Original Sin, Free Will and Grace in The

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Original Sin, Free Will and Grace in The 1 ORIGINAL SIN, FREE WILL AND GRACE IN THE WORKS OF JEREMY TAYLOR by ANDREW HARVEY A thesis submitted to The University of Birmingham for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Theology and Religion School of Philosophy and Theology The University of Birmingham December 2010 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. 2 Abstract Taylor is an early example of a divine who wanted to find a way of remaining an orthodox Christian while rejecting the Augustinian doctrine of original sin. Taylor could not see how the term ‘sin’ could be correctly applied to anything but an individual’s freely-chosen acts. However, he recognised that the reduction of the Christian concept of sin to particular sins constituted the Pelagian heresy. He attempted to avoid it by placing the insight behind the traditional doctrine in the challenge posed to the will by a naturalised version of the Augustinian fallen state, which was nonetheless morally indifferent in itself. The insights and confusions in Taylor’s treatment of original sin and his anthropology, notably regarding the human will and its freedom, provide a fruitful basis for a more general consideration of the question of ‘orthodoxy’ concerning original sin and the classical Christian doctrine of man. 3 Table of Contents Introduction p6. Chapter 1: Secularising the fallen state, and upholding free choice: Taylor in context. p9. 1.1 Epicureanism, scepticism, Platonism, and naturalising the fallen state p15 Chapter 2: Taylor’s Augustinian anthropology without the Fall. p42 Chapter 3: Will, free will and the nature of 'original sin': Augustine, Taylor and Coleridge's Kantian critique. p71 A. Augustine and Taylor on the will and original sin p71 3.1 Augustine on the will and sin p71 3.2 Pelagius p85 3.3 Taylor’s anthropology and the nature and freedom of the will p92 B. Taylor’s attempt to reconcile an ‘Augustinian’ anthropology with libertarian freedom, and Coleridge’s Kantian critique p116 3.4 Metanoia p123 3.5 Natural propensities and the freedom of the will p126 3.6 Taylor, Coleridge and Kant on the propensity to sin p130 Chapter 4: Taylor on Nature and Grace. p136 4.1 Taylor on Nature and Grace p136 4.2 Taylor's use of the Fathers in his ‘non-lapsarian’ account of nature and grace p147 4 4.3 Taylor's revised Augustinianism on the goodness of the flesh: the example of sex and marriage p169 4.4 Flesh and sinful flesh p178 4.5 Taylor’s understanding of the ‘first Adam’ as human nature in itself p185 4.6 Conclusion to ch.4 p194 Appendix: Newman and Taylor on nature and grace and faith and reason. p198 Chapter 5: Taylor and natural law. p208 5.1 Taylor's idea of nature in the context of questions of natural right and natural law p209 5.2 Taylor’s rejection of natural law and its implications p215 Conclusion p250 Bibliography p259 Note on references and abbreviations: I have used the editorial divisions and numbering (including Roman numerals, or not etc.) of the editions I refer to. If referring to a single text for several pages, or giving a glancing reference, I have at times included the references in the text, rather than footnotes. I give a full reference for secondary literature in the first note for each work, and in the bibliography; then use the author's name and date of publication elsewhere. I have given the volume number and page reference for citations from Taylor's works, and full bibliographical information in the bibliography. In the first note for each, I preface the reference with the title of the book they come from, and thereafter generally 5 abbreviate this to the initials of the title: thus, Unum Necessarium: UN; Ductor Dubitantium: DD; Great Exemplar: GE. I refer to sermons by title, volume and page number. Taylor's developed views concerning my subject are chiefly found in UN, published during the Interregnum (1657) and his great casuistical work, DD, published in the earliest years of the Restoration (1660-2); as well as several important sermons; the Great Exemplar, contains an earlier version. I have either given the titles of Augustine's works in full in English (according to the translation I have used) or Latin, or used the Latin initials; the most common by far being: Conf.: Confessiones: Confessions; De Trin.: De Trinitate: On the Trinity; CD: De Civitate Dei: The City of God; DLA: De Libero Arbitrio Voluntatis: On Free Choice of the Will; DNC: De Nuptiis et Concupiscentia: On Marriage and Concupiscence; DNG: De Natura et Gratia: On Nature and Grace. For simplicity, the abbreviation of Against Two Letters of the Pelagians appears as ATLP. 6 Introduction Jeremy Taylor (1613 - 1667) was a celebrated figure for many generations of Anglicans, especially among those for whom the term “Anglican” acquired a certain positive ideological content. Ultimately Taylor’s reputation came to rest more on his literary talent, pastoral ideals and devotional writing, than his theology: the great Romantic poet Samuel Taylor Coleridge, who arguably became one of the Church of England’s greatest theological writers, called him “our Christian Mercury”, and “this most eloquent of Divines: Had I said, of Men, Cicero would forgive me, and Demosthenes nod assent!”1 Taylor’s Holy Living and Holy Dying became ubiquitous manuals of piety among those who came to be known as ‘high churchmen’; they were also influential for the Wesleys and the Methodist movement, and even in Evangelical circles.2 However, Taylor ought not to be neglected as a theologian. He is highly eclectic, and not always consistent: one of the characters in Newman’s novel Loss and Gain says that “Bishop Taylor differed from himself”.3 But he made a significant contribution to the development of a distinctively ‘Anglican’ identity, which began in earnest with the Laudian divines of the seventeenth century.4 Above all, perhaps, Taylor displays a remarkable subtlety and sensitivity in 1 Aids to Reflection, Routledge edition, p189. 2 Hughes, H. Trevor. "Jeremy Taylor and John Wesley." London Quarterly and Holborn Review 174 (1949): 296-304. 3 Oxford World’s Classics edition, p 61-2. Taylor was a benchmark ‘Anglican’ divine for the Tractarians as well as the older high church tradition. Theirs was far from an uncritical appreciation, however; Taylor was regarded by Newman as one of the fathers of Latitudinarianism and was later excluded from the Library of Anglo-Catholic Theology. 4 Of particular interest in this respect is the bibliography Taylor that attaches to a letter to one Mr Graham, of Trinity College, Dublin, included in Heber’s Life, in his complete edition of Taylor’s works, vol 1 p lxxxviii: “Hee that would improve in the understanding of the doctrine of the church of England, so as to bee able to teach others, must bee careful to understand and bee very perfect in every part of, [the following works].” There follows a very extensive and interesting list, with Taylor’s comments. It includes the Dutch Arminian “Episcopius, whose whole works are excellent, and containe the whole body of orthodox religion”; the reader, Heber comments, “will see from this where [Taylor] may have learned his doctrines respecting Original Sin.” Taylor’s attempts to minimise the traditional doctrine owe something to Episcopius; but his account contains many original aspects, which we shall consider in the following chapters. 7 relating the patristic learning and classical Christian orthodoxy in which he was steeped, with the startling new theories in politics and law, science and epistemology, which were making such an impact in his day, and in which Taylor had a voracious interest.5 In particular, he draws on them to remarkable effect in his writings on the unlikely subject of original sin, and in his related account of the relationship between nature and grace. I shall argue that Taylor tries to substitute for the traditional doctrine of original sin an account of human nature which answers to Augustinian anthropology, but which treats what were generally regarded as the effects of original sin, as natural. However, human nature is not thereby intrinsically corrupt, for Taylor: what St Augustine called ‘ignorance’, ‘difficulty’ and ‘concupiscence’, are both the conditions for human sin and failure, and, ironically, necessary for human freedom and moral responsibility, according to Taylor. The passions, which the Augustinian tradition held to be in a disordered state resulting from original sin, are seen by Taylor as natural, and good when engaged in the right context and degree. Taylor apparently thinks that he can avoid the heresy of Pelagianism by allowing that although sin is not irresistible, it is inevitable: inevitable, for every individual, but not in any given instance, we might say. However, he tends to reduce ‘original sin’ to what Augustine thought of as its effects, in Adam’s descendants; whereas Augustine actually thought that the evil will which led to the first sin, was replicated in Adam’s descendants, not that their wills were simply tempted or overpowered by ‘external’ influences - a view, which, on Augustine’s account, would reduce to ‘Pelagianism’ or ‘Manicheanism’, depending on whether the influence in question was resistible or not.
Recommended publications
  • The Word Made Flesh
    1 The Word Made Flesh et’s begin our study of the Gospel of John with what is called the LPrologue, one of the loftiest and most inspiring passages in the New Testament. It lays out the major premise of the Gospel, so it’s a good way to start our exploration. In spite of its weight and importance, the Prologue is actually quite short, consisting of just the first eighteen verses of John. However, because of their weight and importance, we could easily write an entire book just on these verses. Most scholars believe that portions of these first eighteen verses were an early Christian hymn influenced by Greek and Jewish philosophical ideas. John incorporated the hymn, reworking it a bit, because it captured profound ideas about who Jesus is and the meaning of his life. Before delving into the meat of this section, I want to point out what you no doubt have already noticed, that the Gospel begins 15 Copyright © 2015 by Abingdon Press. All rights reserved. 9781501805332_INT_Layout.indd 15 10/20/15 1:12 PM John: The Gospel of Light and Life with these three words: “In the beginning.” You’ll recall that another book of the Bible starts with these same words. Genesis 1:1 starts, “In the beginning. ” John’s use of these words is no accident. He is pointing back to the creation story. For now, I merely want you to notice the reference, and I’ll say more about it at various points throughout the book. The premise of the entire Gospel, so beautifully introduced in the Prologue, is that Jesus embodies God’s Word.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Intuitionism: a Structural Critique
    J Value Inquiry (2016) 50:631–647 DOI 10.1007/s10790-016-9547-8 Ethical Intuitionism: A Structural Critique Danny Frederick1 Published online: 8 February 2016 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016 1 Introduction Recent years have seen attempts by many philosophers to rehabilitate, with some modifications, a traditional doctrine of ethical intuitionism (henceforward ‘‘intu- itionism’’). Contemporary intuitionists claim that moral knowledge consists of those propositions that are known by intellectual reflection (intuition), by moral observation or by moral emotion, or which are capable of being cogently inferred from propositions which are items of moral knowledge. Some intuitionists, such as Michael Huemer, admit only intuition (of particular or of general propositions) as a non-inferential source of moral knowledge; but others, such as Robert Audi, allow also moral observation and moral emotion. I offer a critique of contemporary intuitionist theories that depends upon their common structure: analysis of the abstract features of the approach show it to be an inadequate account of moral knowledge. I use Huemer and Audi as representative intuitionists. The differences between their views, and between their views and those of other intuitionists, are incidental at the level of generality of my argument. In section 2, I outline the contemporary intuitionist approach to moral knowledge. In sections 3, 4 and 5, I show that the problem of inter-cultural conflict undermines the claims that moral intuition, moral observation and moral emotion, respectively, are sources of non-inferential moral knowledge. I also explain the inadequacy of the intuitionist attempt to solve the problem by invoking bias or intellectual or moral failings.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Mute, Deaf, and Blind’
    Journal of Moral Theology, Vol. 6, Special Issue 2 (2017): 112-137 Seventeenth-Century Casuistry Regarding Persons with Disabilities: Antonino Diana’s Tract ‘On the Mute, Deaf, and Blind’ Julia A. Fleming N 1639, THE FAMOUS THEATINE casuist Antonino Diana published the fifth part of his Resolutiones morales, a volume that included a tract regarding the mute, deaf, and blind.1 Structured I as a series of cases (i.e., questions and answers), its form resembles tracts in Diana’s other volumes concerning members of particular groups, such as vowed religious, slaves, and executors of wills.2 While the arrangement of cases within the tract is not systematic, they tend to fall into two broad categories, the first regarding the status of persons with specified disabilities in the Church and the second in civil society. Diana draws the cases from a wide variety of sources, from Thomas Aquinas and Gratian to later experts in theology, pastoral practice, canon law, and civil law. The tract is thus a reference collection rather than a monograph, although Diana occasionally proposes a new question for his colleagues’ consideration. “On the Mute, Deaf, and Blind” addresses thirty-seven different cases, some focused upon persons with a single disability, and others, on persons with combination of these three disabilities. Specific cases hinge upon further distinctions. Is the individual in question completely or partially blind, totally deaf or hard of hearing, mute or beset with a speech impediment? Was the condition present from birth 1 Antonino Diana, Resolutionum moralium pars quinta (hereafter RM 5) (Lyon, France: Sumpt.
    [Show full text]
  • Total Depravity
    TULIP: A FREE GRACE PERSPECTIVE PART 1: TOTAL DEPRAVITY ANTHONY B. BADGER Associate Professor of Bible and Theology Grace Evangelical School of Theology Lancaster, Pennsylvania I. INTRODUCTION The evolution of doctrine due to continued hybridization has pro- duced a myriad of theological persuasions. The only way to purify our- selves from the possible defects of such “theological genetics” is, first, to recognize that we have them and then, as much as possible, to set them aside and disassociate ourselves from the systems which have come to dominate our thinking. In other words, we should simply strive for truth and an objective understanding of biblical teaching. This series of articles is intended to do just that. We will carefully consider the truth claims of both Calvinists and Arminians and arrive at some conclusions that may not suit either.1 Our purpose here is not to defend a system, but to understand the truth. The conflicting “isms” in this study (Calvinism and Arminianism) are often considered “sacred cows” and, as a result, seem to be solidified and in need of defense. They have become impediments in the search for truth and “barriers to learn- ing.” Perhaps the emphatic dogmatism and defense of the paradoxical views of Calvinism and Arminianism have impeded the theological search for truth much more than we realize. Bauman reflects, I doubt that theology, as God sees it, entails unresolvable paradox. That is another way of saying that any theology that sees it [paradox] or includes it is mistaken. If God does not see theological endeavor as innately or irremediably paradoxical, 1 For this reason the author declines to be called a Calvinist, a moderate Calvinist, an Arminian, an Augustinian, a Thomist, a Pelagian, or a Semi- Pelagian.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics in Health Care Primer: Methods of Analysis
    Augusta University Institute of Public and Preventive Health Center for Bioethics and Health Policy Ethics in Health Care Primer: Methods of Analysis This primer highlights some of the more commonly utilized ethical foundations from which to analyze ethical dilemmas in health care settings including: • Principle Based Approaches (Principlism) • Narrative Ethics • Virtue Ethics • Casuistry (The “Four Boxes”) • Feminist Ethics Each ethical theory emphasizes a different methodology and perspective from which to understand and resolve clinical dilemmas. Applying more than one method to an ethics consultation can enrich case analysis and provide novel insights which may help resolve conflicts. Some ethical questions are more easily addressed using one methodology than another. As a starting point, however, for any clinical ethics consultation, it is important to identify the type of ethical dilemma: Different Types of Ethical Dilemmas DILEMMA TYPE DESCRIPTION POSSIBLE RESPONSE Uncertainty about the Using ethical analysis to Moral Confusion “right” thing to do clarify underlying issues Exploring what could be Belief that there is a “right” changed within the health Moral Distress action that needs to be taken system and community to but being unable to do so reduce constraints Experiencing grief and Identifying what could be Moral Sadness frustration from being part improved and avoiding of a tragic situation blame for circumstances pg. 1 Principlism Principlism refers to a method of analysis utilizing widely accepted norms of moral agency (the ability of an individual to make judgments of right and wrong) to identify ethical concerns and determine acceptable resolutions for clinical dilemmas. In the context of bioethics, principlism describes a method of ethical analysis proposed by Beauchamp and Childress, who believe that there are four principles central in the ethical practice of health care1: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Apostles' Creed the Nicene Creed
    4 The Faith We Profess The Apostles’ Creed The Nicene Creed I believe in God, We believe in one God, the Father almighty, the Father, the Almighty, creator of heaven and earth. maker of heaven and earth, of all that is, seen and unseen. I believe in Jesus Christ, his only We believe in one Lord, Jesus Son, our Lord. Christ, the only Son of God, eternally begotten of the Father, God from God, Light from Light, true God from true God, begotten, not made, one in Being with the Father. Through him all things were made. For us men and for our salvation he came down from heaven: He was conceived by the by the power of the Holy Spirit power of the Holy Spirit he was born of the Virgin Mary, and born of the Virgin Mary. and became man. He suffered under Pontius Pilate, For our sake he was crucified was crucified, died, and was buried. under Pontius Pilate; He descended into hell. he suffered, died, and was buried. On the third day he rose again. On the third day he rose again in fulfillment of the Scriptures; He ascended into heaven he ascended into heaven and is seated at the right and is seated at the right hand of the Father. hand of the Father. He will come again to judge the He will come again in glory to living and the dead. judge the living and the dead, and his kingdom will have no end An Introduction to the Apostles’ Creed 5 The Apostles’ Creed The Nicene Creed I believe in the Holy Spirit, We believe in the Holy Spirit, the holy catholic Church, the Lord, the giver of Life, the communion of saints, who proceeds from the the forgiveness of sins, Father and the Son.
    [Show full text]
  • The Nicene Creed: the Niceno- the Apostles’ Creed: Caesarea: Constantinopolitan Creed
    Jonathan J. Armstrong, Ph.D. Moody Bible Institute The Creed of Eusebius of The Nicene Creed: The Niceno- The Apostles’ Creed: Caesarea: Constantinopolitan Creed: We believe in one only God, We believe in one God, the We believe in one God, the I believe in God the Father Father almighty, maker of all things Father almighty, creator of things Father almighty, maker of heaven almighty, maker of heaven and earth; visible and invisible; and earth, and of all things visible And in Jesus Christ his only Son visible and invisible; And in one Lord Jesus Christ, the and invisible; our Lord, who was conceived by the And in the Lord Jesus Christ, for he Son of God, the only-begotten of his And in one Lord Jesus Christ, the Holy Ghost, born of the Virgin Mary, is the Word of God, God of God, light Father, of the substance of the only begotten Son of God, begotten of light, life of life, his only Son, the Father, God of God, light of light, of his Father before all worlds, light suffered under Pontius Pilate, was first-born of all creatures, begotten very God of very God, begotten, not of light, very God of very God, crucified, dead, and buried; he of the Father before all time, by made, being of one substance begotten not made, being of one descended into hell; the third day he (ὁμοούσιον) with the Father, by whom also everything was created, substance with the Father, by whom rose again from the dead; he whom all things were made, both all things were made, who for us men who became flesh for our ascended into heaven, and sits on which be in heaven and in earth, who and for our salvation came down the right hand of God the Father redemption, who lived and suffered for us men and for our salvation from heaven and was incarnate by among men, rose again the third day, came down from heaven and was the Holy Ghost and the Virgin Mary, almighty; from thence he shall come returned to the Father, and will come incarnate and was made man.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Medieval G
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Religious Studies Faculty Publications Religious Studies 2001 History of Western Ethics: Early Medieval G. Scott aD vis University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/religiousstudies-faculty- publications Part of the Ethics in Religion Commons, and the History of Christianity Commons Recommended Citation Davis, G. Scott. "History of Western Ethics: Early Medieval." In Encyclopedia of Ethics, edited by Lawrence Becker and Charlotte Becker, 709-15. 2nd ed. Vol. 2. New York: Routledge, 2001. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Religious Studies at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. history of Western ethics: 5. Early Medieval Copyright 2001 from Encyclopedia of Ethics by Lawrence Becker and Charlotte Becker. Reproduced by permission of Taylor and Francis, LLC, a division of Informa plc. history of Western ethics: 5. Early Medieval ''Medieval" and its cognates arose as terms of op­ probrium, used by the Italian humanists to charac­ terize more a style than an age. Hence it is difficult at best to distinguish late antiquity from the early middle ages. It is equally difficult to determine the proper scope of "ethics," the philosophical schools of late antiquity having become purveyors of ways of life in the broadest sense, not clearly to be distin­ guished from the more intellectually oriented ver­ sions of their religious rivals. This article will begin with the emergence of philosophically informed re­ flection on the nature of life, its ends, and respon­ sibilities in the writings of the Latin Fathers and close with the twelfth century, prior to the systematic reintroduction and study of the Aristotelian corpus.
    [Show full text]
  • Nature and Human Flourishing in the Laws of Manu and the Daodejing Qijing Zheng Bucknell University, [email protected]
    Bucknell University Bucknell Digital Commons Honors Theses Student Theses Fall 2017 Nature and Human Flourishing in the Laws of Manu and the Daodejing Qijing Zheng Bucknell University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses Part of the Chinese Studies Commons, Comparative Literature Commons, Intellectual History Commons, Social Control, Law, Crime, and Deviance Commons, and the South and Southeast Asian Languages and Societies Commons Recommended Citation Zheng, Qijing, "Nature and Human Flourishing in the Laws of Manu and the Daodejing" (2017). Honors Theses. 428. https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses/428 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Theses at Bucknell Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Bucknell Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Nature and Human Flourishing in the Laws of Manu and the Daodejing ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​​ ​ ​ ​ ​​ by Qijing Zheng ​ ​ Dec 13, 2017 ​ ​ ​ ​ Approved by: ​ ​ James Mark Shields Digitally signed by James Shields ​ ​ ​ ​ Date: 2017.12.15 09:55:11 -05'00' Adviser: John Hunter ​ ​ Program Chair (proxy): ​ ​ ​ ​ Introduction By comparing the interpretation of dharma in the ancient Indian Laws of Manu ​ ​ (Manusmṛti ) with the concepts of dao 道 in the Chinese classic, Daodejing 道德經, I will ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ ​ demonstrate that, despite the plausible perception that the former represents despotic, hierarchical governance while the latter promotes freedom (and even anarchy), the two texts in fact share a similar envision of human flourishing through the following of one's nature, as well as a foundational belief that both laws and political ideals emerge from nature.
    [Show full text]
  • NARRATIVE, CASUISTRY, and the FUNCTION of CONSCIENCE in THOMAS AQUINAS – Stephen Chanderbhan –
    Diametros 47 (2016): 1–18 doi: 10.13153/diam.47.2016.865 NARRATIVE, CASUISTRY, AND THE FUNCTION OF CONSCIENCE IN THOMAS AQUINAS – Stephen Chanderbhan – Abstract. Both the function of one’s conscience, as Thomas Aquinas understands it, and the work of casuistry in general involve deliberating about which universal moral principles are applicable in particular cases. Thus, understanding how conscience can function better also indicates how casuistry might be done better – both on Thomistic terms, at least. I claim that, given Aquinas’ de- scriptions of certain parts of prudence (synesis and gnome) and the role of moral virtue in practical knowledge, understanding particular cases more as narratives, or parts of narratives, likely will result, all else being equal, in more accurate moral judgments of particular cases. This is especially important in two kinds of cases: first, cases in which Aquinas recognizes universal moral principles do not specify the means by which they are to be followed; second, cases in which the type-identity of an action – and thus the norms applicable to it – can be mistaken Keywords: Thomas Aquinas, conscience, narrative, casuistry, prudence, virtue, moral judgment, moral development, moral knowledge. Introduction ‘Casuistry’ has a bad reputation in some circles. It tends to be associated wi- th formalized, but too legalistic, approaches to determining and enumerating mo- ral faults. In a more generic sense, though, casuistry just refers to deliberating about and discerning what universal moral principles apply in particular cases, based on relevant details of the case at issue. As Thomas Aquinas understands things, casuistry parallels the ordinary, everyday function of one’s conscience, which specifically regards particular cases in which one deliberates about one’s own morally relevant actions.1 Given this, we might be able to gain insight to how formalized casuistry can be done well by drawing an analogy from what it takes for conscience to function well.
    [Show full text]
  • The Doctrine of Sin in the Thought of George R. Knight: Its Context and Implications
    Andrews University Digital Commons @ Andrews University Master's Theses Graduate Research 2009 The Doctrine of Sin in the Thought of George R. Knight: Its Context and Implications Jamie Kiley Andrews University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.andrews.edu/theses Recommended Citation Kiley, Jamie, "The Doctrine of Sin in the Thought of George R. Knight: Its Context and Implications" (2009). Master's Theses. 47. https://digitalcommons.andrews.edu/theses/47 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Research at Digital Commons @ Andrews University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Andrews University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Thank you for your interest in the Andrews University Digital Library of Dissertations and Theses. Please honor the copyright of this document by not duplicating or distributing additional copies in any form without the author’s express written permission. Thanks for your cooperation. ABSTRACT THE DOCTRINE OF SIN IN THE THOUGHT OF GEORGE R. KNIGHT: ITS CONTEXT AND IMPLICATIONS by Jamie Kiley Adviser: Denis Fortin ABSTRACT OF GRADUATE STUDENT RESEARCH Thesis Andrews University Seventh-day Adventist Theological Seminary Title: THE DOCTRINE OF SIN IN THE THOUGHT OF GEORGE R. KNIGHT: ITS CONTEXT AND IMPLICATIONS Name of researcher: Jamie Kiley Name and degree of faculty adviser: Denis Fortin, Ph.D. Date completed: December 2009 George R. Knight attempts to chart a middle course between various historical extremes on the doctrine of sin. His view of the Fall and of the consequent effects on human nature is not as pessimistic as that of theologians in the Augustinian tradition (including Martin Luther and John Calvin), who stress the complete corruption of human nature and the loss of free will.
    [Show full text]
  • Courtney Cain, Ph.D. 2017 Letter from the Chair
    University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign www.history.illinois.edu Spring 2018 Courtney Cain, Ph.D. 2017 Letter from the Chair uring the past year, from Charlottesville to the 500th anniversary of Martin Luther’s launching of the Protestant Reformation to the centennial of the Russian Revolution Dand the sesquicentennial of our beloved University of Illinois, we were continuously reminded of the ways in which history impacts our present. Events also strengthened our conviction that historians and lovers of history must vigorously engage public discourse. Our job is not merely to set the record straight but also to add complexity and multiple perspec- tives to what might seem to be simple issues. Commitment to history as a form of civic engagement is what led many of our own faculty and graduate students to our discipline and it continues to drive our teaching and research. Over the past year, it has been thrilling to see our undergraduate students adopt this passion and reach out to share it with new audiences. This could take the form of Hidden History tours of campus conducted by public history students based on their own research projects. Or it could transform the airwaves via the People’s History Hour radio show, created by two of our majors. One of them, Nick Goodell, spoke for all of us when he declared, “History seems to me to be the best way to understand our world.” Clare Crowston The pages of this newsletter reflect our colleagues’ close engagement with a number of important anniversaries and historical events. Perhaps closest to our hearts is the 150th anniversary of the founding of our own university.
    [Show full text]