THE CARTESIAN EXPERIMENT Renaissance, Rather Than from the Middle Ages, to the Modern World
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
The Human Striving and the Categories of Science
THE HUMAN STRIVLXG AND THE CATEGORIES OF SCIENCE' BY BENJAMIN GINZBURG CERTAIN school of philosophers have tried to persuade us A that the human striving, or the moral consciousness, and the principles of scientific reason have no relationship in common. It is but necessary to cast a glance at the history of pragmatism to appreciate the inadequacy of such an assertion. In the original arti- cle of C. S. Peirce on "How to Make Our Ideas Clear," - the argu- ment concerned the principles of scientific method. After review- ing the notions of Bacon and Descartes, as well as the attempts of lesser philosophers to legislate for science, the American mathemati- cian came to the conclusion that it was necessary to bring reason into the laboratory—much as Kepler had done when he painstak- ingly plotted every possible curve that could explain the movement of Mars. From a discussion of the logic of science, pragmatism w^as transformed into a philosophy of voluntaristic fideism. And even if Mr. Dewey has attempted to swing the movement away from some of the temperamental excesses of James, the fact remains that in the pragmatic philosophy logic and moral striving are still very closely united. To be sure, the realistic critics have used pragmatism as the hoi rible example of what happens when reasons of the heart are allowed to interfere with reasons of the intellect. And it certainly is true that pragmatism in many instances has weakened the authority of the intellect, and has opened the door to all manner of affective vagaries. The same charge is applicable to the Bergsonian phil- osophy of the intuition, which beginning as a critique of scientific orthodoxy has ended up as an apology for modernistic Catholicism. -
Galileo's Assayer
University of Nevada, Reno Galileo's Assayer: Sense and Reason in the Epistemic Balance A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in History. by James A Smith Dr. Bruce Moran/Thesis Advisor May 2018 c by James A Smith 2018 All Rights Reserved THE GRADUATE SCHOOL We recommend that the thesis prepared under our supervision by JAMES A. SMITH entitled Galileo's Assayer: Sense and Reason in the Epistemic Balance be accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Bruce Moran, Ph.D., Advisor Edward Schoolman, Ph.D., Committee Member Carlos Mariscal, Ph.D., Committee Member Stanislav Jabuka, Ph.D., Graduate School Representative David W. Zeh, Ph.D., Dean, Graduate School May, 2018 i Abstract Galileo's The Assayer, published in 1623, represents a turning point in Galileo's philo- sophical work. A highly polemical \scientific manifesto," The Assayer was written after his astronomical discoveries of the moons of Jupiter and sunspots on a rotating sun, but before his mature Copernican work on the chief world systems (Ptolemaic versus Copernican). The Assayer included major claims regarding the place of math- ematics in natural philosophy and how the objects of the world and their properties can be known. It's in The Assayer that Galileo wades into the discussion about the ultimate constituents of matter and light, namely, unobservable particles and atoms. Galileo stressed the equal roles that the senses and reason served in the discovery of knowledge, in contradistinction to Aristotelian authoritarian dogma that he found to hinder the processes of discovery and knowledge acquisition. -
Computer Simulations and the Trading Zone
PETER &A Computer Simulations and the Trading Zone At the root of most accounts of the development of science is the covert premise that science is about ontology: What objects are there? How do they interact? And how do we discover them? It is a premise that underlies three distinct epochs of inquiry into the nature of science. Among the positivists, the later Carnap explicitly advocated a view that the objects of physics would be irretrievably bound up with what he called a "framework," a full set of linguistic relations such as is found in Newtonian or Eiustcini;~mechanics. That these frameworks held little in common did not trouble Car- nap; prediction mattered more than progress. Kuhn molded this notion and gave it a more historical focus. Unlike the positivists, Kuhn and other commentators of the 1960's wanted to track the process by which a community abandoned one framework and adopted another. To more recent scholars, the Kuhnian categoriza- tion of group affiliation and disaffiliation was by and large correct, but its underlying dynamics were deemed deficient because they paid insufficient attention to the sociological forces that bound groups to their paradigms. All three generations embody the root assumption that the analysis of science studies (or ought to study) a science classified and divided according to the objects of its inquiry. All three assume that as these objects change, particular branches of science split into myriad disconnected parts. It is a view of scientific disunity that I will refer to as "framework relativism. 55 In this essay, as before, I will oppose this view, but not by Computer Simulations I 19 invoking the old positivist pipe dreams: no universal protocol languages, no physicalism, no Corntian hierarchy of knowledge, and no radical reductionism. -
(Claude-François, Abbé), Histoire Littéraire Du Règne De Louis XIV, Paris, Chez Prault Fils-Guillyn- Quillau Fils, 1751, 3 Vol
LAMBERT (Claude-François, abbé), Histoire littéraire du règne de Louis XIV, Paris, chez Prault fils-Guillyn- Quillau fils, 1751, 3 vol. TOME I Dédicace. Plan de l’ouvrage. Approbation et privilège. DISCOURS SUR LES PROGRÈS DES SCIENCES SACRÉES SOUS LE RÈGNE DE LOUIS XIV. Écriture Sainte. Théologie scholastique. Conciles. Théologie Morale. SS. Pères, Antiquités Ecclésiastiques. Droit Canon. Théologie polémique. Théologie Mystique. ÉLOGES HISTORIQUES : DES THÉOLOGIENS SCHOLASTIQUES, MORAUX, MYSTIQUES, DES CONTROVERSISTES, & DES CANONISTES – LIVRE PREMIER. Jacques Sirmond. Godefroi Hermant. Jean-Pierre Camus. Antoine Arnauld. Denis Petau. Pierre Nicole. Jacques Goar. Louis Thomassin. Jean Morin. Louis Ferrand. Jean Fronteau. Jean Gerbais. Pierre de Marca. Antoine Pagy. Blaise Pascal. Jean Le Bouthilier de Rancé, abbé de la Trappe. Théophile Rainaud. Jacques-Bénigne Bossuet. Amable de Bourzeis. Paul Pezron. Pierre L’Allemant. Jean Gisbert. Jean Nicolaï. Claude Frassen. Emmanuel Maignan. Richard Simon. Jean de Launoy. François de Salignac de La Mothe-Fénelon. François de Combesis. Bernard Lamy. Jean Garnier. Charles Witasse. Luc d’Acheri. Étienne Baluze. © Centre de recherche du château de Versailles / 2012 Louis Ellies Dupin. Jean Hardouin. Michel Le Tellier. Catalogue de ses ouvrages. Michel Le Quien. Eusèbe Renaudot. René-Joseph de Tournemine. Pierre-Daniel Huet. Edmond Martenne. Noël Alexandre. Charles Duplessis d’Argentré. Pierre Le Brun. Bernard de Mont-Faucon. Simon Gourdan. DISCOURS SUR LES PROGRÈS DE L’ÉLOQUENCE DE LA CHAIRE SOUS LE RÈGNE DE LOUIS XIV. ÉLOGES HISTORIQUES : DES ORATEURS SACRÉS – LIVRE SECOND Hardouin de Péréfixe. Jean de La Roche. Jean-François Senault. Fabio Brulart de Sillery. Claude de La Colombière. Mathieu Hubert. Jean-Louis de Fromentières. Charles de La Rue. -
Descartes, Mathematics and Music
Descartes, Mathematics and Music Donald DeMarco Descartes's influence in shaping the intellectual climate of the modern world is without parallel. More than any other figure of the seventeenth century, he marks the intellectual transition from the Middle Ages to the modern world. It is generally conceded that he is the "father of modern philosophy" as well as the "father of modern mathematics." In addition, his literary influence is inestimable. He is said to have been the first to have offered a perfect model of French prose. Karl Stern refers to him as the Saint Augustine of the Age of Reason. And Alfred North Whitehead regards his marriage of algebra and geometry as one of the truly stirring moments in the history of human discovery: It is impossible not to feel stirred at the thought of the emotions of men at certain historic moments of adventure and discovery Columbus when he first saw the Western shore, Pizarro when he stared at the Pacific Ocean, Franklin when the electric spark came from the string to his kite, Galileo when he first turned his telescope to the heavens. Such moments are also granted to students in the abstract regions of thought, and high among them must be placed the morning when Descartes lay in bed and invented the method of co-ordinate geometry. 1 Pythagoras and Plato saw mathematics as a key to understanding the physical world. Aristotle, whose intellectual inclinations were far more naturalistic, did not share his predecessors enthusiasm for numbers. And since the mind of Aristotle dominated the intellectual temper of the Middle Ages, it was left to Descartes, together with a host of seventeenth century mathematical physicists, to revive mathematics as the key to understanding nature. -
Xviii Marie-Adélaïde De Savoie
ÉTUDES SUR LE 18 SIÈCLE XVIII MARIE-ADÉLAÏDE DE SAVOIE (1685-1712) DUCHESSE DE BOURGOGNE, ENFANT TERRIBLE DE VERSAILLES ÉDITIONS ÉDITIONS DE L’UNIVERSITÉ DE BRUXELLES / n r-t o rsi ÉTUDES SUR LE l 8* SIÈCLE XVIII Revue fondée par Roland Mortier et Hervé Hasquin DIRECTEURS Valérie André et Brigitte D’Haînaut-Zveny COMITÉ ÉDITORIAL Bruno Bernard, Claude Bruneel (Université catholique de Louvain), Carlo Capra (Università degli studi, Milg David Charlton (Royal Holloway College, Londres), Manuel Couvreur, Nicolas Cronk (Voltaire Foundation, University of Oxford), Michèle Galand, Jan Herman (Katholieke Unîversiteît Leuven), Michel Jangoux, Huguette Krief (Université de Provence, Aix-en-Provence), Christophe Loir, Roland Mortier, Fabrice Preyat, Daniel Rabreau (Université de Paris I, Panthéon-Sorbonne), Daniel Roche (Collège de France) et Renate Zedînger (Universität Wien) GROUPE D'ÉTUDE DU 1 8* SIÈCLE ÉCRIRE A Valérie André [email protected] Brigitte D’Hainaut-Zveny [email protected] ou à [’adresse suivante Groupe d’étude du XVIIIe siècle Université libre de Bruxelles (CP175/01) Avenue F.D. Roosevelt 50 • B -1050 Bruxelles MARIE-ADÉLAÏDE DE SAVOIE (1685-1712) DUCHESSE DE BOURGOGNE, ENFANT TERRIBLE DE VERSAILLES Publié avec l’aide financière du Fonds de la recherche scientifique - FNRS DANS LA MÊME COLLECTION Les préoccupations économiques et sociales des philosophes, littérateurs et artistes au XVIIIe siècle, 1976 Bruxelles au XVIIIe siècle, 1977 L’Europe et les révolutions (1770-1800), 1980 La noblesse belge au XVIIIe siècle, 1982 Idéologies de la noblesse, 1984 Une famille noble de hauts fonctionnaires : les Neny, 1985 Le livre à Liège et à Bruxelles au XVIIIe siècle, 1987 Unité et diversité de l’empire des Habsbourg à la fin du XVIIIe siècle, 1988 Deux aspects contestés de la politique révolutionnaire en Belgique : langue et culte, 1989 Fêtes et musiques révolutionnaires : Grétry et Gossec, 1990 Rocaille. -
Evaluating the Metaphysical Realism of Étienne Gilson
Studia Gilsoniana 4:4 (October–December 2015): 363–380 | ISSN 2300–0066 Brian Kemple Center for Thomistic Studies University of St. Thomas, Houston Texas, USA EVALUATING THE METAPHYSICAL REALISM OF ÉTIENNE GILSON It is true to say that there would likely be far fewer students of Thomas Aquinas in North America today if not for the work of Étienne Gilson; it is equally true to say that Gilson’s work has made significant contributions both to the overcoming of modern philosophy and to the understanding of Thomas himself, particularly as regards the Angelic Doc- tor’s metaphysics and philosophy of knowledge. The resurgence of genu- ine Thomism—as opposed to the Suarezian impostor which had come to dominate—which followed Leo XIII’s Aeterni Patris had much to over- come, not the least of which was the preponderance of modernity’s idealist epistemology. Descartes’ mathematicism, the insistence that all things lacking the certitude of mathematics cannot truly be called “knowledge,”1 begot Cartesian idealism, which in turn launched a centuries-long quest, carried out by numerous philosophers, for an answer to what might be best described as “the wrong question,” namely: “How is it that we can know things outside the mind?” This question, particularly in the most thorough treatment among moderns given it by Kant, coursed through philosophy so strongly that even many Thomists were swept along by its current. Enter Gilson. By participating in the recovery of the thought of the scholastics, especially Thomas Aquinas, Gilson was able to formulate a theory of knowledge which, though aimed at answering the question of the moderns, avoided their fundamental errors. -
Numb and Number
Numb and Number John Zerzan October 2013 The digital age is pre-eminently the ultimate reign of Number. The time of Big Data,computers (e.g. China’s, world’s fastest) that can process 30 quadrillion transactions per second, algorithms that increasingly predict—and control—what happens in society. Standardized testing is another example of the reductive disease of quantification. Number surpasses all other ideas for its combination of impact and implication. Counting means imposing a definition and a control, assigning a number value. It is the foundation fora world in which whatever can be domesticated and controlled can also be commodified. Number is the key to mastery: everything must be measured, quantified. It is not what we can do with number, but what it does to us. Like technology, its intimate ally, number is anything but neutral. It tries to make us forget that there is so much that shouldn’t or can’t be measured. Fifth Estate published my “Number: Its Origin and Evolution” in Summer 1985, justasthe digital age was gaining traction following the personal computer explosion at the beginning of the 80s.i The quickening (anti-) pulse of technological change over the past 30 years has beenat base a mathematization. Social life in the post-community era is detached, disembodied, drained, statistical. Its core is administration, just as the essence of number is calculation. “Mathematical thinking is coercive,” disclosed British philosopher J.R. Lucas.ii Number totalizes; in mathematics, ambiguity is anathema. The technoculture obeys these norms, and we dance to its tune, its code: number. -
Aspects of Early Modern British Philosophy
UK-Japan Special Conference Aspects of Early Modern British Philosophy Organized by the University of Oxford and Japanese Society for British Philosophy, under the auspices of Musashino University Date: 11th and 12th September 2019. Venue: St Peter’s College of the University of Oxford Programme 11 September 9:00-10:15am Hiroyuki Yorozuya (Assistant Professor, Hiroshima Institute of Technology) “Hume, Causation and Agentive Experience” 10:15-11:30 am Jonathan Cottrell (Lecturer, University of Edinburgh) “Interpreting Hume on Mental Representation” 11:30 am Coffee 11:45am-1:00pm Shigeyuki Aoki (Associate Professor, Chuo University) “Locke versus Berkeley revisited – an interpretive essay on historiography” 1:00 pm Lunch 2:15-3:30pm Ruth Boeker (Assistant Professor, University College Dublin) “Shaftesbury on Liberty and Self-Mastery” 3:30 pm Tea 3:45-5:00 pm Masaki Ichinose (Professor of Musashino University, Emeritus Professor of UTokyo) “Locke on language and its privateness” 12 September 9:00-10:15am Clare Moriarty (Visiting Research Associate, King's College London) “Berkeley and Anti-Mathematicism” 10:15-11:30 am Tomokiyo Nomura (Regular Lecturer, Shumei University) “Let others think for you: Berkeley and Assent” 11:30 am Coffee 11:45am-1:00pm James Harris (Professor, University of St Andrews) “Between Locke and Filmer: Hume on allegiance” 1:00 pm Lunch 2:15-3:30pm Taro Okuda (Professor, Nanzan University) “Hume's Moral Sentiments and Moral Particularism” 3:30 pm Tea 3:45-5:00 pm Peter Kail (Associate Professor, University of Oxford) “Berkeley and the Material Attitude” Contact Organiser in Japan: Masaki Ichinose, Musashino University, Tokyo, JAPAN Email: [email protected] Abstracts ●“Hume, Causation and Agentive Experience” Hiroyuki Yorozuya (Assistant Professor, Hiroshima Institute of Technology) In the contemporary philosophy of action, David Hume has widely been assumed to defend the causal theory of action. -
Monseigneur, Louis De France, Dit Le Grand Dauphin, Fils De Louis XIV
Université de Strasbourg UFR de sciences historiques Thèse de doctorat en Histoire et Civilisation de l'Europe Jean-Pierre MAGET Monseigneur, Louis de France, dit Le Grand Dauphin, fils de Louis XIV volume I : Thèse sous la direction de Monsieur Le Professeur Dominique DINET Septembre 2010 Université de Strasbourg UFR de sciences historiques Thèse de doctorat en Histoire et Civilisation de l'Europe Jean-Pierre MAGET Monseigneur, Louis de France, dit Le Grand Dauphin, fils de Louis XIV Sous la direction de Monsieur le Professeur Dominique DINET Composition du jury : Monsieur Dominique DINET, professeur émérite à l'Université de Strasbourg. Monsieur Hervé DRÉVILLON, professeur à l'Université de Paris I - Panthéon-Sorbonne Monsieur Martial GUÉDRON, professeur à l'Université de Strasbourg. Monsieur Jean-François SOLNON, professeur à l'Université de Franche-Comté. volume I : THÉSE soutenue à Strasbourg le 14 septembre 2010 Je remercie vivement et respectueusement Monsieur Le Professeur Dominique DINET, lui sans lequel cette thèse ne serait que ce qu'elle était. - Table des matières - TABLE des MATIÈRES Abréviations : ........................................................................ pp. 7 - 8 Introduction : ................................................................ pp. 9 - 21 Première partie : FILS de ROI : .................................................. pp. 23 - 197 Chapitre I : Le Dauphin, un titre de la monarchie française : .................... pp. 26 - 119 A) L'institution du delphinat : .................................................................... -
Logicism, Interpretability, and Knowledge of Arithmetic
ZU064-05-FPR RSL-logicism-final 1 December 2013 21:42 The Review of Symbolic Logic Volume 0, Number 0, Month 2013 Logicism, Interpretability, and Knowledge of Arithmetic Sean Walsh Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science, University of California, Irvine Abstract. A crucial part of the contemporary interest in logicism in the philosophy of mathematics resides in its idea that arithmetical knowledge may be based on logical knowledge. Here an implementation of this idea is considered that holds that knowledge of arithmetical principles may be based on two things: (i) knowledge of logical principles and (ii) knowledge that the arithmetical principles are representable in the logical principles. The notions of representation considered here are related to theory-based and structure- based notions of representation from contemporary mathematical logic. It is argued that the theory-based versions of such logicism are either too liberal (the plethora problem) or are committed to intuitively incorrect closure conditions (the consistency problem). Structure-based versions must on the other hand respond to a charge of begging the question (the circularity problem) or explain how one may have a knowledge of structure in advance of a knowledge of axioms (the signature problem). This discussion is significant because it gives us a better idea of what a notion of representation must look like if it is to aid in realizing some of the traditional epistemic aims of logicism in the philosophy of mathematics. Received February 2013 Acknowledgements: This is material coming out of my dissertation, and I would thus like to thank my advisors, Dr. Michael Detlefsen and Dr. -
Recent Thomistic Interpretations of Ens Primum Cognitum
chapter 2 Recent Thomistic Interpretations of Ens Primum Cognitum When we turn our attention to the Thomistic authors of later centuries, we find much different concerns; for our two representatives, Gilson and Marit- ain, ens primum cognitum, though addressed, was not an explicit topic of con- cern. The ability of the human intellect to truly grasp things as existing outside of the mind takes precedence in their work, confronted as they were with the yet-unresolved problem of modernity’s epistemological quagmire. While they succeeded in overcoming this problem, their ardor for realism may be taken too far in some cases, to the exclusion of a complete perspective on ens pri- mum cognitum. Let us, therefore, address their considerations of being and the human intellect. 2.1 Étienne Gilson’s “Metaphysical Realism” It is true to say that there would likely be far fewer students of Thomas Aqui- nas in North America today if not for the work of Étienne Gilson. It is equally true to say that Gilson’s work has made significant contributions both to the overcoming of modern philosophy and to the understanding of Thomas him- self, particularly as regards the Angelic Doctor’s metaphysics and philosophy of knowledge. The resurgence of genuine Thomism—as opposed to the Su- arezian impostor which had come to dominate—following Leo xiii’s Aeterni Patris had much to overcome, not the least of which was the preponderance of modernity’s idealist epistemology. Descartes’ mathematicism, the insistence that all things lacking the certitude of mathematics cannot truly be called “knowledge”,1 begat Cartesian idealism, which in turn launched a centuries- long quest, carried out by numerous philosophers, for an answer to what is perhaps best called “the wrong question”: namely, “how is it that we can know things outside the mind?” This question, particularly in the most thorough treatment among moderns given by Kant, coursed through philosophy so strongly that many Thomists were swept along by its current.