Thomas Bradwardine's De Continuo and the Structure of Fourteenth-Century Learning

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Thomas Bradwardine's De Continuo and the Structure of Fourteenth-Century Learning THOMAS BRADWARDINE'S DE CONTINUO AND THE STRUCTURE OF FOURTEENTH-CENTURY LEARNING EDITH D.SYLLA The late medieval Christian Aristotelian worldview, when pressed to its logical extremes, was incompatible with Euclidean geometry. In the stan­ dard medieval Aristotelian classification of the sciences, natural philosophy and geometry were separate disciplines, each with its own principles and conclusions. Geometry assumed as a principle, without proof, that continua must be infinitely divisible into ever smaller continua, while natural phi­ losophy proved it.1 Geometry included in its subject matter indivisibles such as points, lines, and planes—meanwhile asserting that higher-order continua are not composed of such indivisibles. Natural philosophy asserted that quantities—including indivisibles such as points, lines, and surfaces— really exist in substances as their accidental forms, although they are con­ sidered mathematically in abstraction from such substances.2 But when geometric indivisibles such as points and lines, or purported physical indivisibles such as instants or exact degrees of quality, were sup­ posed to exist in reality {esse in re), paradoxes ensued. In view of these paradoxes, some idiosyncratic scholars opted to compose continua of indi­ visibles at the price of inconsistency with Euclidean geometry and/or Aris­ totelian physics. Mainstream scholars, including William of Ockham, John Buridan, and Thomas Bradwardine, often concluded that geometric indi­ visibles do not in fact exist, thus resolving the apparent paradoxes by deny­ ing the entities that led to them.3 In either case, whether scholars adopted 1 For Thomas Bradwardine's quotation of Averroes's statement of this view, see John Murdoch, "Thomas Bradwardine: Mathematics and Continuity in the Fourteenth Century/' in Mathematics and Its Applications to Science and Natural Philosophy in the Middle Ages, ed Edward Grant and John E. Murdoch (Cambridge, London, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 136 n. 62.1 discuss this passage below. 2 For a discussion of John Dumbleton, whose ideas about the relation of mathematics to physics mirror part of the standard view, see Edith Sylla, "The Oxford Calculators and Math­ ematical Physics: John Dumbleton's Summa Logicae et Philosophiae Naturalis, Parts Π and III," in Physics, Cosmology and Astronomy, 1300-1700: Tension and Accommodation, ed. Sabetai Unguru, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 126 (Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer, 1991), pp. 129-61. 3 For reference to a number of sources on this point, see John Murdoch, "Philosophy and the Enterprise of Science in the Later Middle Ages," in The Interaction between Science and Philosophy, ed. Yehuda Elkana (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1974), p. 61. It is notable that Bradwardine and the nominalists, although often portrayed as belonging to opposing metaphysical camps, agreed on denying the existence of indivisibles. It should be noted that philosophers who denied the existence of geometric indivisibles nevertheless held the prime movers of the celestial spheres (or angels more generally) and human souls to be indivisible substances. EDITH SYLLA 149 some sort of atomism or denied the existence of geometric indivisibles al­ together, the previously standard Aristotelian understanding of the relation between mathematics and physics broke down: geometry could no longer be understood to deal with quantities existing in, but considered in abstrac­ tion from, physical bodies. In this paper I want to use Thomas Bradwardine's De continuo as a source of evidence about the structure of fourteenth-century learning, par­ ticularly as it involved the relations between natural philosophy, mathemat­ ics, logic, and theology. Thanks to the wide-ranging research of John Mur­ doch, we have extensive knowledge about Bradwardine's text and about the earlier texts of such "atomist" authors as Henry of Harclay and Walter Chatton to which Bradwardine was reacting.4 In addition, in a number of papers Murdoch has presented a broad picture of what he calls "the unitary character of late medieval learning," arguing for the identity of fourteenth- century science and philosophy and for a close connection of natural phi­ losophy and theology through a group of shared tools, tactics, or conceptual schemes ranging from supposition theory in logic, through the mathematics of ratios, to the habit of arguing de potentia Dei absoluta or secundum imaginationem, and so forth.5 What I want to do here is to put these two parts of Murdoch's scholarly contribution more explicitly together—that is, 4 As evidence for my paper I have used both John Murdoch's published work and his un­ published draft editions of a wide range of texts, especially Thomas Bradwardine's De con­ tinuo and Henry of Harclay's question Utrum mundus potent durare in eternum a parte post. In the 1960s Murdoch prepared critical editions and translations of Harclay, Chatton, Odo, Bonetus, and John the Canon, as well as of Bradwardine's De continuo, which were to form the basis of a several-volume study on the problem of the continuum and related issues in the Middle Ages; see John Murdoch and Edward Synan, "Two Questions on the Continuum: Walter Chatton (?), O.F.M. and Adam Wodeham, O.F.M.," Franciscan Studies 26 (1966): 215 n. 10 (hereafter Murdoch and Synan, "Two Questions"). At that time he gave me copies of his editions and translations. It is perhaps appropriate to my topic, if awkward in other ways, that my study is based in part on thirty-year-old manuscript copies of these editions and translations, most of which have yet to appear in print. I have not checked the editions, but I have sometimes made my own translations, because it was simpler to do so and because Murdoch's translations had not been published or were not available for citation. All credit for the texts and the substance of the translations should go to him, while any blame for erro­ neous deviations from the true sense should fall on me. The text of Thomas Bradwardine's De continuo in John Murdoch, "Geometry and the Continuum in the Fourteenth Century: A Philosophical Analysis of Thomas Bradwardine's Tractatus de continuo" (Ph.D. diss., Uni­ versity of Wisconsin, 1957), available in microfilm, is similar but not identical to the edition I am using. 5 John Murdoch, "Mathesis in philosophiam scholasticam introducta: The Rise and De­ velopment of the Application of Mathematics in Fourteenth-Century Philosophy and Theol­ ogy," in Arts libéraux et Philosophie au Moyen Age (Actes du Quatrième Congres Interna­ tional de Philosophie Médiévale) (Montreal and Paris, 1969), pp. 215-54; idem, "Philosophy and the Enterprise of Science," (n. 3), pp. 51-113; idem, "From Social into Intellectual Fac­ tors: An Aspect of the Unitary Character of Late Medieval Learning," in The Cultural Con- text of Medieval Learning, ed. J. E. Murdoch and E. D. Sylla (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1975), pp. 271-339. .
Recommended publications
  • The Fourteenth and Seventeenth Century Project of Mathematical Physics
    ORG ANON 41:2009 Elżbieta Jung (Łódź, Poland) THE FOURTEENTH AND SEVENTEENTH CENTURY PROJECT OF MATHEMATICAL PHYSICS. CONTINUITY OR DISCONTINUITY?* Introduction Medieval philosophers while commenting on Aristotle's works on natural philosophy noticed many apporiai in his physics. What is more, inspired by William of Ockham (ca. 1280-1349), they rejected Aristotelian prohibition of metabasis limiting the use of geometry only to scientice media? (intermediate sciences), such as optics or astronomy, which deal only with quantified aspects of natural phenomena and not the whole phenomenon'. In the 14th century the members of the famous English School, so-called Oxford Calculators introduced to physics both: mathematics, understood as a proper language of science, and logic understood as the convenient way to pose problems. Therefore, it seems interesting to examine if they have any project of mathematical physics and if so whether it made them stand any closer to modern science. Since it is no more doubtful that Galileo, while proving a proper rule of accelerate motion, used the Mean Speed Theorem, formulated by one of the Calculators, William Heytesbury (ca. 1313-1372)2, and that Newton employed the 14lh century theory of compounding ratios3, it seems attractive to go back to a continuity/discontinuity in the history of natural science. One of the most distinguished historians of medieval science, Annelise Maier, regarded the history of natural philosophy from the thirteenth to the 181'1 century as the history of the gradual rejection of Aristotelianism. She claimed that it did not evolve uniformly from century to century, but it " The paper is a revised version of an article titled: Why vra.v Medieval Mechanics Doomed? The Failure lo Substitute Mathematical Physics for Aristotelianism in: Miscellanea Mediaevalia: Herbst des Mittelalters? Fragen zur Bewertimg des 14, und 15.
    [Show full text]
  • 62F16fbeaf706c4a09c9a65a7f2c
    TOWARDS THE MODERN THEORY OF MOTION Oxford Calculators and the new interpretation of Aristotle vol. IV Elżbieta Jung Robert Podkoński TOWARDS THE MODERN THEORY OF MOTION Oxford Calculators and the new interpretation of Aristotle Łódź 2020 Elżbieta Jung, Robert Podkoński – University of Lodz Faculty of Philosophy and History, 90-131 Lodz, 3/5 Lindleya St., Poland Series Research on Science & Natural Philosophy, vol. IV EDITORIAL BOARD Jagna Brudzińska, Universität zu Köln Daniel A. Di Liscia, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, München Paweł Maślanka, University of Lodz Jean-Paul Pittion, Trinity College, Dublin Sabine Rommevaux-Tani, Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Paris Elżbieta Żądzińska, University of Lodz REVIEWER Mikołaj Olszewski INITIATING EDITOR Natasza Koźbiał EDITORS Latin – Dariusz Gwis English – Guy Torr TYPESETTING Katarzyna Turkowska TECHNICAL EDITOR Anna Sońta COVER DESIGN Katarzyna Turkowska Cover Image: © depositphotos.com/Exi Printed directly from camera-ready materials provided to the Łódź University Press by Faculty of Philosophy and History © Copyright by Elzbieta Jung, Robert Podkoński, Łódź 2020 © Copyright for this edition by University of Łódź, Łódź 2020 NATIONAL SCIENCE CENTER, POLAND 2015/17/B/HS1/02376 Published by Lodz University Press Edition I. W.09767.20.0.K Printing sheets 28.75 ISBN 978-83-8220-327-1 e-ISBN 978-83-8220-328-8 Lodz University Press 90-131 Lodz, 8 Lindleya St. www.wydawnictwo.uni.lodz.pl e-mail: [email protected] phone. 42 665 58 63 Table of contents Preface .......................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • William of Ockham (C.1287-1347)
    HPS 322 Michael J. White History of Science Fall semester, 2013 The 14th century A.D.: A. (1) William of Ockham (c.1287-1347). (2) The ‘Oxford Calculators’ or ‘Mertonians’ (after Merton College, Oxford) of the 14th century: Thomas Bradwardine, William Heytesbury, Richard Swineshead, John Dumbleton. The graphic/geometrical representation of the ‘intension and remission of forms’ (of which ‘speed’ is only one). ‘Uniform’, ‘uniformly difform’, and ‘difformly difform’ continuous change (i.e., continuous qualitative ‘intension’ or increase and ‘remission’ or decrease–which includes intension/remission of speed). Statement and proof of a ‘mean-value theorem’: a body moving with at a constant speed v/2 travels the same distance s in a time t as does a body uniformly accelerated body from rest to speed v in the same time t. Representation of quantity of motion (distance traversed) as area of plane figure. B. Those associated with the University of Paris: Jean Buridan (ca. 1300-1361)–further development of impetus theory. Nicole Oresme (ca. 1323-1382). C. Oresme on commensurability/incommensurability of the orbital periods of the celestial bodies. Recollect that: magnitudes A and B are commensurable iff (if and only if) there exists some positive magnitude M that is a common ‘aliquot part’ of both A and B (i.e., there exist positive integers n and m such that A = M × n and B = M × m). Consider any spatial configuration S of alignment of celestial bodies (e.g., planets) P1 and P21 and assume that the periods of P and P2 (T1 and T2, respectively) are incommensurable. Will P12 and P ever again assume exactly that alignment S? Answer: no.
    [Show full text]
  • Behind the Mirror Revealing the Contexts of Jacobus's Speculum
    Behind the Mirror Revealing the Contexts of Jacobus’s Speculum musicae by Karen Desmond A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Music New York University May, 2009 ___________________________ Edward H. Roesner © Karen Desmond All Rights Reserved, 2009 DEDICATION For my family iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank my advisor, Edward Roesner, for his unfaltering support throughout this process, for his thoughtful suggestions regarding lines of inquiry, and his encyclopedic knowledge of the field. I would like to thank Stanley Boorman and Gabriela Iltnichi for their friendship and expertise, and their critical eye in their careful reading of many drafts of my work. For their assistance during my research trip to Belgium, I must mention Monsieur Abbé Deblon and Christian Dury at the Archives de l’Evêché, Liège, Paul Bertrand at the Archives de l’Etat, Liège, Philippe Vendrix for his kind hospitality, and to Barbara Haggh-Huglo for her tips and advice in advance of my trip, and for also reading a final draft of this dissertation. I would also like to thank Margaret Bent and Ruth Steiner for help during the early stages of my doctoral research, and Suzanne Cusick for her reading of the final draft. Finally, heartfelt thanks are due to my husband, Insup; my two sons, Ethan and Owen; and my parents, John and Chris, who have been steadfast in their encouragement of this endeavor. v ABSTRACT This study addresses the general question of how medieval music theory participated in the discourse of the related disciplines of philosophy, natural science and theology.
    [Show full text]
  • What the Middle Ages Knew IV
    Late Medieval Philosophy Piero Scaruffi Copyright 2018 http://www.scaruffi.com/know 1 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – The Bible is infallible, therefore there is no need for scientific investigation or for the laws of logic – Conflict between science and religion due to the Christian dogma that the Bible is the truth – 1.Dangerous to claim otherwise – 2.Pointless to search for additional truths – Tertullian (3rd c AD): curiosity no longer necessary because we know the meaning of the world and what is going to happen next ("Liber de Praescriptione Haereticorum") 2 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – Decline of scientific knowledge • Lactantius (4th c AD) ridicules the notion that the Earth could be a sphere ("Divinae Institutiones III De Falsa Sapientia Philosophorum") • Cosmas Indicopleustes' "Topographia Cristiana" (6th c AD): the Earth is a disc 3 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – Plato's creation by the demiurge in the Timaeus very similar to the biblical "Genesis" – Christian thinkers are raised by neoplatonists • Origen was a pupil of Ammonius Sacca (Plotinus' teacher) • Augustine studied Plotinus 4 What the Middle Ages knew • Preservation of classical knowledge – Boethius (6th c AD) translates part of Aristotle's "Organon" and his "Arithmetica" preserves knowledge of Greek mathematics – Cassiodorus (6th c AD) popularizes scientific studies among monks and formalizes education ("De Institutione Divinarum" and "De artibus ac disciplinis liberalium litterarum") with the division of disciplines into arts (grammar, rhetoric, dialectic) – and disiplines (arithmeitc,geometry, music, astronomy) – Isidore of Sevilla (7th c AD) preserves Graeco- Roman knowledge in "De Natura Rerum" and "Origines" 5 What the Middle Ages knew • Preservation of classical knowledge – Bede (8th c AD) compiles an encyclopedia, "De Natura Rerum" – St Peter's at Canterbury under Benedict Biscop (7th c AD) becomes a center of learning – Episcopal school of York: arithmetic, geometry, natural history, astronomy.
    [Show full text]
  • REBIRTH, REFORM and RESILIENCE Universities in Transition 1300-1700
    REBIRTH, REFORM AND RESILIENCE Universities in Transition 1300-1700 Edited by James M. Kittelson and Pamela J. Transue $25.00 REBIRTH, REFORM, AND RESILIENCE Universities in Transition, 1300-1700 Edited by James M. Kittelson and Pamela]. Transue In his Introduction to this collection of original essays, Professor Kittelson notes that the university is one of the few institutions that medieval Latin Christendom contributed directly to modern Western civilization. An export wherever else it is found, it is unique to Western culture. All cultures, to be sure, have had their intellec­ tuals—those men and women whose task it has been to learn, to know, and to teach. But only in Latin Christendom were scholars—the company of masters and students—found gathered together into the universitas whose entire purpose was to develop and disseminate knowledge in a continu­ ous and systematic fashion with little regard for the consequences of their activities. The studies in this volume treat the history of the universities from the late Middle Ages through the Reformation; that is, from the time of their secure founding, through the period in which they were posed the challenges of humanism and con­ fessionalism, but before the explosion of knowl­ edge that marked the emergence of modern science and the advent of the Enlightenment. The essays and their authors are: "University and Society on the Threshold of Modern Times: The German Connection," by Heiko A. Ober­ man; "The Importance of the Reformation for the Universities: Culture and Confessions in the Criti­ cal Years," by Lewis W. Spitz; "Science and the Medieval University," by Edward Grant; "The Role of English Thought in the Transformation of University Education in the Late Middle Ages," by William J.
    [Show full text]
  • The Scientific Revolution Revisited
    MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science 2012 PREPRINT 432 Mikuláš Teich The Scientific Revolution Revisited THE SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION REVISITED Mikuláš Teich To the memory of Alistair Crombie (1915‐1996) Rupert Hall (1920‐2009) Joseph Needham (1900‐1995) Roy Porter (1946‐2002) scholars most learned and friends most loyal CONTENTS Preface...............................................................................................................................................................1 Author's Preface............................................................................................................................................3 Note on terminology and acknoWledgements................................................................................3 Introduction....................................................................................................................................................4 1. From pre‐classical to classical pursuits.......................................................................................8 2. Experimentation and quantification..........................................................................................20 3. Institutionalization of science....................................................................................................... 37 4. Truth(s)....................................................................................................................................................49
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes' Natural Philosophy and Its Reception in the Latin West Http
    Averroes’ Natural Philosophy and its Reception in the Latin West Edited by Paul J.J.M. Bakker With contributions from: Jean-Baptiste Brenet (Universite de Paris I – Pantheon-Sorbonne), Cristina Cerami (cnrs, umr 7219:sphere/chspam), Silvia Donati (Albertus-Magnus-Institut, Bonn), Dag Nikolaus Hasse (Julius-Maximilians-Universitat Wurzburg), Craig Martin (Oakland University), Edith Dudley Sylla (North Carolina State University), Cecilia Trifogli (All Souls College, Oxford) © 2015 by Leuven University Press / Presses Universitaires de Louvain / Universitaire Pers Leuven, Minderbroedersstraat 4, B-3000 Leuven (Belgium) ISBN 978 94 6270 046 8 D / 2015 / 1869 / 48 Distributed by Leuven University Press http://upers.kuleuven.be/nl/book/9789462700468 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 Unported License: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/ 2015167 [Bakker] 001-Prelims-print [date 1510191536 : version 1509110900] page -3 AVERROES’ NATURAL PHILOSOPHY AND ITS RECEPTION IN THE LATIN WEST Edited by Paul J.J.M. Bakker LEUVEN UNIVERSITY PRESS Reprint from Averroes’ Natural Philosophy and its Reception in the Latin West - ISBN 978 94 6270 046 8 - © Leuven University Press, 2015 2015167 [Bakker] 001-Prelims-print [date 1510191536 : version 1509110900] page -4 © 2015 by De Wulf-Mansioncentrum – De Wulf-Mansion Centre Leuven University Press / Presses Universitaires de Louvain / Universitaire Pers Leuven Minderbroedersstraat 4, B-3000 Leuven (Belgium) All rights reserved. Except in those cases expressly determined by law, no part of this publication may be multiplied, saved in an automated datafile or made public in any way whatsoever without the express prior written consent of the publishers. ISBN 978 94 6270 046 8 D/2015/1869/48 NUR: 732 Reprint from Averroes’ Natural Philosophy and its Reception in the Latin West - ISBN 978 94 6270 046 8 - © Leuven University Press, 2015 2015167 [Bakker] 001-Prelims-print [date 1510191536 : version 1509110900] page -5 ..
    [Show full text]
  • Late-Medieval Natural Philosophy: Some Recent Trends in Scholarship*
    LATE-MEDIEVAL NATURAL PHILOSOPHY: SOME RECENT TRENDS IN SCHOLARSHIP* 1. General Orientation In this survey, I should like to present an overview of the scholarly literature that appeared during the last decade or so in the field of fourteenth-century natural philosophy1. This survey is partial in both senses of the term: it is fragmentary, and occasionally, it records my disagreements with some of the scholarly literature. Before narrowing down its scope it might be well to raise two methodological problems which one encounters when attempting to deal with the history of late-medieval natural philosophy of the sort with which this survey is * Research for this article was financially supported by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (200-22-295). I wish to thank Christoph Lüthy and Paul Bakker for their helpful suggestions. 1. To my knowledge, no other surveys of scholarship in the field of late-medieval nat- ural philosophy have recently appeared. A useful introduction to the scholarly literature up until approximately 1989 is given in the following essays: J. COLEMAN, «The Oxford Calculatores: Richard and Roger Swineshead», in: G. FLØISTAD (ed.), Contemporary Phi- losophy. A New Survey, Dordrecht-Boston-London 1990, Vol. 6/1, pp. 467-471; J. SARNOWSKY, «The Oxford Calculatores», in: G. FLØISTAD (ed.), Contemporary Philosophy. A New Survey, pp. 473-480; E. GRANT et J. E. MURDOCH, «The Parisian School of Sci- ence in the Fourteenth Century», in: G. FLØISTAD (ed.), Contemporary Philosophy. A New Survey, pp. 481-493; J. ZUPKO, «The Parisian School of Science in the Fourteenth Cen- tury», in: G.
    [Show full text]
  • The Calculators on the Insolubles: Bradwardine, Kilvington, Heytesbury, Swyneshed and Dumbleton
    The Calculators on the Insolubles: Bradwardine, Kilvington, Heytesbury, Swyneshed and Dumbleton Stephen Read July 31, 2019 Abstract The most exciting and innovative period in the discussion of the insolubles (i.e., logical paradoxes) before the twentieth century occurred in the second quar- ter of the fourteenth in Oxford, and at its heart were many of the Calculators. It was prompted by Thomas Bradwardine's iconoclastic ideas about the insolubles in the early 1320s. Framed largely within the context of the theory of (logical) obligations, it was continued by Richard Kilvington, Roger Swyneshed, William Heytesbury and John Dumbleton, each responding in different ways to Brad- wardine's analysis, particularly his idea that propositions had additional hidden and implicit meanings. Kilvington identified an equivocation in what was said; Swyneshed preferred to modify the account of truth rather than signification; Heytesbury exploited the respondent's role in obligational dialogues to avoid Bradwardine's tendentious closure postulate on signification; and Dumbleton re- lied on other constraints on signification to give new life to two long-standing accounts of insolubles that Bradwardine had summarily dismissed. The present paper focusses on the central thesis of each thinker's response to the insolubles and their interaction. Keywords: signification, liar paradox, insolubles, truth; Bradwardine, Dumbleton, Heytesbury, Kilvington, Paul of Venice, Swyneshed. 1 Introduction This paper considers the work on logic of five of the Oxford Calculators, in particular, their novel approaches to the insolubles, that is, the logical paradoxes. In the thirteenth century, right up until 1320, among the various solutions on the market, two dominated, those of the cassantes and the restringentes.1 Nonetheless, although these are often 1See e.g., Spade (1987, xxVI-VII).
    [Show full text]
  • Gregory of Rimini on the Intension and Remission of Corporeal Forms
    GREGORY OF RIMINI ON THE INTENSION AND REMISSION OF CORPOREAL FORMS Can L. LOEWE Abstract The goal of this paper is to provide an account of Gregory of Rimini’s (1300- 1358) theory of the intension and remission of corporeal forms. Under the influence of new Oxford ideas of the fourteenth century Gregory adopts a highly quantitative approach to intensive change. The paper discusses Gregory’s defense of the addition theory, especially in light of Walter Burley’s counter- arguments. It also considers Gregory’s account of the continuity of intensive change, as well as his views on the possibility of the co-presence of contrary qualities in the same subject. Introduction The goal of this paper is to provide an account of Gregory of Rimini’s (1300-1358)1 theory of the intension and remission of corporeal forms,2 as laid out in book 1, d. 17, qq. 2-4 of his Sentences commentary 1 On the author, see R.L. FRIEDMAN – C. SCHABEL, “Gregory of Rimini,” in: H. LAGER- LUND (ed.), Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy. Philosophy Between 500 and 1500, Vol. 1, Dordrecht 2011, pp. 439-444. All references are to the critical edition: GREGORY OF RIMINI, Lectura Super Primum et Secundum Sententiarum, 6. Vols. (= Spätmittelalter und Reformation. Texte und Untersuchungen, vols. 6-11), ed. A.D. TRAPP – V. MARCOLINO – W. ECKERMANN – M. SANTOS-NOYA – W. SIMON – W. SCHULZE – W. URBAN – V. WEND- LAND, Berlin 1979-84. I refer to Gregory’s Sentences commentary as Sent. All translations from the Latin are mine. (NB: I do not necessarily respect the punctuation and orthography of any text I use.) 2 By ‘corporeal forms’ Gregory means those forms that inhere in extended surfaces.
    [Show full text]
  • Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Medieval Representations
    MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science 2010 PREPRINT 402 TOPOI – Towards a Historical Epistemology of Space Matthias Schemmel Medieval Representations of Change and Their Early Modern Application TOPOI – TOWARDS A HISTORICAL EPISTEMOLOGY OF SPACE The TOPOI project cluster of excellence brings together researchers who investigate the formation and transformation of space and knowledge in ancient civilizations and their later developments. The present preprint series presents the work of members and fellows of the research group Historical Epistemology of Space which is part of the TOPOI cluster. The group is based on a cooperation between the Humboldt University and the Max Planck Institute for the History of Science in Berlin and commenced work in September 2008. Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Medieval Representations of Change and Their Early Modern Application Matthias Schemmel Contents 1 Symbolic means and derivations of the law of fall 3 2 Symbolic means as shared knowledge 6 3 Old means for new purposes 13 4 Diagrams as catalysts for conceptual development 19 5 The epistemic role of symbolic means 25 References 26 1 Symbolic means of knowledge representation and early modern deriva- tions of the law of fall This paper discusses the epistemic role of symbolic means of knowledge representation by way of a concrete historical example: the early modern use of medieval representa- tions of change to describe functional relations between quantities, in particular relating to the motion of fall. The means for the external, or material, representation of knowledge in general play a double, on the face of it paradoxical role in the history of knowledge.
    [Show full text]