A Study in the Transcendental Dialectic of Immanuel Kant by Whi. H. Hollis a Thesis Submitted To

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Study in the Transcendental Dialectic of Immanuel Kant by Whi. H. Hollis a Thesis Submitted To The ontological argument; a study in the transcendental dialectic of Immanuel Kant Item Type text; Thesis-Reproduction (electronic) Authors Hollis, William Heym, 1914- Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction or presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 04/10/2021 04:44:19 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/553502 The OntolOjErlcal Argument? a Study In the Transcendental Dialectic of Immanuel Kant by Whi. H. H o llis A Thesis submitted to the faculty of the Department of Philosophy end Psychology in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Graduate College University of Arizona 1940 Approved: x7-). /? . & ,9 y / . / $ <*4 n liejor Professor <7 ^ 9 7 9 / f 9 < /o Certe Id quo mejus coHtarl neqult, non potest esse in intellect* solo. Si enim vel in solo intellect* "9t, potest coritari esse et in re: quod majus est. Si ergo id quo majus coritari non potest, est in solo intellect*; id ipsum cuo majue cogitari non . potest, est quo raajus cogitari potest. Sed ^ certe hoc esse non potest. - Anselm of Canterbury 130753 Contents Introduction 1 . The Contemporary Scene and Metaphysics 1 E. The Problem 6 I. !Rie Meaning of Ontology and the Ontological Argument 9 1* Etymology and Itefiniticms 9 2. Brief History of Ontology 15 3. The Meaning of the Ontological Argument 27 4. The History of the Ontological Argument 34 II. Immanuel Kent and the Ontological Argument 57 1. The General Philosophy of Kant 57 2. The Transeendental D ia le c tic 66 3. The Impossibility of an Ontological Proof 77 III. Criticisms and Conclusions 97 1. Kant1 s General Conception of the Argument 97 2. Post-Kantian Criticism 105 3. Virtues of Kant1 s Analysis 116 4. The Fundamental Issue 126 ' •- •' ,• - “> Appendix I. Aristotle and Meta^iysies 148 Appendix II. Wolff and Ontology 149 Appendix III. Augustine mi the Immortality of the Soul 150 Appendix IV. Anselm and the Ontological Argument 151 Appendix V. Kant and Kantianism 153 Bibliography 165 nfioroofies Thm Gontem?o?ar:r Seen© end Metaphysics The Enihjeet of this thesis, the ontological argument. Is a subject definitely metaphysical in nature. But it is hoped that the investigation of the argument is more exposi- ticmal end critical than metaphysical. With this hope and this purpose in mind, Kant has been selected as the philoso­ pher most capable as a guide in conducting the investigation. It is most difficult to approach a metaphysical subject with ■ ■ - - ■ . ■ ' - the simple, open-eyed realism of the ancient Greek thinkers, and still more difficult to avoid metaphysical speculation in any treatment of an argument ■which has proved to be a primary philosophical question par excellence since humans first at­ tempted to sound the depths of existence. It is hoped that the analysis and presentation of the argument in the follow­ ing pages has suffered from no great prejudice or bias. We moderns, with our distrust and skepticism, our hustle and bustle, find little time or Interest in a question frankly metaphysical and speculative. The philosophic attempt to me things steadily and as a whole, the quest for a synoptic vi­ sion of tru th , beauty, and goodness h a s become h ig h ly d i f f i ­ cult in what Sorokin calls this "overripe Sonsate culture*! 1 1 Sorokin. Social and Cultural Bynamics. II, 206-207. of ours.2 Perhaps nhe who has magnificence of mind and is the spectator of all time end all existence”,® the true phi­ losopher, has become rather a myth of the past. Then again, the human spirit, with its profound faith and abysmal ignorance, has often succeeded In shamefacedly de­ ceiving itself. The extravagant systems of the past are sur­ veyed with a skeptical eye. System upon system was erected with adolescent enthusiasm. The zealous metaphysician seized' his building-blocks of the universe and carefully put them in architectural order only to find that the house of dreams had fallen into complete ruin overnight. This, say many astute critics, has been the entire history of aetaphysleal theory. The cobwebs of the brain are swept ceaselessly by more rigor­ ous and less romantic housekeepers of ideas. The business of living begins where nightmares pass from the scene. What is i t th a t the poet S c h ille r says somewhere a f te r the p u b licatio n of that Copernlcan revolution in pure ideas, the Critique of Pur® Reason?: Pa die Ifetaphyeik vor kurzem unbeerbt abging Worden die Binge an si eh morgen sub hasta verkauft. , It is interesting to note the recent remarks of the - ' . * celebrated mathematician end writer, Bertrand . Bussell, concern­ ing hie attitude toward metaphysical theory. He writes: 23 2 Plato; Republic. Book Six highly apropos here. 3 Plato. Bepuolle. 486A. - 3 - Academic philosophers, ever since the time of Parmenides, have 'believed that the world is a unity. This view has been taken over from them by clergymen and journalists, and its acceptance has been considered the touchstone of wisdom. The most fundamental of my intelloetual beliefs is that this is*rubbish, I think the universe is all spots and jumps, without unity, without continuity, without coherence or orderliness or any of the other properties that governesses love. Indeed, there is little but prejudice and habit to.be said for the view that there is a world at all,* We have here a modern representative of Sextus Bmplrleus without a trace of his urbanity and nothing of his malicious wit and refreshing humor. But Bus soil 1 s caustic criticism is hardly more pointed than the following words of Professor ■ ■ . * - ' ■ . Schlick, sworn enemy of a l l m etaphysical th eo ry . The metaphysician will not know things, he will experience them .. All our knowledge of Being is principally acquired throu^i the methods of the particular sciences; every other "ontology" is idle babbling ... "Metaphysics is impossible because contradictory. If the metaphysician seeks only experience, his demands may be fulfilled, through, poetry and art and life itself, But if he wishes thoroughly to experience the tram- eeendent be mistakes experience for knowledge and, befogged by double ocmiradict 1 on, seeks empty shad­ ows Metaphysical systems c<mtain much science, - and much poetry, but they never contain metaphysics. But these gentlemen, and many others, find that the < ' " dreaded metaphysio, decently entombed and burled, raises its ‘ . • • ' Mostly appariti<m in another philosophic garret, and another wide-eyed mortal stumbles across the forbidden threshold with the fruits of his laborious metaphysical reflections. And 45 4 Russell. The Scientific Outlook. 94-95. 5 Sehliek. ^Erleben, lirkennen, Metaphysik.' Kant Studlen, Band UU. 156-159. more often than not he "brings with him a new version of an incredibly old argument, the ontological argument. For ell these eon sclentIons objeetors to metaphysical theory Professor 7 . H. Bradley has proposed a singular and not unsatisfactory justiflostion of its pursuit. He writes: All of us, I presume, more or less, are led beyond the region-of ordinary facts. Some in on® way and s€m© in o th ers, we seem to touch and have communion with what is beyond the visible world. In various manners we find something higher, which both supporte and humbles, both chastens and transports us. And, with certain persons, the intellectual effort to understand the universe is a principal way of thus experiencing the Deity. Ho one, probably, who has not felt thi s, however differently he might &e scribe it, has ever cared much for metaphysics. And, where- ever it has been felt strongly, it has been its own justification . 6 . On the o th er hand, when we consider the enormems range and astounding number of metaphysical systems proposed in the history of philosophy, we feel that much may be said In favor of the positivist, overcome with the subtleties of cerebral creation, attempting to grope toward a kind of clas­ sical simplicity with Ockham's laser or the principle of par simony or some similar methodological instrument. And our 4 " ' ' positivist may find, if he tread carefully on the analytic road, one of .the most subtle yet perfectly simple arguments, capable of endless discussion and infinite confusion, near his destination. Ho will have discovered the ontological argument. It may not be found in its time-honored form as 6 6 Bradley. Appearance and Reality. 5-6. - 5 - an attempt to prove the exlatenee of Goa, perhaps: it is an argument of many curious extensions and has appeared In many forms. From the time of Plato to the contemporary thought of Giovanni Gentile it has "been invested with philo soph teal sig­ nificance and metaphysical or psychological attributes. And long before philosophers concerned themselves with the pecu­ liar aspects of the relationship between essence and existence, when simple men on a simple e a rth re fle c te d upon, th e ir thoughts, their words, end their experiences, we find this fundamental argument, lacking the sophistication of dialectic, perhaps, but inevitable end. inexorable in its power to convince* Hot in that time, nor in this, does its power convince all nenf but its appearances have been somewhat regular and its mani­ festations rather constant* The psychologist, William James, the defender of Pragmatism and foe of impractical dreamers asleep in the un­ conditioned bosom of the Absolute, divided all men into •tou^i- minded" and "tender^ainded* individuals on the basis of their particular faiths end beliefs.
Recommended publications
  • Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Western Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 9-23-2015 12:00 AM Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought Ben Woodard The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Tilottama Rajan The University of Western Ontario Joint Supervisor Joan Steigerwald The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Theory and Criticism A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Ben Woodard 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Woodard, Ben, "Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3314. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3314 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought (Thesis Format: Monograph) by Benjamin Graham Woodard A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctorate of Philosophy in Theory and Criticism The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Ben Woodard 2015 Abstract: This dissertation examines F.W.J. von Schelling's Philosophy of Nature (or Naturphilosophie) as a form of early, and transcendentally expansive, naturalism that is, simultaneously, a naturalized transcendentalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Studia Philosophiae Religionis 21
    STUDIA PHILOSOPHIAE RELIGIONIS 21 Editores: Catharina Stenqvist et Eberhard Herrmann Ulf Zackariasson Forces by Which We Live Religion and Religious Experience from the Perspective of a Pragmatic Philosophical Anthropology UPPSALA 2002 Doctoral Dissertation in Philosophy of Religion for the Degree of Doctor of Theology at Uppsala University 2002. ABSTRACT Zackariasson, Ulf. 2002. Forces by which We Live. Religion and Religious Experience from the Perspective of a Pragmatic Philosophical Anthropology. Studia Philosophiae Religionis 21. 254 pp. ISBN 91–628–5169–1. ISSN 0346–5446. This study argues that a pragmatic conception of religion would enable philosophers to make important contributions to our ability to handle concrete problems involving religion. The term ’philosophical anthropology’, referring to different interpretative frameworks, which philosophers draw on to develop conceptions of human phenomena, is introduced. It is argued that the classical pragmatists embraced a philosophical anthro- pology significantly different from that embraced by most philosophers of religion; accordingly, pragmatism offers an alternative conception of religion. It is suggested that a conception of religion is superior to another if it makes more promising contributions to our ability to handle extra-philosophical problems of religion. A pragmatic philosophical anthropology urges us to view human practices as taking shape as responses to shared experienced needs. Religious practices develop to resolve tensions in our views of life. The pictures of human flourishing they present reconstruct our views of life, thereby allowing more significant interaction with the environment, and a more significant life. A modified version of reflective equilibrium is developed to show how we, on a pragmatic conception of religion, are able to supply resources for criticism and reform of religious practices, so the extra-philosophical problems of religion can be handled.
    [Show full text]
  • Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge
    Western Kentucky University TopSCHOLAR® Honors College Capstone Experience/Thesis Honors College at WKU Projects Fall 2007 Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy William Turner Western Kentucky University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.wku.edu/stu_hon_theses Part of the Other Philosophy Commons, Other Physics Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Turner, William, "Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy" (2007). Honors College Capstone Experience/Thesis Projects. Paper 111. http://digitalcommons.wku.edu/stu_hon_theses/111 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by TopSCHOLAR®. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors College Capstone Experience/ Thesis Projects by an authorized administrator of TopSCHOLAR®. For more information, please contact [email protected]. P │ S─Z─T │ P Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy Will Turner Western Kentucky University Abstract Zeno of Elea, despite being among the most important of the Pre-Socratic philosophers, is frequently overlooked by philosophers and scientists alike in modern times. Zeno of Elea’s arguments on have not only been an impetus for the most important scientific and mathematical theories in human history, his arguments still serve as a basis for modern problems and theoretical speculations. This is a study of his arguments on motion, the purpose they have served in the history of science, and modern applications of Zeno of Elea’s arguments on motion.
    [Show full text]
  • Skepticism and Pluralism Ways of Living a Life Of
    SKEPTICISM AND PLURALISM WAYS OF LIVING A LIFE OF AWARENESS AS RECOMMENDED BY THE ZHUANGZI #±r A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2004 By John Trowbridge Dissertation Committee: Roger T. Ames, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Chung-ying Cheng James E. Tiles David R. McCraw © Copyright 2004 by John Trowbridge iii Dedicated to my wife, Jill iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing this research, I would like to express my appreciation first and foremost to my wife, Jill, and our three children, James, Holly, and Henry for their support during this process. I would also like to express my gratitude to my entire dissertation committee for their insight and understanding ofthe topics at hand. Studying under Roger Ames has been a transformative experience. In particular, his commitment to taking the Chinese tradition on its own terms and avoiding the tendency among Western interpreters to overwrite traditional Chinese thought with the preoccupations ofWestern philosophy has enabled me to broaden my conception ofphilosophy itself. Roger's seminars on Confucianism and Daoism, and especially a seminar on writing a philosophical translation ofthe Zhongyong r:pJm (Achieving Equilibrium in the Everyday), have greatly influenced my own initial attempts to translate and interpret the seminal philosophical texts ofancient China. Tamara Albertini's expertise in ancient Greek philosophy was indispensable to this project, and a seminar I audited with her, comparing early Greek and ancient Chinese philosophy, was part ofthe inspiration for my choice ofresearch topic. I particularly valued the opportunity to study Daoism and the Yijing ~*~ with Chung-ying Cheng g\Gr:p~ and benefited greatly from his theory ofonto-cosmology as a means of understanding classical Chinese philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Inside the Epistemological Cave All Bets Are
    Inside the epistemological cave all bets are off Colin Wight Department of Politics, School of Humanities and Social Sciences, The University of Exeter, The Queen’s Drive, Exeter, Devon EX4 4QJ, UK. E-mail: [email protected] In this short rejoinder to Friedrich Kratochwil’s plea for a ‘pragmatic approach to theory building’, I argue that, despite his claims to the contrary, his position essentially rests on a curious form of foundationalism and relativism. The problem, as I identify it, is that Kratochwil’s attempt to move contemporary debate forward fails because he treats the issue only in epistemological terms. Kratochwil is deeply suspicious of the very idea of the ‘real world’and reduces it to an infinitely malleable construct of our ways of thinking and talking about it. This means that he remains trapped in the epistemological cave and is condemned to an endless quest to solve problems that have no solution. But the real world is not simply something that we think and talk about but, rather, we engage with it in practice and as such it offers resistance to our attempts to grasp it. Hence, it is not a subject without a voice in the global conversation. This is an important theoretical limit, particularly in relation to contemporary issues surrounding global environmental problems. Journal of International Relations and Development (2007) 10, 40–56. doi:10.1057/palgrave.jird.1800109 Keywords: dogmatism epistemology; foundationalism; reality; relativism; theoretical pluralism; truth Introduction When, in Plato’s Allegory of the Cave, the prisoner released from his chains returns to inform his fellow inmates that he has discovered that their world is an illusion, he could be forgiven for being surprised by their response.
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2012 The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Joseph Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Joseph, "The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno" (2012). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 125. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/125 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno A Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy October, 2011 By Joseph Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois 2 ABSTRACT Joseph Weiss Title: The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Critical Theory demands that its forms of critique express resistance to the socially necessary illusions of a given historical period. Yet theorists have seldom discussed just how much it is the case that, for Walter Benjamin and Theodor W.
    [Show full text]
  • What Literature Knows: Forays Into Literary Knowledge Production
    Contributions to English 2 Contributions to English and American Literary Studies 2 and American Literary Studies 2 Antje Kley / Kai Merten (eds.) Antje Kley / Kai Merten (eds.) Kai Merten (eds.) Merten Kai / What Literature Knows This volume sheds light on the nexus between knowledge and literature. Arranged What Literature Knows historically, contributions address both popular and canonical English and Antje Kley US-American writing from the early modern period to the present. They focus on how historically specific texts engage with epistemological questions in relation to Forays into Literary Knowledge Production material and social forms as well as representation. The authors discuss literature as a culturally embedded form of knowledge production in its own right, which deploys narrative and poetic means of exploration to establish an independent and sometimes dissident archive. The worlds that imaginary texts project are shown to open up alternative perspectives to be reckoned with in the academic articulation and public discussion of issues in economics and the sciences, identity formation and wellbeing, legal rationale and political decision-making. What Literature Knows The Editors Antje Kley is professor of American Literary Studies at FAU Erlangen-Nürnberg, Germany. Her research interests focus on aesthetic forms and cultural functions of narrative, both autobiographical and fictional, in changing media environments between the eighteenth century and the present. Kai Merten is professor of British Literature at the University of Erfurt, Germany. His research focuses on contemporary poetry in English, Romantic culture in Britain as well as on questions of mediality in British literature and Postcolonial Studies. He is also the founder of the Erfurt Network on New Materialism.
    [Show full text]
  • Art As a Form of Negative Dialectics: 'Theory' in Adorno's Aesthetic Theory Author(S): WILLIAM D
    Art as a Form of Negative Dialectics: 'Theory' in Adorno's Aesthetic Theory Author(s): WILLIAM D. MELANEY Reviewed work(s): Source: The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, New Series, Vol. 11, No. 1 (1997), pp. 40-52 Published by: Penn State University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25670205 . Accessed: 10/12/2011 23:11 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Speculative Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org WILLIAM D. MELANEY Art as a Form ofNegative Dialectics: Theory' inAdorno's Aesthetic Theory Adorno's dialectical approach to aesthetics is inseparable from his concep as a tion of art socially and historically consequential source of truth.None theless, his dialectical approach to aesthetics is perhaps understood better in terms of his monumental work, Aesthetic Theory (1984), which attempts to relate the speculative tradition in philosophical aesthetics to the situation of art in twentieth-century society, than in terms of purely theoretical claims. In an effort to clarify his aesthetic position, I hope to demonstrate both that Adorno embraces theKantian thesis concerning art's autonomy and that he criticizes transcendental philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Which Liberalism? Franco Sbarberi
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Institutional Research Information System University of Turin Bobbio and Croce – Which Liberalism? Franco Sbarberi Abstract: Benedetto Croce taught Norberto Bobbio to distinguish between two kinds of commitment, namely an intellectual and a political one. The expression “politica della cultura” effectively translates the idea of the autonomy or independence of scholarly and intellectual research. Another idea which was passed on from Croce to Bobbio is that of liberalism as the theoretical basis of every form of civil government insofar as the liberal conception rejects any notion of “Providence” as a covert agent of history. But Bobbio differed from Croce since he never believed that democracy could essentially contradict the perspective of liberalism, and was convinced that true emancipation is a sort of “conguagliamento delle libertà,” or, in other words, that it implies a strong relation between individual political rights and the demands of social justice. In the Preface to a bibliography of his writings that was published in 1984, Bobbio made reference to a “half-score” of his preferred authors. For the early modern period the selection seemed “almost inevitable” as far as the names of Hobbes, Locke, Kant, and Hegel were concerned. For more contempo- rary authors, on the other hand, he specifically singled out Croce, Cattaneo, Kelsen, Pareto, and Weber since they all represented, at one point or another, a crucial point of reference either for his own political development or for the considerable range of his intellectual interests (which also show him to have been a subtle analyst and systematic interpreter of the classic writers).
    [Show full text]
  • How to Represent Human Behavior and Decision Making in Earth System Models?
    Earth Syst. Dynam. Discuss., doi:10.5194/esd-2017-18, 2017 Manuscript under review for journal Earth Syst. Dynam. Discussion started: 2 March 2017 c Author(s) 2017. CC-BY 3.0 License. How to represent human behavior and decision making in Earth system models? A guide to techniques and approaches Finn Müller-Hansen1,2, Maja Schlüter3, Michael Mäs4, Rainer Hegselmann5, 6, Jonathan F. Donges1,3, Jakob J. Kolb1,2, Kirsten Thonicke1, and Jobst Heitzig1 1Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research, Telegrafenberg A31, 14473 Potsdam, Germany 2Department of Physics, Humboldt University Berlin, Newtonstraße 15, 12489 Berlin, Germany 3Stockholm Resilience Center, Stockholm University, Kräftriket 2B, 114 19 Stockholm, Sweden 4Department of Sociology and ICS, University of Groningen, Grote Rozenstraat 31, 9712 TG Groningen, The Netherlands 5Frankfurt School of Finance & Manangement, Sonnemannstraße 9-11 60314 Frankfurt am Main, Germany 6Bayreuth Research Center for Modeling and Simulation, Bayreuth University, Universitätsstrasse 30, 95440 Bayreuth, Germany Correspondence to: Finn Müller-Hansen ([email protected]) Abstract. In the Anthropocene, humans have a critical impact on the Earth system and vice versa, which can generate complex feedback processes between social and ecological dynamics. Integrating human behavior into formal Earth System Models (ESMs), however, requires crucial modeling assumptions about actors and their goals, behavioral options and decision rules, as well as modeling decisions regarding human social interactions and the aggregation of individuals’ behavior. In this tutorial 5 review, we compare existing modeling approaches and techniques from different disciplines and schools of thought dealing with human behavior at various levels of decision making. Providing an overview over social-scientific modeling approaches, we demonstrate modelers’ often vast degrees of freedom but also seek to make modelers aware of the often crucial consequences of seemingly innocent modeling assumptions.
    [Show full text]
  • History As Contemporary History in the Thinking of Benedetto Croce
    Open Journal of Philosophy, 2015, 5, 54-61 Published Online February 2015 in SciRes. http://www.scirp.org/journal/ojpp http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2015.51007 History as Contemporary History in the Thinking of Benedetto Croce Nicola Conati Department of Humanities, University of Trento, Trento, Italy Email: [email protected] Received 12 January 2015; accepted 30 January 2015; published 3 February 2015 Copyright © 2015 by author and Scientific Research Publishing Inc. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution International License (CC BY). http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ Abstract In this brief consideration of mine, trying to remain as faithful as possible to the texts taken into exam, I will first try to introduce the concept of history as contemporary history in the thinking of Benedetto Croce, whereas the second part of the reasoning will point toward proving and medi- tating on how such concept crosses the whole philosophical system of the Italian intellectual. What does contemporary history mean according to Benedetto Croce? Why is the spirit of the historian fundamental in the description of this concept? What kind of connection exists between story and contemporary history? What does pathology of history mean? How does the concept of contem- porary history relate to that of awareness, of finished and thinking? These are but a few of the questions to which I tried to find an answer with this essay. Keywords Benedetto Croce, History, Philosophy of History, Historical Knowledge, Contemporary History, Pathology of History, Heidegger, Rosmini, Idealism 1. Introduction I would like to begin my consideration by taking into account “Storia, cronaca e false storie”, a brief 1912 de- liberation originally born as a “memoir” for the Accademia Pontiniana of Naples, which will later merge into the 1917 “Teoria e storia della storiografia” (although the first edition was published in Germany in 1915).
    [Show full text]
  • Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics CAMBRIDGE TEXTS in the HISTORY of PHILOSOPHY
    CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY IMMANUEL KANT Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Series editors KARL AMERIKS Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame DESMOND M. CLARKE Professor of Philosophy at University College Cork The main objective of Cambridge Textsin the History of Philosophy is to expand the range, variety and quality of texts in the history of philosophy which are available in English. The series includes texts by familiar names (such as Descartes and Kant) and also by less well-known authors. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each volume contains a critical introduction together with a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and textual apparatus. The volumes are designed for student use at undergraduate and postgraduate level and will be of interest not only to students of philosophy, but also to a wider audience of readers in the history of science, the history of theology and the history of ideas. For a list of titles published in the series, please see end of book. IMMANUEL KANT Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science with Selections from the Critique of Pure Reason TRANSLATED AND EDITED BY GARY HATFIELD University of Pennsylvania Revised Edition cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521828246 © Cambridge University Press 1997, 2004 This publication is in copyright.
    [Show full text]