<<

Q Academy of Management Review 2017, Vol. 42, No. 4, 745–755.

WHAT INSPIRES THE ACADEMY: Jean M. Bartunek BOOK REVIEWS AND BEYOND Review Essays Editor

Luigi Pareyson’s Estetica: Teoria della The contemporary reader should note that formativita` and Its Implications for Pareyson’sbookappearedinItalianin1954and Organization Studies that it was almost fifty years later that Peter Carravetta wrote as follows in the introduction to By Silvia Gherardi, University of Trento and the recent publication in English of a selection of ’ University of Oslo, and Antonio Strati, University Pareyson sessays: of Trento and i3-CRG, Universite´ Paris-Saclay The appearance of a substantial selection of Luigi Pareyson’swritingsinEnglishismotivefor Luigi Pareyson wrote, “The whole of spiri- atransnationalcelebrationinthehistoryofideas. tual life is in some way ‘art’:ineveryfieldof AthinkeroftherankofGadamerandRicoeur,to whom he is often compared, surprisingly little has human industriousness nothing can be done been known or written about him. An original in- without also inventing in some way how it is terpreter of existentialism and German Idealism, to be done” (1988: 63). Therefore, if we want to Pareyson developed an authentic hermeneutic in follow in Pareyson’sstepsandappreciate the nineteen-fifties, a time in which the Italian his contribution to organization and manage- panorama was being shaped by growing Marxist hegemony and the turn towards the sciences es- ment studies, we can see management as pecially linguistics (2010: 99). art, production processes as artistry, a work well done as a work of art, and, of course, art in Pareyson was not attracted by Marxist philos- itself. ophy, since he was a Catholic and a militant in “ ’ ” “ ” The very idea that art is always an art of Partito d Azione and Giustizia e Liberta` dur- something is what motivates us to propose ing the Resistance to Nazi fascism. He was born in a reading of Pareyson’s aesthetic philosophy that 1918, and he worked at the University of Torino can talk to the hearts and minds of organiza- almost until his death in 1991. In 1935 and 1936, he spent time with in Heidelberg, and tional scholars. One of our aims in reviewing during the 1940s and 1950s, he published, in Ital- Pareyson’s main oeuvre—Estetica: Teoria della ian, several essays on Kierkegaard, Heidegger, formativita` —is to encourage the readers of this and mainly Schelling’s existentialist philosophy. journal to engage with literature they might not In the following years he published on normally read. Our other purpose is to take the and on interpretation: Estetica: Teoria della for- opportunity provided by a recent and partial mativita` in 1954, Conversazioni di estetica in 1966, ’ translation of Pareyson s work into English to in- Verita` e interpretazione in 1971—recently trans- troduce management scholars to a philosopher lated into English (Pareyson, 2013)—and his last whose work resonates with a relatively new in- work, Ontologia e liberta,` published posthumously terest in practical knowledge and in forms of in 1995. As an academic at the University of Torino, knowing outside the cognitive domain. In fact, if among his followers were the semiologist Umberto we locate a “turn to practice” in social sciences Eco and the philosophers , Mario around the year 2000, we may argue that it is Perniola, and Sergio Givone, who worked on aes- through the organizational aesthetics approach thetics. He was also the director of the journal that the idea of sensible knowing and aesthetic Rivista di estetica. judgment arrived in practice-based studies. Today we can gain a more complete overview Pareyson’s philosophy is important for grounding of his inquiries in philosophy, , a philosophy of knowing that is an aesthetic phi- and existentialism because of the translations losophy of production—that is, based on doing— of his writings into English, French, Portuguese, rather than contemplation. Spanish, and other languages. It has been a very

745 Copyright of the Academy of Management, all rights reserved. Contents may not be copied, emailed, posted to a listserv, or otherwise transmitted without the copyright holder’s express written permission. Users may print, download, or email articles for individual use only. 746 Academy of Management Review October long time since 1954, when Pareyson, “at the existentialist aesthetics. The Italian philosophi- time aged thirty-six” and despite his young age, cal context of Formativita` , therefore, was influ- “was not an unknown scholar” (Tiberghien, enced by social ideologies at the basis of political 2007: 5). and economic choices that would give rise to both Why did it take so long to translate Pareyson’s the decade of economic boom of the 1960s and the work? After all, he is celebrated as a great phi- student protests and the workers’ and trade union losopher. One possible answer is that his work struggles of 1968 and 1969. focused on the “practical” character of art and If, then, on the one hand, Formativita` “marked the productive moment of art. In commonsense the decisive moment of the renewal of Italian language, as in philosophy, practice is opposed aesthetics in the middle of this century involving, to theory, and the two terms are considered not besides the legacy of pre-Hegelian German ide- only oppositional but hierarchically related alism, also the ontological-hermeneutic current so that practical knowledge is devalued with of twentieth-century existentialism” (wrote Gianni respect to theory and theoretical knowledge Vattimo [1977: 42], an Italian philosopher in- (Gherardi, 2000). In this regard we argue that an ternationally known for his theory of “weak aesthetic philosophy, like the one elaborated by thought”), on the other hand, there were other Pareyson, can provide a firm grounding for the- currents that creatively rethought themes of orizing about knowing in practice and knowing Marxist (Galvano della Volpe) or phenomeno- as corporeal doing. logical (Luciano Anceschi and Antonio Banfi) In the following sections we address three origin. The decisive renewal represented by themes: (1) the Italian philosophical context in Formativita` was due to the definitive liberation which Estetica: Teoria della formativita` appeared, of Italian aesthetics from the “dictatorship of (2) how the book was received within the aes- Crocean idealism.” In 1902 had thetic organizational research field, and (3) published his thesis on aesthetics as the sci- Pareyson’scontributiontothestudyoforgani- ence of expression, in which art is considered zational practices. We conclude with a discus- to be knowledge that is intuition and expression sion of the value of reading Pareyson today within at the same time because there are no pro- a community of organizational and management found intuitions unless they are formed and scholars. expressed—as happens with a musical motif, where there is no intuition unless it is heard al- most as if it were being played. Moreover, for THE ITALIAN PHILOSOPHICAL CONTEXT OF Croce, intuition was art, and the distinction be- THE BOOK tween the intuition of ordinary people and that of Estetica: Teoria della formativita` (henceforth an artist was a mere empirical distinction owing simply Formativita` )waspublishedinTurinby to the fateful separation of art from common Edizioni di Filosofia, in 1954, as mentioned spiritual life. In fact, for Croce, art techniques above. The Second World War was now long and practices constituted a level of reflection past, the fascist period was over, and Italy was that had little to do with aesthetics because it no longer a monarchy but, rather, a republic with was an economic fact that reverberated on the universal suffrage, because the right to vote had diversity of arts and artistic genres. been extended to women. This was the historical This thesis of Benedetto Croce is well known period in Italy known as the “Ricostruzione,” and because it had broad international resonance there was heated political debate between the and projected the Italian aesthetic philosophy communist and socialist left, on the one hand, of the twentieth century along idealist lines and the Christian democrat and liberal center, on (D’Angelo, 1997; Restaino, 1991). What is perhaps the other hand, which had participated in the Re- less well known is that the devaluation of the sistance against the fascist dictatorship and Nazi “practical” character of art and the productive occupation. moment of art was the aesthetic issue that gen- There was also a sharp division among com- erated aversion to Crocean theoreticism. This munist, socialist, Catholic, and liberal intellec- aversion was shared by several salient move- tuals regarding aesthetic philosophy, which was ments of Italian aesthetic philosophy in the expressed by the opposition of the aesthetics of postwar period because it developed both Marxist origin against the phenomenological and among philosophers extraneous to Crocean 2017 What Inspires the Academy: Book Reviews and Beyond 747 idealism, such as Luigi Pareyson and Luciano We can find the first reference in organizational Anceschi, and among philosophers tied to studies to Pareyson’s aesthetic philosophy in the Croce’s thought. What happened in Italy, in fact, book Organization and Aesthetics (Strati, 1999)—that was that is to say, when the study of the aesthetic dimension of organization was becoming established, and much of the aesthetics of the 1950s set itself on the part of the producer rather than that of the user or not at its beginnings in the late 1980s, nor even the art work. This is interesting also out of [the contemporaneously with the proposal for the Italian] context, because an attitude of this kind is aesthetic study of organization made in the early relatively rare in the history of aesthetics. We find 1990s in the pages of this journal, the Academy of it, to a very marked extent, also in Pareyson and Management Review (Strati, 1992). This signals Brandi, and in Anceschi’s strong interest in critics who are also artists (D’Angelo, 1997: 174–175). an important aspect of aesthetic research on or- ganizational life. In fact, if one reviews the first Added to this rare occurrence in the history of decade of reflection on the aesthetic side of or- aesthetics was the fact that while Croce consid- ganization, one notes that specific references to ered artwork when it had been accomplished, aesthetic philosophy were sporadic and some- both Pareyson and other Italian philosophers like times appeared ritualistic—one notes, that is, Diano or Brandi were interested in artwork “in its that these references indicated a process that was making”—that is, the work of art as a research weak, a dialogue between organizational literature process, and doing art as an artistic process. on aesthetics and philosophy that was still in its Pareyson himself said as much, in his preface to infancy. Some philosophers, such as Giambattista the fourth edition of Formativita` : Vico, Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, or Immanuel First of all, it was extremely urgent to discuss Kant, were posited to be the basis of aesthetic those issues that Croce’scensorshiphaddetri- organizational research, while others, such mentally expunged from Italy; and it was also as Susanne Langer, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, or necessary to develop categories that could meet Jacques Derrida, were recurrently present. But the new needs of the changed situation. This was real “dialogue” with philosophical aesthetics be- the starting point and the ambitious design of this book, which came out in serial form in a philo- came established in the next decade, which sophical journal between 1950 and 1954 (Pareyson, was the period where attention to aesthetics by 1988: 7). organizational scholars was especially animated. This was also the starting point for the flourishing Pasquale Gagliardi noted that this was thanks to of other philosophical inquiries developed during a growing body of literature on aesthetic themes, the first half of the twentieth century in Italy. one in which systematic reflection is conducted on In the next section we examine Pareyson’s the- the relationships between these and organization ory of aesthetic formativeness and its place in the (Dean et al. 1997; Strati 1999) and between art and management (Guillet de Monthoux 2004); there are philosophy and epistemology of the aesthetic research anthologies as well as special journal study of organizational life. issues (Organization 3/2, 1996; Linstead and Hopfl¨ 2000; Human Relations 55/7, 2002), which have resulted from seminars and conferences expressly FORMATIVITA` AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF devoted to analysis of the methodological impli- cations of taking an aesthetic approach to the study AESTHETIC ORGANIZATIONAL RESEARCH of organizations. The aesthetics of organization is Formativita` made its appearance in organiza- therefore taking shape as a distinct field of inquiry within organizational studies (2006: 702). tion studies a decade before its partial translation into English in 2009. It did so in the context of the For obvious reasons, this dialogue does not organizational research on the aesthetic di- set organizational aesthetics and philosophical mension of everyday working life in organizations aesthetics in a symmetrical and interactive re- that, during the late 1980s, was one of several new lationship with each other, given that philo- lines of inquiry pursued by organizational theo- sophical aesthetics has its origins in the works rists. Subsequently, Formativita` would also be of Vico (1725) and Baumgarten (1750–1758), and a theoretical reference for the study of social in the writings of Joseph Addison on “the plea- practices in organizational contexts, particularly sures of the imagination,” published in June in the area of practice-based studies (Gherardi & 1712 in his and Richard Steele’sjournal,The Strati, 2012), as we shall see later in this essay. Spectator (Addison & Steele, 1982). There is no 748 Academy of Management Review October dialectical relation between them also because authenticexperiencethattransformsus;itisalso contemporary scholars of philosophical aes- an experience inherently characterized by the thetics have not paid particular attention to or- symbolism that distinguishes the human being. ganizational reflection on aesthetics, with rare In the same years when Gadamer propounded exceptions such as the volume on ordinary the close link between hermeneutics and aes- beauty edited by Janusz Przychodzen, François- thetics in philosophy, Pareyson was arguing that Emmanuel¨ Boucher, and Sylvain David (2010). art “is the locus par excellence of interpretation: the The aesthetic discourse on organization, how- interpretation of truth” (Vercellone, Bertinetto, & ever, has not “appropriated” philosophical aes- Garelli, 2003: 357). It is important to emphasize that thetics; rather, it has resorted to it in a diversified Pareyson contributed independently from Gadamer and sporadic manner. It has “conversed” with to the development of hermeneutic aesthetics and some philosophical aesthetics and neglected that the theories of these two philosophers do not others, depending on both the personal taste of coincide at all. To grasp the originality of Pareyson’s the organization scholar and the peculiarities of contribution to hermeneutics, one must return to his the organizational context studied. reading of Kierkegaard’sexistentialism,particu- Hence, among the philosophers who have larly his Scritti sull’esistenzialismo: gradually become part of the theoretical heritage of organizational aesthetics, besides the already Only in the essential relation between myself and the situation am I really myself: unique, incarnated, mentioned Addison, Baumgarten, Derrida, Kant, placed, singularized, concrete. Thus after all, in- Langer, and Vico, we find Schopenhauer and carnation is a relation I maintain with myself, a con- Nietzsche’s aesthetics of the crisis of rationalism, crete and singularized self-identity: my own ipseity Schiller’s romantic aesthetics, Dewey’s naturalist (Pareyson, 1943: 15–16; English translation, 2009: 42). pragmatism, Husserl’sphenomenologicalaes- In this way, Pareyson proposes the hermeneutic thetics, Benjamin’sMarxistaesthetics,Gadamer’s perspective that is defined as personalistic her- hermeneutics, and Pareyson’sexistentialistherme- meneutics, whereby “hermeneutics is the consis- neutics. Other philosophers and philosophical aes- tent outcome of an existentialism that does not thetics may be added to complete this overview of lose its ties to the being and rights of the person” ’ organization studies philosophical reflections, but (Vercellone et al., 2003: 356). In fact, he reprises the variegated picture, composed of facets often at from the thought of Kierkegaard the distinctive- odds with each other, that emerges does not change. ness of the individual’s peculiarities and his or “ ” There are three philosophical sensibilities that her irreducibility to objectification. characterize aesthetic research on organization: (1) With his existentialist hermeneutics, therefore, the hermeneutic sensibility, (2) the aesthetic sensi- Pareyson takes a polemic position toward the bility, and (3) the performative sensibility (Strati, hermeneutics of Heidegger, which he neverthe- ’ 2016). Luigi Pareyson s aesthetic theory is an im- less appreciated—“I am ‘thrown’ to live in a situ- portant philosophical referent for all three of these ation, as might be said using a fitting expression sensibilities, as we shall now see. of Heidegger,” he comments (Pareyson, 1943: 15–16; English translation, 2009: 42)—precisely Pareyson’s Personalistic Hermeneutics because the German philosopher neglected the concreteness of the person’s human existence The hermeneutic philosophical sensibility has and reduced it to an ontological instance. characterized the aesthetic discourse on organi- zation since its inception, because it distin- Ihavethis body, these relatives, these friends, this guishes the works most concerned with the study homeland, this job, these relations with others and of the symbolism of organizational aesthetics. other things: that is I have a very definite position in the universe, a specific place in the world. In a word: The interpretation of aesthetics in terms of their asituation,orbetter,my situation. I cannot regard my symbolic construction and as an expression of situation as one among many others, any of which I organization as organizational culture has drawn could have been given at random. My situation is my mainly on the philosophical reflections of Gadamer, concreteness, my configuration, or, to use Marcel’s ‘ ’ who, more than Schlegel,Schleiermacher,or word, my incarnation :withoutit,I,asasingleperson, would not exist. The bonds that connect me to my sit- Heidegger himself, applied hermeneutic thought uation are very tight, and above all, they are essential to aesthetics. Gadamer (1977) maintained that the to me: they are not links of ‘features’,butof‘essence’ experience of beauty through art is not only an (Pareyson, 1943: 15–16; English translation, 2009: 42). 2017 What Inspires the Academy: Book Reviews and Beyond 749

But, Pareyson warns, the person must not be re- discourse on organization because, among the duced to the situation, as if there were no clear many different aspects that the concept of doing distinction between them, because incarnation “is may assume, Pareyson posits as formativeness the a choice: I do not reduce myself to my situation, but doing that, while it is being done, invents how to do I choose it. Choice, through which I assume my it, and that for this reason is a doing that forms: situation, acts so that I do not identify myself with ‘ ’ ” Forming, therefore, means doing ,butitisadoing it (Pareyson, 1943: 18; English translation, 2009: 44). that as it is being done, invents how it is to be done. This is doing without how it is to be done being predetermined and imposedsothatitsufficesto Formativita` and the Aesthetic and apply it to do well: it must be found by doing, and only Performative Sensibilities by doing can one discover it, so that, properly speaking, it is a matter of inventing, without which “Aesthetics,” in the philosophical tradition of the operation fails. . . . To form, therefore, means to Addison, Baumgarten, and Vico that has informed ‘do’ and ‘know how to do’ together: to do while a large part of the aesthetic discourse on organi- inventing at the same time how in the particular case zation, means taste, sensory perception, and what is to be done lets itself be done. Forming means ‘being able to do’,thatis,doinginawaythat,without aesthetic judgment through the senses, imagina- appeal to pre-established technical rules, one can tion, and symbolic construction, mythical think- and must say that what has been done has been ing, and poetic logic. It signifies not only art and done as it should have been done (Pareyson, 1988: 59). artistic worlds but also the ordinary beauty and The whole of human experience is character- the ordinary ugliness that are collectively con- ized by the aesthetic dimension, says Pareyson, structed even in nonartistic organizations, through because “present in the entirety of human in- negotiation of the aesthetic and the interaction dustriousness is an inventive and innovative side among aesthetic feelings that are like the thinking that is the precondition for any achievement” and of the body in a world of sensible knowing. Aes- because “it is precisely the formative character of thetics is action. It is action when we activate our all human industriousness that explains how one perceptive faculties and aesthetic judgment to can speak of the beauty of any work” (1988: 19). perform a task, to enjoy a product, to imagine our- This is a conception of aesthetics that is not new in selves in a situation that does not yet exist, or to the philosophy of the twentieth century and that immerse ourselves in a context. Itis action when we brings Pareyson’s thought close, for example, to activate the proprioceptive faculties that enable us that of Dewey on aesthetics and human experi- to move in a situation. It is action when we set about ence. But it highlights Pareyson’s distance from contemplating a work of art, listening to a concert, Crocean idealism, his connection to other Italian or being entertained by a story. Aesthetics is philosophers attentive to the practice of aesthetics, therefore “doing,” and intertwined in this doing and also the importance of Formativita` for the are both the philosophical aesthetic sensibility aesthetic study of organization and for practice- and the performative sensibility of aesthetic re- based studies. There is no evaluation of human search on organization: work that does not involve, in everyday organiza- The beauty of nature is a beauty of forms, and so it is tional work, some aesthetic appreciation, from the evident for a gaze that is capable of seeing the form beauty of an argument to that of a way of working, as a form, after having searched for it, inquired into from a work of thought to the proposal of a style in it, surveyed it, interpreted it, to finally admire and enjoy it. Therefore the vision and the appreciation of the performance of an activity: the beauty of nature presuppose an effort of in- In these cases one certainly performs an aesthetic terpretation, an exercise of faithfulness, discipline evaluation, and one can use such language with of attention, a concentrated gaze, and the cultivation good reason, because these are successful works, of a way of seeing, to reach that deep and all-seeing and the work, whatever the activity in which it view, which is, in one way, vision of forms, and in concludes, will fail without making form, definite another, production of forms, since an interpreted and consistent, because no activity, be it moral or form and formed image must coincide in that speculative, can generate works if not by exercis- conformation which is peculiar to contemplation ing the process of invention and production that (Pareyson, 1954: 212; English translation, 2009: 101). constitutes the forming (Pareyson, 1988: 20). Pareyson’s aesthetic theory is particularly con- For Pareyson, therefore, it takes art to do any- genial to the intertwining of aesthetic sensibility thing. This is apparent in the most diverse of hu- and performative sensibility in the aesthetic man activities, because every human experience 750 Academy of Management Review October has an aesthetic character owing to the for- within the third way of engaging practice as mativeness that distinguishes it, because it is philosophical focus, and, thus, we consider prac- done with art, it is done artfully, or the art of doing tices as fundamental to the production and re- it is discovered or invented. Formativeness thus production of social reality and organizations as coincides with the aesthetics of the art of orga- constituted in ongoing knowledgeable practices. nizing, with the art of managing a firm, with the art Our understanding of the central phenomenon in of tuning a machine, and with the art of industrial practice-based studies is knowing in practice. design, as well as with the experience of an event Hence, we define knowledge as a practical activity, in the organization or an organizational space. and Pareyson’s work has been influential in Art, however, occupies a position apart in these grounding an aesthetic theory of knowledge. It is experiential dynamics because art is not “art of” through organizational aesthetics that Pareyson’s but art tout court: contribution enters the theorization of work prac- tices, in that sensible knowledge, the body, and the If every operation is always formative, in the sense aesthetic judgment are present in various ways in that it cannot be itself without forming, and one cannot think or act without forming, instead the knowing in practice (Strati & Gherardi, 2015). artistic operation is formation, in the sense that it The practical knowledge acquired through the intentionally seeks to form, and within it thought five senses of sight, hearing, smell, taste, and touch and action intervene only to make it possible that it was also considered by Michael Polanyi (1958), cannot but be formation. The artistic operation is when he drew the distinction between explicit and a process of invention and production undertaken, not to achieve speculative or practical works, or tacit knowledge: the former type of knowledge is others besides, but only for itself: forming to form, formalized in scientific terms, whereas the latter is only pursuing the form for itself: art is pure for- constituted by the awareness of knowing how to do mativeness (Pareyson, 1988: 23). something without being able to provide an ade- It is, however, the emphasis on the fact that one quate analytical description of it and, thus, without needs “art to do” that has most influenced the being able to translate it into formal and general- study of organization, as we discuss further in the izable knowledge. It is for this latter form of next section. knowledge that the aesthetic understanding is fundamental for studying situated practices. In this framework the contribution of Pareyson’s LUIGI PAREYSON’S INFLUENCE ON aesthetic philosophy to the study of practices ORGANIZATION STUDIES comprises three main topics: (1) the concept of for- mativeness makes it possible to analyze and in- The thought of Pareyson is important for un- terpret how the object of a practice acquires form, derstanding organizational life and for theorizing (2) the idea of the inseparability of knowing and about and empirically analyzing work practices. expressing supports an understanding of practice We will illustrate this point by referring to as collective tastemaking, and (3) the inseparability a broader set of studies based on practice, which of knowing and sensing explains practice as we will denote with the umbrella term practice- grounded in sensible knowledge and therefore in based studies, without going into detail on the the materiality of bodies that work. We develop different theories of practice that inform them. these three topics below, starting from the theoret- In fact, the field of practice-based studies has ical and methodological issues of a practice-based being growing very fast in the last several years, approach in order to focus on how Pareyson’s and it is difficult to give a brief but accurate map. thought is relevant to the argument. Therefore, we can refer to the distinctions pro- vided by Feldman and Orlikowski, who differen- Formativeness: How the Object of a Practice tiated between different ways of engaging in Acquires Form practice research: “an empirical focus on how people act in organizational contexts, a theoreti- One of the main concerns of a practice-based cal focus on understanding relations between the approach is theorizing the relationship between actions people take and the structures of organi- the activities that form a practice and the effect zational life, and a philosophical focus on the that follows when the practice is performed. For constitutive role of practices in producing organi- example, in an elderly residential care home, the zational reality” (2011: 1240). Our work is positioned activities that form various work practices relate 2017 What Inspires the Academy: Book Reviews and Beyond 751 to cleaning, feeding, entertainment, medical knowing is seeing the “thing” formed. Particularly treatment, and so on, while “care” is the object of evident in the production of objects is the perfor- the practice and is realized within a texture of mative and creative aspect that characterizes interdependent work practices. every “doing,” even when it consists in thinking or While the objectives of an activity are the acting: “one does not operate without completing, intended outcomes of that process, the object of performing, producing, and realizing” (Pareyson, a practice is the thing, or project, that people are 1988: 18). A work is “accomplished” insofar as working on to transform. This distinction between its doing comprises the way in which it must be the output of the activities that form care practices done. and care as an emergent object makes it possible There is formativeness both in the way a mate- to conceive of the elderly as receivers not of rial object, like the craft work of the artisan women service but of solicitude. In fact, taking care of studied by Gherardi and Perrotta (2014), is man- asickbodywithoutconsideratenessismere ufactured and in the narratives on their creative service work, not care. Therefore, the object of practices that the craftswomen performed for the a practice is also an epistemic object—discussed researchers. In fact, in our empirical research we by Knorr-Cetina as “always in the process of being used Pareyson’s concept of formativeness to in- materially defined” (2001: 184), and capable of terpret how the research participants described acquiring new properties and modifying the the creative process whereby form was given to properties that it has—and it is simultaneously an object understood as unique, and how they given, socially constructed, contested, and emer- were showing us the difference between an ac- gent (Blackler & Regan, 2009: 164). In producing care complished piece (fait comme il faut) and one less as the emergent object of different professional well done. Competence was performed for us re- practices, thus, there is the idea that practice is searchers, making the art of doing present to an a collective knowledgeable doing. audience. Nevertheless, a process of giving form, In Pareyson’s terms, we can see formativeness as a doing that invents the way of doing, was at in the process whereby care takes form and be- work not only as material production but also in comes realized. In fact, Pareyson’s aesthetic the- the discursive practices that were authoring the ory is an aesthetics of production, as opposed to craftswoman as she was using words that an aesthetics of contemplation, and it concerns expressed her knowledge and her sense of iden- the becoming of the form—that is, the outcome of tity and competence in doing. Therefore, we can a formation process. Pareyson was fascinated by say that in formativeness the boundaries among the idea of human life as the invention of forms epistemic objects, materiality, and discursivity that acquire lives of their own: they detach are blurred or, in other words, that there is no need themselves from their creators and engender to presume distinctions between the knowing, styles. There is, hence, a formative character in doing, and talking. the whole of human industriousness, and art is In this sense the epistemology of practice may only a specific domain of this formativeness, as be defined as an epistemology of becoming in we illustrated above. Pareyson proposes that order to stress impermanence and the tentative a work of art be regarded as pure formativeness, and ongoing process of knowledge production. It and the topic of his book on aesthetics is the work may also be defined as an epistemology of of art in its process of forming and being formed. transformation in order to point to how knowledge But he also writes: changes through its use or, in the Wittgenstein (1953) tradition, as knowledge in transition—an If all spiritual life is formative, behold the possibility of beauty possessed by every work, be it specula- expression intended to capture the difficulties tive, practical or utilitarian . . . and formative, too, is that we face “in trying to make sense of activities the sensible knowledge that grasps every ‘thing’, that are still incomplete, still unfolding in relation producing it, and ‘forming thereof’ the image, so that to their actual surroundings” (Shotter, 2012: 247). ‘ ’ this is accomplished and reveals and captures, These considerations on the fundamental for- indeed is the thing (Pareyson, 1988: 11). mative nature of all human industriousness en- The realization of the object of a practice able us to move a step further in considering therefore emerges from a formative process in Pareyson’s argument on the inseparability of which an attempt is made to produce the image knowing and expressing and its relevance to that renders the “thing,” and the outcome of theorizing on the relation between practitioners’ 752 Academy of Management Review October knowledgeable doing and their emotional at- a set of situated practices in order to use and enjoy tachment to the object of their practice. the object of his or her passion individually and collectively. But the practitioner is also passive, in that he or she deliberately, and in a “cultivated” Inseparability of Knowing and Expressing: How manner, abandons him/herself to the effect of the Collective Tastemaking Sustains Practices object insofar as he or she predisposes the mate- To consider practitioners’ attachment to their rial conditions for the enjoyment of music, food, or practices, we need to define our understanding of drugs and socially shares this passion within practice in terms of normative accountability of a community of amateurs. various performances. Rouse wrote, “Actors share The concept of tastemaking has been pro- a practice if their actions are appropriately posed (Gherardi, 2009) to account for practi- regarded as answerable to norms of correct or tioners’ attachment to the object of practice and incorrect practice” (2001: 190). In other words, negotiation of an aesthetic judgment on it. practices are not only recurrent patterns of action Tastemaking refers to the process of giving (level of production) but also recurrent patterns of voice to passion and negotiating aesthetic cri- socially sustained action (production and re- teria that support what constitutes a “good” production). What people produce in their situ- practice or a “sloppy” one and a “beautiful” ated practices is not only work but also the (re) practice or an “ugly” one within a community of production of society. In this sense practice is an practitioners. It is formed within situated dis- analytic concept that enables interpretation of cursive practices. The aesthetic judgment is how people achieve active being-in-the-world. made by being said—and therefore it pre- Apracticeisnotrecognizableoutsideits supposes the collective elaboration and mas- intersubjectively created meaning, and what tery of a vocabulary for saying—and it is said by makes possible the competent reproduction of being made. Tastemaking, thus, is the process a practice over and over again and its refinement that socially sustains the formation of taste and while being practiced (or its abandonment) is the the sophistication of practices through the mo- constant negotiation of what is thought to be bilization of sensible knowledge (the bodily a correct/beautiful or incorrect/ugly way of prac- ability to perceive and to taste)—the sharing of ticing within the community of its practitioners. avocabularyforappraisingtheobjectandthe Within every community of practitioners, discus- object in place. Developing a vocabulary of sing and disputing practice, developing different appraisal enables the community of practi- cultures of practice yet identifying with a shared tioners to communicate about sensible experi- practice, and making practice into terrain legiti- ences, to draw distinctions of taste, and to mately contestable by its practitioners are dynam- spread them through the community. ics that socially sustainthatpractice.These Pareyson’scontributiontothereadingof dynamics construct the conditions in which the practices sustained by sensation, sentiment, practice is reproduced. They can be conceived as and sensory knowledge proceeds in the follow- the everyday work of practice reproduction and as ing way: the dynamic work that adapts the practice to changed circumstances so that it is once again It is impossible to know sensitively without expe- “ ” riencing a sentimental reaction, and on the other performed for another first time (Garfinkel, 1967: 9). hand sentiment is always a mood which colors and The attachment to the object of practice—be it of accompanies a sensation. . . . If it is true that I love or hate or of love and hate—is what makes cannot make contact with the world except through practices socially sustained by judgments re- the emotions I feel about it, it is also true that I do lated not only to utility but to ethics and aes- not feel emotions unless I make contact with the world (Pareyson, 1950; English translation, 2009: 79). thetics as well. Taste and amateur practices like those of music Therefore, sensation and sentiment are insepara- buffs, food or wine tasters, or even drug addicts ble, but between knowing and expressing also constitute the empirical basis on which a sociol- there is a relation of mutual constitution: ogy of attachments has developed (Hennion, 2001, — There is neither knowing which is not expressing, 2004). The relationship with the object food, nor expressing that is not knowing: I know only music, drug—exemplifies a relationship in which while expressing, and through expression I know the practitioner is indeed active—that is, deploys (Pareyson, 1950; English translation, 2009: 82). 2017 What Inspires the Academy: Book Reviews and Beyond 753

Intuition, for Pareyson, is what includes sensa- organizational event like “I don’t like this thing,” it tion and sentiment, and it constitutes the principle is unarguable, given that further reason-based of the aesthetic nature of knowledge: negotiation on the matter is impossible. Sensible knowledge reveals the continuous in- Knowledge does not grasp something without expressing the knower, and that expression does teractions between the knowing subject and the not express sentiments without also grasping other. The other is usually considered as a human something known. I do not know something unless I being, but also the nonhuman element sensed via express myself, and in expressing myself I declare touch, hearing, smell, sight, and taste reveals its knowledge of something. This is the principle of the active involvement in the process of producing aesthetic nature of knowledge (Pareyson, 1950; English translation, 2009: 82). sensible knowledge. To give an example, we can consider the case of honey (Merleau-Ponty, 2002; This relationship among the process of know- Strati, 2007). Honey is fluid but has some consis- ing, the formation of a subjectivity as “knower,” tency and is viscous. Whenever it is touched, it and the expression of a collective taste that sus- “touches” in its turn. The nonhuman element tains (or does not sustain) a certain way of prac- shows an ability to be active in its relationship ticing is what enables researchers to inquire into with the human being, since it takes the initiative how practitioners are able to put their passions of spattering his or her fingers with “mud,” color- into practice (Gherardi, Nicolini, & Strati, 2007) ing and perfuming them, or dirtying them. It may and how practicing their passions may contribute be unpleasant to feel honey on one’s fingers, to the development of a field of practices and to a negative emotion that only subsides when the the elaboration of an aesthetics of practice. honey stops “touching” the fingers. One may feel disgust at the viscosity of the honey, or, alterna- tively, one may feel pleasure at its sweetness and Inseparability of Knowing and Sensing: How perfume. These are sensitive judgments of the Sensible Knowing Is Embodied in Practicing senses, as if they were the body’s thought. In fact, In the writings of Pareyson, language mainly sensory activity always involves passion, and ev- depicts the single individual knower in relation ery sensation is affective. In other words, sensible with the world, while the collective and social knowledge involves what is “got” emotionally—the dimension of sensations, sentiments, and sensory affectivity connected with what is perceived, taste- knowledge has to be intuited rather than read. By based judgment, the style of action. contrast, a practice approach addresses the same The valorization of aesthetics in organizational phenomena in their social dimension, leaving the practices has led to the appreciation of the corpo- individual in the background. We emphazised reality of personal knowledge in the process of the collective dimension of knowing in practice in knowing in practice. It shows that knowing cannot the previous section, and we pass now to focusing be confined to the sphere of cognition, nor should more on the individual, embodied, and sensory all forms of knowledge be translated into cognitive knowledge. In fact, the relationship between knowledge. Rather, due account should be taken of the (individual) body—origin of sensations and the personal knowledge based on the faculty of emotions—and the process of interpreting and re- aesthetic judgment and the perceptive-sensorial lating is at the heart of what constitutes sensory capacities. On this rests the radical break of knowledge and how it is shaped by social processes practice-based studies with the dominant tradition and shapes social processes in working practices. of cognitive theory as regards knowing in practice. People participate in working practices on the A radical break to which Formativita` has contrib- basis of their individual capacities to see, hear, uted: “It is always a concrete person that, from his/ smell, taste, feel, and judge aesthetically. It is this her point of view, seeks to render and bring to life that differentiates between them, given that not the work as itself wants” (Pareyson, 1988: 11). everyone sees the same things, reacts to the same odors, or has the same taste. There are those who CONCLUSIONS “have an eye” for things while others do not, those who have an “ear” or a “nose,” and those who are In this essay we have illustrated how the phil- “good with their hands” or “have taste.” This is osophical aesthetics expounded in Pareyson’s personal knowledge that is ineradicable and ir- Estetica: Teoria della formativita` has been rele- reducible. In fact, if we take a remark on an vant to the study of social practices in organizational 754 Academy of Management Review October life. We have shown that this happened in the This is why the issue of the lack of prompt context of renewed interest in organization translations into other languages like English or studies toward philosophical aesthetics that French or Spanish is so important. Certainly, the was developed through organizational aesthetics recent translations of Formativita` —even though research (Chytry, 2008; Guillet de Monthoux, 2004; there is not yet a complete translation of the book in Strati, 1999) and the debate on the concept of English—have prompted us to illustrate its im- practice and of knowing and learning in organi- portance both for Italian aesthetic philosophy and, zation that has configured practice-based studies especially, for the study of organizational life. (Gherardi & Strati, 2012). Thus, “philosophy” con- stituted the link between Pareyson’s Formativita` REFERENCES and the aesthetic discourse on organizational life, Addison, J., & Steele, R. 1982. (First published in 1712.) Selec- while “practice” constituted the link among for- tions from The Tatler and The Spectator. (Edited by A. mativeness, organizational aesthetics research, Ross.) London: Penguin. and practice-based studies. We have argued that Anceschi, L. 1936. Autonomia ed eteronomia dell’arte. Saggio these two terms—philosophy and practice—are di fenomenologia delle poetiche. Milano: Garzanti. closely bound up with each other in Pareyson’s Banfi, A. 1988. (First published in 1947.) Vita dell’arte. Scritti di aesthetic theory, as well as in other Italian philos- estetica e di filosofia dell’arte—Opere, vol. V. (Edited by ophies contemporary with Pareyson’sthought— E. Mattioli & G. Scaramuzza.) Reggio Emilia: Istituto A. Banfi. that is, Anceschi’s (1936) and Banfi’s (1988/1947) phenomenological aesthetics and Della Volpe’s Baumgarten, A. G. 1750–1758. Aesthetica, vols. I–II. Frankfurt am Oder: Kleyb. (1960) neo-Marxist aesthetics. Pareyson pointed out this theoretical relation throughout Formativita` , Blackler, F., & Regan, S. 2009. Intentionality, agency, change: Practice theory and management. Management Learn- from the preface onward: ing, 40: 161–176. The aesthetic theory proposed in this book starts Carravetta, P. 2010. Review article: Form, person, and in- from the aesthetic experience and then returns to it exhaustible interpretation: Luigi Pareyson, Existence, In- according to the above idea of philosophy as based terpretation, Freedom. Selected Writings. Translated, and on the inseparability of experience and thought, so with an introduction, by Paolo . Davies that it is constantly open to ever new contributions Group Publishers, 2009. Parrhesia, 12: 99–108. and ever new developments. It arose from living Chytry, J. 2008. Organizational aesthetics: The artful firm and contact with the aestheticexperienceasitresults the aesthetic moment in contemporary business and from the industriousness of artists, studied both in management theory. Aesthesis: International Journal of their ongoing work and their valuable thoughts and Art and Aesthetics in Management and Organizational statements about it, from the activity of readers and Life, 2(2): 60–72. Available at http://digitalcommons.wpi. interpreters and art critics,aswellasfromtheatti- edu/aesthesis/23. tudes of the producers and contemplators of beauty Croce, B. 1902. Estetica come scienza dell’espressione e lin- wherever this is to be found, either in the natural guistica generale. Milano: Adelphi. sphere or in the practical and intellectual one (1988: 8). D’Angelo, P. 1997. L’estetica italiana del Novecento. Roma– The core of the aesthetics set out in Formativita` is Bari: Laterza. “doing” in practice, which is why it is a philosophy Dean, J. W., Ramirez, R., & Ottensmeyer, E. 1997. An aesthetic that has a “concrete character because it starts from perspective on organizations. In C. Cooper & S. Jackson experience and adheres to it” (Pareyson, 1988: 17) and (Eds.), Creating tomorrow’s organizations: A handbook for future research in organizational behavior: 419–437. aspeculativecharacterthatpreventsitfrombeing Chichester, UK: Wiley. reduced to experience and being identified with it. Della Volpe, G. 1960. Critica del gusto. Milano: Feltrinelli. It is a strong and forcefully expressed philosoph- ical . It starts with opposition to the idealism Feldman, M., & Orlikowski, W. 2011. Theorizing practice and practicing theory. Organization Science, 22: 1240–1253. of Benedetto Croce and dissent with the hermeneutic aesthetics of Heidegger, and it ends with the differ- Gadamer, H. G. 1977. Die Aktualitat¨ des Schonen.¨ Kunst als Spiel, Symbol und Fest. Stuttgart: Phillip Reclam Jr. ences that distinguish it from Italian phenomeno- logical or Marxist aesthetics. There are no other Gagliardi, P. 2006. Exploring the aesthetic side of organiza- tional life. In S. R. Clegg, C. Hardy, T. B. Lawrence, Italian aesthetic philosophies that had so much im- & W. R. Nord (Eds.), The Sage handbook of organization portance in the Italian philosophical landscape of studies: 701–724. London: Sage. the post-World War II period and the years of re- Garfinkel, H. 1967. Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood construction and the Italian miracle. Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. 2017 What Inspires the Academy: Book Reviews and Beyond 755

Gherardi, S. 2000. Practice-based theorizing on learning and Pareyson, L. 1966. Conversazioni di estetica. Milano: Mursia. knowing in organizations: An introduction. Organization, Pareyson, L. 1988. Estetica: Teoria della formativita` (4th ed.). – 7: 211 223. Milano: Bompiani. ’ Gherardi, S. 2009. Practice? It s a matter of taste! Management Pareyson, L. 2013. Truth and interpretation.(TranslatedbyR.T. – Learning, 40: 535 550. Valgenti.) Albany, NY: SUNY Press. (Original Italian publica- Gherardi, S., Nicolini, D., & Strati, A. 2007. The passion for tion: Pareyson, L. 1971. Veritaeinterpretazione.` Milano: Mursia.) – knowing. Organization, 14: 309 323. Polanyi, M. 1958. Personal knowledge. Towards a post-critical Gherardi, S., & Perrotta, M. 2014. Between the hand and the philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. head: How things get done, and how in doing the ways of Przychodzen, J., Boucher, F. E., & David, S. (Eds.). 2010. doing are discovered. Qualitative Research in Organiza- L’esthetique´ du beau ordinaire dans une perspective tion and Management, 9: 134–150. transdisciplinaire. Ni du gouffre ni du ciel. Paris: Gherardi, S., & Strati, A. 2012. Learning and knowing in l’Harmattan. practice-based studies. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. Restaino, F. 1991. Storia dell’estetica moderna. Torino: UTET. Guillet de Monthoux, P. 2004. The art firm: Aesthetic man- Rouse, J. 2001. Two concepts of practices. In T. R. Schatzki, agement and metaphysical marketing from Wagner to K. Knorr-Cetina, & E. von Savigny (Eds.), The practice turn Wilson. Stanford, CA: Business Books. in contemporary theory: 189–198. London: Routledge. Hennion, A. 2001. Music lovers. Taste as performance. Theory, Shotter, J. 2012. Knowledge in transition: The role of pro- Culture & Society, 18(5): 1–22. spective, descriptive concepts in a practice-situated, Hennion, A. 2004. Une sociologie des attachements: D’une hermeneutical-phronetic social science. Management sociologie de la culture a` une pragmatique de l’amateur. Learning, 43: 245–260. Societ´ es,´ 85(3): 9–24. Strati, A. 1992. Aesthetic understanding of organizational life. Human Relations. 2002. Special issue on organizing aes- Academy of Management Review, 17: 568–581. thetics, 55(7). Strati, A. 1999. Organization and aesthetics. London: Sage. Knorr-Cetina, K. 2001. Objectual practice. In T. R. Schatzki, Strati, A. 2007. Sensible knowledge and practice-based K. Knorr-Cetina, & E. von Savigny (Eds.), The practice turn learning. Management Learning, 38: 61–77. in contemporary theory: 184–197. London: Routledge. Strati, A. 2016. Aesthetics and design: An epistemology of the Linstead, S. & Hopfl,¨ H. (Eds.). 2000. The aesthetics of organi- unseen. In R. Mir, H. Willmott, & M. Greenwood (Eds.), The zation. London: Sage. Routledge companion to philosophy in organization – Merleau-Ponty, M. 2002. Causeries 1948. Paris: Editions´ du Seuil. studies: 251 259. London: Routledge. Organization. 1996. Special issue on aesthetics and organi- Strati, A., & Gherardi, S. 2015. La philosophie de Luigi zation, 3(2). Pareyson et la recherche esthetique´ des pratiques organisationnelles: Un dialogue. Le Libellio d’Aegis, Pareyson, L. 1943. Studi sull’esistenzialismo. Firenze: Sansoni. 11(3): 21–33. Available at http://lelibellio.com/. (Partial English translation: Pareyson, L. 2009. Existence, Tiberghien, G. A. 2007. Introduction. In L. Pareyson, Esthe-´ interpretation, freedom: Selected writings. [Edited and tique: Theorie´ de la formativite´:3–18. (Translated into translated by P. D. Bubbio.] Aurora, CO: Davies Group.) French by G. A. Tiberghien.) Paris: Editions´ Rue d’Ulm. Pareyson, L. 1950. Arte e conoscenza: Intuizione e inter- Vattimo, G. 1977. Introduzione. In G. Vattimo (Ed.), Estetica pretazione. Filosofia, 2. (Partial English translation: moderna:7–46. Bologna: Il Mulino. Pareyson, L. 2009: Existence, interpretation, freedom: Selected writings. [Edited and translated by P. D. Bubbio.] Vercellone, F., Bertinetto, A., & Garelli, G. 2003. Storia del- Aurora, CO: Davies Group.) l’estetica moderna e contemporanea. Bologna: Il Mulino. Pareyson, L. 1954. Estetica: Teoria della formativita` . Torino: Vico, G. 1725. Principi di una scienza nuova. Napoli: Mosca. Edizioni di Filosofia. (Partial English translation: Pareyson, L. Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical investigations. London: 2009. Existence, interpretation, freedom: Selected writings. Blackwell. [Edited and translated by P. D. Bubbio.] Aurora, CO: Davies Group.) https://doi.org/10.5465/amr.20160165RE Copyright of Academy of Management Review is the property of Academy of Management and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.