Practical Language: Its Meaning and Use

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Practical Language: Its Meaning and Use View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Practical Language: Its Meaning and Use by Nathan A. Charlow A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in The University of Michigan 2011 Doctoral Committee: Professor Allan F. Gibbard, Chair Professor Richmond H. Thomason Assistant Professor Ezra Russell Keshet Assistant Professor Eric Peter Swanson Professor Paul H. Portner, Georgetown University © Nathan A. Charlow 2011 All Rights Reserved For P&N ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS It was a great surprise to have to finish this dissertation so soon. It was also a huge task. I want to thank so many people for their help with it. I will, I’m sure, forget a few of you. I especially want to thank Allan Gibbard for taking this project on. I am sure he was a bit skeptical about why a philosopher of language would wish to be supervised by an ethicist. In reading this, I think he (and you) will see why it made such good sense. My brother Simon introduced me to hardcore formal semantics and kept me in touch with the field during the years when Michigan lacked a bona fide semanticist. He, more than anyone else, helped me to become a linguist in addition to a philosopher. Eric Swanson has been my mentor since I took the plunge into philosophical linguistics in his 2006 seminar. He has read and given comments on nearly everything I have written since then. I owe him a great deal. Rich Thomason taught me modal logic. It has served me better than any other tool I acquired during graduate school. Rich also pressed me early and often with questions about the conceptual foundations of what I was doing with imperatives and Expressivism. I hope I’ve been able to answer some of those questions in what follows. I learned an incredible amount from Thony Gillies and Peter Ludlow. Thony introduced me to Paul Portner’s work on imperatives, which is the foil for so much of what follows here, and he supervised my Candidacy Dossier, for which I eventually won the Charles L. Stevenson Prize. Peter taught me Heim and Kratzer, and was the first person I knew to try and give Allan’s Expressivism its linguistic due. Mark van Roojen and Al Casullo are pretty much wholly responsible for my going to graduate school. I’m glad to call them my friends. For sundry inspiration, advice, and discussion, I’m grateful to Chris Barker, Gordon Belot, Billy Dunaway, Kai von Fintel, Benj Hellie, Lina Jansson, Ezra Keshet, Sam Liao, Clayton Littlejohn, Sarah Moss, Dilip Ninan, David Plunkett, Paul Portner, Peter Railton, Craige Roberts, Anders Schoubye, Alex Silk, Will Starr, Andreas Stokke, Sergio Tenenbaum, Dustin Tucker, Jonathan Weisberg, and Jessica Wilson. My Michigan friends are the best. Lina Jansson is a great person, a great philosopher, and was an ideal flatmate for the past two years. Jason Konek turned down a record deal with Akon to be my roommate for my first two years in Michigan. Sam Liao and I have shared many good times, in bars, in restaurants, in New York, Bloomington, and New Haven. Dave Wiens helped me remember how awful I am at basketball. Alex Plakias has iii impeccable taste in Nineties Hip-Hop. Eduardo García-Ramírez’s friendship was especially important to me last year. There is no way that I would have found a job—even secured an interview—without Linda Shultes’ tireless help. Judith Beck has been unfailingly warm and helpful. Molly Mahony kept my spirits up during the job market. Thank you all. I will keep things informal for people, things, and cats non-academic. *zilla. VT. Jingjing. Zingerman’s, which still makes the best Americano in Ann Arbor. Rori Cat, my beloved three-fanged, barbarically yawping hillbilly =^-_-^= Lots of love to C. Qui nolet fieri desidiosus, amet. Finally, thanks Mom. Thanks Dad. I love you both. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS DEDICATION ........................................ ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ................................. iii LIST OF APPENDICES . viii ABSTRACT .......................................... ix CHAPTER I. Introduction ....................................1 1.1 Interest...................................1 1.2 Overview..................................2 1.3 Synopsis...................................4 1.3.1 Identifying a Conventional Use................4 1.3.2 Embeddings...........................6 1.3.3 Applications: Expressivism and Conditionals.......7 II. Dynamic Accounts and the Problematics of Conventional Force ...... 10 2.1 Masters, Slaves, and Permissibility Spheres.............. 11 2.2 A Less Idealized Model.......................... 13 2.3 Imperatives and Obligation-Imposition................. 15 2.4 Non-Command Uses........................... 18 2.4.1 The Data............................. 18 2.4.2 Interpretation and Explanation................ 20 2.4.3 A Problem: Instruction Imperatives............. 22 2.4.4 A Ninan-Inspired Reply?................... 23 2.4.5 Varieties of Permission..................... 26 2.5 Recap.................................... 30 III. Imperatives and Necessitation .......................... 32 3.1 Indirect Speech Acts: A Primer in Defeasibility............ 33 3.2 Conventions as Defaults......................... 37 3.2.1 Convention and Cancellation................. 38 3.2.2 The Mechanics of Interpretation............... 41 v 3.2.3 Data for Declaratives and Interrogatives........... 44 3.3 Imperatives Express Necessitation.................... 45 3.3.1 Conventional Use Data.................... 46 3.3.2 Necessitation Data....................... 48 3.4 Computing ISAs.............................. 50 3.4.1 ISAs in General......................... 50 3.4.2 Voiding.............................. 53 3.4.3 Binding............................. 55 3.4.4 Permission as an ISA...................... 57 3.4.5 Instruction as an ISA...................... 62 3.5 Recap.................................... 66 IV. A Dynamic Theory of Imperative Meaning .................. 67 4.1 A “Standard” Account.......................... 69 4.1.1 Motivations........................... 70 4.1.2 Modeling the Standard Notion of a Speech Act....... 76 4.2 Information, Issues, and Preferences.................. 81 4.2.1 Information States....................... 81 4.2.2 Integrating Issues........................ 82 4.2.3 Integrating Preferences..................... 85 4.2.4 A Compositional System................... 87 4.3 Direction as Necessitation (as Coming to Recognize a Requirement) 93 4.3.1 Imperative Presuppositions.................. 93 4.3.2 Coming to Recognize a Requirement............. 98 4.3.3 Instituting Requirements................... 99 4.3.4 Conservative Preference Update................ 101 4.3.5 Prima Facie and Inconsistent Directives........... 107 4.3.6 Instituting Recognition..................... 109 4.3.7 Requirement Recognition as Decision............ 113 4.3.8 Strong Permission as Recognized Permission........ 115 4.3.9 Practical Questions and Preferential Issues......... 117 4.3.10 Summing Up.......................... 119 4.4 Against the Standard Account...................... 121 4.4.1 Bad Arguments Against the Standard Account....... 121 4.4.2 The Challenge of Embedded Imperatives.......... 129 4.4.3 Regular Operations....................... 131 4.4.4 Conjunction: Contrived Examples.............. 133 4.4.5 Conjunction: Sequencing Designation............ 135 4.4.6 Disjunction, Permission Content, and the Ross Paradox.. 137 4.4.7 Quantifiers?........................... 151 4.5 Conditional Imperatives......................... 162 4.5.1 A Standard Account (Wide-Scoping)............. 163 4.5.2 Conditional Speech Acts (Narrow-Scoping)......... 166 4.5.3 Challenging the Dynamic Program: The Modal Analysis. 169 4.5.4 Against the Modal Analysis.................. 173 4.5.5 A New Account......................... 178 4.5.6 The Semantics of Conditional Requirements........ 187 vi 4.5.7 Conditional Imperatives as Fundamental.......... 193 4.5.8 Upshot.............................. 195 V. Concluding Remarks ............................... 197 5.1 Taking Stock................................ 197 5.2 Editorial Digression............................ 197 5.3 Meaning, Force, Semantics, and Logic.................. 199 APPENDICES ......................................... 201 BIBLIOGRAPHY ....................................... 271 vii LIST OF APPENDICES Appendix A. Meaning for Expressivists.............................. 202 B. Conditional Utility, Preference, Obligations, and Imperatives......... 234 viii ABSTRACT Practical Language: Its Meaning and Use by Nathan A. Charlow Chair: Allan F. Gibbard I demonstrate that a “speech act” theory of meaning for imperatives is—contra a dominant position in philosophy and linguistics—theoretically desirable. A speech act- theoretic account of the meaning of an imperative !f is characterized, broadly, by the following claims. LINGUISTIC MEANING AS USE !f’s meaning is a matter of the speech act an utterance of it convention- ally functions to express—what a speaker conventionally uses it to do (its conventional discourse function, CDF). IMPERATIVE USE AS PRACTICAL !f’s CDF is to express a practical (non-representational) state of mind—one concerning an agent’s preferences and plans, rather than her beliefs. Opposed to speech act accounts is a preponderance of views which deny that a sentence’s linguistic meaning is a matter of what speech act it is used to perform, or its CDF. On such accounts, meaning is, instead, a matter of “static” properties of the sentence—e.g.,
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy: Third Edition Robert Audi & Paul Audi Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-01505-0 - The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy: Third Edition Robert Audi & Paul Audi Frontmatter More information THE CAMBRIDGE DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY THIRD EDITION This is the most comprehensive dictionary of philosophical terms and thinkers available in English. Previously acclaimed as the most author- itative and accessible dictionary of philosophy in any language, it has been widely translated and has served both professional philosophers and students of philosophy worldwide. Written by a team of more than 550 experts – including more than 100 new to this third edition – the dictionary contains approximately 5,000 entries ranging from short definitions to full-length articles. It concisely defines terms, concretely illustrates ideas, and informatively describes philosophers. It is designed to facilitate the understanding of philosophy at all levels and in all fields. Key features of this third edition: Some 500 new entries covering both Eastern and Western philosophy, as well as individual countries such as China, France, Germany, Italy, and Spain Increased coverage of such growing fields as ethics and philosophy of mind Scores of new intellectual portraits of leading contemporary thinkers Wider coverage of Continental philosophy Dozens of new concepts in cognitive science and other areas Enhanced cross-referencing to add context and to increase under- standing Expansions of both text and index to facilitate research and browsing Robert Audi is John A. O’Brien Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame. He is the author of numerous books and articles. His recent books include Moral Perception (2013); Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State (2011); Rationality and Religious Commitment (2011); Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge (2010); and Moral Value and Human Diversity (2007).
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Logic, Second Edition
    Introduction to Logic “This new edition is a significant improvement on an already excellent text. The virtues of the original remain including clear expositions, an intuitive proof procedure that generalizes naturally from propositional logic to more advanced logics and a wealth of problems drawn from philosophical sources. There are new chapters on the history of logic, deviant logics and the philoso- phy of logic and the accompanying LogiCola program has been improved. This is a student friendly approach to logic.” Michael Bradie, Bowling Green State University Introduction to Logic combines likely the broadest scope of any logic textbook with clear, concise writing and interesting examples and arguments. Its key features, all retained in the Second Edition, include: • Simpler ways to test arguments, including the star test for syllogisms • A wide scope of materials, suiting it for introductory or intermediate courses • Engaging examples, from everyday life and the great philosophers • Useful for self-study and preparation for standardized tests, like the LSAT • A reasonable price (a third the cost of some competitors) • Exercises that correspond to the free LogiCola instructional program This Second Edition also: • Arranges chapters in a more natural way, going from easier to more difficult material • Adds new chapters on history of logic, deviant logic, and philosophy of logic • Refines many explanations and expands several sections (such as informal fallacies and relational translations) • Includes a fuller index and a new appendix on suggested further readings • Updates LogiCola, which is now more visually attractive and easier to down- load, update, and use (install from http://www.jcu.edu/philosophy/gensler/lc or http://www.routledge.com/textbooks/9780415996518) Harry J.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Semantics for Imperatives
    JPhilosLogic DOI 10.1007/s10992-013-9284-4 Logic and Semantics for Imperatives Nate Charlow Received: 11 May 2012 / Accepted: 26 March 2013 ©SpringerScience+BusinessMediaDordrecht2013 Abstract In this paper I will develop a view about the semantics of imperatives, which I term Modal Noncognitivism, on which imperatives might be said to have truth conditions (dispositionally, anyway), but on which it does not make sense to see them as expressing propositions (hence does not make sense to ascribe to them truth or falsity). This view stands against “Cognitivist” accounts of the semantics of imper- atives, on which imperatives are claimedtoexpresspropositions,whicharethen enlisted in explanations of the relevant logico-semantic phenomena. It also stands against the major competitors to Cognitivist accounts—all of which are non-truth- conditional and, as a result, fail to provide satisfying explanations of the fundamental semantic characteristics of imperatives (or so I argue). The view of imperatives I defend here improves on various treatments of imperatives on the market in giving an empirically and theoretically adequate account of their semantics and logic. It yields explanations of a wide range of semantic and logical phenomena about imperatives— explanations that are, I argue, at least as satisfying as the sorts of explanations of semantic and logical phenomena familiar from truth-conditional semantics. But it accomplishes this while defending the notion—which is, I argue, substantially correct—that imperatives could not have propositions, or truth conditions, as their meanings. This work has benefited greatly from the input of others. I would like to thank Andrew Alwood, Chris Barker, Simon Charlow, Allan Gibbard, Benj Hellie, Paul Portner, Will Starr, Eric Swanson, and Richmond Thomason, as well as audiences at the Association for Symbolic Logic’s 2011 APA Group Session on Dynamic Semantics, Cornell University, Ecole´ Normale Sup´erieure, NYU, University of Toronto, and York University.
    [Show full text]
  • What the Tortoise Said to Kripke: the Adoption Problem and the Epistemology of Logic
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 2-2015 What the Tortoise Said to Kripke: the Adoption Problem and the Epistemology of Logic Romina Padro Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/603 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] WHAT THE TORTOISE SAID TO KRIPKE: THE ADOPTION PROBLEM AND THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF LOGIC by ROMINA PADRO A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2015 © 2015 ROMINA PADRO All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Gary Ostertag October 7th, 2014 _________________________________ Date Chair of Examining Committee Rosemarie Iannuzzi October 7th, 2014 _________________________________ Date Executive Officer Michael Devitt, Advisor Arnold Koslow Michael Levin Paul Boghossian Supervisory Committee THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii Abstract WHAT THE TORTOISE SAID TO KRIPKE: THE ADOPTION PROBLEM AND THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF LOGIC by ROMINA PADRO Advisor: Michael Devitt In chapter 1 I introduce the main topics to be addressed and provide a summary of the dissertation. In chapter 2 I summarize Lewis Carroll’s famous note “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles” and briefly review some of its most influential interpretations.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic A-Z from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Chapter 1
    Logic A-Z From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Chapter 1 Antepredicament Antepredicaments, in logic, are certain previous matters requisite to a more easy and clear apprehension of the doctrine of predicaments or categories. Such are definitions of common terms, as equivocals, univocals, etc., with divisions of things, their differences, etc. They are thus called because Aristotle treated them before the predicaments, hoping that the thread of discourse might not afterwards be interrupted. 1.1 References • This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain: Chambers, Ephraim, ed. (1728). "*article name needed". Cyclopædia, or an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences (first ed.). James and John Knapton, et al. 2 Chapter 2 Apophasis Not to be confused with Apophysis (disambiguation), Apoptosis, or Apophis (disambiguation). Apophasis is a rhetorical device wherein the speaker or writer brings up a subject by either denying it, or denying that it should be brought up.*[1] Accordingly, it can be seen as a rhetorical relative of irony. Also called paralipsis (παράλειψις) – also spelled paraleipsis or paralepsis –, or occupatio,*[2]*[3]*[4]*[5] and known also as prae- teritio, preterition, antiphrasis (ἀντίφρασις), or parasiopesis (παρασιώπησις), apophasis is usually employed to make a subversive ad hominem attack, which makes it a frequently used tactic in political speeches to make an attack on one's opponent. Using apophasis in this way is often considered to be bad form. The device is typically used to distance
    [Show full text]