Replies to Critics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Replies to Critics SYMPOSIUM LIBERALISM AND SOCIAL JUSTICE REPLIES TO CRITICS BY SAMUEL FREEMAN © 2020 – Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 10, No. 1 (2020): 175-347 Luiss University Press E-ISSN 2240-7987 | P-ISSN 1591-0660 [THIS PAGE INTENTIONALLY LEFT BLANK] LIBERALISM AND SOCIAL JUSTICE Replies to Critics Samuel Freeman 1 Reply to Edmundson ill Edmundson primarily focuses on my arguments in chapter 4 of Liberalism and Distributive Justice on property-owning democracy and its connection with B the difference principle. Basically, he sees Rawls’s argument against welfare state capitalism as resting almost exclusively on the fair value of the political liberties, and contends that only socialism of some form can satisfy Rawls’s stated aim to guarantee democratic citizens’ equality of opportunity for political influence. Property-owning democracy he contends cannot meet the requirements of the fair value of the political liberties. This is the primary thesis of Edmundson’s important recent book, John Rawls: Reluctant Socialist. I contend in my book that the difference principle plays a crucial role in Rawls’s argument for social equality and against any form of capitalism, and that the difference principle together with fair political value and fair equal opportunity supports a property-owning democracy as well as liberal socialism. Instead of restricted utility, which I contend © 2020 – Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 10, No. 1 (2020): 175-347 Luiss University Press E-ISSN 2240-7987 | P-ISSN 1591-0660 Philosophy and Public Issues – Liberalism and Social Justice underlies Rawls’s conception of the capitalist welfare state, Edmundson somewhat surprisingly contends that a better way to understand welfare state capitalism is in terms of Rawls’s principles of justice themselves, absent the guarantee of the fair value of political liberties, a position he calls ”justice-without-fair-value.” Justice-without-fair-value is exactly like justice-as-fairness, he says, but without the first-principle guarantee of the fair value of the political liberties. On this interpretation, the second principle of justice is perfectly compatible with the vast inequalities typical of welfare state capitalist economies, so long as they benefit the least advantaged members of society.1 This is a familiar reading of Rawls’s justice as fairness, especially by many on the critical left; it has long been assumed that his aim in A Theory of Justice (TJ) was to justify the capitalist welfare state that evolved in liberal democracies between the Great Depression up until the 1980’s. Rawls sought to combat this (mis)interpretation, in the Preface to the 1999 revised edition of A Theory of Justice (TJ) – which was originally the Preface to the 1987 French edition – and he argued at greater length in Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (2001) that the principles of justice do not justify welfare state capitalism.2 Justice 1 Edmundson says in his book, “what could be termed Neoliberalism…is just like the two principles, but without a guarantee of the fair value of equal political liberties” (Edmundson 2017, 76, n.3). I argue below that neoliberalism or “justice without-fair-value” cannot be squared either with the 2nd principle’s requirement to mitigate inequalities implicit in fair equality of opportunity, or with the “deep reciprocity” of the difference principle. 2 Here referred to as ‘JF’ or the ‘Restatement.’ As the editor, Erin Kelly, says (JF, xii), the Restatement consists of Rawls’ lecture notes for his class in the history of political philosophy in the 1980’s, and were substantially completed by 1989 with some revisions in the early 1990’s as he completed Political Liberalism (here PL). The remaining lecture notes for this class were on Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, 176 Samuel Freeman – Replies to Critics as fairness instead justifies either a property owning democracy or market socialism – as Rawls initially claimed to little fanfare or notice in the first edition of Theory.3 Edmundson and I disagree primarily about his contention that Rawls’s argument against the welfare state and for property- owning democracy or liberal socialism rests solely on the conditions necessary to guarantee political fair value. I contend on the other hand that the difference principle together with fair value and FEO are all three crucial components of Rawls’s argument against welfare state capitalism (WSC). A second major disagreement lies within Edmundson’s rejection of both Rawls’s and my separate arguments for property owning democracy. Edmundson suggests here the striking thesis – developed at length in his book John Rawls: Reluctant Socialist – that no private property system, not even POD, is capable of guaranteeing the fair value of the political liberties with equal political influence; hence some form of socialism is required by Rawls’s principles of justice. He argues there, not for liberal socialism of the kind Rawls endorses, but for a kind of democratic socialism, at least at the level of “the commanding heights of the economy,” (Keynes’s term) that resembles in many respects British socialism of the post-WWII years, where the state owned and controlled major industries. Here, I will focus first (in § I) on the difference principle and how my understanding of it differs from Edmundson’s. Then I will discuss why I think the difference principle and fair equality of opportunity are crucial components of Rawls’s argument for both Hume, Mill, and Marx, and were published as Lectures in the History of Political Philosophy (Rawls 2008). 3 See, TJ orig. 258, 271, 272-274, 279; cf. TJ rev., 228, 240-242, 247. See also “Fairness to Goodness,” (1975) in Rawls 1999, 277, where Rawls says that both “associational socialism or property-owning democracy” may be realized by the principles of justice. 177 Philosophy and Public Issues – Liberalism and Social Justice property- owning democracy and liberal socialism. The fair value of political liberties itself is not enough. First, in §§ II-III, I discuss and contest some of Edmundson’s main reasons for contending that property owning democracy does not meet the requirements of Rawls’s principles of justice. Then in § IV, I discuss reasons why Rawls’s second principle requires the fair distribution of economic powers and prerogatives to all citizens, including in their place of work. I address in § V Edmundson’s and others’ argument that my position is basically a defense of syndicalism – or exclusively worker-owned and managed firms. In arguing that workers should have fair opportunities to exercise powers and prerogatives in their work, it was not my intention to defend syndicalism – or exclusively worker ownership and control of firms – but rather a wide variety of arrangements in which workers can exercise a guaranteed minimum of powers and prerogatives in their employment. Finally, in § VI I respond to Edmundson’s and others’ contention that my position violates freedom of association and occupation. I argue that, while the first principle protects freedom to choose one’s occupation and workplace, it does not protect either the freedom to engage in impermissible occupations or the freedom to contract into or join forms of economic association that conflict with the second principle of justice. Before beginning, I should say that Edmundson’s book is an important contribution, in large part because it stands as a much- needed correction to the longstanding criticism from the Marxist and critical left, that Rawls’s justice as fairness is but one more liberal attempt to justify the inequalities inherent in capitalism. I respond in chapter 3 of my book to G.A. Cohen’s version of this criticism, which I contend rests on misunderstanding the difference principle. Edmundson argues differently, that the criticism rests instead on misunderstanding the crucial role of the fair value of political liberties in mitigating economic inequalities and dissolving the concentration of private wealth that attends 178 Samuel Freeman – Replies to Critics private ownership of means of production. So, we agree on the outcome – that far from being incompatible with (liberal) socialism, justice as fairness is a reasonable – perhaps the most reasonable – justification of it. I go one step further, and agree, with Rawls, that property-owning democracy is (also) justified by Rawls’s conception of justice. Here I’ll also note that Edmundson’s primary thesis in his book exactly controverts Alan Thomas’ argument in his book – which is that only property-owning democracy, not liberal or democratic socialism, can satisfy Rawls’s principles of justice. I respond to Thomas’ argument in my reply to his comments. I Democratic Equality and the Difference Principle I.1. My case for property owning democracy rests in large part on Rawls’s difference principle, as I believe Rawls’s does as well. I agree with Edmundson that the conditions for guaranteeing the fair value of political liberties (and fair equality of opportunity as well) are an important part of Rawls’s argument against welfare state capitalism. But I disagree with his contention (developed at length in his book) that the fair value requirement is sufficient to eliminate property owning democracy from consideration as well. One reason I focus most of my attention on the role of the difference principle in Rawls’s argument for POD and liberal socialism is that, unlike the difference principle, Rawls had little to say about the economic arrangements required to guarantee the fair value of political liberties. Clearly, he thought fair equality of opportunity for political influence (like the 2nd principle’s fair equality of opportunity principle itself) required mitigating economic inequalities and diminishing as far as possible the influence of wealth on the electoral and political process; also, that 179 Philosophy and Public Issues – Liberalism and Social Justice fair value could not be realized in a capitalist economy, even combined with the welfare state, because of capitalism’s unregulated inequalities and inevitable concentration of wealth.
Recommended publications
  • The Infirmity of Social Democracy in Postcommunist Poland a Cultural History of the Socialist Discourse, 1970-1991
    The Infirmity of Social Democracy in Postcommunist Poland A cultural history of the socialist discourse, 1970-1991 by Jan Kubik Assistant Professor of Political Science, Rutgers University American Society of Learned Societies Fellow, 1990-91 Program on Central and Eastem Europe Working Paper Series #20 January 1992 2 The relative weakness of social democracy in postcommunist Eastern Europe and the poor showing of social democratic parties in the 1990-91 Polish and Hungarian elections are intriguing phenom­ ena. In countries where economic reforms have resulted in increasing poverty, job loss, and nagging insecurity, it could be expected that social democrats would have a considerable follOwing. Also, the presence of relatively large working class populations and a tradition of left-inclined intellec­ tual opposition movements would suggest that the social democratic option should be popular. Yet, in the March-April 1990 Hungarian parliamentary elections, "the political forces ready to use the 'socialist' or the 'social democratic' label in the elections received less than 16 percent of the popular vote, although the class-analytic approach predicted that at least 20-30 percent of the working population ... could have voted for them" (Szelenyi and Szelenyi 1992:120). Simi­ larly, in the October 1991 Polish parliamentary elections, the Democratic Left Alliance (an elec­ toral coalition of reformed communists) received almost 12% of the vote. Social democratic parties (explicitly using this label) that emerged from Solidarity won less than 3% of the popular vote. The Szelenyis concluded in their study of social democracy in postcommunist Hungary that, "the major opposition parties all posited themselves on the political Right (in the Western sense of the term), but public opinion was overwhelmingly in favor of social democratic measures" (1992:125).
    [Show full text]
  • French Romantic Socialism and the Critique of Liberal Slave Emancipation Naomi J
    Santa Clara University Scholar Commons History College of Arts & Sciences 9-2013 Breaking the Ties: French Romantic Socialism and the Critique of Liberal Slave Emancipation Naomi J. Andrews Santa Clara University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.scu.edu/history Part of the European History Commons, and the Feminist, Gender, and Sexuality Studies Commons Recommended Citation Andrews, Naomi J. (2013). Breaking the Ties: French Romantic Socialism and the Critique of Liberal Slave Emancipation. The ourJ nal of Modern History, Vol. 85, No. 3 (September 2013) , pp. 489-527. Published by: The nivU ersity of Chicago Press. Article DOI: 10.1086/668500. Article Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/668500 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Arts & Sciences at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in History by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Breaking the Ties: French Romantic Socialism and the Critique of Liberal Slave Emancipation* Naomi J. Andrews Santa Clara University What we especially call slavery is only the culminating and pivotal point where all of the suffering of society comes together. (Charles Dain, 1836) The principle of abolition is incontestable, but its application is difficult. (Louis Blanc, 1840) In 1846, the romantic socialist Désiré Laverdant observed that although Great Britain had rightly broken the ties binding masters and slaves, “in delivering the slave from the yoke, it has thrown him, poor brute, into isolation and abandonment. Liberal Europe thinks it has finished its work because it has divided everyone.”1 Freeing the slaves, he thus suggested, was only the beginning of emancipation.
    [Show full text]
  • Giuseppe Mazzini's International Political Thought
    Copyrighted Material INTRODUCTION Giuseppe Mazzini’s International Political Thought Giuseppe Mazzini (1805–72) is today largely remembered as the chief inspirer and leading political agitator of the Italian Risorgimento. Yet Mazzini was not merely an Italian patriot, and his influence reached far beyond his native country and his century. In his time, he ranked among the leading European intellectual figures, competing for public atten­ tion with Mikhail Bakunin and Karl Marx, John Stuart Mill and Alexis de Tocqueville. According to his friend Alexander Herzen, the Russian political activist and writer, Mazzini was the “shining star” of the dem­ ocratic revolutions of 1848. In those days Mazzini’s reputation soared so high that even the revolution’s ensuing defeat left most of his Euro­ pean followers with a virtually unshakeable belief in the eventual tri­ umph of their cause.1 Mazzini was an original, if not very systematic, political thinker. He put forward principled arguments in support of various progressive causes, from universal suffrage and social justice to women’s enfran­ chisement. Perhaps most fundamentally, he argued for a reshaping of the European political order on the basis of two seminal principles: de­ mocracy and national self­determination. These claims were extremely radical in his time, when most of continental Europe was still under the rule of hereditary kingships and multinational empires such as the Habs­ burgs and the ottomans. Mazzini worked primarily on people’s minds and opinions, in the belief that radical political change first requires cultural and ideological transformations on which to take root. He was one of the first political agitators and public intellectuals in the contemporary sense of the term: not a solitary thinker or soldier but rather a political leader who sought popular support and participa­ tion.
    [Show full text]
  • L. T. Hobhouse and J. A. Hobson
    Two years before the Labour Party victory of 1997, Tony Blair made a seminal speech L. T. HOBHOUSE AND J. A. HOBSON: to the Fabian Society in celebration of the fiftieth anniversary ThE NEW LIBERAL INFLUENCE ON ThiRD WAY idEAS of the 1945 Labour election victory. The speech was a major media event because it was a defining moment for New Labour ‘modernisers’. They were seeking to move the party from its socialist history on to ‘new’ political and ideological ground – as well as reap the tactical electoral benefits they felt could be gained by such a shift. Blair used the speech to pronounce himself ‘proud’ to be a ‘democratic socialist’ while redefining socialism to create ‘social-ism’. More relevant here, as seen above, was Blair’s reiteration of British political history from this revised New Labour position. Dr Alison Holmes examines New Liberal influences on Blair’s ‘Third Way’. 16 Journal of Liberal History 55 Summer 2007 L. T. HOBHOUSE AND J. A. HOBSON: ThE NEW LIBERAL INFLUENCE ON ThiRD WAY idEAS lair listed both L. T exercise it. So they argued for the New Liberal ideas of writers Hobhouse and J. A. collective action, including such as Hobhouse and Hobson Hobson amongst the state action, to achieve positive that were to carry through to intellectual corner- freedom, even if it infringed the modern interpretation of the stones of both New traditional laissez-faire liberal Third Way. BLiberalism and New Labour – orthodoxy … They did not call later termed the Third Way: themselves socialists, though Hobhouse coined the term J.
    [Show full text]
  • JS Mill's Political Thought
    P1: JZZ 0521860202pre CUFX079B/Urbinati 0 521 86020 2 cupusbw December 26, 2006 7:38 This page intentionally left blank ii P1: JZZ 0521860202pre CUFX079B/Urbinati 0 521 86020 2 cupusbw December 26, 2006 7:38 J. S. MILL’S POLITICAL THOUGHT The year 2006 marked the two hundredth anniversary of John Stuart Mill’s birth. Although his philosophical reputation has varied greatly in the interven- ing years, it is now clear that Mill ranks among the most influential modern political thinkers. Yet despite his enduring influence, and perhaps also because of it, the breadth and complexity of Mill’s political thought is often under- appreciated. Although his writings remain a touchstone for debates over liberty and liberalism, many other important dimensions of his political philosophy have until recently been mostly ignored or neglected. This volume aims, first, to correct such neglect by illustrating the breadth and depth of Mill’s political writings. It does so by drawing togetheracollection of essays whose authors explore underappreciated elements of Mill’s political philosophy, including his democratic theory, his writings on international relations and military inter- ventions, and his treatments of socialism and despotism. Second, the volume shows how Mill’s thinking remains pertinent to our own political life in three broad areas – democratic institutions and culture, liberalism, and international politics – and offers a critical reassessment of Mill’s political philosophy in light of recent political developments and transformations. Nadia Urbinati
    [Show full text]
  • Egalitarian Liberalism and Economic Freedom
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2019 Egalitarian Liberalism And Economic Freedom Pierce Randall University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Randall, Pierce, "Egalitarian Liberalism And Economic Freedom" (2019). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 3680. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/3680 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/3680 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Egalitarian Liberalism And Economic Freedom Abstract This dissertation considers three major challenges to egalitarian liberal institutions made by classical liber- als: that egalitarian liberal institutions involve too much coercive interference with individual economic decisions, that free markets tend to do better at rewarding people on the basis of their economic choices, and that only by recognizing full liberal rights of ownership can a society best promote a stable property regime consistent with our pre-political conventions of ownership. Each of these objections fails, but they point to an underlying concern that egalitarian liberal institutions fail to adequately protect economic freedom. The dissertation then develops and defends a conception of economic freedom that is reflected in egalitar- ian liberal institutions. Economic freedom depends on the quality and availability of options individuals have in markets,
    [Show full text]
  • Socialism and Democracy: New Labour and the Constitution
    UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works Title Socialism and Democracy: New Labour and the Constitution Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/5sk4j92d Journal Observatoire de la Société Britannique, 3 Author Bevir, Mark Publication Date 2007 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Socialism and Democracy: New Labour and the Constitution By Mark Bevir I. CONTACT INFORMATION Department of Political Science, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720-1950 Email: mbevir@ berkeley.edu II. BIOGRAPHICAL NOTE Mark Bevir is a Professor in the Department of Political Science, University of California, Berkeley. He is the author of The Logic of the History of Ideas (1999); New Labour: A Critique (2005); and, with R.A.W. Rhodes, Interpreting British Governance (2003), and Governance Stories (2006). 1 Keywords New Labour, Blair, Constitutionalism, Liberalism, Third Way, Institutionalism, Communitarianism Abstract : This paper suggests that one way to make sense of New Labour’s constitutional reforms is to show how they draw on concepts of democracy embedded in the British traditions of thought that have inspired New Labour. In this view, the constitutional reforms draw on a representative concept of democracy that has been characteristic of the liberal and Fabian traditions that have long dominated British socialism. Similarly, New Labour’s other public sector reforms often draw on a concept of democracy associated with communitarianism and the new institutionalism – two strands of social science upon which New Labour, following the Fabian tradition with its faith in expertise, has drawn to respond to issues raised by the New Right. The paper contrasts the dominant liberal and Fabian traditions upon which New Labour has drawn with some neglected participatory and pluralist alternatives that have long inspired socialist opposition to the Labour Party.
    [Show full text]
  • Destroying Democracy: Neoliberal Capitalism and the Rise Of
    Across the world, democracy is under threat from the wealth and power that is ever more concen- trated in the hands of the few. But the rule of the few over the many rests on very shaky ground. When we have both the ideas and the power, and when we unite, we can overcome these crises and build a world of peace and justice. This volume provides a space for campaigners from different places and different traditions to discuss, refine and share ideas, which is essential to building movements that can provide hope and real change. Jeremy Corbyn, former leader of the UK Labour Party, Member of Parliament and founder of the Peace and Justice Project The democratic rights won under capitalism have always been limited yet crucial to gaining some control over our lives and allowing vital space for challenging capitalism itself. The volume poses neoliberalism’s polarisation of this dichotomy. On the one hand, the various authors agree, neo- liberalism represents an authoritarian turn; on the other, they argue, that threat poses the neces- sity and promise of deepening substantive democracy. Sam Gindin, former Research Director of the Canadian Auto Workers Contributors draw on Marxist theoretical tools to expose deep tensions between neoliberal cap- italism and democracy while determinedly refusing repressive alternatives inspired by orthodox Marxism. Their project is one of democratic and ecological socialism. This book will constitute a stimulating and valuable resource to the many who are committed to that project. Daryl Glaser, Professor of Political Studies, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg This volume makes a compelling case for why fascist populist movements are manifestations of broad crises at the heart of modern globalising capitalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Proposed DSA Political Platform (Second Draft)
    Proposed DSA Political Platform for 2021 Convention Second Draft Notes: This second draft is the baseline of what delegates will discuss at the 2021 National Convention. It involves many hours of work to incorporate input from individual members and national committees. Thank you to everyone who gave feedback through the form and in discussions at our Pre-Convention Conferences. Amendments may be submitted here. ● The deadline to submit amendments is midnight on Thursday, 7/15. ● Amendments require 250 signatures from members in good standing ● Each amendment may only pertain to one section of the platform ● An author may submit a maximum of 4 amendments ● Amendments must be politically substantive. Style edits, copy edits, or other language edits that are not substantive will not be considered ● Amendments adding new platform planks, removing existing planks, or reordering planks will not be accepted ● Platform planks are listed in alphabetical order, with the exception of Deepening and Strengthening Democracy, which the Platform and Resolutions Subcommittee voted to place first in order to foreground our commitment to political and economic democracy as necessary conditions to achieve a democratic socialist society. Preamble The Democratic Socialists of America are fighting to win a world organized and governed by and for the vast majority, the working class. We are socialist because we share a vision of a humane social order based on popular control of resources and production, economic planning, equitable distribution, feminism, racial equality and non-oppressive relationships. We are democratic because we know that this transformation cannot be won from the top down, by a small group of elites who claim to have all the answers, or by even well-meaning politicians.
    [Show full text]
  • The Quest for a Liberal-Socialist Democracy and Development
    The Quest for a Liberal-Socialist Democracy and Development The Quest for a Liberal-Socialist Democracy and Development: Against the Behemoth By Vjeran Katunarić The Quest for a Liberal-Socialist Democracy and Development: Against the Behemoth By Vjeran Katunarić This book first published 2018 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2018 by Vjeran Katunarić All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-5275-0907-9 ISBN (13): 978-1-5275-0907-8 TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ................................................................................... vii Introduction ................................................................................................ ix Chapter One ................................................................................................. 1 Liberal Socialism Faced with the Behemoth Chapter Two ................................................................................................ 9 The Higher Immorality of the New Power Elites Chapter Three ............................................................................................ 16 The Impossible Self-Production Chapter Four .............................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Liberal Democracy and Socialist Democracy: the Antinomies of C.B
    LIBERAL DEMOCRACY AND SOCIALIST DEMOCRACY: THE ANTINOMIES OF C.B. MACPHERSON Leo Panitch ‘ . what I have been trying to do all along (and am still trying to do). is to work out a revision of liberal-democratic theory, a revision which clearly owes a good deal to Marx, in the hope of making that theory more democratic while rescuing that valuable part of the liberal tradition which is submerged when liberalism is identified with capitalist market relations.’ C.B. MACPHERSON .1 There are two different ways in which creative intellectuals, who seek to make use of Marxism in their life’s work, locate themselves in terms of Marxism.1 One way is for the intellectual to see himself in his work as part of the revolutionary socialist movement. It means taking one’s standpoint and judging the contribution one makes in terms of maximising the human potentialities of man as expressed in the revolutionary potentialities of the socialist movement taken as a whole. The role of the intellectual, on this view, is to help develop the strategy and tactics of the socialist movement in terms of his understanding of Marxism (and of the world through it); and to help develop Marxism in terms of the changing world and the needs of the socialist movement as it confronts this world. A second way of locating oneself in terms of one’s knowledge of Marxism, entails taking a standpoint, locating oneself, outside of both Marxism and the revolution­ ary socialist movement. Here one seeks to bring the insight of Marxism to some other set of ideals or social entity and enrich them thereby.
    [Show full text]
  • Representative Democracy, Conflict, and Consensus in J. S. Mill An
    Representative Democracy, Conflict, and Consensus in J. S. Mill An abridged and translated version of a dissertation presented by Gustavo Hessmann Dalaqua to The Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Political Philosophy University of São Paulo Advisor: Prof. Alberto Ribeiro Gonçalves de Barros Co-advisor: Prof. Maria Isabel Limongi Examiners: Prof. Cicero Romão de Araujo, Prof. Silvana Ramos, Prof. Nadia Urbinati São Paulo 2019 Autorizo a reprodução e divulgação total ou parcial deste trabalho, por qualquer meio convencional ou eletrônico, para fins de estudo e pesquisa, desde que citada a fonte. Catalogação na Publicação Serviço de Biblioteca e Documentação Faculdade de Filosofia, Letras e Ciências Humanas da Universidade de São Paulo Dalaqua, Gustavo Hessmann D136r Representative Democracy, Conflict, and Consensus in J. S. Mill / Gustavo Hessmann Dalaqua ; orientador Alberto Ribeiro Gonçalves de Barros. - São Paulo, 2019. 245 f. Tese (Doutorado)- Faculdade de Filosofia, Letras e Ciências Humanas da Universidade de São Paulo. Departamento de Filosofia. Área de concentração: Filosofia. 1. Mill, John Stuart 1806-1873. 2. Democracy. 3. Political Representation. 4. Consensus. 5. Conflict. I. Barros, Alberto Ribeiro Gonçalves de, orient. II. Título. TABLE OF CONTENTS Overview of the Portuguese version of the dissertation………………….………p. 11 1. Democracy and truth: A contingent defense of epistemic democracy ...…………p. 31 1.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………...……p. 31 1.2 The critique against the epistemic conception of democracy…………………....p. 33 1.3 Deliberation and truth: Mill’s epistemic democracy…………………………….p. 37 1.3.1 “With the eyes of a working man”: representation, knowledge, and social perspective…………………………………………………………………….……..p.
    [Show full text]