Seeing Difference: the Ethics and Epistemology of Stereotyping By

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Seeing Difference: the Ethics and Epistemology of Stereotyping By ! ! ! ! ! Seeing Difference: The Ethics and! Epistemology of Stereotyping ! By! ! Erin Marie! Beeghly ! A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the degree requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley ! Committee in charge: Professor Véronique Munoz-Dardé, Co-Chair Professor R. Jay Wallace, Co-Chair Professor Victoria! Plaut ! ! Spring! 2014 ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! Abstract Seeing Difference: The Ethics and Epistemology of Stereotyping by Erin Marie Beeghly Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professor Véronique Munoz-Dardé, Co-Chair Professor R. Jay Wallace, Co-Chair ! When we call something a stereotype, we tend to mean it as a criticism. If someone says, “Asians are good at math” or “women are empathetic,” for example, I might interject, “You’re stereotyping” in order to convey my disapproval of their utterance. But why is stereotyping wrong? One tempting idea is that stereotyping fails to treat persons as individuals. Yet this idea itself is puzzling. How should we understand it? One possibility, to which many people are drawn, is to articulate the wrong in epistemic terms: we see the world in an incorrect way when we stereotype. Call this the epistemic hypothesis about the wrong of stereotyping. Another pos- sibility is that the relevant failure is moral in nature: stereotyping is always morally wrong. In this dissertation, I consider both the epistemic and moral hypotheses and show that neither is de- fensible. Actually, stereotyping can be morally and epistemically permissible. One upshot is that we must give up the idea that stereotyping as such is wrong and think more carefully about how to distinguish permissible and impermissible cases. I argue that there will be no simple way to make this distinction, as there is no one wrong—epistemic or moral—that unifies all bad cas- es. So we must be pluralists about what’s wrong with stereotyping. Moreover, we must recog- nize that the wrongs of stereotyping are purely extrinsic in nature, i.e., due to bad causes or con- sequences rather than due to features intrinsic to the very act of stereotyping. A second upshot is that we must think of stereotyping as normatively diverse: sometimes epistemic and moral norms prohibit it; other times, they do not. Epistemic and moral norms also have the potential to con- flict in specific cases: a person might be epistemically rational to stereotype even if stereotyping is seriously objectionable from a moral point of view. I examine cases of alleged conflict and argue that, in fact, bona fide conflicts between moral and epistemic norms are far rarer than one would expect. Moreover, I demonstrate that—despite first appearances—they do not present tragic normative dilemmas in which people are forced to choose between morality and epistemic rationality. People can do the right thing without being irrational. ! #1 ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! To my mother and father, Amy and Brian! Beeghly. ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! #i ! Acknowledgements! !This dissertation could not have been written without the help of a great many people. The philosophy department and graduate division at Berkeley have been generous in offering me both fellowships and teaching throughout my eight years of graduate school. My first year of graduate work was funded by the Frank and Patricia Yeary Fellowship for Ethics in the Humani- ties. I also received year-long dissertation fellowships from the Townsend Center for Humanities at Berkeley in 2011-12 and the American Association for University Women in 2012-13. A spe- cial thanks to Mary Ann Mason for securing normative time funding for me and all other UC Berkeley grads in her tenure as dean of the Graduate Division at Berkeley. I also want to thank Suzanne Martinez and Mark Zimmelman of Lang Antiques. Had I not worked at Lang through- out my undergraduate and graduate careers, I would have been neither financially solvent nor !half as happy as I actually was. Friends helped to emotionally sustain me throughout the long road to finishing and to make life good: Richard Frey, Jing Jacobs, Laura McKee, Courtney Dillon, Kimberly Conley, Nandini Pandey, Katrina Winzeler, Benjamin Boudreaux, Annie McClanahan and Ted Martin, Lindsey Crawford and Anna Bailey, Lisa Igelesias and Paul Gerlitz, Aja Gabel and Katie Bellas, Nicola Maayan and Katie Wood, Stephanie Soileau and Harriet Clark. Here my family deserves special !thanks, especially my mother and sister Alison, for always picking up the phone. I have also been blessed with a supportive community of scholars. I came to this topic—stereo- typing—through a seminar at Boalt School of Law in Fall of 2009 with psychologist Victoria Plaut. Véronique Munoz-Dardé convinced me of its philosophical worth. She, Mike Martin, Vicky, and Jay Wallace helped me to develop and revise the arguments presented here. I owe whatever is correct in the manuscript to them. Other faculty members generously shared their time and expertise with me: Lara Buchak, John Campbell, Niko Kolodny, Tania Lombrozo, and A.J. Julius, who sponsored me during a visiting semester at UCLA in Spring 2011. I would also like to thank audiences at the Birbeck College, L’École des Hautes Études, the University of Utah, the Townsend Center for Humanities at Berkeley, Princeton’s Political Theory Conference, the Implicit Bias Conference at the University of Sheffield, and the Society for Applied Philoso- phy Annual Conference for thought-provoking discussions. Special thanks to Sally Haslanger, Rae Langton, Sarah-Jane Leslie, Kate Manne, Jennifer Saul, and Jacob Stegenga—and also my !Berkeley colleagues Alex Madva, Joseph Barnes, Lindsay Crawford, and Katrina Winzeler. ! A few people deserve to be singled out for special thanks. Véronique Munoz-Dardé has been like a second mother to me. She and Mike Martin have been a constant presence in my life since I arrived for graduate school at Berkeley, and I thank the stars for sending them my way. To my mother, Amy Beeghly, I owe my love of reading and writing—and my sense of possibility in the world. To my husband and favorite poet, Joshua Rivkin, I owe both my sanity and daily happi- ness. You are my Vera, and I am yours. May we grow old together and keep our patience with !the incomparable Esme Rivkin, who always smiles, even when she fails to sleep. ! #ii Table of Contents! ! !Introduction 1 !Chapter 1: What are Stereotypes? What is Stereotyping? 5 !Chapter 2: What’s the Wrong of Stereotyping? The Epistemic Hypothesis 28 !Chapter 3: What’s the Wrong of Stereotyping? The Moral Hypothesis 49 Chapter 4: Normative Conflict in Cases of Stereotyping: ! Does Morality Require Stupidity? 70 !Conclusion 102 Bibliography ! 106 ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! #iii ! ! Introduction Human societies are marked by diversity and difference: ethnic and racial difference, gender dif- ference, religious difference, sexual difference, difference in age and ability, difference in social !status and wealth, in professional status and political affiliation. Faced with diversity, humans stereotype. We seek to find order in the world, to classify people as types, and to imbue these classifications with meaning. We generalize. We form expectations about individuals based on the groups to which they belong. It is hard to imagine human psy- chology without these tendencies, essential as they are for simplifying and understanding a com- !plex social environment. But for these tendencies, we would not be fully rational. Nonetheless, stereotyping is problematic. Stereotypes have the reputation of being false, unreli- able views of social groups. Deemed uniformly bad, they have been associated with cultural im- perialism, prejudice, oppression, and all manner of moral and political evil. Moreover, stereo- typing is thought to be inherently objectionable. “You’re stereotyping,” an interlocutor might interject, if I say something like “Asians are bad drivers” or joke that this or that Asian person !will be terrible behind the wheel. These reflections should bother us. What are stereotypes, exactly? How do they affect judgment and behavior? Is stereotyping always morally wrong? Is it ever rational? In so far as stereo- types are part and parcel of how we cope with a diverse social world, what’s wrong with stereo- !typing? In chapter 1, I introduce readers to the psychological literature on stereotypes and stereotyping. Then I argue for what I call the descriptive view of stereotyping. According to this view, stereo- types can be expressed in speech—for example, when we say things like “little girls wear pink” or “doctors wear white coats.” However, we cannot not think of stereotypes as generic proposi- tions about social groups, which are typically expressed in speech acts. After all, we know that stereotypes can influence people’s plans, expectations, and actions even if they are not expressed in public, either directly or indirectly. We must therefore think of stereotypes as having a psy- chological reality, and it becomes tempting to identify them with concepts or as associated with the use or formation of concepts. To stereotype, according to the descriptive view, is thus to em- ploy a generalized view of groups associated with one’s concepts or their formation or use. In the chapter's last part, I consider an objection to the descriptive view, namely, that it does not in- clude the idea that stereotyping is always problematic. I argue that this is actually a benefit of the view. Moreover, I demonstrate that the view is not question begging: it is consistent with the idea that stereotyping is, in fact, always problematic. One would have to argue for that conclu- !sion, however; it wouldn’t follow merely from the term’s definition. In chapter 2, I begin to investigate claim that stereotyping is always wrong. One tempting idea— just mentioned—is that stereotyping fails to treat persons as individuals. Yet this idea itself is #1 puzzling.
Recommended publications
  • Conjunction Fallacy' Revisited: How Intelligent Inferences Look Like Reasoning Errors
    Journal of Behavioral Decision Making J. Behav. Dec. Making, 12: 275±305 (1999) The `Conjunction Fallacy' Revisited: How Intelligent Inferences Look Like Reasoning Errors RALPH HERTWIG* and GERD GIGERENZER Max Planck Institute for Human Development, Berlin, Germany ABSTRACT Findings in recent research on the `conjunction fallacy' have been taken as evid- ence that our minds are not designed to work by the rules of probability. This conclusion springs from the idea that norms should be content-blind Ð in the present case, the assumption that sound reasoning requires following the con- junction rule of probability theory. But content-blind norms overlook some of the intelligent ways in which humans deal with uncertainty, for instance, when drawing semantic and pragmatic inferences. In a series of studies, we ®rst show that people infer nonmathematical meanings of the polysemous term `probability' in the classic Linda conjunction problem. We then demonstrate that one can design contexts in which people infer mathematical meanings of the term and are therefore more likely to conform to the conjunction rule. Finally, we report evidence that the term `frequency' narrows the spectrum of possible interpreta- tions of `probability' down to its mathematical meanings, and that this fact Ð rather than the presence or absence of `extensional cues' Ð accounts for the low proportion of violations of the conjunction rule when people are asked for frequency judgments. We conclude that a failure to recognize the human capacity for semantic and pragmatic inference can lead rational responses to be misclassi®ed as fallacies. Copyright # 1999 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. KEY WORDS conjunction fallacy; probabalistic thinking; frequentistic thinking; probability People's apparent failures to reason probabilistically in experimental contexts have raised serious concerns about our ability to reason rationally in real-world environments.
    [Show full text]
  • Author's Personal Copy
    Author's personal copy Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 35 (2011) 1042–1051 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/neubiorev Review Human threat management systems: Self•protection and disease avoidance Steven L. Neuberg a,∗, Douglas T. Kenrick a, Mark Schaller b a Department of Psychology, Arizona State University, Tempe, AZ 85287•1104, United States b Department of Psychology, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada V6T 1Z4 article info abstract Article history: Humans likely evolved precautionary systems designed to minimize the threats to reproductive fitness Received 8 March 2010 posed by highly interdependent ultrasociality. A review of research on the self•protection and disease Received in revised form 18 August 2010 avoidance systems reveals that each system is functionally distinct and domain•specific: each is attuned Accepted 18 August 2010 to different cues; engages different emotions, inferences, and behavioral inclinations; and is rooted in somewhat different neurobiological substrates. These systems share important features, however. Each Keywords: system is functionally coherent, in that perceptual, affective, cognitive, and behavioral processes work Self•protection in concert to reduce fitness costs of potential threats. Each system is biased in a risk•averse manner, Disease avoidance Threat management erring toward precautionary responses even when available cues only heuristically imply threat. And Precautionary psychology each system is functionally flexible, being highly sensitive to specific ecological and dispositional cues Evolutionary psychology that signal greater vulnerability to the relevant threat. These features characterize a general template Domain specificity useful for understanding not only the self•protection and disease avoidance systems, but also a broader Fear set of evolved, domain•specific precautionary systems.
    [Show full text]
  • The Availability Heuristic
    CHAPTER 11 THE AVAILABILITY HEURISTIC According to Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman (1974, p. 1127), the availability heuristic is a rule of thumb in which decision makers "assess the frequency of a class or the probability of an event by the ease with which instances or occurrences can be brought to mind." Usually this heuristic works quite well; all things being equal, common events are easier to remember or imagine than are uncommon events. By rely­ ing on availability to estimate frequency and probability, decision mak­ ers are able to simplify what might otherwise be very difficult judg­ ments. As with any heuristic, however, there are cases in which the general rule of thumb breaks down and leads to systematic biases. Some events are more available than others not because they tend to occur frequently or with high probability, but because they are inherently easier to think about, because they have taken place recently, because they are highly emotional, and so forth. This chapter examines three general questions: (1) What are instances in which the availability heuristic leads to biased judgments? (2) Do decision makers perceive an event as more likely after they have imagined it happening? (3) How is vivid information dif­ ferent from other information? AVAILABILITY GOES AWRY Which is a more likely cause of death in the United States-being killed by falling airplane parts or by a shark? Most people rate shark attacks as more probable than death from falling airplane parts (see Item #7 of the Reader Survey for your answer). Shark attacks certainly receive more publicity than do deaths from falling airplane parts, and they are far easier to imagine (thanks in part to movies such as Jaws).
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking About the Ultimate Argument for Realism∗
    Thinking About the Ultimate Argument for Realism∗ Stathis Psillos Department of Philosophy and History of Science University of Athens Panepistimioupolis (University Campus) Athens 15771 Greece [email protected] 1. Introduction Alan Musgrave has been one of the most passionate defenders of scientific realism. Most of his papers in this area are, by now, classics. The title of my paper alludes to Musgrave’s piece “The Ultimate Argument for Realism”, though the expression is Bas van Fraassen’s (1980, 39), and the argument is Hilary Putnam’s (1975, 73): realism “is the only philosophy of science that does not make the success of science a miracle”. Hence, the code-name ‘no-miracles’ argument (henceforth, NMA). In fact, NMA has quite a history and a variety of formulations. I have documented all this in my (1999, chapter 4). But, no matter how exactly the argument is formulated, its thrust is that the success of scientific theories lends credence to the following two theses: a) that scientific theories should be interpreted realistically and b) that, so interpreted, these theories are approximately true. The original authors of the argument, however, did not put an extra stress on novel predictions, which, as Musgrave (1988) makes plain, is the litmus test for the ability of any approach to science to explain the success of science. Here is why reference to novel predictions is crucial. Realistically understood, theories entail too many novel claims, most of them about unobservables (e.g., that ∗ I want to dedicate this paper to Alan Musgrave. His exceptional combination of clear-headed and profound philosophical thinking has been a model for me.
    [Show full text]
  • Graphical Techniques in Debiasing: an Exploratory Study
    GRAPHICAL TECHNIQUES IN DEBIASING: AN EXPLORATORY STUDY by S. Bhasker Information Systems Department Leonard N. Stern School of Business New York University New York, New York 10006 and A. Kumaraswamy Management Department Leonard N. Stern School of Business New York University New York, NY 10006 October, 1990 Center for Research on Information Systems Information Systems Department Leonard N. Stern School of Business New York University Working Paper Series STERN IS-90-19 Forthcoming in the Proceedings of the 1991 Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences Center for Digital Economy Research Stem School of Business IVorking Paper IS-90-19 Center for Digital Economy Research Stem School of Business IVorking Paper IS-90-19 2 Abstract Base rate and conjunction fallacies are consistent biases that influence decision making involving probability judgments. We develop simple graphical techniques and test their eflcacy in correcting for these biases. Preliminary results suggest that graphical techniques help to overcome these biases and improve decision making. We examine the implications of incorporating these simple techniques in Executive Information Systems. Introduction Today, senior executives operate in highly uncertain environments. They have to collect, process and analyze a deluge of information - most of it ambiguous. But, their limited information acquiring and processing capabilities constrain them in this task [25]. Increasingly, executives rely on executive information/support systems for various purposes like strategic scanning of their business environments, internal monitoring of their businesses, analysis of data available from various internal and external sources, and communications [5,19,32]. However, executive information systems are, at best, support tools. Executives still rely on their mental or cognitive models of their businesses and environments and develop heuristics to simplify decision problems [10,16,25].
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae - Miranda Fricker
    Curriculum Vitae - Miranda Fricker Date of birth: 12/3/1966 Academic address: Dept of Philosophy, University of Sheffield, 45 Victoria St, Sheffield S3 7QB. Email address: [email protected] Web page: http://www.shef.ac.uk/philosophy/staff/profiles/fricker Career & Education 2013 Leverhulme Major Research Fellow (2014-16) 2012 Professor of Philosophy, University of Sheffield 2011 Head of Philosophy Department, Birkbeck, University of London 2011 Assistant Dean for Postgraduate Research in the School of Social Science, History and Philosophy 2010 University of London Research Fellow, Institute of Philosophy, School of Advanced Study 2008 Promoted to Reader 2006 Promoted to Senior Lecturer 2000-12 Lecturer in Philosophy, Birkbeck College, University of London 1998-00 Lecturer in Philosophy, and British Academy Postdoctoral Fellow, Heythrop College, University of London 2000 Visiting Scholar, Dept of Philosophy, University of California, Berkeley 1997-98 British Academy Postdoctoral Fellow, Birkbeck College, University of London 1996 Awarded DPhil, Oxon 1995-97 Jacobsen Research Fellow, Birkbeck College, University of London 1991-96 Wolfson College, University of Oxford: DPhil in Philosophy 1994-95 Balliol College Lectureship 1992/94 Wolfson Graduate Prize 1989-90 University of Kent at Canterbury: MA in Women's Studies, Distinction 1985-88 Pembroke College, Oxford, BAHons 2.1 Philosophy & Modern Languages Teaching Areas of specialism: Ethics, Social Epistemology, Feminist Philosophy Curriculum design: In 2013-14 I served as Chair of the Working Party set up to design the mandatory first-year Faculty Challenge for the whole Arts & Humanities Faculty, University of Sheffield. In 2010 I set up the modular Philosophy MA at Birkbeck; in 2007 I successfully proposed an option in Gender & Philosophy for the London MPhilStud; previously in 2004 two colleagues and I introduced the University of London intercollegiate MA option in Gender & Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Contact Information
    REBECCA NEEL Department of Psychology Arizona State University Tempe, AZ 85287-1104 602-965-3326 EMPLOYMENT Beginning August, 2013 Assistant Professor, Department of Psychology, University of Iowa EDUCATION Ph.D., Psychology (May, 2013). Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona. Thesis: “Expert in the language of fear”: Stigmatized targets’ perception of others’ emotion-specific prejudice M.A., Psychology (2010). Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona. Thesis: When does seeing through your eyes help me? Emotions functionally encourage and inhibit perspective taking B.A., English Literature (2002). Carleton College, Northfield, Minnesota. Cum Laude AWARDS AND HONORS 2013 SPSP Graduate Student Travel Award 2012 SPSSI Grant-in-Aid for Dissertation Research 2012 The Robert B. Cialdini Dissertation Project Prize in Social Psychology, ASU 2012 The Darwyn and Marie Linder Fellowship in Experimental Social Psychology, ASU 2012 ASU Graduate and Professional Student Association Grant for Independent Research 2011 Summer Institute in Social Psychology, Princeton, NJ; SPSP program funded by NSF 2009, 2010, 2011, 2012 ASU Graduate and Professional Student Association Grant for Conference Travel 2008 ASU Graduate and Professional Student Association Grant for Independent Research 2007 Departmental Research Excellence Award, ASU Psychology Department Neel CV RESEARCH Publications White, A.E., Kenrick, D.T., Neel, R., & Neuberg, S.L. (in press). From the bedroom to the budget deficit: Mate competition changes men’s attitudes toward economic redistribution. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. Sadalla, E., Berlin, A., Neel, R., & Ledlow, S. (in press). Priorities in residential water use: A trade-off analysis. Environment and Behavior. Neel, R., Neufeld, S.L., & Neuberg, S.L. (2013). Would an obese person whistle Vivaldi? Targets of prejudice self-present to minimize appearance of specific threats.
    [Show full text]
  • RN and Russell's Regress
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2001, 79 (3), pp. 395-408. RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM AND RUSSELL’S REGRESS Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra University of Edinburgh In a famous passage Bertrand Russell argued that any attempt, like that of Resemblance Nominalism, to get rid of universals in favour of resemblances fails [20, p. 48]. More precisely, Russell thought that no resemblance theory could avoid postulating a universal of resemblance without falling into a vicious infinite regress. And he added that admitting a universal of resemblance made it pointless to avoid other universals. In this paper I shall defend Resemblance Nominalism, a theory which gets rid of universals in terms of resemblances, from both of Russell’s points by arguing (a) Resemblance Nominalism can avoid the postulation of a universal of resemblance without falling into a vicious infinite regress (§V) and (b) even if Resemblance Nominalism had to admit a universal of resemblance, this would not make it pointless to avoid the postulation of other universals (§VI). But before doing so I shall briefly introduce Resemblance Nominalism (§I) and Russell’s regress (§II), and then I shall consider some failed arguments and strategies against the regress (§§III−IV). I. Resemblance Nominalism. Resemblance Nominalism is a solution to the Problem of Universals. I have argued elsewhere that the Problem of Universals, strictly understood, is what I call the Many over One, rather than the traditional One over Many [17, pp. 269-70]. The Many over One is the problem of explaining how a single particular can have a multiplicity of properties [17, pp. 269-70]. Thus solutions to the Problem of Universals account for what it is for any thing or particular a to have properties F, G, H etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Nudge Theory
    Nudge Theory http://www.businessballs.com/nudge-theory.htm Nudge theory is a flexible and modern concept for: • understanding of how people think, make decisions, and behave, • helping people improve their thinking and decisions, • managing change of all sorts, and • identifying and modifying existing unhelpful influences on people. Nudge theory was named and popularized by the 2008 book, 'Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness', written by American academics Richard H Thaler and Cass R Sunstein. The book is based strongly on the Nobel prize- winning work of the Israeli-American psychologists Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky. This article: • reviews and explains Thaler and Sunstein's 'Nudge' concept, especially 'heuristics' (tendencies for humans to think and decide instinctively and often mistakenly) • relates 'Nudge' methods to other theories and models, and to Kahneman and Tversky's work • defines and describes additional methods of 'nudging' people and groups • extends the appreciation and application of 'Nudge' methodology to broader change- management, motivation, leadership, coaching, counselling, parenting, etc • offers 'Nudge' methods and related concepts as a 'Nudge' theory 'toolkit' so that the concept can be taught and applied in a wide range of situations involving relationships with people, and enabling people to improve their thinking and decision- making • and offers a glossary of Nudge theory and related terms 'Nudge' theory was proposed originally in US 'behavioral economics', but it can be adapted and applied much more widely for enabling and encouraging change in people, groups, or yourself. Nudge theory can also be used to explore, understand, and explain existing influences on how people behave, especially influences which are unhelpful, with a view to removing or altering them.
    [Show full text]
  • Committees and Welcomes
    Committees and Welcomes SPSP Execut ive and Com m it t ees Welcome to the Fourth Annual SPSP President Jim BlascovichMeeting! Past President Claude SteeleDear SPSP Colleagues, President Elect Hazel Markus It is my great pleasure to welcome you to the annual meetings Executive Officer Harry Reis of the Society for Personality and Social Psychology. Co-Secretary Treasurers Leslie Zebrowitz Sharon Brehm This is our fourth annual meeting – a remarkably brief history Members-at-Large David Dunning for a convention that is now so firmly established. Our confer- David Funder ences in Nashville, San Antonio, and Savannah each drew crowds that were greatly in excess of expectations. In so doing, Judith Harakiewicz they rapidly established SPSP as the major national or interna- APA Council Representatives Monica Biernat tional scientific meeting for personality and social psycholo- June Tangney gists. Publication Committee John Dovidio Gifford Weary We now look forward to building on this string of success in Universal City/Los Angeles, site of our 2003 meeting. This Joanne Wood year, we once again have an exceptionally strong and diverse Convention Committee Dan Cervone chair set of scientific presentations. Our program is expanded even Lynne Cooper beyond last year’s offerings, thanks in part to funding from the Rick Hoyle Decade of Behavior initiative, which is supporting a plenary Training Committee Lisa Aspinwall address by the renowned biologist and author Jared Diamond. Kim Bartholomew We also have expanded on the lighter side of things; on Satur- Allen Omoto day night, we will end our meetings with a social event featur- PSPB Editor Fred Rhodewalt ing DJ’d music at 8 pm followed by a live performance by the PSPR Editor Eliot Smith LA rock band Lustra.
    [Show full text]
  • From Ressentiment to Resentment As a Tertiary Emotion
    Review of European Studies; Vol. 10, No. 4; 2018 ISSN 1918-7173 E-ISSN 1918-7181 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education From Ressentiment to Resentment as a Tertiary Emotion Warren D. TenHouten1 1 Department of Sociology, University of California, Los Angeles, California, USA Correspondence: Warren D. TenHouten, Department of Sociology, 264 Haines Hall, UCLA, 405 Hilgard Avenue, Los Angeles, CA 90095–1551, USA. Received: May 14, 2018 Accepted: June 28, 2018 Online Published: September 5, 2018 doi:10.5539/res.v10n4p49 URL: https://doi.org/10.5539/res.v10n4p49 Abstract Resentment is a noxious emotion that can exist in sublimated form as a result of being subjected to inferiorization, stigmazation, or violence. In its active form, resentment can be a forceful response to acts that have created unjustified and meaningless suffering. We consider sociomoral conceptualizations of resentment by Adam Smith, Hume, and Lévinas. Nietzsche and Scheler developed the broader notion of ressentiment, a generalized form of resentment arising out of powerlessness and the experience of brutalization neither forgotten nor forgiven. Resentment is seen historically as a sentiment that is saturated with frustration, contempt, outrage, and malevolence. Marshall described oppositional class-consciousness as permeated with resentment and anger, but resentment also contains the basic emotions of surprise and disgust. Resentment is linked to the concept of relative deprivation. A partial classification of emotions is used to further analyze resentment as containing three secondary-level emotions: contempt (anger & disgust), shock (surprise & disgust), and outrage (surprise & anger). Thus, resentment is conceptualized as a tertiary-level emotion, containing three primary and three secondary emotions.
    [Show full text]
  • Indignation, Appreciation, and the Unity of Moral Experience
    Indignation, Appreciation, and the Unity of Moral Experience Uriah Kriegel Forthcoming in Ethical Theory and Moral Practice (special issue on moral phenomenology) Introduction/Abstract Moral experience comes in many flavors. Some philosophers have argued that there is nothing common to the many forms moral experience can take. In this paper, I argue that close attention to the phenomenology of certain key emotions, combined with a clear distinction between essentially and accidentally moral experiences, suggests that there is a group of (essentially) moral experiences which in fact exhibits significant unity. 1 The Diversity of Moral Experience Some of our mental states embody moral commitments, some do not. Thinking that the table is brown and deciding to read this rather than that novel, for instance, have no obvious moral dimension; believing that genocide is wrong and deciding to donate to an anti-corruption charity, in contrast, do. Of our morally committal mental states, some are consciously experienced but many are not. For most of our lives, the belief that genocide is wrong is not consciously entertained; in contrast, a decision to donate to charity is typically taken consciously. For now, let us call the domain of mental states which both embody moral commitment and are consciously experienced ‘moral experience’ – and the study of this domain ‘moral phenomenology.’ Is there anything common to all moral experiences, in virtue of which they are moral experiences? One is forgiven for being antecedently skeptical, and several philosophers have developed explicit arguments for a negative answer (Yasenchuk 1997, Gill 2008, Sinnott-Armstrong 2008). In the remainder of this section, I discuss Sinnott- Armstrong’s argument.
    [Show full text]