Pierre De Fermat Ismail Tawil

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Pierre De Fermat Ismail Tawil Pierre de Fermat Ismail Tawil Fermat's life Pierre de Fermat, a French mathematician born on the 17th of August, 1601 in Beaumont de Lomagne, France and passed away on the 12th of January, 1665 in Castres, France. He was the son of a successful leather merchant. While not much is known of his early life and education, there is evidence that his primary education might have been at a local Franciscan monastery; it is known that Fermat did attended the University of Toulouse and then later moved to Bordeaux in the second half of the 1620s. Fermat was fluent in Greek, Latin, Spanish, and Italian. He also studied a little in philological problems and even some Latin poetry. Fermat began his first critical mathematical research in Bordeaux. From Bordeaux Fermat went to the University of Orlans, where he studied law. He later received a Bachelor's Degree in Civil Law. His mother and her side of the family were Pierre biggest influence for studying law and for deciding to work in Parliament. Fermat eventually married and had five children. By 1631, Fermat was a lawyer and a government official in Toulouse, as well as given the title of "commissioner of requests." In 1648, Fermat was promoted to a king's councilor-ship in the parliament of Toulouse. The stature he now held entitled him to change his name from Pierre Fermat to Pierre de Fermat ("de" is the mark of nobility in France). From his appointment in 1631, Fermat worked in the lower chamber of parliament but in 1638 he was appointed to a higher chamber, then in 1652 he was promoted to the highest level in the criminal court. Promotion was done mostly on seniority and when the plague struck the region in the early 1650s, many of the older men died. Fermat himself was afflicted with the plague and in 1653 his death was wrongly reported and was later corrected. For the most part, math was a hobby to Fermat seeing as how he was a busy lawyer and did not let his love of math take up all of his time; however, he was at times preoccupied with his mathematical progress, so much so that he continued to cherish his mathematical friendship with a mathematician named Beaugrand, who he had previously done research with, even after he moved to Toulouse. Fermat also met another mathematician named Carcavi during his work in the government due to the fact that both of them were councilors in Toulouse; they both had a shared love for mathematics where Fermat discussed with Carcavi about his mathematical researches ad well as discoveries. During his research in Bordeaux, Fermat studied the works of a French mathematician from the 16th century, named Franois Vite. Vites idea of algebra as an Analytic Art largely guided Fermat in his choice of the type of problems he had became interested in. Fermat viewed his own work as a sort of continuation to the Vitan tradition. From Vite, Fermat inherited the idea of Symbolic Algebra as a tool made for uniting the realms of both Geometry and Arithmetic, which would later influence his work in Number Theory. Algebraic equations had meaning in both fields, depending on whether the variables were line segments or numbers. Moreover, Vites Theory of Equations shifted Fermat's attention away from the solutions of certain formulas to the relationships between the solutions and the structures of their parent equations or between the solutions of one equation and those of another. Most of Fermats research headed toward Reduction Analysis, where any given problem could be reduced to another or identified with a certain class of problems for which the general solution was known. This Reduction Analysis could be reversed, in most cases, to act as a generator of families of solutions to problems. Due to his love for language and literature and Vite's influence on his young brilliant mind, Fermat was very concerned with the restoration of a number of lost texts and so he began to restore lost works such as Apollonius Plane Loci, Euclids Porisms, and Diophantus Arithmetica. In terms of his mathematical work, there is speculation that Fermat never wanted any of his work to be published as he had considered math to be but a hobby. However, the few works that he did publish, he published them anonymously. Many of Fermat's work was done by mail or correspondence; he would mail many other famous mathematicians his progress in the mathematical field. Fermat rarely provide his proofs in his correspondence with other mathematicians; usually stating the theorems, however, he had always managed to neglected the proofs of these such theorems. Due to his "negligence", many of his theorems were left without any proofs, which eventually led to much doubt as to his authenticity as a mathematician. In fact, his most famous work, which was dubbed 'Fermat's Last Theorem', stayed without a proof until, in 1993, a mathematician named Andrew J. Wiles provided the first proof to this particular theorem. Fermat received very little recognition as a mathematician during his life, and if not for the fact that other mathematicians saved his papers and letters, he may not have had the legacy that he has to this day. Together with Ren Descartes, a very distinguished French mathematician in the 17th century, Fermat was one of the two leading mathematicians of the first half of the 17th century. Following his death, his oldest son, Clment-Samuel inherited his law offices in 1665 and then later decided to publish all of his fathers mathematical papers. Fermat's mathematical works The Method of Maxima and Minima An astronomer and mathematician by the name of Johannes Kepler, influenced the development of Fermat's early mathematical works. Kepler began to observe the volumes for specific dimensions. Keplers observations determined that as a maximum value was approached from either side, the change in volume started to become increasingly small. Bearing this same concept in mind, Fermat chose to expand on this wokr by finding maximum or minimum values of any of the given functions. Fermat understood that if a function f(x) had a maximum or minimum at x, then making e to be very small, it can be shown that the value of f(x − e) was almost equal to that of f(x). Therefore, this method involved what can be called a "pseudo-equality," in which Fermat carefully set: f(x) = f(x − e) However, before Fermat could find the roots of this equation, which would enable him to find the maximum and/or minimum of the function, he would need to correct the function's "pseudo-ness" by letting e "assume the value of zero". 2 Calculus and Curves During his work on the properties of curves, Fermat helped in the development of the mathematical field of calculus. As his studies of curves and their equations continued, Fermat noticed he could take the equation of an ordinary parabola (ay = x2), as well as an equation for a rectangular hyperbola (xy = a2), and generalize it to the follwowing form an−1y = xn The curves made by this equation are known as the parabolas/hyperbolas of Fermat (n is positive or negative). He similarly generalized the Archimedean spiral, r = aQ In the 1630s, he discovered an algorithm from these curves, that was similar to differentiation. This procedure let him find tangents of curves and locate the maximum, minimum, and inflection points of polynomials. For any equation, Fermat's way of finding the tangent at any given point was to find the subtangent for that specific point. Fermat found an equation for the areas bounded by curves through a summation process; this process has now been dubbed Integral Calculus. Such an equation is: Z A = xn dx = an+1=(n + 1) It is not known whether or not Fermat noticed that the differentiation of xn, leading to nan−1 was actually the inverse of integrating xn. Fermat took on problems involving even more general algebraic curves. Fermat applied his knowledge of infinitesimal quantities to many other problems, including the calculation of centers of gravity as well as finding the length of a curve. Fermat did not notice the idea of what is now known as the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus, however, his work in this area aided in the development of Differential Calculus. Additionally, he contributed to the Law of Refraction1 by disagreeing with his colleague, a philoso- pher and amateur mathematician, Ren Descartes. Fermat had claimed that Descartes had incorrectly deduced his Law of Refraction because it was deep-seated in his assumptions. As a result, Descartes became irritated and attacked Fermat's Method of Maxima and Minima. Fermat differed with Carte- sian views concerning the Law of Refraction, which was published by Descartes in 1637. Descartes attempted to justify the Sine Law through the assumption that light travels faster the denser the two media involved in the refraction. Twenty years later, Fermat noticed that this seemed to conflict with the view of the Aristotelians where nature always chooses the shortest path. Number Theory 1According to Fermat's theory, if light passes from point A to point B, while being reflected and refracted in any manner during the passage, the path it takes can be calculated and the time it takes to pass from A to B is an extreme 3 One may define a prime number as any natural number greater than 1 which has a divisor (without remainder) of only 1 and the number itself. Fermat noticed that numbers such as 3; 5; 17; 257; 65537 all belonged to a single sequence and can be generated by one simple process: 3 = 2 + 1; 5 = 22 + 1; 17 = 24 + 1; 257 = 28 + 1; 65537 = 216 + 1 The sequence seen here is such an equation 2n 1 2 + 1 jn=1 Now if we wanted to see if one of these numbers is prime it would be a difficult and lengthy process, unless we follow and understand Fermat who claimed that all numbers in the previous sequence are prime.
Recommended publications
  • Differential Calculus and by Era Integral Calculus, Which Are Related by in Early Cultures in Classical Antiquity the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus
    History of calculus - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia 1/1/10 5:02 PM History of calculus From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia History of science This is a sub-article to Calculus and History of mathematics. History of Calculus is part of the history of mathematics focused on limits, functions, derivatives, integrals, and infinite series. The subject, known Background historically as infinitesimal calculus, Theories/sociology constitutes a major part of modern Historiography mathematics education. It has two major Pseudoscience branches, differential calculus and By era integral calculus, which are related by In early cultures in Classical Antiquity the fundamental theorem of calculus. In the Middle Ages Calculus is the study of change, in the In the Renaissance same way that geometry is the study of Scientific Revolution shape and algebra is the study of By topic operations and their application to Natural sciences solving equations. A course in calculus Astronomy is a gateway to other, more advanced Biology courses in mathematics devoted to the Botany study of functions and limits, broadly Chemistry Ecology called mathematical analysis. Calculus Geography has widespread applications in science, Geology economics, and engineering and can Paleontology solve many problems for which algebra Physics alone is insufficient. Mathematics Algebra Calculus Combinatorics Contents Geometry Logic Statistics 1 Development of calculus Trigonometry 1.1 Integral calculus Social sciences 1.2 Differential calculus Anthropology 1.3 Mathematical analysis
    [Show full text]
  • Calculus? Can You Think of a Problem Calculus Could Be Used to Solve?
    Mathematics Before you read Discuss these questions with your partner. What do you know about calculus? Can you think of a problem calculus could be used to solve? В A Vocabulary Complete the definitions below with words from the box. slope approximation embrace acceleration diverse indispensable sphere cube rectangle 1 If something is a(n) it В Reading 1 isn't exact. 2 An increase in speed is called Calculus 3 If something is you can't Calculus is the branch of mathematics that deals manage without it. with the rates of change of quantities as well as the length, area and volume of objects. It grew 4 If you an idea, you accept it. out of geometry and algebra. There are two 5 A is a three-dimensional, divisions of calculus - differential calculus and square shape. integral calculus. Differential calculus is the form 6 Something which is is concerned with the rate of change of quantities. different or of many kinds. This can be illustrated by slopes of curves. Integral calculus is used to study length, area 7 If you place two squares side by side, you and volume. form a(n) The earliest examples of a form of calculus date 8 A is a three-dimensional back to the ancient Greeks, with Eudoxus surface, all the points of which are the same developing a mathematical method to work out distance from a fixed point. area and volume. Other important contributions 9 A is also known as a fall. were made by the famous scientist and mathematician, Archimedes. In India, over the 98 Macmillan Guide to Science Unit 21 Mathematics 4 course of many years - from 500 AD to the 14th Pronunciation guide century - calculus was studied by a number of mathematicians.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Notes on Calculus
    Historical notes on calculus Dr. Vladimir Dotsenko Dr. Vladimir Dotsenko Historical notes on calculus 1/9 Descartes: Describing geometric figures by algebraic formulas 1637: Ren´eDescartes publishes “La G´eom´etrie”, that is “Geometry”, a book which did not itself address calculus, but however changed once and forever the way we relate geometric shapes to algebraic equations. Later works of creators of calculus definitely relied on Descartes’ methodology and revolutionary system of notation in the most fundamental way. Ren´eDescartes (1596–1660), courtesy of Wikipedia Dr. Vladimir Dotsenko Historical notes on calculus 2/9 Fermat: “Pre-calculus” 1638: In a letter to Mersenne, Pierre de Fermat explains what later becomes the key point of his works “Methodus ad disquirendam maximam et minima” and “De tangentibus linearum curvarum”, that is “Method of discovery of maximums and minimums” and “Tangents of curved lines” (published posthumously in 1679). This is not differential calculus per se, but something equivalent. Pierre de Fermat (1601–1665), courtesy of Wikipedia Dr. Vladimir Dotsenko Historical notes on calculus 3/9 Pascal and Huygens: Implicit calculus In 1650s, slightly younger scientists like Blaise Pascal and Christiaan Huygens also used methods similar to those of Fermat to study maximal and minimal values of functions. They did not talk about anything like limits, but in fact were doing exactly the things we do in modern calculus for purposes of geometry and optics. Blaise Pascal (1623–1662), courtesy of Christiaan Huygens (1629–1695), Wikipedia courtesy of Wikipedia Dr. Vladimir Dotsenko Historical notes on calculus 4/9 Barrow: Tangents vs areas 1669-70: Isaac Barrow publishes “Lectiones Opticae” and “Lectiones Geometricae” (“Lectures on Optics” and “Lectures on Geometry”), based on his lectures in Cambridge.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution of Mathematics: a Brief Sketch
    Open Access Journal of Mathematical and Theoretical Physics Mini Review Open Access Evolution of mathematics: a brief sketch Ancient beginnings: numbers and figures Volume 1 Issue 6 - 2018 It is no exaggeration that Mathematics is ubiquitously Sujit K Bose present in our everyday life, be it in our school, play ground, SN Bose National Center for Basic Sciences, Kolkata mobile number and so on. But was that the case in prehistoric times, before the dawn of civilization? Necessity is the mother Correspondence: Sujit K Bose, Professor of Mathematics (retired), SN Bose National Center for Basic Sciences, Kolkata, of invenp tion or discovery and evolution in this case. So India, Email mathematical concepts must have been seen through or created by those who could, and use that to derive benefit from the Received: October 12, 2018 | Published: December 18, 2018 discovery. The creative process of discovery and later putting that to use must have been arduous and slow. I try to look back from my limited Indian perspective, and reflect up on what might have been the course taken up by mathematics during 10, 11, 12, 13, etc., giving place value to each digit. The barrier the long journey, since ancient times. of writing very large numbers was thus broken. For instance, the numbers mentioned in Yajur Veda could easily be represented A very early method necessitated for counting of objects as Dasha 10, Shata (102), Sahsra (103), Ayuta (104), Niuta (enumeration) was the Tally Marks used in the late Stone Age. In (105), Prayuta (106), ArA bud (107), Nyarbud (108), Samudra some parts of Europe, Africa and Australia the system consisted (109), Madhya (1010), Anta (1011) and Parartha (1012).
    [Show full text]
  • Pure Mathematics
    good mathematics—to be without applications, Hardy ab- solved mathematics, and thus the mathematical community, from being an accomplice of those who waged wars and thrived on social injustice. The problem with this view is simply that it is not true. Mathematicians live in the real world, and their mathematics interacts with the real world in one way or another. I don’t want to say that there is no difference between pure and ap- plied math. Someone who uses mathematics to maximize Why I Don’t Like “Pure the time an airline’s fleet is actually in the air (thus making money) and not on the ground (thus costing money) is doing Mathematics” applied math, whereas someone who proves theorems on the Hochschild cohomology of Banach algebras (I do that, for in- † stance) is doing pure math. In general, pure mathematics has AVolker Runde A no immediate impact on the real world (and most of it prob- ably never will), but once we omit the adjective immediate, I am a pure mathematician, and I enjoy being one. I just the distinction begins to blur. don’t like the adjective “pure” in “pure mathematics.” Is mathematics that has applications somehow “impure”? The English mathematician Godfrey Harold Hardy thought so. In his book A Mathematician’s Apology, he writes: A science is said to be useful of its development tends to accentuate the existing inequalities in the distri- bution of wealth, or more directly promotes the de- struction of human life. His criterion for good mathematics was an entirely aesthetic one: The mathematician’s patterns, like the painter’s or the poet’s must be beautiful; the ideas, like the colours or the words must fit together in a harmo- nious way.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectiones Qvintae Y Disqvisitio Metaphysica De Pierre Gassendi
    OBJECTIONES QVINTAE Y DISQVISITIO METAPHYSICA DE PIERRE GASSENDI . TESIS DOCTORAL. REALIZADA POR JESÚS DEL VALLE CORTÉS. DIRIGIDA POR EL CATEDRÁTICO DOCTOR DON MARCELINO RODRÍGUEZ DONÍS. A la memoria de Fernando del Valle Vázquez, de su hijo agradecido. Y a Silvia Aguirrezábal Guerrero. LIBRO PRIMERO. EXHORDIVM. A MODO DE INTRODUCCIÓN. ería necesario un largo estudio para establecer con detalle las condiciones en las cuales fueron compuestas, en primer lugar, las S Quintas Objeciones de Pierre Gassendi, Prepósito de la Iglesia de Digne y agudísimo Filósofo, designadas de esta manera en un Índice redactado por Mersenne, y después las Instancias 1, fechadas el 15 de marzo de 1642, pero que seguramente comenzaron a difundirse durante el invierno anterior . Son palabras de Bernard Rochot 2 y con ellas comenzaba la introducción de su traducción francesa de la Petri Gassendi Disquisitio metaphysica . Esta tesis no es sino el cumplimiento de este anhelo de Rochot, que ha ya mucho convertimos en propio, si bien hemos ampliado los límites de la empresa, toda vez que este trabajo no se contenta con plasmar los acontecimientos que dieron lugar a la aparición de ambos escritos, sino que incluye el análisis pormenorizado de ellos, e incluso el de las escuetas réplicas de Descartes a las Instancias . Es la primera vez que se recorre el ciclo completo de los argumentos de la querella, hasta su cierre con la Carta a Clerselier . Eran años de carrera cuando estudiábamos, bajo la tutela del Doctor D. Marcelino Rodríguez Donís, las Meditationes de prima philosophia , con sus siete Objeciones y Respuestas y, de entre ellas, las agrias Objectiones quintae sobresalían, a nuestro juicio, muy por encima de las demás, a pesar de que uno de los siete objetores fuese el ínclito Thomas Hobbes 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Pascal's and Huygens's Game-Theoretic Foundations For
    Pascal's and Huygens's game-theoretic foundations for probability Glenn Shafer Rutgers University [email protected] The Game-Theoretic Probability and Finance Project Working Paper #53 First posted December 28, 2018. Last revised December 28, 2018. Project web site: http://www.probabilityandfinance.com Abstract Blaise Pascal and Christiaan Huygens developed game-theoretic foundations for the calculus of chances | foundations that replaced appeals to frequency with arguments based on a game's temporal structure. Pascal argued for equal division when chances are equal. Huygens extended the argument by considering strategies for a player who can make any bet with any opponent so long as its terms are equal. These game-theoretic foundations were disregarded by Pascal's and Huy- gens's 18th century successors, who found the already established foundation of equally frequent cases more conceptually relevant and mathematically fruit- ful. But the game-theoretic foundations can be developed in ways that merit attention in the 21st century. 1 The calculus of chances before Pascal and Fermat 1 1.1 Counting chances . .2 1.2 Fixing stakes and bets . .3 2 The division problem 5 2.1 Pascal's solution of the division problem . .6 2.2 Published antecedents . .7 2.3 Unpublished antecedents . .8 3 Pascal's game-theoretic foundation 9 3.1 Enter the Chevalier de M´er´e. .9 3.2 Carrying its demonstration in itself . 11 4 Huygens's game-theoretic foundation 12 4.1 What did Huygens learn in Paris? . 13 4.2 Only games of pure chance? . 15 4.3 Using algebra . 16 5 Back to frequency 18 5.1 Montmort .
    [Show full text]
  • Fermat's Technique of Finding Areas Under Curves
    Fermat’s technique of finding areas under curves Ed Staples Erindale College, ACT <[email protected]> erhaps next time you head towards the fundamental theorem of calculus Pin your classroom, you may wish to consider Fermat’s technique of finding expressions for areas under curves, beautifully outlined in Boyer’s History of Mathematics. Pierre de Fermat (1601–1665) developed some impor- tant results in the journey toward the discovery of the calculus. One of these concerned finding areas under simple polynomial curves. It is an amazing fact that, despite deriving these results, he failed to document any connection between tangents and areas. The method is essentially an exercise in geometric series, and I think it is instructive and perhaps refreshing to introduce a little bit of variation from the standard introductions. The method is entirely accessible to senior students, and makes an interesting connection between the anti derivative result and the factorisation of (1 – rn+1). Fermat considered that the area between x = 0 and x = a below the curve y = xn and above the x-axis, to be approximated by circumscribed rectangles where the width of each rectangle formed a geometric sequence. The divi- sions into which the interval is divided, from the right hand side are made at x = a, x = ar, x = ar2, x = ar3 etc., where a and r are constants, with 0 < r < 1 as shown in the diagram. A u s t r a l i a n S e n i o r M a t h e m a t i c s J o u r n a l 1 8 ( 1 ) 53 s e 2 l p If we first consider the curve y = x , the area A contained within the rectan- a t S gles is given by: A = (a – ar)a2 + (ar – ar2)(ar)2 + (ar2 – ar3)(ar2)2 + … This is a geometric series with ratio r3 and first term (1 – r)a3.
    [Show full text]
  • A Tale of the Cycloid in Four Acts
    A Tale of the Cycloid In Four Acts Carlo Margio Figure 1: A point on a wheel tracing a cycloid, from a work by Pascal in 16589. Introduction In the words of Mersenne, a cycloid is “the curve traced in space by a point on a carriage wheel as it revolves, moving forward on the street surface.” 1 This deceptively simple curve has a large number of remarkable and unique properties from an integral ratio of its length to the radius of the generating circle, and an integral ratio of its enclosed area to the area of the generating circle, as can be proven using geometry or basic calculus, to the advanced and unique tautochrone and brachistochrone properties, that are best shown using the calculus of variations. Thrown in to this assortment, a cycloid is the only curve that is its own involute. Study of the cycloid can reinforce the curriculum concepts of curve parameterisation, length of a curve, and the area under a parametric curve. Being mechanically generated, the cycloid also lends itself to practical demonstrations that help visualise these abstract concepts. The history of the curve is as enthralling as the mathematics, and involves many of the great European mathematicians of the seventeenth century (See Appendix I “Mathematicians and Timeline”). Introducing the cycloid through the persons involved in its discovery, and the struggles they underwent to get credit for their insights, not only gives sequence and order to the cycloid’s properties and shows which properties required advances in mathematics, but it also gives a human face to the mathematicians involved and makes them seem less remote, despite their, at times, seemingly superhuman discoveries.
    [Show full text]
  • Cycloid Article(Final04)
    The Helen of Geometry John Martin The seventeenth century is one of the most exciting periods in the history of mathematics. The first half of the century saw the invention of analytic geometry and the discovery of new methods for finding tangents, areas, and volumes. These results set the stage for the development of the calculus during the second half. One curve played a central role in this drama and was used by nearly every mathematician of the time as an example for demonstrating new techniques. That curve was the cycloid. The cycloid is the curve traced out by a point on the circumference of a circle, called the generating circle, which rolls along a straight line without slipping (see Figure 1). It has been called it the “Helen of Geometry,” not just because of its many beautiful properties but also for the conflicts it engendered. Figure 1. The cycloid. This article recounts the history of the cycloid, showing how it inspired a generation of great mathematicians to create some outstanding mathematics. This is also a story of how pride, pettiness, and jealousy led to bitter disagreements among those men. Early history Since the wheel was invented around 3000 B.C., it seems that the cycloid might have been discovered at an early date. There is no evidence that this was the case. The earliest mention of a curve generated by a -1-(Final) point on a moving circle appears in 1501, when Charles de Bouvelles [7] used such a curve in his mechanical solution to the problem of squaring the circle.
    [Show full text]
  • Leonhard Euler English Version
    LEONHARD EULER (April 15, 1707 – September 18, 1783) by HEINZ KLAUS STRICK , Germany Without a doubt, LEONHARD EULER was the most productive mathematician of all time. He wrote numerous books and countless articles covering a vast range of topics in pure and applied mathematics, physics, astronomy, geodesy, cartography, music, and shipbuilding – in Latin, French, Russian, and German. It is not only that he produced an enormous body of work; with unbelievable creativity, he brought innovative ideas to every topic on which he wrote and indeed opened up several new areas of mathematics. Pictured on the Swiss postage stamp of 2007 next to the polyhedron from DÜRER ’s Melencolia and EULER ’s polyhedral formula is a portrait of EULER from the year 1753, in which one can see that he was already suffering from eye problems at a relatively young age. EULER was born in Basel, the son of a pastor in the Reformed Church. His mother also came from a family of pastors. Since the local school was unable to provide an education commensurate with his son’s abilities, EULER ’s father took over the boy’s education. At the age of 14, EULER entered the University of Basel, where he studied philosophy. He completed his studies with a thesis comparing the philosophies of DESCARTES and NEWTON . At 16, at his father’s wish, he took up theological studies, but he switched to mathematics after JOHANN BERNOULLI , a friend of his father’s, convinced the latter that LEONHARD possessed an extraordinary mathematical talent. At 19, EULER won second prize in a competition sponsored by the French Academy of Sciences with a contribution on the question of the optimal placement of a ship’s masts (first prize was awarded to PIERRE BOUGUER , participant in an expedition of LA CONDAMINE to South America).
    [Show full text]
  • Marin Mersenne As Mathematical Intelligencer
    Hist. Sci., li (2013) SMall SkIllS, BIG NETwORkS: MaRIN MERSENNE aS MaTHEMaTICal INTEllIGENCER Justin Grosslight Independent Scholar Writing in August 1634, the French polymath Nicolas-Claude Fabri de Peiresc reflected upon Marin Mersenne’s endeavours. Mersenne, Peiresc asserted, had forced himself into “frontiers that are a little more in fashion of the times than these prolix treaties of the schools that so few men handle outside of the colleges”.1 Peiresc was quite prescient to realize the novel claims that Mersenne was promoting. From the middle of the 1620s until his death in 1648, Mersenne encouraged discussion on a number of new mathematical concepts, ideas that lacked a secure home within the Aristotelian university curriculum.2 By mathematics, I am referring to mixed mathematics, the application of arithmetic and geometry often to physical proc- esses, and related topics in natural philosophy: examples include Galilean mechan- ics, the question of whether a void exists in nature, and analysis of conic sections and their spatial counterparts.3 For Peiresc and others, Mersenne was an exemplar of new, heterodox ideas: though he was a member of the religious Minim order, he was respected widely as a mathematician, he lived a gregarious life in cosmopoli- tan Paris, and he was an intimate friend of the famed French mathematician rené Descartes as well as a correspondent with the Italian Galileo Galilei and the Dutch Christiaan huygens.4 But while Mersenne is still remembered as a mathematician and correspondent of famous mathematicians, Peiresc’s description of Mersenne as trend-conscious or even a trendsetter has been effectively forgotten.
    [Show full text]