NOTES to PART ONE C.D. Broad, "Hume's Theory of the Credibility Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

NOTES to PART ONE C.D. Broad, NOTES TO PART ONE 1 C.D. Broad, "Hume's Theory of the Credibility of Miracles," Proceedings oj the Aristotelian Society, NS XVIII (1916-1917), p. 77. The arguments that Broad critiques are in David Hume, Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding, Section X, "Of Miracles," ed., L.A. Selby-Bigge, 3rd ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Pr., 1975). All references to Hume's "Essay on Miracles" (i.e. "Of Miracles") will be to this edition of the Enquiries. I omit section and part numbers and give only page references. 2 Broad, p. 92. This criticism of Hume by Broad is probably the most often repeated criticism of Hume's position in Part I "Of Miracles." Among those that have criticized Hume along these lines are the following: F.R. Tennant, Miracle (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1925, p. 82; A.E. Taylor, David Hume and The Miraculous (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1927), pp. 34- 38; Anthony Flew, Hume's Philosophy oj BelieJ(London: RKP, 1961), p. 17l. 3 David Hume, A Treatise OJ Human Nature, ed., L.A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 165. All references to the Treatise are to this edition. I omit book, section and part numbers and give only page references. 4 Even if belief is regarded, in part, as a function of custom and ideally nothing else, it is not clear that we would always say that our belief that B will follow A is, or ideally should be, stronger in cases where A's have always been observed to be followed by B's, than in cases where they have not. The psychological conviction with which a belief is held might, in some circumstances, be regarded as intrinsic to the belief itself. Firmly believing B will follow A, due to past experience, may be a different belief than less firmly believing B will follow A. The propositional content of the beliefs might vary accordingly. "B will follow A" might be an abbreviation for content that includes implicit or explicit reference to the conviction with which the belief is held and so be part of the belief itself. But far more often it is unlikely to suppose that the propositional content of our beliefs contain a self-reflective component concerning the conviction with which the belief is held. So speaking, as Hume does, of the belief "B will follow A" as ideally being stronger in proportion to the degree of one's experience of their conjunction, is not objectionable on the grounds that believing some proposition p strongly, and believing the same proposition p weakly, are two different beliefs. The content of those beliefs may well be the same no matter what the degree of conviction is with which they are held. Where Hume's account is objectionable is in the very strange idea, which rests on his analysis of the causal relation, that there is no justifiable reason for believing that B will follow A. Not even past experience provides justifiable reason. 5 Hume equates this transition with the idea of a necessary connection between cause and effect - a connection that Hume says "exists in the mind, not in 75 76 NOTES TO PART ONE the objects." The necessary connection between causes and effects is the foundation of our inference from one to the other. The foundation of our inference is the transition arising from the accustomed union. These are, therefore, the same. The idea of necessity arises from some impression. There is no impression conveyed by our senses, which can give rise to that idea. It must, therefore, be derived from some internal impression, or impression of refiexion. There is no internal impression, which has any relation to the present business, but that propensity, which custom produces, to pass from an object to the idea of its usual attendant. This, therefore, is the essence of necessity ... necessity is something that exists in the mind, not in the objects ... Either we have no idea of necessity, or necessity is nothing but that determination of the thought to pass from causes to effects and from effects to causes, according to their experienced union [Treatise, pp. 165-6]. This is a somewhat stilted way of describing the matter, but one that is is in keeping with Hume's theory of belief. If A's have been followed by B's fifty percent of the time in the past, we would not ordinarily say that our inference that A will be followed by B this time is fifty percent warranted or justified. Rather, we would say that we can justifiably infer that A will be followed by B with a fifty percent probability. (I am referring here only to those cases, if any, in which we assume, with Hume, that inferences can be justified, in some sense, on the basis of past experience and only on such a basis.) J.L. Mackie, The Cement of The Universe (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974), p.15. For Stove's argument see D.C. Stove, "Hume, Probability and Induction," in Hume, ed. V.C. Chappell (Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1966), pp. 187-212. Also see D.C. Stove, Probability and Hume's Inductive Skepticism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973); Tom L. Beauchamp and Alexander Rosenberg, Hume and the Problem of Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981). For a discussion of the sense in which past experience should be understood see Dennis Ahern, "Hume on the Evidential Impossibility of Miracles," in Studies in Epistemology, ed. Nicholas Rescher (Oxford: Blackwell, 1975), pp. 1-32. See pp.4-5. Hume concludes his essay on miracles with a similar sarcastic remark. ... upon the whole, we may conclude that the Christian Religion not only was at first attended with miracles, but even at this day cannot be believed by any reasonable person without one. Mere reason is insufficient to convince us of its veracity: And whoever is moved by Faith to assent to it, is conscious ofacontinued miracle in his own person, which subverts all the principles of his understanding, and gives him a determination to believe what is most contrary to custom and experience [po 131]. But as J.L. Mackie says:" ... this is only ajoke. What the believer is conscious of in his own person, though it may be a mode of thinking that goes against 'custom and experience', and so is contrary to the ordinary rational principles of the understanding, is not, as an occurrence, a violation of natural law." J.L Mackie, The Miracle of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), p. 29. Also see, R.M Burns, The Great Debate On Miracles (Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press, 1981). Burns supports the view that this, and some other NOTES TO PART ONE 77 problematic passages like it in Hume's essay, should be interpreted as ironic or sarcastic (chapters 6-7). He also argues (chapter 7), contrary to Flew, that Hume's argument in Part I is intended as an a priori argument, and contrary to Gaskin, that Hume intended his argument to apply to the case of seeing a miracle for oneself as well as to belief based on testimony (p. 295, note 120). On all of these points I agree. Burn's is the only author I know of who also contends that Hume's argument against miracles is, in a sense, superfluous given his view that divine activity is impossible to know. However, he doesn't see how this position ofHume's, aside from logically preempting Hume's argument in part I, also plays a crucial role in it. If, contrary to Hume's empiricism, it were possible to know divine activity, then it would be possible to justifiably believe that a miracle occurred. Burn's discussion of the historical background to Hume's essay, and of the origin of the essay itself, is extremely useful in helping to understand Hume's essay. Chapters 7 and 8 are valuable in helping to understand both Hume's argument and criticisms of it. Although Burn's discusses the essay in the context of the publication of the Treatise and Enquiries I don't think he sees how integrally related to Hume's philosophy it is. But in his discussion (chapter 8) of various criticism's of Hume's a priori argument in part I, he does argue that Hume's argument cannot be supported apart from his theory of explanation and that this theory is connected to his empiricism. As I argue in part I, this insight is both true, important and has largely been overlooked. Burns cites a passage from one of Hume's letters to George Campbell, author of a Dissertation on Miracles, 1762 which was a reply to Hume. I quote some of it because it shows, I think, that in Hume's view the argument against miracles was integrally connected with the Treatise. Hume writes: It may perhaps amuse you to learn the first hint, which suggested to me that argument which you have so strenuously attacked. I was walking in the cloisters of the Jesuits College at La Fleche ... engaged in conversation with a Jesuit of some parts and learning who was relating to me, and urging some nonsensical miracle performed in their convent, when I was tempted to dispute against him; and as my head was full of the topics of my Treatise 'if Human Nature, which I was at that time composing, this argument immediately occurred to me ... [Burns, p.1331· Burns thinks that Hume's argument is not especially original (pp.140-1). The same argument occurred in earlier writers that Hume may have read. However, if my overall thesis that Hume's Essay must be interpreted in the context of his theory of a posteriori reasoning is correct, then Hume's position is, of course, highly original.
Recommended publications
  • Beliefs in Miraculous Healings, Religiosity and Meaning in Life
    Religions 2015, 6, 1113–1124; doi:10.3390/rel6031113 OPEN ACCESS religions ISSN 2077-1444 www.mdpi.com/journal/religions Article Beliefs in Miraculous Healings, Religiosity and Meaning in Life Jakub Pawlikowski 1,*, Michał Wiechetek 2, Jarosław Sak 1 and Marek Jarosz 2 1 Department of Ethics and Human Philosophy, Medical University of Lublin, Aleje Racławickie 1, 20-950 Lublin, Poland; E-Mail: [email protected] 2 Institute of Psychology, John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin, Aleje Racławickie 14, 20-950 Lublin, Poland; E-Mails: [email protected] (M.W.); [email protected] (M.J.) * Author to whom correspondence should be addressed; E-Mail: [email protected]; Tel.: +48-81-4486-850. Academic Editors: Arndt Büssing and René Hefti Received: 1 June 2015 / Accepted: 9 September 2015 / Published: 17 September 2015 Abstract: Throughout centuries, many interpretations of miraculous healings have been offered by philosophers, theologians, physicians and psychologists. Different approaches to miracles originate from the differences in understanding of causative factors, concepts of nature and the relationship between God and nature. Despite many skeptical arguments, a vast majority of people (approximately 70%) in modern Western societies share a belief in miracles and millions of sick people pilgrimage to sanctuaries seeking their occurrence. The aim of the research was to describe the social perception of miraculous healings, and the relationship between beliefs in miraculous healings, religiosity and meaning in life. A survey was conducted on a group of 178 respondents aged 18 to 30 (M = 21.5; SD = 2.31), 90% Catholics. The obtained results show that it is possible to describe the perception of miraculous healings in category of the essence of the causative factors (natural/supranatural) and definiteness (defined/undefined).
    [Show full text]
  • The Epistemology of Testimony
    Pergamon Stud. His. Phil. Sci., Vol. 29, No. 1, pp. 1-31, 1998 0 1998 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved Printed in Great Britain 0039-3681/98 $19.004-0.00 The Epistemology of Testimony Peter Lipton * 1. Introduction Is there anything you know entirely off your own bat? Your knowledge depends pervasively on the word of others. Knowledge of events before you were born or outside your immediate neighborhood are the obvious cases, but your epistemic dependence on testimony goes far deeper that this. Mundane beliefs-such as that the earth is round or that you think with your brain-almost invariably depend on testimony, and even quite personal facts-such as your birthday or the identity of your biological parents--can only be known with the help of others. Science is no refuge from the ubiquity of testimony. At least most of the theories that a scientist accepts, she accepts because of what others say. The same goes for almost all the data, since she didn’t perform those experiments herself. Even in those experiments she did perform, she relied on testimony hand over fist: just think of all those labels on the chemicals. Even her personal observations may have depended on testimony, if observation is theory-laden, since those theories with which it is laden were themselves accepted on testimony. Even if observation were not theory-laden, the testimony-ladenness of knowledge should be beyond dispute. We live in a sea of assertions and little if any of our knowledge would exist without it. If the role of testimony in knowledge is so vast, why is its role in the history of epistemology so slight? Why doesn’t the philosophical canon sparkle with titles such as Meditations on Testimony, A Treatise Concerning Human Testimony, and Language, Truth and Testimony? The answer is unclear.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY of RELIGION Selected Readings Second Edition IQ:Pl
    PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Selected Readings Second Edition IQ:Pl Edited by MICHAEL PETERSON Asbury College WILLIAM HASKER Huntington College BRUCE REICHENBACH Augsburg College DAVID BASINGER Roberts Wesleyan College New York Oxford OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 2001 416 Miracles the event but whether nature was in fact the sole c I . question. ausa agent m the case in DAVID HUME The Evidence for Finally, many philosophical discussions revolve around th Miracles Is Weak whetherh hthe undisputed. occurrence of certa·1n un usua I events coulde question . of onest, t .oughtful individuals to acknowledge that G d h require all This selection contains a classic and influential argument against belief in mir- m ea:thly affairs. Some maintain that in- acles crafted by David Hume (1711-1776). The wise person, Hume informs us, healmgs or resurrections) would force all to '.e:g., as- Other philosophers argue that althou h belief . g.e d1vin.e .in- will always proportion his or her belief to the evidence. He goes on to say that may at times be acceptable for those al read .direct d1v1ne our belief in the relevant laws of nature are based on uniform, public, past ex- exists, no single event or series of events could ever com I y el1:ve that God perience, which provides a great amount of objective evidence, while the evi- to assent to the existence of a perfectly good people dence supporting alleged violations of these laws consists solely of personal tes- ample, the tremendous amount of horrific evil in th Id . agent. For ex- timonies that cannot be substantiated by independent testing.
    [Show full text]
  • Complete Dissertation
    VU Research Portal Miracles in the age of science Bersee, A.N.J.M. 2020 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) Bersee, A. N. J. M. (2020). Miracles in the age of science: A philosophical analysis and evaluation of arguments used in the debate between science and Western theology. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 30. Sep. 2021 VRIJE UNIVERSITEIT Miracles in the age of science: A philosophical analysis and evaluation of arguments used in the debate between science and Western theology ACADEMISCH PROEFSCHRIFT ter verkrijging van de graad Doctor of Philosophy aan de Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, op gezag van de rector magnificus prof.dr. V. Subramaniam, in het openbaar te verdedigen ten overstaan van de promotiecommissie van de Faculteit Religie en Theologie op woensdag 25 maart 2020 om 13.45 uur in de aula van de universiteit, De Boelelaan 1105 door Anthonius Nicolaas Johannes Maria Bersee geboren te Bloemendaal promotoren: prof.dr.
    [Show full text]
  • An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding
    OXFORD WORLD’S CLASSICS DAVID HUME An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding Edited with an Introduction and Notes by PETER MILLICAN 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York Editorial material © Peter Millican 2007 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published as an Oxford World’s Classics paperback 2007 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Hume, David, 1711-1776 [Philosophical essays concerning human understanding] An enquiry concerning human understanding / David Hume; edited with an introduction and notes by Peter Millican.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume's Fork, and His Theory of Relations
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. XCV No. 1, July 2017 doi: 10.1111/phpr.12385 © 2017 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Hume’s Fork, and his Theory of Relations1 PETER MILLICAN Hertford College, Oxford Hume’s Fork—the distinction between “relations and ideas” and “matters of fact” intro- duced in his first Enquiry—is well known, though considered by most specialist scholars to be a crude simplification of the far more sophisticated theory of relations in his Trea- tise. But close analysis of the Treatise theory shows it to be an unsatisfactory reworking of Locke’s taxonomy, implausibly identifying relations with mental operations and deliv- ering a confused criterion of demonstrability which Hume subsequently abandons in favour of his Conceivability Principle. The latter then becomes the basis for Hume’s Fork, the theory of which, as implicitly defined by the various criteria he specifies, turns out to be consistent and plausible. However it faces a number of potential problems, some of which Hume might have been expected to address, while others—particularly concerning his tendency to identify apriority, demonstrability, and necessity—derive from relatively recent Epistemology, Philosophy of Language, and Philosophy of Mathematics. All of these are considered, some requiring tightening of Hume’s distinction while others imply limitations. Finally, a conclusion is drawn emphasising the continuing value of Hume’s position, despite these difficulties. Hume’s Fork—his distinction between “relations of ideas” and “matters of fact”—is justly famous, and widely acknowledged as an influential ancestor of the familiar modern analytic/synthetic distinction. Given Hume’s tendency to see ideas as the determinants of meaning, the very term “relations of ideas” suggests something like “truth in virtue of meaning”.
    [Show full text]
  • Habermas Vs Hume: an Argument for the Possibility of Miracles
    Proposal for Graduate Research Symposium Name: Olaoluwa Apata Topic: Habermas vs Hume: An Argument for the Possibility of Miracle Department: Philosophy Name of Mentor/Professor: Dr. Ed Martin. David Hume, an eighteenth century empiricist, skeptic, and a widely acclaimed philosopher of the Enlightenment, formulated one of the greatest modern critique, against the reliability and plausibility of religion in general and Christianity in particular in the modern era of philosophy. During his time, religion depended mainly on the testimonies of miracles and it was probably taken for granted that miracles, an ancient religious tradition, was never considered to be an ideology whose truthfulness could be doubted or denied. But Hume, being a skeptic, argued against not just the possibility of miracles but also the truthfulness of the various testimonies and miraculous claims in history. While Hume continues to argue against the possibility of miracles, Christian and theistic philosophers who believe in the historicity and possibility of miracles have also made effort to respond to some of the philosophical questions aimed at denying the possibility of miracles and the plausibility of religious beliefs in general. Hume defines a miracle as an event that is rationally and practically improbable. In his article titled, Of Miracles, he defines a miracle as “the violation of the laws of nature.”1 Logically and metaphysically speaking, an event that can only be brought about by the violation of the laws of nature is such an event that might as well require an obstruction to the universal and an unalterable natural order. From the very nature of this definition, a miracle is not just improbable but its effects, upon which sets of belief system rests, is false.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Affinities Between Hume and Kierkegaard
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Jyrki Kivelä On the Affinities Between Hume and Kierkegaard Academic dissertation to be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki in auditorium XII (Main Building, Unioninkatu 34), on the 16th of March, 2013 at 10 o’clock. Filosofisia tutkimuksia Helsingin yliopistosta Filosofiska studier från Helsingfors universitet Philosophical Studies from the University of Helsinki Publishers: Theoretical Philosophy and Philosophy (in Swedish) Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies Social and Moral Philosophy Department of Political and Economic Studies P.O. box 24 (Unioninkatu 40 A) 00014 University of Helsinki Finland Editors: Panu Raatikainen Tuija Takala Bernt Österman Jyrki Kivelä On the Affinities Between Hume and Kierkegaard ISBN 978-952-10-8613-7 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-8614-4 (PDF) ISSN 1458-8331 Kopio Niini Oy Helsinki 2013 Contents Acknowledgements..............................................................................................................................7 List of Abbreviations and Methods of Citation....................................................................................8 1. Introduction....................................................................................................................................14 1.1 Background..............................................................................................................................14
    [Show full text]
  • AN EMPIRICIST TRADITION on the SUBJECT of MIRACLES By
    AN EMPIRICIST TRADITION ON THE SUBJECT OF MIRACLES by KHANAM MUMTAZ Thesis presented for the M.A. Degree in Philosophy in the University of London, May, 1967. ProQuest Number: 10097292 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest. ProQuest 10097292 Published by ProQuest LLC(2016). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 ABSTRACT This work is an attempt at a critical study of *an empiricist tradition on the subject of miracles'. This tradition is the one that began with David Hume's argument against miracles and was then carried on by J* S. Mill and some contemporary empiricists. The views of these thinkers are discussed not with a view to developing any explanatory theory of miracles, but with the intention of estimating how far the tradition as a whole has succeeded in establishing its claim against miracles. The discussions begin with a very brief repro­ duction of the opinions that had been maintained by some eminent philosophers prior to the development of this empiricist tradition. This is done in Chapter I, The views of Hume, Mill and some present-day empiricists are then taken up separately in three successive chapters for somewhat detailed considerations.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume's Abject Failure,The Argument Against Miracles
    Hume's Abject Failure, The Argument Against Miracles John Earman, Professor of the History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh Abstract : Hume's famous essay on miracles is set in the context of the larger debate that was taking place in the eighteenth century about the nature of miracles and the ability of eyewitness testimony to establish the credibility of such events. The author contents that Hume's argument against miracles is largely unoriginal and chiefly without merit where it is original. To advance the issues so provocatively posed by Hume's essay requires the tools of the probability calculus being developed by Hume's contemporaries but largely ignored by Hume. Content Part I Hume on Miracles 1. Abstract 1 2 Hume's Religious Orientation 4 3 The Origins of Hume's Essay 6 4 The Puzzles of Hume's Definitions of “Miracles” 8 5 Conceptions of Miracles 9 6 What a Miracle Is for Hume 12 7 The Eighteenth-Century Debate on Miracles 14 8 The Structure of Hume's Essay 20 9 Hume's Straight Rule of Induction and His “Proof” Against Miracles 22 10 Hume, Bayes, and Price 24 11 Bayes and Bayesianism 26 12 The Bayes-Price Rejection of Hume's Straight Rule 29 13 Hume's Stultification of Scientific Inquiry 31 14 The Indian Prince 33 15 Hume's Maxim 38 16 What Is Hume's Thesis? 43 17 Hume's Diminution Principle 49 18 Multiple Witnessing 53 19 More Multiple Witnessing 56 20 What Is Right About Hume's Position 59 21 Fall Back Positions for Hume 61 22 Probabilifying Religious Doctrines 65 23 Hume's Contrary Miracles Argument 67 24
    [Show full text]
  • C.S. Lewis's Critique of Hume on Miracles
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 25 Issue 2 Article 3 4-1-2008 C.S. Lewis's Critique Of Hume On Miracles Robert A. Larmer Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Larmer, Robert A. (2008) "C.S. Lewis's Critique Of Hume On Miracles," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 25 : Iss. 2 , Article 3. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200825214 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol25/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. C. S. LEWIS'S CRITIQUE OF HUME'S "OF MIRACLES" Robert A. Larmer In this article I argue that C. S. Lewis is both a perceptive reader and trenchant critic of David Hume's views on miracle. Despite his popularity as a Christian apologist and despite the fact that one of his major works is Miracles: A Preliminary Study, C. S. Lewis is virtually ignored in contemporary discussions of miracles. When he is mentioned, he is usually quickly dismissed as displaying a superficial understanding of David Hume's famous criticism of the possibility of rational belief in miracles based on testimonial evidence. My contention in this article is that such dismissals are unjustified. Al­ though he did not write as a professional philosopher and did not direct his writing to specialists in philosophy, Lewis was well trained in philoso­ phy.
    [Show full text]
  • Miracles As Evidence for the Existence of God
    Luther Seminary Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary Faculty Publications Faculty & Staff Scholarship 2017 Miracles as Evidence for the Existence of God Alan G. Padgett Luther Seminary, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.luthersem.edu/faculty_articles Part of the Christianity Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Padgett, Alan G., "Miracles as Evidence for the Existence of God" (2017). Faculty Publications. 335. https://digitalcommons.luthersem.edu/faculty_articles/335 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty & Staff Scholarship at Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. CHAPTER 9 Miracles as Evidence for the Existence of God Alan G. Padgett Professor of Systematic Theology Luther Seminary, St. Paul, MN Miracle claims are common throughout the world and in most religious traditions. The most common miracles appear to be those of healing, but other types also appear across cultures and ages. The discussion in this chapter is limited to monotheistic systems and to Western thought. The European rationalist age was the first in which philosophers and scientists openly doubted the reality of miracles. In that context the sciences, rather than religion, became the model of truth wherein miracles were dismissed as unscientific superstition. Granted, not everyone today thinks that the sciences explain everything worth knowing. Nevertheless, rationalism and a mechanistic worldview created skepticism toward the very idea of miracles, and this attitude is with us still.
    [Show full text]