The Metaphysics of Divine Causation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Metaphysics of Divine Causation The Metaphysics of Divine Causation THE METAPHYSICS OF DIVINE CAUSATION Danielle Helen Adams Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Leeds School of Philosophy, Religion, and History of Science July 2016 [i] The Metaphysics of Divine Causation The candidate confirms that the work submitted is her own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. © 2016 The University of Leeds and Danielle Helen Adams The right of Danielle Helen Adams to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted by her in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. [ii] The Metaphysics of Divine Causation ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS There are many, many people I would like to thank for their encouragement and support over the years. This thesis could not have been completed, had I not been surrounded by such kind, generous, and lovely people, and I thank every single person who has helped get me here. I would like to begin by thanking the School of PRHS at Leeds for awarding me a Graduate Teaching Assistantship, which funded me for the first three years of my PhD. Even though the teaching has been very time consuming, it’s something I’ve very much enjoyed, and I value the experience greatly. My thanks also to the Royal Institute of Philosophy, whose generous Jacobsen Studentship provided me with much needed funding in my fourth year. Many people along the way have inspired me to pursue my studies in philosophy. I thank Ms. Bull at the Bulmershe School, who helped to spark my initial interest in the subject, and whose kind words gave me the confidence to pursue the subject at university. Thanks also to John Divers, Bob Hale, Rosanna Keefe, Steven Makin, and Eric Olsen, whose teaching at Sheffield University was exceptional, and who helped me to realise that metaphysics was my biggest passion. I also benefitted greatly from excellent teaching whilst studying for my MA at Leeds, particularly from Elizabeth Barnes, Ross Cameron, Robin Le Poidevin, Andrew McGonigal, and Scott Shalkowski. Leeds has been a fantastic place to conduct postgraduate research. The office staff have always been lovely to me, and I thank each of the following people for being fantastic colleagues, and for giving the department such a friendly atmosphere: Denise Aston, Sarah Cason, Trish Davies, Louise Hawksworth, Charlie Heslop, Jo Luff, Jenneke Stevens, and Roz Walsh. My friends in HPS have also been fantastic colleagues. Each of them has provided much needed banter and friendship, but I would particularly like to thank Becky Bowd, Liz Bruton, Clare O’Reilly, Sean McNally, and Laura Sellers. I have also benefited greatly from studying at a department which has such fantastic lecturers – these people have been an inspiration to me, and I have learned a lot just from spending time with them. There are too many to mention, but I particularly thank the following people who have not already been mentioned: Mikel Burley, Daniel Elstein, Steven French, Simon Hewitt, Gerald Lang, Heather Logue, Tasia Scrutton, Pekka Väyrynen, Robbie Williams, and Mark Wynn. Thank you also to Nick Jones and Adrian Wilson, for their wisdom, and for helping me to keep my head above by employing me as their assistant and gardener respectively – jobs I’ve very much enjoyed. I’d also like to extend my gratitude to Penny Tharratt and Leslie Geary, whose guidance and support has been very valuable to me. I thank my family very much for their love, support, and encouragement, even though I’m not sure any of them knows exactly what it is I’ve been doing all these years – or why! [iii] The Metaphysics of Divine Causation Endless amounts of love and gratitude to my Mum, Dad, Grandad, late Grandmother, and brothers Ben and Matthew. To my non-academic friends, especially Oliver Farrell, Becca Hartley, and Matthew Peter Dean, I am sorry I haven’t seen nearly enough of you for the past few years, but thank you for always being there for me. I will be seeing much more of you from now on! I have loved my time at Leeds and this is largely because of the amazing postgraduate community here. I have met many people over the years who have made this a great place to study and socialise. Again, there are too many to mention, but I give my love and thanks especially to: John Baldari, Jordan Bartol, Marc Cole, Dave Cornell, John Fernley, James Fraser, Lewis Hickley, Christina Nick, Olof Leffler, Adam Patel-Somers, Christina Nick, Will Perry, Rob Pezet, Sam Symons, Alison Toop, James Rimmer, Liz Watkins, and Marc Wilcox. Very importantly, I would like to express my heartfelt thanks to my supervisors, who have been extremely kind, supportive, generous and patient with me. Robin Le Poidevin and Helen Steward are two of the nicest people I’ve ever met; they’ve been the best supervisors I could have wished for, and their thinking has influenced me massively. I thank Robin particularly for helping me to think through the big-picture stuff, and for helping me to come up with the thesis proposal in the first place. I thank Helen particularly for the tea, the kind notes which were always left at the end of my work, and the encouragement to defend my own view. Thanks too to Jason Turner, who also supervised me for the first two years of my PhD – although my time with him was limited, I learned a lot from him, and the chapter on counterfactuals benefited hugely from his advice. For going above and beyond the call of duty as friends and colleagues and for putting up with me the longest I thank Jon Banks, Mike Bench-Capon, Thomas Brouwer, Rich Caves, Jade Fletcher, Will Gamester, Emily Paul, Jon Robson, Nahuel Sznajderhaus, Nick Tasker, and Carl Warom. You people are the best – big love to you all. Extra special heartfelt thanks goes to my sister, Sarah, for giving me endless amounts of her time and thoughts. She has proof-read every single word in this thesis and has talked through every single idea with me. I would not have done this without her support and encouragement. If this thesis is half as good as hers, I’ll be very happy indeed. Lastly, but very importantly, infinite love and thanks to my partner, Jo, who has given me endless amounts of love, support, and kindness – always with a smile on her face, despite the stress of completing a doctorate in Clinical Psychology herself. I could not have done this without her. [iv] The Metaphysics of Divine Causation ABSTRACT It is something of an orthodoxy that the nature of causation can be characterised by the following metaphysical theses: that causes do not necessitate their effects, that causes must temporally precede their effects, that causation is governed by laws of nature, that causation entails counterfactual dependence, and that causation is not systematically overdetermined. Two further commonly accepted metaphysical claims are that causal notions give us the correct tools to properly understand agency, and that the causes of actions are mental events. Classical theism, however, is comprised by certain commitments which seem to be in direct tension with each of these metaphysical theses. God is understood to be causally efficacious – a divine being who creates, sustains, and intervenes in worldly affairs – and so who is, indeed the, paradigmatic causal agent. Further, God is said to be atemporal, non-physical, and such that he exists independently of all else. The God of classical theism is also characterised as being omnipotent, at least in the sense that whatever he wills to be the case cannot fail to be the case. The apparent tension between these metaphysical theses which concern causation and those which concern God thus threaten the very coherence of the notion of divine causality. The goal of this thesis is therefore to examine these prima facie theistically problematic theses concerning causation, and to consider ways of making room for a coherent notion of divine causality. In some cases, it will argue that certain causal theses ought to be rejected, in others, it will find ways of resolving the tension. [v] The Metaphysics of Divine Causation TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ................................................................................................................. iii ABSTRACT ............................................................................................................................................ v LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ............................................................................................................. ix INTRODUCTION & OUTLINE ...................................................................................................... x I: DIVINE CAUSATION & NECESSITY ..................................................................................... 1 1. Introduction .......................................................................................................................... 1 2. The Argument from Logically Sufficient Conditions ....................................... 1 2.1 The Argument .............................................................................................................. 1 2.2 An Anticipated Objection to [P1] ..................................................................... 3 2.3 [P1] and Humean Considerations .....................................................................
Recommended publications
  • In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics Versus Science
    To appear in Journal for General Philosophy of Science (2004) In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics versus Science F.A. Muller Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Mathematics Utrecht University, P.O. Box 80.000 3508 TA Utrecht, The Netherlands E-mail: [email protected] August 2003 Summary Over the past years, in books and journals (this journal included), N. Maxwell launched a ferocious attack on B.C. van Fraassen's view of science called Con- structive Empiricism (CE). This attack has been totally ignored. Must we con- clude from this silence that no defence is possible against the attack and that a fortiori Maxwell has buried CE once and for all, or is the attack too obviously flawed as not to merit exposure? We believe that neither is the case and hope that a careful dissection of Maxwell's reasoning will make this clear. This dis- section includes an analysis of Maxwell's `aberrance-argument' (omnipresent in his many writings) for the contentious claim that science implicitly and per- manently accepts a substantial, metaphysical thesis about the universe. This claim generally has been ignored too, for more than a quarter of a century. Our con- clusions will be that, first, Maxwell's attacks on CE can be beaten off; secondly, his `aberrance-arguments' do not establish what Maxwell believes they estab- lish; but, thirdly, we can draw a number of valuable lessons from these attacks about the nature of science and of the libertarian nature of CE. Table of Contents on other side −! Contents 1 Exordium: What is Maxwell's Argument? 1 2 Does Science Implicitly Accept Metaphysics? 3 2.1 Aberrant Theories .
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 086 604 SO 006 822 AUTHOR Norris, Jack A., Jr. TITLE Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla. PUB DATE 72 NOTE 20p.; Authorized Course of Instruction for the Quinmester Program EDRS PRICE MF-$0.65 HC-$3.29 DESCRIPTORS Course Objectives; Curriculum Guides; Grade 10; Grade 11; Grade 12; *Language Arts; Learnin4 Activities; *Logic; Non Western Civilization; *Philosophy; Resource Guides; Secondary Grades; *Social Studies; *Social Studies Units; Western Civilization IDENTIFIERS *Quinmester Program ABSTRACT Western and non - western philosophers and their ideas are introduced to 10th through 12th grade students in this general social studies Quinmester course designed to be used as a preparation for in-depth study of the various schools of philosophical thought. By acquainting students with the questions and categories of philosophy, a point of departure for further study is developed. Through suggested learning activities the meaning of philosopky is defined. The Socratic, deductive, inductive, intuitive and eclectic approaches to philosophical thought are examined, as are three general areas of philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology,and axiology. Logical reasoning is applied to major philosophical questions. This course is arranged, as are other quinmester courses, with sections on broad goals, course content, activities, and materials. A related document is ED 071 937.(KSM) FILMED FROM BEST AVAILABLE COPY U S DEPARTMENT EDUCATION OF HEALTH. NAT10N41
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow*
    1 Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow* Raphaël Millière École normale supérieure, Paris – October 2011 Translated by Mark Ohm with the assistance of Leah Orth, Jon Cogburn, and Emily Beck Cogburn “By metaphysics, I do not mean those abstract considerations of certain imaginary properties, the principal use of which is to furnish the wherewithal for endless dispute to those who want to dispute. By this science I mean the general truths which can serve as principles for the particular sciences.” Malebranche Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion 1. The interminable agony of metaphysics Throughout the twentieth century, numerous philosophers sounded the death knell of metaphysics. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rudolf Carnap, Martin Heidegger, Gilbert Ryle, J. L. Austin, Jacques Derrida, Jürgen Habermas, Richard Rorty, and, henceforth, Hilary Putnam: a great many tutelary figures have extolled the rejection, the exceeding, the elimination, or the deconstruction of first philosophy. All these necrological chronicles do not have the same radiance, the same seriousness, nor the same motivations, but they all agree to dismiss the discipline, which in the past was considered “the queen of the sciences”, with a violence at times comparable to the prestige it commanded at the time of its impunity. Even today, certain philosophers hastily spread the tragic news with contempt for philosophical inquiry, as if its grave solemnity bestowed upon it some obviousness. Thus, Franco Volpi writes: ‘Grand metaphysics is dead!’ is the slogan which applies to the majority of contemporary philosophers, whether continentals or of analytic profession. They all treat metaphysics as a dead dog.1 In this way, the “path of modern thought” would declare itself vociferously “anti- metaphysical and finally post-metaphysical”.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Analysis of Immanuel Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics Of
    International Journal of Research and Review www.ijrrjournal.com E-ISSN: 2349-9788; P-ISSN: 2454-2237 Original Research Article A Critical Analysis of Immanuel Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Abraham Tsehay Jemberie Debre Berhan University, Debre Berhan, Ethiopia ABSTRACT Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), a German philosopher, is considered as the father of modern ethics and one of the great philosophers in the history of philosophy. He wanted to establish firm foundation for moral philosophy. He contributed something new to modern ethics which was not attempted by earlier ethicists. He wanted to show by using reason that morality is based on a single supreme universal principle, which is binding to all rational beings. Precisely, Kant wanted to establish the first principle of morality which neglects all consideration of self-interest and even particular human problems. In the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant claimed that his intention is to seek out and establish the supreme principle of morality, and that supreme principle is the categorical imperative. He puts the supreme principle of morality or the categorical imperative in at least five ways. These are formula of universal law (FUL), formula of universal law (FLN), formula of humanity (FH), formula of humanity (FA), and formula of realm of ends (FRE). However, Kant affirms that there is one canonical and general formulation of the categorical imperative and it is the FUL. For him, the other formulas are not distinct ethical principles; rather they are the reformulations or variant formulations of the single categorical imperative. Kant put this position in his works, The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals.
    [Show full text]
  • Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics CAMBRIDGE TEXTS in the HISTORY of PHILOSOPHY
    CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY IMMANUEL KANT Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Series editors KARL AMERIKS Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame DESMOND M. CLARKE Professor of Philosophy at University College Cork The main objective of Cambridge Textsin the History of Philosophy is to expand the range, variety and quality of texts in the history of philosophy which are available in English. The series includes texts by familiar names (such as Descartes and Kant) and also by less well-known authors. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each volume contains a critical introduction together with a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and textual apparatus. The volumes are designed for student use at undergraduate and postgraduate level and will be of interest not only to students of philosophy, but also to a wider audience of readers in the history of science, the history of theology and the history of ideas. For a list of titles published in the series, please see end of book. IMMANUEL KANT Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science with Selections from the Critique of Pure Reason TRANSLATED AND EDITED BY GARY HATFIELD University of Pennsylvania Revised Edition cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521828246 © Cambridge University Press 1997, 2004 This publication is in copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • Field Epistemology Metaphysics
    To appear in Philosophical Studies, 2009. Online publication January 2009, available on springerlink.com: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9338-1. Epistemology without Metaphysics Hartry Field A common picture of justification among epistemologists is that typically when a person is looking at something red, her sense impressions pump in a certain amount of justification for the belief that there is something red in front of her; but that there can be contrary considerations (e.g. testimony by others that there is nothing red there, at least when backed by evidence that the testimony is reliable) that may pump some of this justification out. In addition, the justification provided by the senses can be fully or partially undercut, say by evidence that the lighting may be bad: this involves creating a leak (perhaps only a small one) in the pipe from sense impressions to belief, so that not all of the justification gets through. On this picture, the job of the epistemologist is to come up with an epistemological dipstick that will measure what overall level of justification we end up with in any given situation. (Presumably the “fluid” to be measured is immaterial, so it takes advanced training in recent epistemological techniques to come up with an accurate dipstick.) Of course there are plenty of variations in the details of this picture. For instance, it may be debated what exactly are the sources of the justificatory fluid. (Does testimony unaided by evidence of its reliability produce justification? Do “logical intuitions” produce it? And so on.) Indeed, coherentists claim that the idea of sources has to be broadened: build a complex enough array of pipes and the fluid will automatically appear to fill them.
    [Show full text]
  • Edwards Metaphysics of Truth Review
    Book Review The Metaphysics of Truth, by Douglas Edwards. Oxford University Press, 2018, 208pp. Published in Mind 128(511) 2019, 970–976 https://doi-org.ezproxy.nottingham.ac.uk/10.1093/mind/fzy066 There’s recently been a revival of interest in what truth is. For a long time, deflationism ruled the roost, telling us that there’s not much of metaphysical interest in studying truth. Metaphysicians turned their attention to truthmaking and, for the most part, didn’t connect their findings to theories of truth. But the pendulum swings back. Enter Douglas Edwards’s The Metaphysics of Truth, which boldly sets out a theory of truth in the grand old style. In fact, you get not one but several theories of truth, for Edwards is a pluralist about truth. Traditional realist correspondence theories are fine as far as they go; as are (broadly anti-realist) pragmatist theories. Each works well within its own domain, but none covers all the cases. Some truths are true because they correspond to mind-independent states of affairs. Others are true because they possess a warrant which would survive arbitrarily close scrutiny and improvement in information (they are superassertible). Nevertheless, being true is a unified property, not a ‘mere disjunction’, as it satisfies the conceptual platitudes governing our concept of truth. Edwards starts by arguing that being true is a genuine property (chapter 1) and, more importantly, that it is a substantial property, with a nature we can investigate metaphysically (chapters 2 and 3). Pluralism about truth emerges in chapters 4 and 5. Edwards then claims that its nature cannot be given purely by any traditional approach to truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Metaphysics of the Self
    Philosophers’ volume 10, no. 8 ot many philosophers would turn to Kant for a positive view august 2010 about the metaphysics of the self (the referent of ‘I’). On the Imprint N contrary, most of Kant’s interpreters read him as warning that any attempt to give a positive account of the self’s nature is doomed to failure, and as building his theories without metaphysical assump- tions about the self.1 This broad interpretive approach, which I’ll call the “anti-metaphysical interpretation,” often sees Kant’s project as an- Kant’s Metaphysics ticipating Wittgenstein’s claims that the self or subject “doesn’t belong to the world, but is a limit of the world.”2 In some form or other, the anti-metaphysical interpretation is pres- ent in all major discussions of Kant’s views on the self. In a 1993 sur- of the Self vey of the literature, Günter Zöller stated that “[d]ifferences of method and philosophical approach aside, the interpretations … show a re- markable agreement in their understanding of Kant’s thinking self as a form or structure that eludes any attempt at reification.”3 The consen- sus now is similar — for instance, in the most recent book on the topic Arthur Melnick argues that in Kant’s theoretical philosophy the self should be understood as something like an activity precisely because this avoids construing it as an entity of any sort.4 In what follows, I argue that not only is the anti-metaphysical in- terpretation mistaken, but that Kant offers us a subtle, plausible meta- physical account of the self that has no direct analogue in the contem- porary literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Translated by W
    Aristotle Metaphysics translated by W. D. Ross Book Α 1 All men by nature desire to know. An indication of this is the delight we take in our senses; for even apart from their usefulness they are loved for themselves; and above all others the sense of sight. For not only with a view to action, but even when we are not going to do anything, we prefer seeing (one might say) to everything else. The reason is that this, most of all the senses, makes us know and brings to light many differences between things. By nature animals are born with the faculty of sensation, and from sensation memory is produced in some of them, though not in others. And therefore the former are more intelligent and apt at learning than those which cannot remember; those which are incapable of hearing sounds are intelligent though they cannot be taught, e.g. the bee, and any other race of animals that may be like it; and those which besides memory have this sense of hearing can be taught. The animals other than man live by appearances and memories, and have but little of connected experience; but the human race lives also by art and reasonings. Now from memory experience is produced in men; for the several memories of the same thing produce finally the capacity for a single experience. And experience seems pretty much like science and art, but really science and art come to men through experience; for ‘experience made art’, as Polus says, ‘but inexperience luck.’ Now art arises when from many notions gained by experience one universal judgement about a class of objects is produced.
    [Show full text]
  • Husserl's Early Concept of Metaphysics As the Ultimate
    Husserl’s Early Concept of Metaphysics As the Ultimate Science of Reality Emiliano Trizio University of the West of England [email protected] Reception date: 04-10-2017 Acceptance date: 13-11-2017 Abstract This article reconstructs the development of Husserl’s definition of metaphysics as the ultimate science of reality in the courses and lectures written up to the year 1905. The analysis of these texts casts light on Husserl’s philosophical self-understanding in the wider context of late Nineteenth Century German philosophy as well as on the fundamental role that metaphysical interests played in the development of his thought from its earliest stage. A particular attention is devoted to Husserl’s early views about the relation between the theory of knowledge and metaphysics, whose analysis is a necessary preliminary step to address the theoretical issue of the relation between transcendental phenomenology and metaphysics. Keywords: Husserl, Metaphysics, Theory of Knowledge, Phenomenology 1. Introduction The relation between Husserl’s thought and metaphysics has been approached in a number of different ways. The questions that, by far, have attracted more attention since Husserl’s own time revolve around the so-called metaphysical neutrality of phenomenology. In particular, readers of Husserl have tried to understand whether pre-transcendental phenomenology could be considered in some sense “metaphysically neutral”1 and whether and to what extent the 1 See, for instance, Benoist 1997, Zahavi 2001. transcendental turn implies forsaking such neutrality or, perhaps, even embracing a form of metaphysical idealism. Consequently, a number of publications address questions such as whether phenomenological idealism is itself a metaphysical thesis, or whether it has metaphysical implications at all2.
    [Show full text]
  • On Philosophy of Mind, Quantum Physics and Metaphysics of the Uni-Multiverse
    On philosophy of mind, quantum physics and metaphysics of the uni-multiverse Paolo Di Sia1-3 1School of Science & School of Medicine (Department of Neuroscience), University of Padova, Via Jappelli 1, 35121 Padova, Italy 2Faculty of Science and Technology, Free University of Bozen-Bolzano, Piazza Università 5, 39100 Bozen-Bolzano, Italy 3Corresponding author e-mail address: [email protected] Abstract Metaphysics, as discipline dealing with the most fundamental aspects of reality, studies the essence of entities, leaving to particular sciences the study of empirical, specific, changeable and unstable aspects. In this sense metaphysics is close to ontology, tackling problems as the existence of God, the being in himself, the immortality of consciousness, the origin and meaning of the universe. Speculative physics pushes its interest to metaphysical questions too, both at a technical (mathematical) level, and at the level of thought (in relation to philosophy). In recent years interesting concepts and ideas have been considered and developed, involving the latest unified quantum-relativistic theories and the consequences on reality deriving from them. The search for a meaning of life, one of Anscombe’s themes, finds ferment in the search for meaning about the existence of our universe in itself and as a possible part of a multiverse containing it. The problem of measurement in quantum mechanics appears from the application of the mathematical formalism to macroscopic situations and the central position of the observer in this process has produced a deviation towards a metaphysical subjectivism. There are controversial aspects about the role of consciousness in the process of reducing the wave function of quantum mechanics.
    [Show full text]
  • Storozhenko, Mykyta, Ma May 2020
    STOROZHENKO, MYKYTA, M.A. MAY 2020 PHILOSOPHY PHENOMENOLOGY AND METAPHYSICAL REALISM (72 pp.) Thesis Advisor: Gina Zavota The recent re-turn to metaphysical realism in Continental Philosophy, evident in the emergence of the Speculative Realism movement, has posed challenging questions to phenomenology. Most importantly, is phenomenology compatible with metaphysical realism? Meillassoux, Harman, and Sparrow charge phenomenology with being, respectively, correlationist, a philosophy of access, and metaphysically agnostic or idealist. However, their charges do not go unanswered. Zahavi responds to the challenges by pointing out how phenomenology is compatible with, and indeed inclined toward realism. He does so by looking at concrete interactions between phenomenology and realism, as well as addressing what realism is and what it entails within phenomenology. Following Zahavi, as well as my own investigation into Husserl's phenomenology, I conclude that phenomenology is compatible with metaphysical realism. PHENOMENOLOGY AND METAPHYSICAL REALISM A thesis submitted To Kent State University in partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Mykyta Storozhenko May 2020 © Copyright All rights reserved Except for previously publised materials Thesis writted by Mykyta Storozhenko B.A., Florida Atlantic University, 2018 M.A., Kent State University, 2020 Approved by Gina Zavota , Advisor Michael Byron , Chair, Department of Philosophy James L. Blank , Dean, College of Arts and Sciences TABLE OF CONTENTS------------------------------------------------------------------------------------iv
    [Show full text]