An Introduction to the Hermeneutics of Luigi Pareyson
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Differentia: Review of Italian Thought Number 3 Combined Issue 3-4 Spring/Autumn Article 22 1989 An Introduction to the Hermeneutics of Luigi Pareyson Peter Carravetta Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.library.stonybrook.edu/differentia Recommended Citation Carravetta, Peter (1989) "An Introduction to the Hermeneutics of Luigi Pareyson," Differentia: Review of Italian Thought: Vol. 3 , Article 22. Available at: https://commons.library.stonybrook.edu/differentia/vol3/iss1/22 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Academic Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Differentia: Review of Italian Thought by an authorized editor of Academic Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. An Introduction to the Hermeneutics of Luigi Pareyson Peter Carravetta La vera interpretazionee quella che si consegueai limiti de/la comprensibilita.-L. Pareyson 1. PREMISES This introductory critical assessment of Luigi Pareyson' s thought, being part of a larger project, 1 is to be understood bearing the following three perspectives in mind. First, within the horizon of the theory-method relation. Second, in terms of a referential hermeneutic yardstick which will serve as an external, "empirical control," or better yet, a screen upon which to trace the movements of about ten conditions to be met. And third, in view of a still-in progress idea of interpretation as diaphoristics. Concerning the first parameter, we are provisionally going to assume that interpretation is constituted and activated by a grounding dialectic between the requirements of epistemology, which underlie and legitimate methodic process, and those of ontology, which are inherent in theory. Otherwise stated, one cannot use or apply a critical method without at the same time positing a referential ontology, whether explicitly or tacitly; vice DIFFERENT/A 3-4 (Spring/Autumn 1989) 0/FFERENTIA 218 versa, one cannot theorize about any object or phenomenon, be it Picasso's Guernica, the university system or Kafka's texts, with out resorting to certain systematic, organizational "moves," in other words, without doing it methodically. This will explain, I hope, my emphasis on specific key terms and tenets of Pareyson's thought, instead of others which, though important enough to warrant other perspectives, need not occupy us here. 2 The second parameter for our reading is constituted by certain more or less established principles of hermeneutics as derived primarily from the tradition that leads into, and is systematized by, the work of Hans-Georg Gadamer. A makeshift compendium of Gadamer's thought-which is at the same time sensitive to the conceptual innovations brought about by Schleiermacher, Hegel, Dilthey, Husserl and Heidegger 3-would give us the following decalogue: Interpretation is, intrinsically, historical,linguistic, dialectic,ontolog ical, the event of being, objective,begins with the text, exists within the present of the interpreter, is a disclosingof truth, and, finally, interpre tation is the locus where the aesthetichas beenabsorbed by or transformed into the genuinely hermeneutic.4 The specific range and depth of each of these terms will become evident through this reading and in the conclusions. The critical metaphor of the Diaphoraderives from another context, one in which poetry and philosophy are not conceived as being in opposition to each other, or in radical, mutually exclu sive antithesis, but, rather, as necessarily co-originary and thus constantly con-versing. The interpretation of the text comes into existence when it enters this field, initiating a dialogue with several voices, a mise-en-scene which might be, but does not have to be a mise-en-abyme, a speaking, we might say, with several possible differentiated characters. 5 2. AESTHETICS First published in 1954 after studies on existentialism, Jaspers and German idealism, 6 Luigi Pareyson's Estetica: teoria della for mativita is the third and last (after Croce's and Gentile's) of the great books on aesthetics written in this century in Italy, coming out at a time when this genre seemed to have outlived its reason to be.7 The importance of this work rests on its being the first, at least in the Italian panorama, to deal with the beingof the interpreter and the being of art, setting them in relation by means of interpre- PETER CARRAVETTA 219 tation itself, and describing the process in ontological terms. The key term in Pareyson is Forma in its dynamic, interacting sense. As such Forma is, at any one time, either forma formante-form as an enabling process which gives a specific shape to whatever it is dealing with-or forma formata-form as what something exhibits when at rest, what makes it recognizable as such. Pareyson anchors his vision in the heart of human existence, believing that humankind in its broadest sense is essentially a producer of forms (Estetica19-23 et passim). Thus Forma exists" as an organism living of its own life and inner legitimation, closed and open both within the definiteness that encloses the infinite" [comeorganismo vivente di propria vita e legalita interna, conclusaed aperta insieme nella sua definitezza che racchiudel'infinito]. From these premises, art is described by means of a phenomenology of its realization or "coming into being" [nel suo farsi]. Here we discover that art is both production and invention, which means that in effect art is a making which invents its own manner or way of doing, realizing itself as a series of attempts toward a successful or fulfilled completion [tentativi verso la rius cita]. One cannot produce art without inventing the means to "make" it, but, by the same token, one does not invent anything unless it is also produced, made real. The underlying principle is called forming-activity [formativita, literally 'formativity'], 8 which assumes a content, a material means and an inner working law peculiar and specific to it (E 22-27). Among the preliminary find ings of this position is that, above all, art is conscious of and respects the alterity of the work, "protecting" it so to speak from blind insight or misguided appropriation. Later, the same concern with alterity will mark interpretation in general. 3. ART If, as Pareyson holds, art is a forming-activity both specific and intentional, then the question arises: How do we distinguish it from the rest of experience, if our entire existence is dependent upon this forming capacity? First point: Art has no pre-establishedend-that is, it is not a forming-activity-of anything in particular, but form which aims at becoming Form, and that's all. Notice how this sounds very much like what was postulated by such diverse and indeed strange bedfellows as Benedetto Croce and Gertrude Stein. But this ought not to be seen as a contradiction or inconsistency as much as the fullest exploitation of what both the Idealistic tradition and the DIFFERENT/A 220 Idealism of all theorizing done by artists in general have yielded as unshakable premises of cultural humankind: every person is an idealist at one time or another; moreover, let's not forget that idealist/idealism contains the root notion of idea, eidos, vision. However, we will also see radical divergencies among these posi tions once we explore other aspects. For instance, Pareyson says that thinking and ethics, though subordinated to the "formation principle," interact with it, so that the forming-activity [formativita] is directed at a given action or phenomenon by taking into consid eration thought-i.e., that which thought has formulated-while at the same time respecting its alterity. This argument rests on the fundamental ontology of the persona, or person, which in Pareyson embodies the opening or disclosedness as the coinci dence of self-relation and hetero-relation. Person, in short, can be thought of as the recognition of alterity, and is therefore emi nently social, interpersonal. It can be seen that the argument is pointing toward a dialogics of sorts. But to defer this discussion, it should also be clear that art may-it doesn't have to-incorporate the contribution of thought (of ethics, ideology, politics), without sacrificing its primary ideal, which is to become Form. 9 This will be crucial to criticism, as we will see further down. On the other hand, even in terms of action guided by what sounds like a very pragmatic telos-whether it regards shaping an idea, or a simple constructive gesture, or even just going through the rituals of everydayness handed down through his tory-people always try to do things "aesthetically." In the original Italian, Pareyson relies on the idiomatic expression fare le case ad arte, literally "to make things as if they were a work of art," better yet, "to do it right," or according to the inner necessity to do things well, perfectly and beautifully. In art there's a shaping activity which seeks the Forming process itself : though each and every human action is forming-activity [formativita],the work qua work of art is Formation [formazione],"in the sense that the work intentionally aims at Formation, and thought and action intervene only in order to insure that it reaches it" (E 23). The work of art is also intrinsically matter/substance, in Italian materia, a concrete entity that denies the genitive to art insofar as it must evidence itself as pure form. As such, the material aspect of the work sets up a polarity with respect to the shaping principle of the artistic process, which is identified as puro tentare, pure groping and attempting. 10 This calls to mind another vector, the pull of interpretive dynamics, the seeking of a path guided by a Form which is not yet there (and is, therefore, unknown, ungrasp able, invisible so to speak) and must, therefore, be guessed or divined: PETER CARRAVETTA 221 The divination of form is thus only a law guiding the execution in progress, a law that cannot be explicated in terms of precepts, but rather, as an inner norm of the action aiming at its successful completion [alla riuscita]; thus it is not a single law valid for all artistic cases, but a rule which is immanent to the one specific process in question.