Descartes and the Scientific Revolution: Some Kuhnian Reflections

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Descartes and the Scientific Revolution: Some Kuhnian Reflections Descartes and the Scientific Revolution: Some Kuhnian Reflections Daniel Garber Princeton University Important to Kuhn’s account of scientiªc change is the observation that when paradigms are in competition with one another, there is a curious breakdown of rational argument and communication between adherents of competing pro- grams. He attributed this to the fact that competing paradigms are incom- mensurable. The incommensurability thesis centrally involves the claim that there is a deep conceptual gap between competing paradigms in science. In this paper I argue that in one important case of competing paradigms, the Aristo- telian explanation of the properties of bodies in terms of matter and form as opposed to the Cartesian mechanist paradigm, where the properties of bodies are explained on the model of machines, there was no such conceptual gap: the notion of a machine was as fully intelligible on the Aristotelian paradigm as it was on the Cartesian. But this does not mean that the debate between the two sides was conducted on purely rational terms. Rational argument breaks down not because of Kuhnian incommensurability, I argue, but because of other cultural factors separating the two camps. Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of Scientiªc Revolutions (Kuhn 1970) was, from the beginning, closely connected with a particular scientiªc revolution, the Scientiªc Revolution of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Kuhn’s seminal book followed closely on the heels of his Copernican Revolution (Kuhn 1957), and the astronomical revolution of the period served as one of the central examples of what Kuhn meant by a scientiªc revolution. In this paper, I would like to return to the period and reassess the extent to which the Scientiªc Revolution really ªts Kuhn’s paradigm, as it were. However, I don’t want to deal with the astronomical issues that are at the Earlier versions of this paper were given at Virginia Tech, University of Wyoming, and the University of California, Berkeley. I would like to thank audiences there for their helpful comments on earlier drafts. Perspectives on Science 2001, vol. 9, no. 4 ©2002 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology 405 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/106361401760375802 by guest on 25 September 2021 406 Descartes and the Scientific Revolution center of Kuhn’s account. Rather, I would like to turn to a somewhat dif- ferent issue, the transition from the Aristotelian natural philosophy of substantial form and prime matter and to the mechanical philosophy of Descartes and his contemporaries—another central aspect of the Scientiªc Revolution. On Kuhn’s account, of course, a scientiªc revolution occurs when one paradigm is replaced by another. Kuhn noticed, though, that when para- digms are in competition with one another for the hearts and minds of the scientiªc community, there is a curious breakdown of rational argument and communication between adherents of competing programs. Kuhn writes: As in political revolutions, so in paradigm choice—there is no stan- dard higher than the assent of the relevant community. To discover how scientiªc revolutions are effected, we shall therefore have to ex- amine not only the impact of nature and of logic, but also the tech- niques of persuasive argumentation...(Kuhn 1970, p. 94). Similarly: Like the choice between competing political institutions, that be- tween competing paradigms proves to be a choice between incom- patible modes of community life (Kuhn 1970, p. 94). Similarly, Kuhn talks about the change from one paradigm to another in terms of religious conversion or the aspect shift we experience when seeing the duck or the rabbit in the familiar ªgure. One paradigm is replaced by another . not by deliberation and interpretation, but by a relatively sudden and unstructured event like the gestalt switch. Scientists then often speak of the “scales falling from the eyes” or of the “lightning ºash” that “inundates” a previously obscure puzzle, en- abling its components to be seen in a new way that for the ªrst time permits its solution (Kuhn 1970, p. 122). As Kuhn puts it in a memorable phrase, “the proponents of competing paradigms practice their trades in different worlds” (Kuhn 1970, p. 150). Central to Kuhn’s program is a particular explanation of this phenome- non often observed in scientiªc change: the incommensurability thesis. According to the incommensurability thesis, there is a genuine disconnect between one paradigm and another. As he characterizes the situation in Structure, a paradigm embodies a number of different elements of scientiªc practice. He writes: Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/106361401760375802 by guest on 25 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 407 Paradigms provide scientists not only with a map but also with some of the directions essential for map-making. In learning a para- digm the scientist acquires theory, methods, and standards to- gether, usually in an inextricable mixture (Kuhn 1970, p. 109; cf. pp. 109–10). Changes in any of these components of a paradigm (theory, methods, stan- dards) would appear to render competing scientiªc programs unintelligi- ble to one another. For example, according to the mechanist program, ev- erything has to be explained in terms of size, shape, and motion. Consequently, the scientist must explain why it is that planets stay in their trajectories or apples fall in terms of the collision between the small bodies that make up the grosser bodies of everyday experience. However, on the Newtonian paradigm, such explanations are not necessary: one can explain such phenomena in terms of an attractive force between every two bodies in the universe. Because of different standards for what counts as a solved scientiªc problem, the two paradigms, the mechanist and the New- tonian, are incommensurable (Kuhn 1970, pp. 104–6). But there is an- other example that points out a feature of competing paradigms that seems more central to Kuhn’s conception of incommensurability. Kuhn points out that Newtonian mechanics and Einsteinian mechanics don’t even share a common vocabulary: the notions of mass, velocity and posi- tion that are at the core of Newton’s world are very different from the cor- responding concepts in Einstein’s theories. For that reason it is wrong to say that Newton’s mechanics can be derived from Einstein’s, or that New- tonian mechanics is a special case of Einstein’s (Kuhn 1970, pp. 101–2). In this way, scientiªc revolutions most often involve “a displacement of the conceptual network through which scientists view the world” (Kuhn 1970, p. 102). In a sense, the adherent of one paradigm literally cannot understand what his opponent is saying: they speak a different language with a different conceptual vocabulary. In his later writings Kuhn focuses more and more on the conceptual incompatibilities between the theories embedded in competing paradigms. There Kuhn often characterizes incommensurability in terms of differences in the extension of basic predi- cates in the two paradigms.1 While an adherent of one paradigm can learn 1. Rethinking and reformulating the notion of incommensurability is at the center of many of Kuhn’s later papers. See, for example, the essays in part I of Kuhn 2000. In gen- eral, Kuhn came to focus more and more on the relation between theories formulated in competing paradigms, their respective vocabularies and the difªculties in translating be- tween them. See, e.g., the essay, “The Road Since Structure,” in Kuhn 2000, pp. 91–94, where Kuhn characterizes incommensurability in terms of the incomparability of what he calls the lexicons of competing theories. Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/106361401760375802 by guest on 25 September 2021 408 Descartes and the Scientific Revolution to think in another and become “bilingual,” as it were, there is no direct translation from the one to another, so to speak. As I shall understand it, the incommensurability thesis centrally involves the claim that there is a deep conceptual gap between competing paradigms in science, and that as a consequence, one has to go to non-rational means of persuasion in order to convince an adherent of one paradigm to adopt another. As attractive as it is as a picture of scientiªc change, Kuhn’s incom- mensurability thesis is, in an important sense, false. I want to argue that in at least one very interesting (and historically very important) case, there is no conceptual gap between competing paradigms at all. None. For an Aristotelian physicist, natural philosophy is ultimately grounded in the irreducible tendencies bodies have to behave one way or another, as embodied in their substantial forms. Some bodies naturally fall, and others naturally rise; some are naturally cold, and others are natu- rally hot; some are naturally dry, and others are naturally wet. For Des- cartes’ mechanical philosophy, though, everything in nature is to be ex- plained in terms of the size, shape, and motion of the small parts that make up a sensible body. In essence, for the mechanical philosophy, the whole world can be treated as if it were a collection of machines. There could scarcely be a more paradigmatic instance of a Kuhnian scientiªc rev- olution than this, the transition between one scientiªc paradigm and an- other. But, I claim, the case at hand works very differently than Kuhn would have it. I shall try to show that though there were some very signi- ªcant differences between the Aristotelian and the Cartesian, there was one crucial continuity. In particular, I would like to show how the idea of the machine and the science of mechanics provided a link between the two worlds, one that was fully intelligible to both parties in the dispute. Now, in most of the literature in the philosophy of science, the purpose of undermining Kuhn’s incommensurability thesis is to restore order and rationality to scientiªc debate.
Recommended publications
  • The Philosophical Underpinnings of Educational Research
    The Philosophical Underpinnings of Educational Research Lindsay Mack Abstract This article traces the underlying theoretical framework of educational research. It outlines the definitions of epistemology, ontology and paradigm and the origins, main tenets, and key thinkers of the 3 paradigms; positivist, interpetivist and critical. By closely analyzing each paradigm, the literature review focuses on the ontological and epistemological assumptions of each paradigm. Finally the author analyzes not only the paradigm’s weakness but also the author’s own construct of reality and knowledge which align with the critical paradigm. Key terms: Paradigm, Ontology, Epistemology, Positivism, Interpretivism The English Language Teaching (ELT) field has moved from an ad hoc field with amateurish research to a much more serious enterprise of professionalism. More teachers are conducting research to not only inform their teaching in the classroom but also to bridge the gap between the external researcher dictating policy and the teacher negotiating that policy with the practical demands of their classroom. I was a layperson, not an educational researcher. Determined to emancipate myself from my layperson identity, I began to analyze the different philosophical underpinnings of each paradigm, reading about the great thinkers’ theories and the evolution of social science research. Through this process I began to examine how I view the world, thus realizing my own construction of knowledge and social reality, which is actually quite loose and chaotic. Most importantly, I realized that I identify most with the critical paradigm assumptions and that my future desired role as an educational researcher is to affect change and challenge dominant social and political discourses in ELT.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical and Historical Analysis of Cosmology from Copernicus to Newton
    University of Central Florida STARS Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 2017 Scientific transformations: a philosophical and historical analysis of cosmology from Copernicus to Newton Manuel-Albert Castillo University of Central Florida Part of the History of Science, Technology, and Medicine Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Masters Thesis (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STARS Citation Castillo, Manuel-Albert, "Scientific transformations: a philosophical and historical analysis of cosmology from Copernicus to Newton" (2017). Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019. 5694. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd/5694 SCIENTIFIC TRANSFORMATIONS: A PHILOSOPHICAL AND HISTORICAL ANALYSIS OF COSMOLOGY FROM COPERNICUS TO NEWTON by MANUEL-ALBERT F. CASTILLO A.A., Valencia College, 2013 B.A., University of Central Florida, 2015 A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the department of Interdisciplinary Studies in the College of Graduate Studies at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Fall Term 2017 Major Professor: Donald E. Jones ©2017 Manuel-Albert F. Castillo ii ABSTRACT The purpose of this thesis is to show a transformation around the scientific revolution from the sixteenth to seventeenth centuries against a Whig approach in which it still lingers in the history of science. I find the transformations of modern science through the cosmological models of Nicholas Copernicus, Johannes Kepler, Galileo Galilei and Isaac Newton.
    [Show full text]
  • Architectural Theory and Practice, and the Question of Phenomenology
    Architectural Theory and Practice, and the Question of Phenomenology (The Contribution of Tadao Ando to the Phenomenological Discourse) Von der Fakultät Architektur, Bauingenieurwesen und Stadtplanung der Brandenburgischen Technischen Universität Cottbus zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Doktor-Ingenieurs genehmigte Dissertation vorgelegt von Mohammadreza Shirazi aus Tabriz, Iran Gutachter: : Prof. Dr. Eduard Führ Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Karsten Harries Gutachter: Gastprofessor. Dr. Riklef Rambow Tag der Verteidigung: 02. Juni 2009 Acknowledgment My first words of gratitude go to my supervisor Prof. Führ for giving me direction and support. He fully supported me during my research, and created a welcoming and inspiring atmosphere in which I had the pleasure of writing this dissertation. I am indepted to his teachings and instructions in more ways than I can state here. I am particularly grateful to Prof. Karsten Harries. His texts taught me how to think on architecture deeply, how to challenge whatever is ‘taken for granted’ and ‘remain on the way, in search of home’. I am also grateful to other colleagues in L.S. Theorie der Architektur. I want to express my thanks to Dr. Riklef Rambow who considered my ideas and texts deeply and helped me with his advice at different stages. I am thankful for the comments and kind helps I received from Dr. Katharina Fleischmann. I also want to thank Prof. Hahn from TU Dresden and other PhD students who attended in Doktorandentag meetings and criticized my presentations. I would like to express my appreciation to the staff of Langen Foundation Museum for their kind helps during my visit of that complex, and to Mr.
    [Show full text]
  • The Function of Reason in Hume and Consequences for the Classical
    Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2004 If Reason Is Not Sovereign: The Function of Reason in Hume and Consequences for the Classical/Positivist Divide, Rational Choice Theory, Low Self-Control Theory, and the Criminal Propensity Construct Michael Jason Kissner Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] THE FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF CRIMINOLOGY AND CRIMINAL JUSTICE IF REASON IS NOT SOVEREIGN: THE FUNCTION OF REASON IN HUME AND CONSEQUENCES FOR THE CLASSICAL/POSITIVIST DIVIDE, RATIONAL CHOICE THEORY, LOW SELF-CONTROL THEORY, AND THE CRIMINAL PROPENSITY CONSTRUCT By MICHAEL JASON KISSNER A Dissertation submitted to the School of Criminology and Criminal Justice in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Degree Awarded: Fall Semester, 2004 The members of the Committee approve the Dissertation of Michael Jason Kissner defended on November 10, 2004. _______________________ Daniel Maier-Katkin Professor Directing Dissertation _______________________ Barney Twiss Outside Committee Member _______________________ Cecil Greek Committee Member Approved: __________________________ Thomas Blomberg, Dean, School of Criminology and Criminal Justice The Office of Graduate Studies has verified and approved the above named committee members. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT ..................................................................................................Page
    [Show full text]
  • Newton.Indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag
    omslag Newton.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag. 1 e Dutch Republic proved ‘A new light on several to be extremely receptive to major gures involved in the groundbreaking ideas of Newton Isaac Newton (–). the reception of Newton’s Dutch scholars such as Willem work.’ and the Netherlands Jacob ’s Gravesande and Petrus Prof. Bert Theunissen, Newton the Netherlands and van Musschenbroek played a Utrecht University crucial role in the adaption and How Isaac Newton was Fashioned dissemination of Newton’s work, ‘is book provides an in the Dutch Republic not only in the Netherlands important contribution to but also in the rest of Europe. EDITED BY ERIC JORINK In the course of the eighteenth the study of the European AND AD MAAS century, Newton’s ideas (in Enlightenment with new dierent guises and interpre- insights in the circulation tations) became a veritable hype in Dutch society. In Newton of knowledge.’ and the Netherlands Newton’s Prof. Frans van Lunteren, sudden success is analyzed in Leiden University great depth and put into a new perspective. Ad Maas is curator at the Museum Boerhaave, Leiden, the Netherlands. Eric Jorink is researcher at the Huygens Institute for Netherlands History (Royal Dutch Academy of Arts and Sciences). / www.lup.nl LUP Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 1 Newton and the Netherlands Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 2 Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii Abstract
    Leibniz’s Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii Abstract This is a short summary of my new interpretation of Leibniz’s philosophy, including metaphysics and dynamics. Monadology is the core of his philosophy, but according to my interpretation, this document must be read together with his works on dynamics and geometry Analysis Situs, among others. Monadology describes the reality, the world of monads. But in addition, it also contains a theory of information in terms of the state transition of monads, together with a sketch of how that information is transformed into the phenomena via coding. I will argue that Leibniz’s program has a surprisingly wide range, from classical physics to the theories of relativity (special and general) , and extending even to quantum mechanics. 1. How should we read Monadology? Among Leibniz’s papers he completed in his last years, the one that should be regarded as containing the core of his system of knowledge is Monadology (1714). It is a theory of metaphysics, but I take it that Leibniz thought that it is the foundation of dynamics, and he envisaged that dynamics should be combined with his new geometry, called Analysis Situs. There are two firm grounds for the preceding assertion. The first is that Leibniz sketched the relationship between his metaphysics and dynamics, in the two papers New System and Specimen Dynamicum (both published in 1695; English tr. in Ariew and Garber 1989). If we wish to figure out a reasonable interpretation of Monadology, this ground must be taken very seriously. The second ground is the amazing accomplishments shown in The Metaphysical Foundations of Mathematics (written around the same time as Monadology; English tr.
    [Show full text]
  • The Copernican Revolution, the Scientific Revolution, and The
    The Copernican Revolution, the Scientific Revolution, and the Mechanical Philosophy Conor Mayo-Wilson University of Washington Phil. 401 January 19th, 2017 2 Prediction and Explanation, in particular, the role of mathematics, causation, primary and secondary qualities, microsctructure in prediction and explanation, and 3 Empirical Theories, in particular, the place of the earth in the solar system, the composition of matter, and the causes of terrestial and celestial motion. We're on our way to meeting goal three, but we've got two more to go ::: Course Goals By the end of the quarter, students should be able to explain in what ways the mechanical philosophers agreed and disagreed with Aristotle and scholastics about 1 Epistemology, in particular, the role of testimony, authority, experiment, and logic as sources of knowledge, 3 Empirical Theories, in particular, the place of the earth in the solar system, the composition of matter, and the causes of terrestial and celestial motion. We're on our way to meeting goal three, but we've got two more to go ::: Course Goals By the end of the quarter, students should be able to explain in what ways the mechanical philosophers agreed and disagreed with Aristotle and scholastics about 1 Epistemology, in particular, the role of testimony, authority, experiment, and logic as sources of knowledge, 2 Prediction and Explanation, in particular, the role of mathematics, causation, primary and secondary qualities, microsctructure in prediction and explanation, and Course Goals By the end of the quarter,
    [Show full text]
  • Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research Communication Studies, Department of Spring 4-12-2011 Secular Salvation: Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement Brent Yergensen University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/commstuddiss Part of the Speech and Rhetorical Studies Commons Yergensen, Brent, "Secular Salvation: Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement" (2011). Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research. 6. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/commstuddiss/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Communication Studies, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. SECULAR SALVATION: SACRED RHETORICAL INVENTION IN THE STRING THEORY MOVEMENT by Brent Yergensen A DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of The Graduate College at the University of Nebraska In Partial Fulfillment of Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Major: Communication Studies Under the Supervision of Dr. Ronald Lee Lincoln, Nebraska April, 2011 ii SECULAR SALVATION: SACRED RHETORICAL INVENTION IN THE STRING THEORY MOVEMENT Brent Yergensen, Ph.D. University of Nebraska, 2011 Advisor: Ronald Lee String theory is argued by its proponents to be the Theory of Everything. It achieves this status in physics because it provides unification for contradictory laws of physics, namely quantum mechanics and general relativity. While based on advanced theoretical mathematics, its public discourse is growing in prevalence and its rhetorical power is leading to a scientific revolution, even among the public.
    [Show full text]
  • Imagination: a Philosophical Examination of The
    1 The ‘Reality Oriented’ Imagination: a Philosophical Examination of the Imagination in ‘Mentalization’ and ‘Neuropsychoanalysis’. Annie Hardy Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University College London 2017 2 I, Annie Hardy, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. 3 Abstract This thesis is concerned with the conceptualization of the imagination in contemporary psychoanalytic theory, focusing in particular on its connection with knowledge. I will propose that imaginative processes form the core of psychic ‘health’ by instantiating a state of mind in which the subject is genuinely open to ‘learning from experience’. At the centre of the investigation is a psychic process that I term the ‘reality oriented’ imagination: a form of conscious mental activity that facilitates an epistemological connection with both the internal and external worlds and renders the unobservable psychological experiences of others accessible. The concept of the ’reality oriented’ imagination significantly disrupts Freud’s portrayal of the imaginative processes as a form of wish-fulfilment in which the individual’s attention is drawn away from external reality and placed under the sway of the pleasure principle. Such differing presentations of the imagination across psychoanalytic models can arguably be understood by considering several major shifts in psychoanalytic theorizing since Freud’s time. I will propose that these changes can be characterised as an ‘epistemic turn’: a general movement in psychoanalysis towards framing the internal world as strategic rather than compensatory, and a corresponding understanding of psychopathological processes as a response to failures in understanding and prediction rather than instinctual conflict.
    [Show full text]
  • Notices of the American Mathematical Society
    • ISSN 0002-9920 March 2003 Volume 50, Number 3 Disks That Are Double Spiral Staircases page 327 The RieITlann Hypothesis page 341 San Francisco Meeting page 423 Primitive curve painting (see page 356) Education is no longer just about classrooms and labs. With the growing diversity and complexity of educational programs, you need a software system that lets you efficiently deliver effective learning tools to literally, the world. Maple® now offers you a choice to address the reality of today's mathematics education. Maple® 8 - the standard Perfect for students in mathematics, sciences, and engineering. Maple® 8 offers all the power, flexibility, and resources your technical students need to manage even the most complex mathematical concepts. MapleNET™ -- online education ,.u A complete standards-based solution for authoring, nv3a~ _r.~ .::..,-;.-:.- delivering, and managing interactive learning modules \~.:...br *'r¥'''' S\l!t"AaITI(!\pU;; ,"", <If through browsers. Derived from the legendary Maple® .Att~~ .. <:t~~::,/, engine, MapleNefM is the only comprehensive solution "f'I!hlislJer~l!'Ct"\ :5 -~~~~~:--r---, for distance education in mathematics. Give your institution and your students cornpetitive edge. For a FREE 3D-day Maple® 8 Trial CD for Windows®, or to register for a FREE MapleNefM Online Seminar call 1/800 R67.6583 or e-mail [email protected]. ADVANCING MATHEMATICS WWW.MAPLESOFT.COM I [email protected]\I I WWW.MAPLEAPPS.COM I NORTH AMERICAN SALES 1/800 267. 6583 © 2003 Woter1oo Ma')Ir~ Inc Maple IS (J y<?glsterc() crademork of Woterloo Maple he Mar)leNet so troc1ema'k of Woter1oc' fV'lop'e Inr PII other trcde,nork$ (ye property o~ their respective ('wners Generic Polynomials Constructive Aspects of the Inverse Galois Problem Christian U.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Revolution
    Scientific Revolution Learning Objective Students will be able to: * define the Scientific Revolution * identify the historical roots of modern science. (a historical root is the start of something) The Birth of Modern Science Building Background: In the 1500s, Europe was undergoing dramatic changes. The Renaissance was well under way. During the Renaissance, great advances were made in: art writing education The stage was set for another revolution in thinking. For interactive Europe map go to: http://www.yourchildlearns.com/mappuzzle/europe-puzzle.html During the 1500s and 1600s, a handful of brilliant individuals laid the foundations for science as we know it today. Some historians consider the development of modern science the most important event in the intellectual history of humankind. Between 1500 and 1700, modern science emerged as a new way of gaining knowledge about the world. Galileo tested his ideas about gravity by dropping two balls of different sizes and weights from the top of the Leaning Tower of Pisa. Before this time, Europeans relied on two main sources for their understanding of nature: • The Bible and religious teachings. • The work of classical thinkers, especially the philosopher Aristotle. The Scientific Revolution Pair / Share Ques-on What two things did Europeans rely on to help them understand nature? 1. Europeans relied on the Bible. 2. The works of Classical thinkers, particularly Aristotle. Roots of the Scientific Revolution During the Renaissance, many thinkers began to question the conclusions of earlier thinkers. For example, Renaissance scholars rediscovered the cultures of ancient - Greece and Rome. Muslim, Christian, and Jewish scholars in the Muslim Arab world translated many classical works.
    [Show full text]