European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, VII-1 | 2015 Interview with Hilary Putnam 2

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, VII-1 | 2015 Interview with Hilary Putnam 2 European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy VII-1 | 2015 The Pragmatist Method Interview with Hilary Putnam Michela Bella, Anna Boncompagni and Hilary Putnam Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/357 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.357 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Michela Bella, Anna Boncompagni and Hilary Putnam, « Interview with Hilary Putnam », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], VII-1 | 2015, Online since 07 July 2015, connection on 15 September 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/357 This text was automatically generated on 15 September 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Interview with Hilary Putnam 1 Interview with Hilary Putnam Michela Bella, Anna Boncompagni and Hilary Putnam EDITOR'S NOTE The interviews are part of the project “Strengthening the relevance of the American Philosophy to Contemporary Philosophia in Europe and America” sponsored by the Society for the Advancement of Amercian Philosophy and University of Molise. Michela BELLA & Anna BONCOMPAGNI – This conversation will focus on your role and your position with respect to pragmatism; those who you consider allies and enemies in the field; and then finally your ideas about the future of philosophy and the future of pragmatism. You worked with famous philosophers like Carnap, Reichenbach and many others. But let us start from the beginning. Hilary PUTNAM – My alma mater was the University of Pennsylvania. The first teacher who really influenced me there was a pragmatist. His is an interesting story. His name was C. West Churchman. (I do not know what his first name was, because he obviously did not like it.) He was a philosopher of science for a while, but then he eventually left the field of philosophy, and became Professor of Operations Research at the University of California. He was a pragmatist, and he was a student – which makes me a “grandstudent” – of a philosopher named E. A. Singer Jr., who was in turn a student of William James. Singer created a pragmatist tradition at the University of Pennsylvania. The other pragmatist at that point – she did not even have tenure, she was just an assistant professor but later she became a full professor – was Elizabeth Flower. So, there was a pragmatist tradition at the University of Pennsylvania. Singer was retired by the time I came, I never met him, but I heard about him from West Churchman, and I read one of his books, a little book called Modern Thinkers and Present Problems. I was strongly influenced by Churchman in my undergraduate years. For me, the pragmatist theory of truth is not that important (in fact, I regard it as mistaken), and I don’t think Churchman mentioned the pragmatist theory of truth, nor do I remember Singer’s book talking about it. But what Churchman talked about was what I call the entanglement of fact and value. I quoted in one of my books European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, VII-1 | 2015 Interview with Hilary Putnam 2 E. A. Singer, saying four things (which were in turn quoted by Churchman in his lectures): 1) knowledge of facts presupposes knowledge of values; 2) knowledge of values presupposes knowledge of facts; 3) knowledge of theories presupposes knowledge of facts; and 4) knowledge of facts presupposes knowledge of theories. I think by “facts” Singer probably meant observational facts, and by “theories” he meant things beyond observational facts. So, the idea of a triple entanglement of theory, value, and fact is what I got from Churchman and Singer. Unfortunately, I forgot all about it for quite a few years, and had to rediscover it for myself. M. B. & A. B. – This is one of the main topics of your whole work. Hilary PUTNAM – Yes, this is also a central topic of my recent work. The other teacher at the University of Pennsylvania who was very interested in and sympathetic to pragmatism, trying to bring pragmatism, logical empiricism and perhaps a little Wittgenstein together, was Morton White. (Morton White was the professor who suggested that I go to graduate school in philosophy!) He is author of a great book titled Toward Reunion in Philosophy. He and at the same time Quine attacked the analytic/synthetic dichotomy. Quine and White were friends, but neither got the idea from the other. In fact, in a paper titled “A Philosophical letter from Alfred Tarski” (published in The Journal of Philosophy in 1987), White reports that both he and Quine were influenced by Alfred Tarski, with whom Quine discussed the dichotomy and with whom White corresponded about it. In Toward Reunion in Philosophy White makes a point which Quine unfortunately rejected. White argued rightly that if the analytic/ synthetic distinction or dichotomy is untenable, so is the fact/value dichotomy. There is an argument in Toward Reunion in Philosophy that I remember very well in which White argues that when the positivists try to explain how you recognize a factual judgment, they talk about “observation predicates,” but the only way they tell you what an observation predicate is is by giving a list. So, if I say that “steal” is an observation predicate, then “he stole a purse” must be a “factual” judgment, but if I say it is a value predicate, then it must be “cognitively meaningless.” This is wholly unsatisfactory. The idea that the fact/value dichotomy falls if the analytic/synthetic distinction falls, is due to Morton White. For me, the essence of pragmatism is the idea of the entanglement of fact-value-theory. And that idea you find in James, in a lot of places, and in Dewey and in all the classical pragmatists. M. B. & A. B. – What about your successive steps? Hilary PUTNAM – I did my graduate work in three years. I spent one year at Harvard, and coincidentally Morton White left Pennsylvania and went to Harvard the same year I did. I was Morton White’s teaching fellow in a course in American philosophy at Harvard in 1948-49. But Harvard, although it admitted me, did not give me money, and when I asked if I could get financial support for the next year, they said: “You have to wait to the spring and pass the preliminary examinations for the Ph.D..” I did not want to make my future dependent on that. I wrote away for a teaching fellowship. I was offered one at Penn (where I had already been) and one at UCLA. I took the one at UCLA. There was a pragmatist there too, Abraham Kaplan, who had been a student of both Dewey and Carnap. I thought that I was going to UCLA to work with Kaplan, but he did not impress me, and I ended up working with Reichenbach, who fascinated me from day one. A wonderful human being and one of the greatest teachers on the planet. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, VII-1 | 2015 Interview with Hilary Putnam 3 M. B. & A. B. – You had conversations with him. Hilary PUTNAM – Many times. Reichenbach was a great teacher. It was not just a natural gift, although a natural gift he certainly had, it was not just his charisma: he loved pedagogy, he loved thinking about how to teach. But he also could do it and not just think about it. He gave a course in inductive logic which had 300 students. When he died, the number went down to 30, to 10, and then it was discontinued! Incredibly fascinating, his course on the philosophy of space and time. He never called himself a logical positivist. He always called himself a logical empiricist, because he didn’t like the term “positivist,” and he had the same objection Dewey had, namely that the whole idea of sense data, that everything is a construction out of our own sense data, is wrong. Reichenbach probably regarded “metaphysics” as a dirty word. However, unlike Carnap – who was always saying that metaphysics is nonsense – Reichenbach talked about Leibniz and Kant with considerable respect, especially referring to philosophy of space and time. Carnap is still much more highly reputed than Reichenbach by analytic philosophers, but I think Reichenbach’s work deserves to last, not because his views were right, but because they can be built on. Reichenbach was interested in the metaphysical implications of these great new scientific theories like quantum mechanics and relativity theory for traditional problems about the nature of time, the nature of space, causality, and so on. At this time, for example, there are philosophers like Tim Maudlin at NYU who are continuing that very well, and I think it is something that should and will continue. When I got my job at Princeton – I got my Ph.D. in 1951, I taught one year at Northwestern in Illinois, and then I got a job in Princeton starting in the fall of 1953, and that was where I met Carnap – I was hired as a philosopher of science: I had been trained by Reichenbach; my job at Northwestern had been in philosophy of science, and at Princeton I was also a philosopher of science. At the same time I was developing as a mathematician. I think that in my first decade I probably published more mathematical papers than philosophical papers. My first philosophical paper came from something I said in a conversation with Carnap, who told me “you have to published that.” It was “Synonymity, and the Analysis of Belief Sentences,” in the journal Analysis.
Recommended publications
  • IS SEMANTICS POSSIBLE? Author(S): Hilary Putnam Source: Metaphilosophy , July 1970, Vol
    IS SEMANTICS POSSIBLE? Author(s): Hilary Putnam Source: Metaphilosophy , July 1970, Vol. 1, No. 3 (July 1970), pp. 187-201 Published by: Wiley Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/24434824 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Metaphilosophy This content downloaded from 99.137.65.114 on Tue, 12 Jan 2021 15:10:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms M ETA PHILOSOPHY Vol. 1, No. 3, July 1970 IS SEMANTICS POSSIBLE?" Hilary Putnam In the last decade enormous progress seems to have been made in the syntactic theory of natural languages, largely as a result of the work of linguists influenced by Noam Chomsky and Zellig Harris. Comparable progress seems not to have been made in the semantic theory of natural languages, and perhaps it is time to ask why this should be the case. Why is the theory of meaning so hard? The meaning of common nouns. To get some idea of the difficulties, let us look at some of the problems that come up in connection with general names. General names are of many kinds.
    [Show full text]
  • John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History. Seth J
    East Tennessee State University Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University Electronic Theses and Dissertations Student Works 5-2009 John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History. Seth J. Bartee East Tennessee State University Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.etsu.edu/etd Part of the Other History Commons Recommended Citation Bartee, Seth J., "John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History." (2009). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 1859. https://dc.etsu.edu/etd/1859 This Thesis - Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Works at Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History _____________________ A thesis presented to the faculty of the Department in History East Tennessee State University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Masters of Arts in History _____________________ by Seth J. Bartee May 2009 _____________________ Dr. Melvin E. Page, Chair Dr. Daniel Newcomer Dr. William Burgess Dr. Stephen Fritz Keywords: John Dewey, Pragmatism, Historiography, Personhood, Instrumentalism ABSTRACT John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History by Seth J. Bartee John Dewey was America‟s foremost authority on many of the critical issues in the twentieth century. Dewey dedicated his professional career as an expert on the major branches of philosophy. A neglected aspect of Dewey‟s philosophy is his writings on historiography, the philosophy of history, and his influence on American historians.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae of Alvin Plantinga
    CURRICULUM VITAE OF ALVIN PLANTINGA A. Education Calvin College A.B. 1954 University of Michigan M.A. 1955 Yale University Ph.D. 1958 B. Academic Honors and Awards Fellowships Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 1968-69 Guggenheim Fellow, June 1 - December 31, 1971, April 4 - August 31, 1972 Fellow, American Academy of Arts & Sciences, 1975 - Fellow, Calvin Center for Christian Scholarship, 1979-1980 Visiting Fellow, Balliol College, Oxford 1975-76 National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowships, 1975-76, 1987, 1995-6 Fellowship, American Council of Learned Societies, 1980-81 Fellow, Frisian Academy, 1999 Gifford Lecturer, 1987, 2005 Honorary Degrees Glasgow University, l982 Calvin College (Distinguished Alumni Award), 1986 North Park College, 1994 Free University of Amsterdam, 1995 Brigham Young University, 1996 University of the West in Timisoara (Timisoara, Romania), 1998 Valparaiso University, 1999 2 Offices Vice-President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 1980-81 President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 1981-82 President, Society of Christian Philosophers, l983-86 Summer Institutes and Seminars Staff Member, Council for Philosophical Studies Summer Institute in Metaphysics, 1968 Staff member and director, Council for Philosophical Studies Summer Institute in Philosophy of Religion, 1973 Director, National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Seminar, 1974, 1975, 1978 Staff member and co-director (with William P. Alston) NEH Summer Institute in Philosophy of Religion (Bellingham, Washington) 1986 Instructor, Pew Younger Scholars Seminar, 1995, 1999 Co-director summer seminar on nature in belief, Calvin College, July, 2004 Other E. Harris Harbison Award for Distinguished Teaching (Danforth Foundation), 1968 Member, Council for Philosophical Studies, 1968-74 William Evans Visiting Fellow University of Otago (New Zealand) 1991 Mentor, Collegium, Fairfield University 1993 The James A.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1980
    Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1980 Robert L. Richardson, Jr. A dissertation submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of History. Chapel Hill 2009 Approved by, Michael H. Hunt, Chair Richard Kohn Timothy McKeown Nancy Mitchell Roger Lotchin Abstract Robert L. Richardson, Jr. Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1985 (Under the direction of Michael H. Hunt) This dissertation examines the origins and evolution of neoconservatism as a philosophical and political movement in America from 1945 to 1980. I maintain that as the exigencies and anxieties of the Cold War fostered new intellectual and professional connections between academia, government and business, three disparate intellectual currents were brought into contact: the German philosophical tradition of anti-modernism, the strategic-analytical tradition associated with the RAND Corporation, and the early Cold War anti-Communist tradition identified with figures such as Reinhold Niebuhr. Driven by similar aims and concerns, these three intellectual currents eventually coalesced into neoconservatism. As a political movement, neoconservatism sought, from the 1950s on, to re-orient American policy away from containment and coexistence and toward confrontation and rollback through activism in academia, bureaucratic and electoral politics. Although the neoconservatives were only partially successful in promoting their transformative project, their accomplishments are historically significant. More specifically, they managed to interject their views and ideas into American political and strategic thought, discredit détente and arms control, and shift U.S. foreign policy toward a more confrontational stance vis-à-vis the Soviet Union.
    [Show full text]
  • John Dewey's Legacy for the 21 Century
    John Dewey's Legacy for the 21st Century Larry A. Hickman Center for Dewey Studies Southern Illinois University Carbondale Why would anyone today think that John Dewey's ideas are still relevant to the problems of the second decade of the 21st century? For one thing, the six decades since his death in 1952 have seen enormous technical, demographic, climatic, economic, and cultural changes, to name just a few. For another, at the time of death his ideas had already been out of fashion for more than a decade. Nor would they get much in the way of respect during the remainder of the 20th century. Nostalgia aside, do we have any good reasons for continuing to read Dewey with an eye to our current situation? Tracing Lines of Intellectual Influence. Historians of philosophy and intellectual historians might answer this question by reminding us that there is still much that we do not understand about Dewey's role in the history of philosophy, and more specifically about his contributions to the development of American pragmatism and the philosophy of education. Examination of the ways his ideas relate to those of Peirce, James, Mead, Addams, and others, and especially to the many female teachers and school principals who were his collaborators and, as he said, his inspiration as well – all of this holds the promise of expanding our understanding not only of the past, but of our present and future as well. Lines of influence between Dewey and William James, for example are at this point far from clear. Since Dewey was not particularly keen on preserving his correspondence, the entire known extant James/Dewey correspondence comprises only 26 letters.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • The Challenge of Morton White and the Politics of Antiformalism
    Morton White. Social Thought in America: The Revolt Against Formalism. New York: Viking, 1949. viii + 260 pp. $6.95, cloth, ISBN 978-0-19-519837-9. Reviewed by Robert Genter Published on H-Ideas (July, 2000) [Note: This review is part of the H-Ideas Ret‐ of French existentialism than the optimism of rospective Reviews series. This series reviews American pragmatism. It was an era in which books published during the twentieth century "Dewey's views [were] being replaced by which have been deemed to be among the most Kierkegaard's" (p. 3). In this regard, White's con‐ important contributions to the feld of intellectual tribution to the feld of intellectual history in this history.] period lay not only in his particular interpretation The publication in 1949 of Morton White's of the antiformalists but in his willingness to con‐ study of late nineteenth-century antiformalism in sider their contribution to the philosophical en‐ American thought occurred at a very peculiar terprise at all. time in the history of American philosophy. the White's demarcation of the major American post-World War II transformation of American thinkers of the late nineteenth century, including philosophy departments into centers for analytic John Dewey, Charles Beard, Oliver Wendell philosophy succeeded in marginalizing the main Holmes, James Harvey Robinson, and Thorstein currents of antiformalism, including pragmatism Veblen, as antiformalists marked the frst work of and naturalism. The theoretical shift ushered in intellectual history dedicated to a broad theoriza‐ by the emigration to America of the famous Vien‐ tion of this period. He was the frst to treat these na Circle, including Rudolf Carnap, Herbert Feigl, individual critiques of historical analysis, philo‐ and Albert Blumberg, and the turn to logical posi‐ sophical speculation, and economic discourse as tivism vanquished questions of experience and part of a shared intellectual project.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Complexity of Ideas in America: Origins and Achievements of the Classical Age of Pragmatism Review Essays Edward A
    digitalcommons.nyls.edu Faculty Scholarship Articles & Chapters 2002 On the Complexity of Ideas in America: Origins and Achievements of the Classical Age of Pragmatism Review Essays Edward A. Purcell Jr. New York Law School Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.nyls.edu/fac_articles_chapters Recommended Citation 27 Law & Soc. Inquiry 967 (2002) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at DigitalCommons@NYLS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles & Chapters by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@NYLS. On the Complexity of "Ideas in America": Origins and Achievements of the Classical Age of Pragmatism Edward A. Purcell Jr. Louis MENAND. The Metaphysical Club: A Story of Ideas in America. New York: Farrar, Straus, Giroux, 2001. Pp. 546. $27.00. Few historians would disagree with the claim that the events surround- ing the Civil War marked a decisive break in American national develop- ment, and few would deny that a major component of that break was the elaboration and spread of new ideas and attitudes about matters of the most fundamental importance: law, nature, science, religion, politics, psychology, philosophy, and social organization itself. In The Metaphysical Club: A Story of Ideas in America, Louis Menand reexamines the roots of those intellectual changes, their evolution through the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, and their long-term significance in American life and thought. "The Civil War swept away the slave civilization of the South, but it swept away almost the whole intellectual culture of the North along with it," he writes. "It took nearly half a century for the United States to develop a culture to replace it, to find a set of ideas, and a way of thinking that would help people cope with the conditions of modem life." Among its effects, that new culture and new way of thinking profoundly reshaped American views of law and the legal system.
    [Show full text]
  • Proper Names and Their Role in Social Ontology
    Proper Names and Their Role in Social Ontology Marek Nagy Palacký University, Olomouc Abstract: The article deals with an applicability of John Searle’s theory of social ontology to linguistic category of proper names . We suggest that in the context of Searle’s theory we can consider proper names to be a kind of social institution . By several examples from anthropolinguistic research and from the field of theoretical onomastics we try to show that proper names meet conditions specified by John Searle, in particu- lar that – through different communities all over the world – they are “holders” of various types of deontic power . At the end of our article we shortly weigh the possibility that proper names can be regard as status indicators (in terms of Searle’s theory) too . Keywords: baptism, deontic power, onomastics, proper names, social ontology . Blake, John? Nothing here. Alright, try my legal name. You should use your full name. I like that name, Robin. Dark Knight Rises To speak about problems of proper names in the context of philo- sophical views of John Searle makes sense for various reasons . Primar- ily, professor Searle has dealt with the category of proper names re- peatedly: In fact, he started his career with the text Proper Names (see Searle 1958) and the conception presented here brought him directly in “textbooks” of this important philosophical debate; proper names as rather strange and interesting individuals are aptly shown also in Sear- le’s Speech Acts (see Searle 1969; the evidence of strangeness could be the mentioned and everlasting discussion on their reference behavior, Organon F 19 (2012), 137-147 © 2012 The Author.
    [Show full text]
  • A New Reading of Kant's Theory of Punishment
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2015 A New Reading of Kant's Theory of Punishment Robert Hoffman University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Hoffman, Robert, "A New Reading of Kant's Theory of Punishment" (2015). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1063. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1063 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1063 For more information, please contact [email protected]. A New Reading of Kant's Theory of Punishment Abstract There are deep, insurmountable difficulties with the aditionaltr interpretation of Immanuel Kantâ??s writings on the subject of punishment. Although it is undeniable that throughout his published writings on practical philosophy â?? and in particular in his Metaphysics of Morals â?? he consistently advocates for the view that punishment can only be justified as a direct response to an individualâ??s act of wrongdoing, his status as one of the foremost theorists in the retributivist pantheon is philosophically untenable. In this dissertation, I articulate the ways in which Kantâ??s explicit support for retributivism directly contradicts more foundational elements of his practical philosophy and argue instead that he has the resources to consistently construct a deterrent theory of punishment. In particular, I highlight Kantâ??s division
    [Show full text]
  • Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association
    January 2011 Volume 84, Issue 3 Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association apa THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION Central Division Program University of Delaware Newark, DE 19716 www.apaonline.org The American Philosophical Association Central Division One Hundred Eighth Annual Meeting Minneapolis Hilton Hotel Minneapolis, Minnesota March 30 - April 2, 2011 Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association (ISSN 0065-972X) is published five times each year and is distributed to members of the APA as a benefit of membership and to libraries, departments, and institutions for $75 per year. It is published by The American Philosophical Association, 31 Amstel Ave., University of Delaware, Newark, DE 19716. Periodicals Postage Paid at Newark, DE and additional mailing offices. POSTMASTER: Send address changes to Proceedings and Addresses, The American Philosophical Association, University of Delaware, Newark, DE 19716. Editor: David E. Schrader Phone: (302) 831-1112 Publications Coordinator: Erin Shepherd Fax: (302) 831-8690 Associate Editor: Robin Smith Web: www.apaonline.org Meeting Coordinator: Linda Smallbrook Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association, the major publication of The American Philosophical Association, is published five times each academic year in the months of September, November, January, February, and May. Each annual volume contains the programs for the meetings of the three Divisions; the membership list; Presidential Addresses; news of the Association, its Divisions and Committees, and announcements of interest to philosophers. Other items of interest to the community of philosophers may be included by decision of the Editor or the APA Board of Officers.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and History
    Contents PREFACE ix PART I: 'THE LOGIC OF mSTORICAL NARRATION 1. The Logic of Historical Narration 3 by Morton White, Harvard University 2. On "The Logic of Historical Narration" 32 by Lee Benson, Wayne University 3. Objectivism in History 43 by Maurice Mandelbaum, The Johns Hopkins University PART n: THE PROBLEMS OF THE WORKING lUSTORIAN 4. Some Problems of a Working Historian 59 by Leo Gershoy, New York University 5. Relativism and Some Problems of Working Historians 76 by Ernest Nagel, Columbia University 6. The Problems of the Working Historian: A Comment 92 by Bernard Bailyn, Harvard University PART m: PATTERNS IN lUSTORY 7. The Historical Explanation of Actions Reconsidered 105 by William Dray, University of Toronto 8. Comments on Historical Explanation 136 by Leonard Krieger, Yale University 9. Reasons and Covering Laws in Historical Explanation 143 by Carl C. Hempel, Princeton University PART IV: CONTRIBUTIONS BY OTHER PARTICIPANTS 10. Cause and Reason in History by Raziel Abelson, New York University vii viii Contents 11. Rational Explanations in History 174 by Evelyn Barker, Columbus, Ohio 12. Observations on History 185 by Lee A. Belford, New York University 13. Personality Traits as Causal Explanations in Biography 192 by R. B. Brandt, Swarthmore College 14. Do Historians Use Covering Laws? 205 by Carl N. Degler, Vassar College 15. History as Factualized Fiction 212 by Ernest van den Haag, New York University 16. The Philosophy in History 227 by Albert Hofstadter, Columbia University 17. Objectivity and Reconstruction in History 250 by Sidney Hook, New York University 18. On Rational Explanation in History 275 by Bruce Mazlish, Massachusetts Institute of Technology 19.
    [Show full text]