August 1983 The elS f and Death: An Existential Dialectic Robert Slesinski Follow this and additional works at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq Recommended Citation Slesinski, Robert (1983) "The eS lf and Death: An Existential Dialectic," The Linacre Quarterly: Vol. 50 : No. 3 , Article 16. Available at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq/vol50/iss3/16 The Self and Death: An Existential Dialectic Rev. Robert Slesinski Currently pastor of St. Nicholas of Myra Byzantine Catholic Church, Yonkers/ White Plains, N. Y., the author received his doctorate in philosophy from the Pontifical Gregorian University in Rome. He is a professor at the John XXIII Center for Eastern Christian Studies, Bronx, N.Y. Teach me to number my days aright, that I may gain wisdom of heart. -Psalm 90:12 The Epicurean Dilemma If one were to ask us point-blank, and indeed somewhat crudely, why we get all "hung up" about death - the death of our loved ones or our own eventual death - we might well want to respond with indignation. We might take the question more as a challenge and out­ right effrontery to our human sensibilities than as a serious query. We would rightly be aghast at the apparent flippancy of the inquirer or provocateur, as you may have it, in face of the evident human happen­ ing and sorrowful parting that is death. It isn't that we would favor or sustain a morbid preoccupation about death, but simply that we would beg to demand that rudimentary sensitivity and common decency prevail whenever this awesome and, for some, dreadful aspect of life's inevitable end comes to the fore.
    [Show full text]
  • The Venture of Expression in Merleau-Ponty's
    Recasting Objective Thought: The Venture of Expression in Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy Anna Petronella Foultier Recasting Objective Thought: The Venture of Expression in Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy Anna Petronella Foultier ©Anna Petronella Foultier, Stockholm University 2015 ISBN 978-91-7649-095-2 Printed in Sweden by Holmbergs, Malmö 2015 Distributor: Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University Cover photo from an exposition by Hans Fredlund in 2007 at Örebro Castle. To my father, Hans Fredlund (1939–2009) Contents Acknowledgements .................................................................................... ix Works by Merleau-Ponty ........................................................................... xi Note on the Use of Translations ...........................................................................xiii Introduction ................................................................................................ 15 Summary of the Thesis ..................................................................................... 18 Objective Thought and its Categories ............................................................ 20 The Gestalt of Behaviour .................................................................................. 23 The Body-Proper and its Schema .................................................................... 29 Phenomenological Reflection ........................................................................... 31 The Ontology of the Flesh ...............................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Time in the Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel
    TIME IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF GABRIEL MARCEL Helen Tattam, MA. Thesis submitted to the University of Nottingham for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (in French Studies) August 2010 Abstract This thesis aims to determine what is distinctive to the philosophy of Gabriel Marcel (1889-1973). While his work has largely been received as a form of ‘Christian existentialism’ (notably by Jean-Paul Sartre), and thus interpreted in relation to other philosophies of existence, it is my contention that this prevents an appreciation of his specificity. I therefore recommend a new reading of his thought, which, through analysis of his various philosophical presentations of time, re-situates him within the twentieth-century French intellectual tradition. Part I of the thesis provides an introduction to his philosophy of time, analysing his position in specific relation to Henri Bergson (1859-1941). Chapter One raises the question as to whether his position is then compromised by his engagement with eternity, for this seems to undermine time’s significance. However, what begins to emerge from Chapter Two onward, is that such a question may be inappropriate with respect to Marcel’s understanding of philosophy. Part II (Chapters Three and Four) then explores the implications that his work’s various modes have on the content of his arguments: first, the diary-form of his formative works and his (continuing) use of a first-person narrative style in his essays and lectures; and second, the (non-narrative) form of his theatre, to which Marcel also accorded philosophical significance. Here, Marcel is read alongside Paul Ricœur (1913-2005) and Emmanuel Lévinas (1906-1995), who also tried to approach philosophy differently – as is especially manifest in their conceptions of time.
    [Show full text]
  • Jean Wahl (1888–1974) Michel Weberi
    Jean Wahl (1888–1974) Michel Weberi Jean Wahl was born in Marseille, France, where his father, who was professor of English, succeeded to Mallarmé. He studied in the lycée Janson de Sailly (Paris) and, after a preparatory year in the lycée Louis-le-Grand (Paris), he entered the École normale supérieure (Ulm) in 1907. In 1910 he became “agrégé de philosophie” (first in his year, just before his good friend Gabriel Marcel, 1889–1973). Docteur ès lettres in 1920 with a thesis devoted to Les Philosophies pluralistes d’Angleterre et d’Amérique (translated into English by Fred Rothwell as The Pluralist Philosophies of England and America, London: Open Court, 1925) and a supplementary thesis (“Thèse complémentaire”) on Descartes’ concept of the instant (Le Rôle de l'Idée de l'Instant dans la Philosophie de Descartes). He then successively taught in secondary schools (“lycées” in Saint-Quentin, Tours and Le Mans), in the universities of Besançon, Nancy, Lyon, and finally at the Sorbonne—from 1936 to 1967. His career was interrupted, however, by World War II: first, by the exodus of May 1940; second, in December when Vichy ordered the retirement of all university professors with Jewish roots; third, in July 1941 when he was arrested by the Gestapo, imprisoned and finally interned at the Drancy deportation camp (north-east of Paris), from where he was released in November thanks to the mobilization of his fmily and friends. He then left for the U.S. where he taught from 1942 to 1945 at New York’s New School for Social Research, Smith College, Mount Holyoke College (where he created the Decades inspired by the famous “Décades de Pontigny”) and Pennsylvania State College.
    [Show full text]
  • Xavier Tilliette Inedito Tilliette Xavier Di a Cura Russo Antonio Di Prefazione Caterina Genna Di Postfazione Di Giovanni Piero
    505.19_505.5 07/01/20 12:08 Pagina 1 505.19 Xavier Tilliette inedito FILOSOFIA ITALIANA Xavier Tilliette inedito A. Russo a cura di Antonio Russo Il volume è dedicato alla figura e all’opera di Xavier Tilliette (1921-2018), teologo e filosofo, letterato, particolarmente distintosi nell’ambito della cultu- ( Prefazione di ra contemporanea con i suoi studi su Maurice Blondel, l’idealismo tedesco e la di cura a fenomenologia. Allievo di Jean Wahl e di Vladimir Jankélévitch, nel 1938 è en- Caterina Genna trato nella Compagnia di Gesù. A Parigi, ha insegnato presso l’Institut Catholi- que e il Centre Sèvres; a Roma presso la Pontificia Università Gregoriana e la ) Pontifica Università Lateranense. Tra gli autori preferiti da Tilliette, sono da ri- TILLIETTE INEDITO XAVIER Postfazione di cordare soprattutto Blondel e Schelling. Non vanno trascurati Husserl e Mer- leau-Ponty. L’autobiografia inedita di Tilliette, inserita integralmente in questo Piero Di Giovanni volume, consente per la prima volta di ricostruire l’iter formativo dell’uomo di fede e del filosofo. Contributi di: Antonio Russo, Caterina Genna, Walter Kasper, Xavier Tilliette, Daniela Floriduz, Albert Raffelt, Steffen Dietzsch, Jean Ferrari, Peter Reifen- berg, Marcello Zanatta, Andrea Tessier, Paolo Scattolin e Piero Di Giovanni. Antonio Russo è professore ordinario di Filosofia morale (Università di Trieste). Nato a Castroregio (Cs), si è laureato in filosofia nell’Università di Roma “La Sapien- za”, con M. M. Olivetti, M. Simonetti, U. Spirito. Dal 1974 al 1977 ha studiato liturgia presso l’Istituto liturgico di Sant’Anselmo (Roma). Nel 1980 ha conseguito la Licen- za in teologia nella Pontificia Università Gregoriana.
    [Show full text]
  • Fichte Für Die Welt
    AKADEMIE FORSCHUNG PH I LOSOPH ie Fichte für die Welt D ie I NT E RN AT I ON A L E N B E Z ie HUNG E N de R F I CHT E -G E S am T A USG abe . VON ERICH FUCHS Frühe Kontakte nach Italien und Frankreich is heute trägt der Philosoph Johann Gottlieb Fichte Bald nach Erscheinen der ersten B(1762–1814) unter einseitig Bände gingen Briefe an die beiden Interessierten oder ungenügend bekanntesten Fichte-Spezialisten Unterrichteten das Etikett eines des Auslandes. Seinen persönlichen deutschtümelnden, chauvinistischen Vorlieben für Frankreich und Nationalisten. Die seit dem Erschei- Italien entsprechend wandte Lauth nen der Akademieausgabe aufsprie- seinen Blick zuerst dorthin. Der ßende Forschung hat diese These italienische Meister in der Kenntnis längst entsorgt. Man weiß heute, des „Deutschen Idealismus“ Luigi dass Fichtes Patriotismus sich sehr Pareyson (1918–1991) in Turin kam wohl mit einer kosmopolitischen Lauth allerdings zuvor. Er gratulier- Einstellung verträgt. te am 16. Juli 1963 zum Erscheinen der „bellissima nuova edizione Hätte sonst die Fichte-Edition delle opere di Fichte“ und als „un einen so anregenden Impuls in die veterano di studi fichtiani“ fühlte internationale Wissenschaftsland- er sich autorisiert, seine lebhafte schaft werfen können? Auch dieses Zustimmung kundzutun. Zum Verdienst kommt neben der grund- Schluss hofft Pareyson auf künftige legenden Leistung für den Aufbau Kontakte. Lauth übersandte gleich Fichte in Asien: die chinesische der ganzen Edition dem Initiator ein Exemplar des ersten Bandes und (links) und die japanische Fichte- und Leiter der Fichte-Ausgabe, äußerte (2. Sept. 1963) als „unser Ausgabe. Reinhard Lauth (1919–2007), zu.
    [Show full text]
  • Echoes of the Theological Christology in Philosophy and Communication
    ECHOES OF THE THEOLOGICAL CHRISTOLOGY IN PHILOSOPHY AND COMMUNICATION ALEXANDRU PETRESCU, MUGUREL GABRIEL DRAGOMIR Abstract: Starting from some of the dogmatic Christology’s significations, we are trying to show that the Son of God can be considered, through the idea that supports him, a scope of a Christology that tries to present itself as a philosophy. To sustaining this, we refer to a few excerpts of a philosophical creation born out of Christological meditation, excerpts belonging to Pascal, Kierkegaard, Berdyaev, and Kant. Keywords: Philosophia Christus, Divine Logos, dogma, transcendental man, Christology DOGMATIC CHRISTOLOGY: SOME USEFUL MEANINGS FOR COMMUNICATION IN THE CHRISTIAN EXPERIENCE OF LIFE Christianity, within its doctrine, gives an overwhelming importance to Christ’s figure, a self-explanatory issue: it concerns a revealed religion, founded by God’s Son Himself, Jesus Christ, a religion with a name that derives from the One that incarnated himself to be Savior of the world. According to Christian teachings, God is only one in being, but also a indwelling of three persons at the same time: the Father, God the Son and the Holy Spirit. The Son, Jesus, is also known as God’s Word, precisely because “He has the role of revealing God to people”1. He not only does he speaks the divine word, but he also identifies Himself with it. Through Jesus, the divinity reveals itself, it communicates itself to people. Therefore, for a Christian, outside Christ the Trinity Faculty of Political Sciences, Philosophy and Communication Sciences, West University of Timisoara, 300223 - Timisoara, Romania e-mail: [email protected] Department for Teaching Training, “Politehnica” University of Timisoara, 300006 – Timisoara, Romania e-mail: [email protected] 1 D.Stăniloae (1993).
    [Show full text]
  • Teilhard De Chardin (1881–1955) Was Even Thornier
    Original URL: https://referenceworks.brillonline.com/entries/j esuit-historiography-online/*-COM_192562 BrillOnline Reference Works Jesuit Historiography Online Historiography of the Society of Jesus: The Case of France after the Order’s Restoration in 1814 (16,284 words) Article Table of Contents 1. Part One: Jesuit Apologetics versus Anti-Jesuitism (1820–1920) 2. Part Two: A Strictly Catholic Concern (1930–70) 3. Part Three: A Still Debated but No Longer Contentious Object (1970– 2010) 4. Conclusion Dominique Avon and Philippe Rocher [email protected] [email protected] Last modified: March 2017 For a long time, the histories of the Jesuits and of anti-Jesuitism remained intertwined.1 In 1640, one century after the foundation of the order, its members in the Low Countries published the Imago primi sæculi Societatis Jesu a provincia Flandro-Belgica ejusdem Societatis repræsentata. The book, an in-folio volume in praise of the Jesuits, illustrated with over a hundred engravings and printed by Antwerp’s Officina Plantiniana, was censured by Superior General Muzio Vitelleschi (in office 1615–45), but extensively used by the Jesuits’ detractors. Practiced in the daily logging of its activities,2 the Society of Jesus was wasting no time in writing its golden legend,3 not least that of its foreign missions,4 even as its opponents were busy publishing its Black Legend. While one side went about extolling its diverse apostolic works, whether preaching, confession, education and pedagogy, or spiritual direction, the other heaped up blame for seductive indoctrination, for hubris, for a potentially regicidal love of power, for lax morals and an authoritarian form of education begetting lies and denunciation.
    [Show full text]
  • Gilson and Gouhier: Framing 'Christian Philosophy'
    HeyJ XLIX (2008), pp. 995–1014 GILSON AND GOUHIER: FRAMING ‘CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY’ RICHARD FAFARA Northern Virginia Community College, Alexandria Virginia, USA Focusing on their approaches to Nicolas Malebranche, this article compares the contributions of E´tienne Gilson and his student and colleague, Henri Gouhier, to the debate around the notion of Christian philosophy during the mid-1920s into the 1930s. Gilson agreed with Brunschvicg’s characterization of Nicolas Malebranche as an important representative of Christian philosophy, and both Gilson and Gouhier had a profound understanding of Malebranche’s thought. Following St. Thomas that philosophy should strive to be a ‘perfect use of reason’, Gilson posited Christianity’s influence as remaining exterior to philosophy itself. More sympathetic to Malebranche’s Augustinian approach, Gouhier allowed for religious experience to operate at the interior of philosophy. These different approaches stemmed from fundamental differences as to how the historical method should be employed in philosophy and what it reveals. The role of Christian Revelation in philosophy continues to be vigorously debated and discussed by philosophers and theologians today.1 This article focuses on the contributions of E´tienne Gilson and his student and colleague, Henri Gouhier, to this debate; it compares and contrasts their early thinking on issues central to the notion of Christian philosophy. For purposes of this article, ‘early’ will to refer to the formulations of Christian philosophy developed by Gilson and Gouhier during the mid – 1920s into the 1930s. Because of differences about how the historical method should be used in philosophy and what it reveals in philosophy these two great historians and philosophers adopted very different approaches to Christian philosophy.
    [Show full text]